메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 115, Issue 4, 2015, Pages 809-872

Uncivil obedience

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84930252504     PISSN: 00101958     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (28)

References (411)
  • 1
    • 84930247234 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Apr. 26, 1993, on file with the , Columbia Law Review).
    • Josh Meyer, Slowpokes Make Point at 55 M.P.H., L.A. Times (Apr. 26, 1993), http://articles.latimes.com/1993-04-26/local/me-27445_1_speed-limit (on file with the Columbia Law Review).
    • Slowpokes Make Point at 55 M.P.H., L.A. Times
    • Meyer, J.1
  • 2
    • 84930254371 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Infra notes 59–60 and accompanying text (explaining “uncivil obedience” label).
    • Infra notes 59–60 and accompanying text (explaining “uncivil obedience” label).
  • 3
    • 84930254372 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • That is, it involves subversive modes of behaving in conformity with law. An important terminological clarification: In saying that uncivil obedients “obey,” “follow,” or “comply with” the law, we do not mean to suggest that they necessarily or even normally conform their behavior to the law because that is what the law directs them to do. We thus use “obedience” and related terms in a looser sense than some jurisprudes would allow. Note
  • 4
    • 84930254373 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Donald H. Regan, Reasons, Authority, and the Meaning of “Obey”: Further Thoughts on Raz and Obedience to Law, 3 Can. J.L. & Jurisprudence 3, 16 (1990) (“[A]n agent ‘obeys’ authority, in the strict sense, only if she regards the authority’s directives... as intrinsic reasons for action.”).Note
  • 6
    • 84930254375 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The phrase “uncivil obedience” makes an appearance in several memoirs by former activists
    • The phrase “uncivil obedience” makes an appearance in several memoirs by former activists
  • 7
    • 84930254376 scopus 로고
    • The approach I advocate is a form of uncivil obedience. By this, I mean we should obey the law but stick it to the government anyway
    • A. Alan Borovoy, Uncivil Obedience: The Ta ctics and Ta les of a Democratic Agitator 15 (1991) (“The approach I advocate is a form of uncivil obedience. By this, I mean we should obey the law but stick it to the government anyway.”)
    • (1991) Uncivil Obedience: the Ta Ctics and Ta Les of A
    • Alan Borovoy, A.1
  • 9
    • 84930254377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • discussing “UncivilObedience, Disobedience, and Civil Initiative”), and in a smattering of academic articles.We are not aware of any work that has considered the phrase or the phenomenon, however labeled, in depth.
    • discussing “Uncivil Obedience, Disobedience, and Civil Initiative”, and in a smattering of academic articles. We are not aware of any work that has considered the phrase or the phenomenon, however labeled, in depth.
  • 10
    • 84930248321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dec. 20, 2013, hereinafterBrownlee, Civil Disobedience] (on file with the Columbia Law Review). We draw in particular in this discussion on the influential formulations of John Rawls, Joseph Raz,Kimberley Brownlee, and Hugo Bedau.
    • Kimberley Brownlee, Civil Disobedience, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Dec. 20, 2013), http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/civil-disobedience [hereinafter Brownlee, Civil Disobedience] (on file with the Columbia Law Review). We draw in particular in this discussion on the influential formulations of John Rawls, Joseph Raz, Kimberley Brownlee, and Hugo Bedau.
    • Civil Disobedience, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
    • Brownlee, K.1
  • 11
    • 84930238730 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • hereinafter Brownlee, Conscience and Conviction] (“[C]ivil disobedience must include a deliberate breach of law taken on the basis of steadfast personal commitment in order to communicate [one’s] condemnation of a law or policy to a relevantly placed audience.”)
    • Kimberley Brownlee, Conscience and Conviction: The Case for Civil Disobedience 18 (2012) [hereinafter Brownlee, Conscience and Conviction] (“[C]ivil disobedience must include a deliberate breach of law taken on the basis of steadfast personal commitment in order to communicate [one’s] condemnation of a law or policy to a relevantly placed audience.”)
