메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 39, Issue 3, 2011, Pages 262-297

The logical space of Democracy

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 82755190002     PISSN: 00483915     EISSN: 10884963     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1088-4963.2011.01206.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (25)

References (131)
  • 1
    • 82755178598 scopus 로고
    • See Nicolas de Condorcet, Essay sur l'Application de l'Analyse à la Probabilité des Décisions Rendue à la Pluralité des Voix (Paris, 1785), and for an English translation and commentary, Iain McLean and Arnold B. Urken, eds., Classics of Social Choice (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press)
    • See Nicolas de Condorcet, Essay sur l'Application de l'Analyse à la Probabilité des Décisions Rendue à la Pluralité des Voix (Paris, 1785), and for an English translation and commentary, Iain McLean and Arnold B. Urken, eds., Classics of Social Choice (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press), 1995.
    • (1995)
  • 2
    • 0000721263 scopus 로고
    • Thirteen Theorems in Search of the Truth
    • See, among many others
    • Bernard Grofman, Guillermo Owen, and Scott L. Feld, "Thirteen Theorems in Search of the Truth," Theory and Decision 15 (1983): 261-78 See, among many others
    • (1983) Theory and Decision , vol.15 , pp. 261-78
    • Grofman, B.1    Owen, G.2    Feld, S.L.3
  • 3
    • 0000391037 scopus 로고
    • Majority Systems and the Condorcet Jury Theorem
    • Philip J. Boland, "Majority Systems and the Condorcet Jury Theorem," The Statistician 38 (1989): 181-89
    • (1989) The Statistician , vol.38 , pp. 181-89
    • Boland, P.J.1
  • 4
    • 0035603046 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Epistemic Democracy: Generalizing the Condorcet Jury Theorem
    • Christian List and Robert E. Goodin, "Epistemic Democracy: Generalizing the Condorcet Jury Theorem," Journal of Political Philosophy 9 (2001): 277-306.
    • (2001) Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.9 , pp. 277-306
    • List, C.1    Goodin, R.E.2
  • 5
    • 0007192268 scopus 로고
    • An Epistemic Conception of Democracy
    • Contributions include
    • Joshua Cohen, "An Epistemic Conception of Democracy," Ethics 97 (1986): 26-38 Contributions include
    • (1986) Ethics , vol.97 , pp. 26-38
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 6
    • 84935323219 scopus 로고
    • Democracy and Social Choice
    • Jules L. Coleman and John Ferejohn, "Democracy and Social Choice," Ethics 97 (1986): 6-25
    • (1986) Ethics , vol.97 , pp. 6-25
    • Coleman, J.L.1    Ferejohn, J.2
  • 7
    • 84973937996 scopus 로고
    • Controversy: Democratic Theory and the Public Interest: Condorcet and Rousseau Revisited
    • David Estlund, Jeremy Waldron, Bernard Grofman, and Scott L. Feld, "Controversy: Democratic Theory and the Public Interest: Condorcet and Rousseau Revisited," American Political Science Review 83 (1989): 1317-40
    • (1989) American Political Science Review , vol.83 , pp. 1317-40
    • Estlund, D.1    Waldron, J.2    Grofman, B.3    Feld, S.L.4
  • 8
    • 0009326314 scopus 로고
    • Making Truth Safe for Democracy
    • ed. David Copp, Jean Hampton, and John E. Roemer (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • Estlund, "Making Truth Safe for Democracy," in The Idea of Democracy, ed. David Copp, Jean Hampton, and John E. Roemer (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 1993, pp. 71-100
    • (1993) The Idea of Democracy , pp. 71-100
    • Estlund1
  • 9
    • 0003315452 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beyond Fairness and Deliberation: The Epistemic Dimension of Democratic Authority
    • ed. James Bohman and William Rehg (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press)
    • Estlund, "Beyond Fairness and Deliberation: The Epistemic Dimension of Democratic Authority," in Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics, ed. James Bohman and William Rehg (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 1997, pp. 173-204
    • (1997) Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics , pp. 173-204
    • Estlund1
  • 11
    • 82755180878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Estlund distances himself from Condorcet's jury theorem, but still acknowledges the need to frame his discussion in relation to it
    • Estlund distances himself from Condorcet's jury theorem, but still acknowledges the need to frame his discussion in relation to it.
  • 14
    • 82755178599 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A review of the literature is beyond the scope of this article. William Riker sparked a debate by arguing that these problems challenge the meaningfulness of democracy
    • A review of the literature is beyond the scope of this article. William Riker sparked a debate by arguing that these problems challenge the meaningfulness of democracy
  • 15
    • 82755178600 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Liberalism against Populism (San Francisco: W. H. Freeman, 1982)
    • see Liberalism against Populism (San Francisco: W. H. Freeman, 1982).
