메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 32, Issue 3, 2004, Pages 249-276

The many as one: Integrity and group choice in paradoxical cases

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 33644761072     PISSN: 00483915     EISSN: 10884963     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1088-4963.2004.00014.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (54)

References (22)
  • 4
    • 60949086046 scopus 로고
    • The one and the many: Adjudication in collegial courts
    • Lewis A. Kornhauser and Lawrence G. Sager, "The One and the Many: Adjudication in Collegial Courts," California Law Review 81 (1993): 1-59.
    • (1993) California Law Review , vol.81 , pp. 1-59
    • Kornhauser, L.A.1    Sager, L.G.2
  • 5
    • 84936068266 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, esp. ch. 5 and 6.
    • Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1986), esp. ch. 5 and 6.
    • (1986) Law's Empire
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 7
    • 0007118678 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Democracy, electoral and contestatory
    • Pettit, "Democracy, Electoral and Contestatory," Nomos 42 (2000): 105-44
    • (2000) Nomos , vol.42 , pp. 105-144
    • Pettit1
  • 8
    • 22544472843 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Groups with minds of their own
    • ed. Frederick Schmitt (Lanham, Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc.
    • Pettit, "Groups with Minds of their Own," Socializing Metaphysics: The Nature of Social Reality, ed. Frederick Schmitt (Lanham, Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc., 2003), pp. 167-93.
    • (2003) Socializing Metaphysics: The Nature of Social Reality , pp. 167-193
    • Pettit1
  • 9
    • 78751658956 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kornhauser and Sager, "Unpacking the Court."
    • Kornhauser and Sager, "Unpacking the Court."
  • 10
    • 78751655695 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In Law's Empire, Dworkin briefly distinguishes between legislative and adjudicative integrity, and uses legislative examples, such as a compromise "checkerboard ordinance" banning segregation on buses but permitting it in restaurants, to evoke sympathy on behalf of integrity in general (pp. 175-84). But, that work done, the real preoccupation of "law as integrity" is with the work of judges. By and large, legislative integrity enters the picture only briefly and defensively, to explain why it might commonly be sacrificed to other more familiar legislative forces (pp. 217-19), or ascriptively, to justify the interpretive effort of courts to make the best of statutes (pp. 337-38).
  • 11
    • 78751653658 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In Section V, B, below, we observe that Pettit's concern with integrity across a group's members' reasons for resolving a single question before it irresistibly entails a concern with integrity of a group's decision across cases. It is possible that Dworkin's concern with integrity across a group's outcomes over time has a similar entailment regarding integrity across a group's members' basis for their choice in an individual case. We are unaware of any such entailment, however. We mention the possibility of symmetry to signal the rich and largely unexplored territory of integrity as a norm of group behavior.
  • 12
    • 0042354688 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Preference, well-being and morality in social decisions
    • See Kornhauser and Sager, "Unpacking the Court," and Lewis A. Kornhauser, "Preference, Well-Being and Morality in Social Decisions," Journal of Legal Studies 32 (2003): 303-29.
    • (2003) Journal of Legal Studies , vol.32 , pp. 303-329
    • Kornhauser, L.A.1
  • 13
    • 0347194861 scopus 로고
    • Review: Quantitative methods in the law
    • The economic approach to the question of intensity of belief is not uniformly accepted or followed. The practice of fact finding in a civil trial, for example, seems to require that someone who believes HOT with a degree of conviction of .55, and disbelieves NEW, again with a degree of conviction of .55, should endorse RAD though the probability calculus requires its rejection. See, for example, R. Lea Brilmayer and Lewis A. Kornhauser, "Review: Quantitative Methods in the Law," University of Chicago Law Review 46 (1978): 116-53
    • (1978) University of Chicago Law Review , vol.46 , pp. 116-153
    • Brilmayer, R.L.1    Kornhauser, L.A.2
  • 15
    • 0004209735 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, But for our present purposes, we shall assume that the economic approach is a rational guide to individual judgment in our RAD example.
    • Glenn Shafer, The Mathematical Theory of Evidence (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1976). But for our present purposes, we shall assume that the economic approach is a rational guide to individual judgment in our RAD example.