    • (2012) Conscience , pp. 18
    • Brownlee, K.1
  • 12
  • 13
    • 84930254378 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • defining civil disobedience as “a public, nonviolent, conscientious yet political act contrary to law usually done with the aim of bringing about a change in the law or policies of the government
    • defining civil disobedience as “a public, nonviolent, conscientious yet political act contrary to law usually done with the aim of bringing about a change in the law or policies of the government”
  • 15
    • 84930254379 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • “Civil Disobedience is a politically motivated breach of law designed either to contribute directly to a change of a law or of a public policy or to express one’s protest against, and [dissociation] from, a law or a public policy
    • “Civil Disobedience is a politically motivated breach of law designed either to contribute directly to a change of a law or of a public policy or to express one’s protest against, and [dissociation] from, a law or a public policy.”
  • 16
    • 70350560710 scopus 로고
    • On Civil Disobedience
    • 58, hereinafter Bedau, On Civil Disobedience] (“Anyone commits an , act of civil disobedience if and only if he acts illegally, publicly, nonviolently, and conscientiously with the intent to frustrate (one of) the laws, policies, or decisions of his government.”
    • Hugo A. Bedau, On Civil Disobedience, 58 J. Phil. 653, 661 (1961) [hereinafter Bedau, On Civil Disobedience] (“Anyone commits an act of civil disobedience if and only if he acts illegally, publicly, nonviolently, and conscientiously with the intent to frustrate (one of) the laws, policies, or decisions of his government.”).
    • (1961) J. Phil , vol.653 , pp. 661
    • Bedau, H.A.1
  • 17
    • 84930254380 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Compare, e.g., Rawls, supra note 6, at 364–68 (defining civil disobedience narrowly), with Raz, supra note 6, at 269 (arguing features proposed “in an attempt to articulate and justify a doctrine of the permissible forms of civil disobedience” are “arbitrary restrictions”). Note
  • 18
    • 51549085190 scopus 로고
    • [T]he disobedience of laws which are not themselves the target of the protest... , constitutes an act of rebellion, not merely of dissent.”
    • Abe Fortas, Concerning Dissent and Civil Disobedience 63 (1968) (“[T]he disobedience of laws which are not themselves the target of the protest... constitutes an act of rebellion, not merely of dissent.”).
    • (1968) Concerning Dissent and Civil Disobedience , pp. 63
    • Fortas, A.1
  • 19
    • 84930254381 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brownlee, Conscience and Conviction, supra note 6, at 19 (recognizing both subcategories of civil disobedience); Rawls, supra note 6, at 364–65 (same)
    • Brownlee, Conscience and Conviction, supra note 6, at 19 (recognizing both subcategories of civil disobedience); Rawls, supra note 6, at 364–65 (same)
  • 20
    • 84930254382 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hannah Arendt, Civil Disobedience, in Crises of the Republic 49, 55–56 (1969) (same)
    • Hannah Arendt, Civil Disobedience, in Crises of the Republic 49, 55–56 (1969) (same)
  • 21
    • 85048901581 scopus 로고
    • Civil Disobedience in a Constitutional Democracy
    • 10, (same). In Daniel Markovits’s terms, the civil disobedient may “disobey one law... in defianceof another” law or legal regime. Daniel Markovits, Democratic Disobedience, 114 Yale L.J. 1897, 1936 n.85 (2005) (emphases added).
    • Marshall Cohen, Civil Disobedience in a Constitutional Democracy, 10 Mass. Rev. 211, 225 (1969) (same). In Daniel Markovits’s terms, the civil disobedient may “disobey one law... in defiance of another” law or legal regime. Daniel Markovits, Democratic Disobedience, 114 Yale L.J. 1897, 1936 n.85 (2005) (emphases added).