  • 16
    • 0001008280 scopus 로고
    • Condorcet's Paradox
    • On the frequency of Condorcet cycles under some simple assumptions, see
    • William V. Gehrlein, "Condorcet's Paradox," Theory and Decision 15 (1983): 161-97. On the frequency of Condorcet cycles under some simple assumptions, see
    • (1983) Theory and Decision , vol.15 , pp. 161-97
    • Gehrlein, W.V.1
  • 17
    • 0012547007 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aggregating Sets of Judgments: An Impossibility Result
    • See, among many other works
    • Christian List and Philip Pettit, "Aggregating Sets of Judgments: An Impossibility Result," Economics and Philosophy 18 (2002): 89-110 See, among many other works
    • (2002) Economics and Philosophy , vol.18 , pp. 89-110
    • List, C.1    Pettit, P.2
  • 18
    • 10844245755 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aggregating Sets of Judgments: Two Impossibility Results Compared
    • List and Pettit, "Aggregating Sets of Judgments: Two Impossibility Results Compared," Synthese 140 (2004): 207-35
    • (2004) Synthese , vol.140 , pp. 207-35
    • List1    Pettit2
  • 19
    • 33747083265 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Logical Constraints on Judgement Aggregation
    • Marc Pauly and Martin van Hees, "Logical Constraints on Judgement Aggregation," Journal of Philosophical Logic 35 (2006): 569-85
    • (2006) Journal of Philosophical Logic , vol.35 , pp. 569-85
    • Pauly, M.1    van Hees, M.2
  • 20
    • 30444448363 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Judgment Aggregation: (Im)possibility Theorems
    • Franz Dietrich, "Judgment Aggregation: (Im)possibility Theorems," Journal of Economic Theory 126 (2006): 286-98
    • (2006) Journal of Economic Theory , vol.126 , pp. 286-98
    • Dietrich, F.1
  • 21
    • 34247599473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Generalised Model of Judgment Aggregation
    • Dietrich, "A Generalised Model of Judgment Aggregation," Social Choice and Welfare 28 (2007): 529-65
    • (2007) Social Choice and Welfare , vol.28 , pp. 529-65
    • Dietrich1
  • 22
    • 34250878024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arrow's Theorem in Judgment Aggregation
    • Dietrich and List, "Arrow's Theorem in Judgment Aggregation," Social Choice and Welfare 29 (2007): 19-33
    • (2007) Social Choice and Welfare , vol.29 , pp. 19-33
    • Dietrich1    List2
  • 23
  • 24
    • 77949485710 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aggregation of Binary Evaluations
    • Elad Dokow and Ron Holzman, "Aggregation of Binary Evaluations," Journal of Economic Theory 145 (2010): 495-511.
    • (2010) Journal of Economic Theory , vol.145 , pp. 495-511
    • Dokow, E.1    Holzman, R.2
  • 25
    • 84928450283 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Unpacking the Court
    • This literature draws on related work on the "doctrinal paradox" in law and economics, especially
    • Lewis A. Kornhauser and Lawrence G. Sager, "Unpacking the Court," Yale Law Journal 96 82-117 This literature draws on related work on the "doctrinal paradox" in law and economics, especially
    • Yale Law Journal , vol.96 , pp. 82-117
    • Kornhauser, L.A.1    Sager, L.G.2
  • 26
    • 60949086046 scopus 로고
    • The One and the Many: Adjudication in Collegial Courts
    • Kornhauser and Sager, "The One and the Many: Adjudication in Collegial Courts," California Law Review 81 (1993): 1-59.
    • (1993) California Law Review , vol.81 , pp. 1-59
    • Kornhauser1    Sager2
  • 27
    • 0040991277 scopus 로고
    • On the Theory of Aggregation
    • The literature also draws on related work in abstract aggregation theory, especially
    • Robert Wilson, "On the Theory of Aggregation," Journal of Economic Theory 10 (1975): 89-99 The literature also draws on related work in abstract aggregation theory, especially
    • (1975) Journal of Economic Theory , vol.10 , pp. 89-99
    • Wilson, R.1
  • 30
    • 34248083420 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deliberative Democracy and the Discursive Dilemma
    • For contributions addressed to political philosophers, see, e.g.,
    • Pettit, "Deliberative Democracy and the Discursive Dilemma," Philosophical Issues (supplement to Nous) 11 (2001): 268-99 For contributions addressed to political philosophers, see, e.g.,
    • (2001) Philosophical Issues (supplement to Nous) , vol.11 , pp. 268-99
    • Pettit1
  • 32
    • 33644761072 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Many as One: Integrity and Group Choice in Paradoxical Cases
    • Kornhauser and Sager, "The Many as One: Integrity and Group Choice in Paradoxical Cases," Philosophy & Public Affairs 32 (2004): 249-76
    • (2004) Philosophy & Public Affairs , vol.32 , pp. 249-76
    • Kornhauser1    Sager2
  • 33
    • 33645128195 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the Many as One: A Reply to Kornhauser and Sager
    • List and Pettit, "On the Many as One: A Reply to Kornhauser and Sager," Philosophy & Public Affairs 33 (2005): 377-90
    • (2005) Philosophy & Public Affairs , vol.33 , pp. 377-90
    • List1    Pettit2
  • 34
    • 33644764311 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Discursive Dilemma and Public Reason
    • List, "The Discursive Dilemma and Public Reason," Ethics 116 (2006): 362-402.