    • (1976) The Mathematical Theory of Evidence
    • Shafer, G.1
  • 16
    • 84972539429 scopus 로고
    • Combining probability distributions: A critique and an annotated bibliography
    • reviews the relevant literature. It is not clear that our intuitive approach conforms to any of the procedures surveyed in Genest and Zidek, though it might be represented by a weighted average approach.
    • We are aware of no widely accepted approach to this question. Christian Genest and James Zidek, "Combining Probability Distributions: A Critique and an Annotated Bibliography," Statistical Science 1 (1986): 114-18 reviews the relevant literature. It is not clear that our intuitive approach conforms to any of the procedures surveyed in Genest and Zidek, though it might be represented by a weighted average approach.
    • (1986) Statistical Science , vol.1 , pp. 114-118
    • Genest, C.1    Zidek, J.2
  • 17
    • 33845386390 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Complex collective decisions: An epistemic perspective
    • have shown formally that, on the assumption that each judge has an equal probability of reaching a true conclusion on each issue, neither procedure dominates the other in terms of tracking the truth. It is possible, of course, that a given community in a given context might seek to minimize false positives or false negatives (or some weighted combination of the two) rather than to minimize overall deviation from the truth. In private communication, Wlodek Rabinowicz has shown that conclusion-based voting weakly dominates reason-based voting in minimizing false positives but that reason-based voting weakly dominates conclusion-based voting in minimizing false negatives.
    • Luc Bovens and Wlodek Rabinowicz, "Complex Collective Decisions: An Epistemic Perspective," Associations 7 (2003): 37-50, have shown formally that, on the assumption that each judge has an equal probability of reaching a true conclusion on each issue, neither procedure dominates the other in terms of tracking the truth. It is possible, of course, that a given community in a given context might seek to minimize false positives or false negatives (or some weighted combination of the two) rather than to minimize overall deviation from the truth. In private communication, Wlodek Rabinowicz has shown that conclusion-based voting weakly dominates reason-based voting in minimizing false positives but that reason-based voting weakly dominates conclusion-based voting in minimizing false negatives.
    • (2003) Associations , vol.7 , pp. 37-50
    • Bovens, L.1    Rabinowicz, W.2
  • 18
    • 21144466886 scopus 로고
    • Modeling collegial courts. II. legal doctrine
    • For a more elaborate and complete discussion of the structure of doctrine, see Kornhauser, "Modeling Collegial Courts. II. Legal Doctrine," Journal of Law, Economics and Organization 8 (1992): 441-70.
    • (1992) Journal of Law, Economics and Organization , vol.8 , pp. 441-470
    • Kornhauser1
  • 19
    • 78751651235 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • With regard to multi-judge courts, it is our view that no blanket rule of any sort is called for; we favor a "meta-vote" to choose between the available aggregation protocols.
    • With regard to multi-judge courts, it is our view that no blanket rule of any sort is called for; we favor a "meta-vote" to choose between the available aggregation protocols.
  • 20
    • 78751670476 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We offer this example rather than a more recognizable legislature, because that introduces the additional complications of one group deciding for another, which we take up below in Section VI.
    • We offer this example rather than a more recognizable legislature, because that introduces the additional complications of one group deciding for another, which we take up below in Section VI.
  • 21
    • 78751665242 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Legislatures do feel some pressure towards enactment of legislative programs as a whole. The Congressional budgeting procedure, for example, attempts to induce Congress to contemplate the full legislative program that it plans to enact when it makes individual budgeting decisions. The process, however, arose not to generate consistency among reasons but to force some spending discipline on Congress.
  • 22
    • 78751670339 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Under an open rule in which any amendment may be made from the floor, Robert's Rules of Order permit consideration of a bill first on a provision by provision basis and then subsequently as an entirely
    • Under an open rule in which any amendment may be made from the floor, Robert's Rules of Order permit consideration of a bill first on a provision by provision basis and then subsequently as an entirely.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.