    • (1969) Mass. Rev. , vol.211 , pp. 225
    • Cohen, M.1
  • 22
    • 84930250266 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hugo Adam Bedau ed., 1991) [hereinafter Bedau, Personal Responsibility] (noting “undeniable fact that some injustices are inaccessible to direct resistance by some who would protest them” (emphasis omitted))
    • H.A. Bedau, Civil Disobedience and Personal Responsibility for Injustice, in Civil Disobedience in Focus 49, 52 (Hugo Adam Bedau ed., 1991) [hereinafter Bedau, Personal Responsibility] (noting “undeniable fact that some injustices are inaccessible to direct resistance by some who would protest them” (emphasis omitted))
    • Civil Disobedience and Personal Responsibility for Injustice, In , vol.49 , pp. 52
    • Bedau, H.A.1
  • 23
    • 84930254383 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Rawls, supra note 6, at 365 (“[I]f the government enacts a vague and harsh statute against treason, it would not be appropriate to commit treason as a way of objecting to it.... In other cases there is no way to violate the government’s policy directly, as when it concerns foreign afairs....”). Some would also exclude from the category of civil disobedience breaches of law that target nongovernmental entities Note
  • 24
    • 84930254384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Raz, supra note 6, at 264 (bracketing protests against “actions or policies of private agents (trade unions, banks, private universities, etc.)”), while others insist it is arbitrary to exclude such protests insofar as they necessarily challenge “the legal framework that accepts [the condemned] policies and practices as lawful,” Brownlee, Conscience and Conviction, supra note 6, at 19 n.8 Note
  • 26
    • 84930254385 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As long as it does not seriously threaten the legal order, disobedience to correct private injustice cannot be ruled out on principle
    • As long as it does not seriously threaten the legal order, disobedience to correct private injustice cannot be ruled out on principle
  • 27
    • 84930254386 scopus 로고
    • hereinafter Walzer, Civil Disobedience] (describing type of civil disobedience that “takes , place simultaneously in two diferent social arenas, the corporation and the state
    • Michael Walzer, Civil Disobedience and Corporate Authority, in Obligations: Essays on Disobedience, War, and Citizenship 24, 43 (1970) [hereinafter Walzer, Civil Disobedience] (describing type of civil disobedience that “takes place simultaneously in two diferent social arenas, the corporation and the state”).
    • (1970) Civil Disobedience and Corporate , vol.24 , pp. 43
    • Walzer, M.1
  • 28
    • 84930254387 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For instance, is refusing to pay taxes to the extent that one expects them to benefit the military an act of direct or indirect civil disobedience regarding military policy?
    • For instance, is refusing to pay taxes to the extent that one expects them to benefit the military an act of direct or indirect civil disobedience regarding military policy?
  • 29
    • 34247369855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kimberley Brownlee, The Communicative Aspects of Civil Disobedience and Lawful Punishment, 1 Crim. L. & Phil. 179, 184 n.9 (2007) [hereinafter Brownlee, Communicative Aspects] (presenting this example).
    • Kimberley Brownlee, The Communicative Aspects of Civil Disobedience and Lawful Punishment, 1 Crim. L. & Phil. 179, 184 n.9 (2007) [hereinafter Brownlee, Communicative Aspects] (presenting this example).
  • 30
    • 84930254389 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U.S. Const. art. VI, cl. 2
    • U.S. Const. art. VI, cl. 2
  • 31
    • 84930254390 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    •  Arendt, supra note 9, at 53 (“[B]ecause of its dual system[,] American law, in distinction from other legal systems, has found a nonficti-tious, visible place for that higher law on which in one form or another jurisprudence keeps insisting.” (internal quotation marks omitted)).
    •  Arendt, supra note 9, at 53 (“[B]ecause of its dual system[,] American law, in distinction from other legal systems, has found a nonficti-tious, visible place for that higher law on which in one form or another jurisprudence keeps insisting.” (internal quotation marks omitted)).