    • (2006) Ethics , vol.116 , pp. 362-402
    • List1
  • 35
    • 84920753792 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Judgment Aggregation: A Survey
    • For a survey, see ed. Paul Anand, Prasanta Pattanaik, and Clemens Puppe (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
    • List and Puppe, "Judgment Aggregation: A Survey," in The Handbook of Rational and Social Choice, For a survey, see ed. Paul Anand, Prasanta Pattanaik, and Clemens Puppe (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 2009, pp. 457-82.
    • (2009) The Handbook of Rational and Social Choice , pp. 457-82
    • List1    Puppe2
  • 36
    • 84922269933 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a discussion of the roles of intentional attitudes in individual and collective agency, see (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
    • List and Pettit, Group Agency: The Possibility, Design and Status of Corporate Agents For a discussion of the roles of intentional attitudes in individual and collective agency, see (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 2011.
    • (2011) Group Agency: The Possibility, Design and Status of Corporate Agents
    • List1    Pettit2
  • 37
    • 82755180875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The underlying model of agency goes back to David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, reprinted from the original and edited by L. A. Selby-Bigge (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1739/1896)
    • The underlying model of agency goes back to David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, reprinted from the original and edited by L. A. Selby-Bigge (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1739/1896).
  • 39
    • 82755180865 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For different versions of this logic-based model of a decision problem, at increasing levels of generality, see
    • List and Pettit, "Aggregating Sets of Judgments: An Impossibility Result" For different versions of this logic-based model of a decision problem, at increasing levels of generality, see
    • Aggregating Sets of Judgments: An Impossibility Result
    • List1    Pettit2
  • 41
    • 82755178593 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Aggregation of Propositional Attitudes: Towards a General Theory
    • Dietrich and List, "The Aggregation of Propositional Attitudes: Towards a General Theory," Oxford Studies in Epistemology 3 (2010): 215-34.
    • (2010) Oxford Studies in Epistemology , vol.3 , pp. 215-34
    • Dietrich1    List2
  • 45
    • 82755193969 scopus 로고
    • "Arrow's Theorem in Judgment Aggregation," but the idea of a propositional representation of preferences goes back to Georges-Théodule Guilbaud, "Theories of the General Interest, and the Logical Problem of Aggregation," in Readings in Mathematical Social Science, ed. Paul F. Lazarsfeld and Neil W. Henry (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press)
    • Dietrich and List, "Arrow's Theorem in Judgment Aggregation," but the idea of a propositional representation of preferences goes back to Georges-Théodule Guilbaud, "Theories of the General Interest, and the Logical Problem of Aggregation," in Readings in Mathematical Social Science, ed. Paul F. Lazarsfeld and Neil W. Henry (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 1966, pp. 262-307
    • (1966) , pp. 262-307
    • Dietrich1    List2
  • 46
    • 82755180874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • even to Condorcet's Essay The present representation can be interpreted in various ways, which is implicit in the contrast between "preferred" and "preferable" in the formulation of ranking propositions; the details do not matter for present purposes
    • even to Condorcet's Essay The present representation can be interpreted in various ways, which is implicit in the contrast between "preferred" and "preferable" in the formulation of ranking propositions; the details do not matter for present purposes.
  • 47
    • 82755168626 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The model can be further generalized to capture decision problems that involve the formation of nonbinary propositional attitudes, as discussed in
    • Dietrich and List, "The Aggregation of Propositional Attitudes." The model can be further generalized to capture decision problems that involve the formation of nonbinary propositional attitudes, as discussed in
    • The Aggregation of Propositional Attitudes
    • Dietrich1    List2
  • 48
    • 82755168638 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But since real-world democratic decisions typically take a discrete-especially binary-form (requiring the acceptance or rejection of certain propositions, or the ranking of certain options in an order of preference), I set the nonbinary case aside here
    • But since real-world democratic decisions typically take a discrete-especially binary-form (requiring the acceptance or rejection of certain propositions, or the ranking of certain options in an order of preference), I set the nonbinary case aside here.
  • 49
    • 82755180873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an English translation of, and commentary on, Borda's proposal, see McLean and Urken, Classics of Social Choice
    • For an English translation of, and commentary on, Borda's proposal, see McLean and Urken, Classics of Social Choice.
  • 51
    • 23044526664 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the Axiomatic Method and Its Recent Applications to Game Theory and Resource Allocation
    • For an excellent discussion of the axiomatic method in social choice theory, see
    • William Thomson, "On the Axiomatic Method and Its Recent Applications to Game Theory and Resource Allocation," Social Choice and Welfare 18 (2000): 327-86. For an excellent discussion of the axiomatic method in social choice theory, see
    • (2000) Social Choice and Welfare , vol.18 , pp. 327-86
    • Thomson, W.1
  • 52
    • 82755193970 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I thereby follow the technical literature on the aggregation of judgments and other propositional attitudes, as briefly reviewed in earlier notes
    • I thereby follow the technical literature on the aggregation of judgments and other propositional attitudes, as briefly reviewed in earlier notes.
  • 53
    • 82755168632 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Generally, if there are x admissible combinations of individual inputs and y admissible collective outputs, there are y x possible decision procedures. If each individual has z different choices, then x can be further expressed as z n, where n is the group size. In the examples just discussed, y = 2, z = 2, and n = 3 or n = 10
    • Generally, if there are x admissible combinations of individual inputs and y admissible collective outputs, there are y x possible decision procedures. If each individual has z different choices, then x can be further expressed as z n, where n is the group size. In the examples just discussed, y = 2, z = 2, and n = 3 or n = 10.
  • 54
    • 82755193971 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is the universal-domain requirement in the literature on judgment or attitude aggregation. In the special case of preferences, it reduces to Arrow's universal-domain condition
    • This is the universal-domain requirement in the literature on judgment or attitude aggregation. In the special case of preferences, it reduces to Arrow's universal-domain condition.
  • 55
    • 82755180863 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Notice, further, that basic majoritarianism does not imply some of the other standard conditions commonly used to prove impossibility results in formal work on aggregation, such as "independence" or "systematicity." Independence requires that the collective attitude on each proposition depend only on individual attitudes on that proposition, not on individual attitudes on other conditions. Systematicity adds to this the requirement that the pattern of dependence be the same for all propositions
    • Notice, further, that basic majoritarianism does not imply some of the other standard conditions commonly used to prove impossibility results in formal work on aggregation, such as "independence" or "systematicity." Independence requires that the collective attitude on each proposition depend only on individual attitudes on that proposition, not on individual attitudes on other conditions. Systematicity adds to this the requirement that the pattern of dependence be the same for all propositions.
  • 56
    • 33644769829 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Special Majorities Rationalized," British Journal of Political Science
    • For discussions of such rules, see, e.g.,
    • Goodin and List, "Special Majorities Rationalized," British Journal of Political Science 36 (2006): 213-41 For discussions of such rules, see, e.g.,
    • (2006) , vol.36 , pp. 213-41
    • Goodin1    List2
  • 57
    • 34748886083 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Judgment Aggregation by Quota Rules: Majority Voting Generalized
    • Dietrich and List, "Judgment Aggregation by Quota Rules: Majority Voting Generalized," Journal of Theoretical Politics 19 (2007): 391-424
    • (2007) Journal of Theoretical Politics , vol.19 , pp. 391-424
    • Dietrich1    List2
  • 58
    • 82755193959 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • By contrast, weighted majority rules, under which different individuals have different voting weights, do not generally satisfy the present basic majoritarian requirement. Harry Brighouse and Marc Fleurbaey advocate such rules on the grounds of a particular proportionality principle
    • By contrast, weighted majority rules, under which different individuals have different voting weights, do not generally satisfy the present basic majoritarian requirement. Harry Brighouse and Marc Fleurbaey advocate such rules on the grounds of a particular proportionality principle
  • 59
    • 77954803523 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Democracy and Proportionality
    • "Democracy and Proportionality," Journal of Political Philosophy 18 (2008): 137-55.
    • (2008) Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.18 , pp. 137-55
  • 60
    • 82755168629 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • They suggest that, in certain collectivedecisions, each decision maker's voting weight should be proportional to his or her "stake" in the decision. Depending on the precise pattern of stakes, and on whether a simple or qualified version of weighted majority voting is used, the resulting decision procedure may well overrule the majority attitude-not, however, the attitude supported by more than half of the total voting weight. Although Brighouse and Fleurbaey's proposal may require a revision in the formulation of "basic majoritarianism," it is not generally immune to the kinds of technical difficulties illustrated by what I call the "democratic trilemma."
    • They suggest that, in certain collectivedecisions, each decision maker's voting weight should be proportional to his or her "stake" in the decision. Depending on the precise pattern of stakes, and on whether a simple or qualified version of weighted majority voting is used, the resulting decision procedure may well overrule the majority attitude-not, however, the attitude supported by more than half of the total voting weight. Although Brighouse and Fleurbaey's proposal may require a revision in the formulation of "basic majoritarianism," it is not generally immune to the kinds of technical difficulties illustrated by what I call the "democratic trilemma."
  • 61
    • 82755178592 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is the collective-rationality requirement in the literature on judgment aggregation. Again, in the special case of preferences, it reduces to Arrow's ordering condition
    • This is the collective-rationality requirement in the literature on judgment aggregation. Again, in the special case of preferences, it reduces to Arrow's ordering condition.
  • 62
    • 82755193958 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For present purposes, I set aside the distinct case of procedures for ranking distributions of certain goods or units of welfare in an order of social preference. The application of social choice theory to such problems of distributive justice is very important, but raises somewhat different challenges compared to the paradigmatic cases of democratic decision making (in elections, referenda, legislatures, committees, and the like)
    • For present purposes, I set aside the distinct case of procedures for ranking distributions of certain goods or units of welfare in an order of social preference. The application of social choice theory to such problems of distributive justice is very important, but raises somewhat different challenges compared to the paradigmatic cases of democratic decision making (in elections, referenda, legislatures, committees, and the like).
  • 63
    • 0004282258 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the justice-theoretic side of social choice theory, see, e.g., (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press)
    • John E. Roemer, Theories of Distributive Justice On the justice-theoretic side of social choice theory, see, e.g., (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press), 1996
    • (1996) Theories of Distributive Justice
    • Roemer, J.E.1
  • 65
    • 0007129872 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Procedural Democracy
    • 5th series, ed. Peter Laslett and James S. Fishkin (Oxford: Blackwell)
    • Robert A. Dahl, "Procedural Democracy," in Philosophy, Politics and Society, 5th series, ed. Peter Laslett and James S. Fishkin (Oxford: Blackwell), 1979.
    • (1979) Philosophy, Politics and Society
    • Dahl, R.A.1
  • 66
    • 82755193964 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As formally stated here, this result is more general than the familiar observation that majority voting does not generally secure consistent collective attitudes, which has been shown at different levels of generality in the literature on judgment aggregation
    • As formally stated here, this result is more general than the familiar observation that majority voting does not generally secure consistent collective attitudes, which has been shown at different levels of generality in the literature on judgment aggregation.
  • 67
    • 82755180865 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the versions of this standard result most closely related to the present point, see
    • List and Pettit, "Aggregating Sets of Judgments: An Impossibility Result" For the versions of this standard result most closely related to the present point, see
    • Aggregating Sets of Judgments: An Impossibility Result
    • List1    Pettit2
  • 69
    • 34250657050 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Structure of Strategy-Proof Social Choice-Part I: General Characterization and Possibility Results on Median Spaces
    • Nehring and Puppe, "The Structure of Strategy-Proof Social Choice-Part I: General Characterization and Possibility Results on Median Spaces," Journal of Economic Theory 135 (2007): 269-305
    • (2007) Journal of Economic Theory , vol.135 , pp. 269-305
    • Nehring1    Puppe2
  • 71
    • 82755180868 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note that the present contribution is not so much the formal result, but rather its substantive interpretation
    • Note that the present contribution is not so much the formal result, but rather its substantive interpretation.
  • 73
    • 82755178597 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Expressed in terms of the formal conditions for the democratic trilemma stated in the appendix, the present agenda has a minimally inconsistent subset of three propositions: the set consisting of "A is preferred/preferable to B,""B is preferred/preferable to C,""C is preferred/preferable to A." This set is inconsistent relative to the standard constraints on preferences, by violating transitivity, and minimally so, since the removal of any of its elements breaks the preference cycle and thereby restores consistency. Generally, if we wish to rank k options in an order of preference, the largest minimally inconsistent subset of the agenda contains k propositions, corresponding to a preference cycle of length k This shows that, like Condorcet's paradox, the democratic trilemma applies to a preference aggregation problem if and only if there are three or more options to be ranked. See also List and Pettit, "Aggregating Sets of Judgments: Two Impossibility Results Compared"; Dietrich and List, "Arrow's Theorem in Judgment Aggregation"; and Dietrich and List, "Judgment Aggregation by Quota Rules."
  • 74
    • 0001786352 scopus 로고
    • On the Rationale of Group Decision-Making
    • Duncan Black, "On the Rationale of Group Decision-Making," Journal of Political Economy 56 (1948): 23-34.
    • (1948) Journal of Political Economy , vol.56 , pp. 23-34
    • Black, D.1
  • 75
    • 0000411128 scopus 로고
    • A Note on the Simple Majority Decision Rule
    • Other key contributions include
    • K.-I. Inada, "A Note on the Simple Majority Decision Rule," Econometrica 32 (1964): 525-31 Other key contributions include
    • (1964) Econometrica , vol.32 , pp. 525-31
    • Inada, K.-I.1
  • 76
    • 0001653838 scopus 로고
    • A Possibility Theorem on Majority Decisions
    • Amartya K. Sen, "A Possibility Theorem on Majority Decisions," Econometrica 34 (1966): 491-99
    • (1966) Econometrica , vol.34 , pp. 491-99
    • Sen, A.K.1
  • 77
    • 0345202094 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a survey of the literature and more recent results, see (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • Wulf Gaertner, Domain Conditions in Social Choice Theory For a survey of the literature and more recent results, see (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 2001
    • (2001) Domain Conditions in Social Choice Theory
    • Gaertner, W.1
  • 78
    • 77949490000 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Majority Voting on Restricted Domains
    • Dietrich and List, "Majority Voting on Restricted Domains," Journal of Economic Theory 145 (2010): 512-43.
    • (2010) Journal of Economic Theory , vol.145 , pp. 512-43
    • Dietrich1    List2
  • 79
    • 1642424522 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Two Concepts of Agreement
    • On the notion of "metaconsensus" and the pattern of "unidimensional alignment" as discussed here, see
    • List, "Two Concepts of Agreement," The Good Society 11 (2002): 72-79. On the notion of "metaconsensus" and the pattern of "unidimensional alignment" as discussed here, see
    • (2002) The Good Society , vol.11 , pp. 72-79
    • List1
  • 80
    • 33744726255 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reconciling Pluralism and Consensus as Political Ideals
    • For some further, subsequent notions of "metaconsensus," see
    • John Dryzek and Simon Niemeyer, "Reconciling Pluralism and Consensus as Political Ideals," American Journal of Political Science 50 (2006): 634-49. For some further, subsequent notions of "metaconsensus," see
    • (2006) American Journal of Political Science , vol.50 , pp. 634-49
    • Dryzek, J.1    Niemeyer, S.2
  • 82
    • 82755178596 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The significance of Black's result was emphasized even by the critic of populist democracy, William Riker, in Liberalism against Populism (at p. 128): "If, by reason of discussion, debate, civic education, and political socialization, voters have a common view of the political dimension (as evidenced by single-peakedness), then a transitive outcome is guaranteed."
    • The significance of Black's result was emphasized even by the critic of populist democracy, William Riker, in Liberalism against Populism (at p. 128): "If, by reason of discussion, debate, civic education, and political socialization, voters have a common view of the political dimension (as evidenced by single-peakedness), then a transitive outcome is guaranteed."
  • 83
    • 0004238625 scopus 로고
    • Classic contributions include (New York: Basic)
    • Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice Classic contributions include (New York: Basic), 1983
    • (1983) Spheres of Justice
    • Walzer, M.1
  • 84
    • 0004002174 scopus 로고
    • (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
    • David Miller, On Nationality (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 1995.
    • (1995) On Nationality
    • Miller, D.1
  • 86
    • 0002959322 scopus 로고
    • Deliberative Democracy and Social Choice
    • [special issue]
    • David Miller, "Deliberative Democracy and Social Choice," Political Studies 40 (1992): 54-67 [special issue]
    • (1992) Political Studies , vol.40 , pp. 54-67
    • Miller, D.1
  • 87
    • 84970772283 scopus 로고
    • Aggregation and Deliberation: On the Possibility of Democratic Legitimacy
    • Jack Knight and James Johnson, "Aggregation and Deliberation: On the Possibility of Democratic Legitimacy," Political Theory 22 (1994): 277-96
    • (1994) Political Theory , vol.22 , pp. 277-96
    • Knight, J.1    Johnson, J.2
  • 88
    • 0037277275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Social Choice Theory and Deliberative Democracy: A Reconciliation
    • John Dryzek and Christian List, "Social Choice Theory and Deliberative Democracy: A Reconciliation," British Journal of Political Science 33 (2003): 1-28.
    • (2003) British Journal of Political Science , vol.33 , pp. 1-28
    • Dryzek, J.1    List, C.2
  • 94
    • 4644239771 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Model of Path-Dependence in Decisions over Multiple Propositions
    • List, "A Model of Path-Dependence in Decisions over Multiple Propositions," American Political Science Review 98 (2004): 495-513
    • (2004) American Political Science Review , vol.98 , pp. 495-513
    • List1
  • 96
    • 77949492079 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Premised-Based Approach to Judgment Aggregation
    • Franz Dietrich and Philippe Mongin, "The Premised-Based Approach to Judgment Aggregation," Journal of Economic Theory 145 (2010): 562-82.
    • (2010) Journal of Economic Theory , vol.145 , pp. 562-82
    • Dietrich, F.1    Mongin, P.2
  • 97
    • 33645815488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Core of the Case Against Judicial Review
    • Jeremy Waldron, "The Core of the Case Against Judicial Review," Yale Law Journal 115 (2006): 1346-406.
    • (2006) Yale Law Journal , vol.115 , pp. 1346-406
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 98
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • The idea of "reflective equilibrium" goes back, of course, to (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press)
    • John Rawls, A Theory of Justice The idea of "reflective equilibrium" goes back, of course, to (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press), 1971.
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 99
    • 82755180871 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In a judgment-aggregation context, a proposal along the present lines is discussed in List and Pettit, Group Agency, chap. 3
    • In a judgment-aggregation context, a proposal along the present lines is discussed in List and Pettit, Group Agency, chap. 3.
  • 100
    • 0036797666 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Merging Information under Constraints: A Logical Framework
    • Sébastien Konieczny and Ramón Pino Pérez, "Merging Information under Constraints: A Logical Framework," Journal of Logic and Computation 12 (2002): 773-808
    • (2002) Journal of Logic and Computation , vol.12 , pp. 773-808
    • Konieczny, S.1    Pérez, R.P.2
  • 101
    • 33749449752 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Belief Merging and the Discursive Dilemma: An Argument-Based Account to Paradoxes of Judgment Aggregation
    • Gabriella Pigozzi, "Belief Merging and the Discursive Dilemma: An Argument-Based Account to Paradoxes of Judgment Aggregation," Synthese 152 (2006): 285-98
    • (2006) Synthese , vol.152 , pp. 285-98
    • Pigozzi, G.1
  • 102
    • 62349097959 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Methods for Distance-Based Judgment Aggregation
    • Michael K. Miller and Dan Osherson, "Methods for Distance-Based Judgment Aggregation," Social Choice and Welfare 32 (2009): 575-601.
    • (2009) Social Choice and Welfare , vol.32 , pp. 575-601
    • Miller, M.K.1    Osherson, D.2
  • 103
    • 82755168631 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the special case of preference aggregation, the so-called Kemeny method is a well-known distance-based decision procedure
    • In the special case of preference aggregation, the so-called Kemeny method is a well-known distance-based decision procedure.
  • 104
    • 82755180869 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On arguments for and against the Borda method, see, e.g., the debate between Mathias Risse, who advocates a variant of the Kemeny method (which, he argues, is Condorcetian in spirit), and Donald Saari, who advocates Borda's method
    • On arguments for and against the Borda method, see, e.g., the debate between Mathias Risse, who advocates a variant of the Kemeny method (which, he argues, is Condorcetian in spirit), and Donald Saari, who advocates Borda's method.
  • 105
    • 0035402968 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arrow's Theorem, Indeterminacy, and Multiplicity Reconsidered
    • Risse, "Arrow's Theorem, Indeterminacy, and Multiplicity Reconsidered," Ethics 111 (2001): 706-34
    • (2001) Ethics , vol.111 , pp. 706-34
    • Risse1
  • 106
    • 0141655124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Capturing the 'Will of the People
    • Saari, "Capturing the 'Will of the People,'" Ethics 113 (2003): 333-49
    • (2003) Ethics , vol.113 , pp. 333-49
    • Saari1
  • 107
    • 29144474118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why the Count de Borda Cannot Beat the Marquis de Condorcet
    • followed by
    • Risse, "Why the Count de Borda Cannot Beat the Marquis de Condorcet," Social Choice and Welfare 25 (2005): 95-113 followed by
    • (2005) Social Choice and Welfare , vol.25 , pp. 95-113
    • Risse1
  • 108
    • 33745152366 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Which Is Better: The Condorcet or Borda Winner?
    • Saari, "Which Is Better: The Condorcet or Borda Winner?" Social Choice and Welfare 26 (2006): 107-29.
    • (2006) Social Choice and Welfare , vol.26 , pp. 107-29
    • Saari1
  • 109
    • 82755178595 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is well known that inconsistent attitudes make a decision maker-individual as well as collective-vulnerable to various forms of strategic exploitation by others, quite apart from the fact that, at least in classical logical terms, anything can be derived from an inconsistent set of commitments
    • It is well known that inconsistent attitudes make a decision maker-individual as well as collective-vulnerable to various forms of strategic exploitation by others, quite apart from the fact that, at least in classical logical terms, anything can be derived from an inconsistent set of commitments.
  • 114
    • 82755180867 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One Case at a Time: Judicial Minimalism on the Supreme Court (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press)
    • One Case at a Time: Judicial Minimalism on the Supreme Court (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press), 1999.
    • (1999)
  • 115
    • 82755168630 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The acceptance threshold for any proposition must be above (k -1)/ k, where k is the size of the largest "minimal inconsistent" subset of the agenda (a measure of its "complexity")
    • The acceptance threshold for any proposition must be above (k -1)/ k, where k is the size of the largest "minimal inconsistent" subset of the agenda (a measure of its "complexity").
  • 117
    • 82755193960 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the examples above, k = 3 and thus a decision procedure requiring more than two-thirds of the individuals for the acceptance of any proposition would guarantee consistent-albeit incomplete-collective attitudes
    • In the examples above, k = 3 and thus a decision procedure requiring more than two-thirds of the individuals for the acceptance of any proposition would guarantee consistent-albeit incomplete-collective attitudes.
  • 118
    • 82755193963 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Relatedly, on "symmetrical supermajority rules," see
    • Goodin and List, "Special Majorities Rationalized." Relatedly, on "symmetrical supermajority rules," see
    • Special Majorities Rationalized
    • Goodin1    List2
  • 119
    • 82755193961 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the notion of group agency, see List and Pettit, Group Agency
    • On the notion of group agency, see List and Pettit, Group Agency.
  • 121
    • 0001138010 scopus 로고
    • The Impossibility of a Paretian Liberal
    • Amartya K. Sen, "The Impossibility of a Paretian Liberal," Journal of Political Economy 78 (1970): 152-57.
    • (1970) Journal of Political Economy , vol.78 , pp. 152-57
    • Sen, A.K.1
  • 122
    • 82755193962 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This template is relevant not only to impossibility results, but also to possibility results where certain conditions characterize a nonempty class of decision procedures. Many such results can be interpreted in the present terms, too, by classifying the relevant conditions as input, responsiveness, and output conditions
    • This template is relevant not only to impossibility results, but also to possibility results where certain conditions characterize a nonempty class of decision procedures. Many such results can be interpreted in the present terms, too, by classifying the relevant conditions as input, responsiveness, and output conditions.
  • 123
    • 82755178594 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a comprehensive review and helpful methodological discussion of the axiomatic method as it is used in a number of different areas of economic theory, see again Thomson, "On the Axiomatic Method and Its Recent Application to Game Theory and Resource Allocation."
    • For a comprehensive review and helpful methodological discussion of the axiomatic method as it is used in a number of different areas of economic theory, see again Thomson, "On the Axiomatic Method and Its Recent Application to Game Theory and Resource Allocation."
  • 124
    • 82755168634 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That is, we keep weakening the desiderata until we reach a point at which any further weakening would render them mutually compatible. Note that a maximally weak formulation of the desiderata subject to the constraint that the incompatibility persists need not be unique
    • That is, we keep weakening the desiderata until we reach a point at which any further weakening would render them mutually compatible. Note that a maximally weak formulation of the desiderata subject to the constraint that the incompatibility persists need not be unique.
  • 125
    • 82755180864 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For proofs that majority voting guarantees consistent collective attitudes if and only if the agenda has no minimally inconsistent subset of more than two propositions, see Dietrich and List, "Judgment Aggregation by Quota Rules," and Nehring and Puppe, "The Structure of Strategy-Proof Social Choice." For earlier related results, see Nehring and Puppe, "Strategy-Proof Social Choice on Single-Peaked Domains." Strictly speaking, without technical caveats, the "if and only if" claim requires an odd number of individuals
    • For proofs that majority voting guarantees consistent collective attitudes if and only if the agenda has no minimally inconsistent subset of more than two propositions, see Dietrich and List, "Judgment Aggregation by Quota Rules," and Nehring and Puppe, "The Structure of Strategy-Proof Social Choice." For earlier related results, see Nehring and Puppe, "Strategy-Proof Social Choice on Single-Peaked Domains." Strictly speaking, without technical caveats, the "if and only if" claim requires an odd number of individuals.
  • 126
    • 82755168633 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Majority ties are possible only when the number of individuals is even. I set the technicalities raised by ties aside here and implicitly assume, for the sake of simplicity, an odd number of individuals
    • Majority ties are possible only when the number of individuals is even. I set the technicalities raised by ties aside here and implicitly assume, for the sake of simplicity, an odd number of individuals.
  • 127
    • 82755193957 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For earlier discussions of this structure condition on an agenda (the "simplicity" or "median" property)
    • Nehring and Puppe, "The Structure of Strategy-Proof Social Choice" For earlier discussions of this structure condition on an agenda (the "simplicity" or "median" property)
    • The Structure of Strategy-Proof Social Choice
    • Nehring1    Puppe2
  • 130
    • 82755180866 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To avoid a trivial conflict between basic majoritarianism and collective completeness in the case of a majority tie, one may demand completeness only in the absence of a majority tie. The trilemma can then be shown to hold for all group sizes except two and, in case the largest minimally inconsistent subset of the agenda has exactly three elements, four
    • To avoid a trivial conflict between basic majoritarianism and collective completeness in the case of a majority tie, one may demand completeness only in the absence of a majority tie. The trilemma can then be shown to hold for all group sizes except two and, in case the largest minimally inconsistent subset of the agenda has exactly three elements, four.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.