  • 32
    • 84930254391 scopus 로고
    • The Problem of the Compatibility of Civil Disobedience with
    • 43
    • Charles L. Black, The Problem of the Compatibility of Civil Disobedience with American Institutions of Government, 43 Te x. L. Rev. 492, 506 (1965).
    • (1965) Te X. L. Rev , vol.492 , pp. 506
    • Black, C.L.1
  • 33
    • 84930254392 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, supra note 6, at 365.
    • Rawls, supra note 6, at 365.
  • 34
    • 84930254393 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Walzer, Civil Disobedience, supra note 10, at 24
    • Walzer, Civil Disobedience, supra note 10, at 24
  • 35
    • 84930254394 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A man breaks the law [when engaging in civil disobedience], but does so in ways which do notchallenge the legitimacy of the legal or political systems
    • A man breaks the law [when engaging in civil disobedience], but does so in ways which do not challenge the legitimacy of the legal or political systems
  • 36
    • 84930254395 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, supra note 6, at 364 (invoking conscientiousness); Bedau, Personal Responsibility, supra note 10, at 51 (same)
    • Rawls, supra note 6, at 364 (invoking conscientiousness); Bedau, Personal Responsibility, supra note 10, at 51 (same)
  • 37
    • 84930252622 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Features of a
    • 10, same
    • Kimberley Brownlee, Features of a Paradigm Case of Civil Disobedience, 10 Res Publica 337, 338 (2004) (same).
    • (2004) Res Publica , vol.337 , pp. 338
    • Brownlee, K.1
  • 38
    • 84930254396 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Rawls maintains that civil disobedience must be guided and justified by fundamental principles of justice. A civil disobedient may not base her protest on morality or religion, let alone on self-interest (although these may coincide with and support her claims) Note
  • 39
    • 84930254397 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • instead, she must appeal to “the commonly shared conception of justice that underlies the political order” and locate her protest within the majority’s contemporary understanding of justice. Rawls, supra note 6, at 365 Note
  • 40
    • 84930254398 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Cohen, supra note 9, at 212 (stating principles invoked by civil disobedient “are principles that he takes to be generally acknowledged”). Against Rawls, many commentators contend that the civil disobedient may seek to alter or expand the majority’s conception of justice, rather than appeal to its existing conception, and that moral or religious principles can equally motivate her dissent. Note
  • 41
    • 84930254399 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Greenawalt, supra note 10, at 230–35 (challenging narrowness of Rawls’s formulation); Peter Singer, Democracy and Disobedience 88–90 (1973) (same). Note
  • 43
    • 84930254400 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, supra note 6, at 366 (characterizing civil disobedience as “form of address”)
    • Rawls, supra note 6, at 366 (characterizing civil disobedience as “form of address”)
  • 44
    • 84930254401 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz, supra note 6, at 264–65 (noting expressive character of civil disobedience).
    • Raz, supra note 6, at 264–65 (noting expressive character of civil disobedience).
  • 45
    • 84930254402 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, supra note 6, at 366 (“[Civil disobedience] is engaged in openly with fair notice
    • Rawls, supra note 6, at 366 (“[Civil disobedience] is engaged in openly with fair notice
  • 46
    • 84930254403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • it is not covert or secretive.”)
    • it is not covert or secretive.”)
  • 48
    • 84930254404 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Usually, though not always, it is essential to the purpose of the dissenter that both the public and the government should know what he intends to do
    • Usually, though not always, it is essential to the purpose of the dissenter that both the public and the government should know what he intends to do
  • 49
    • 84930254405 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cohen, supra note 9, at 212 (“[I]t is essential that [the civil disobedient’s actions] be performed in public, or called to the public’s attention.”).
    • Cohen, supra note 9, at 212 (“[I]t is essential that [the civil disobedient’s actions] be performed in public, or called to the public’s attention.”).
  • 50
    • 84930254406 scopus 로고
    • The Obligation to Disobey, in Obligations: Essays on Disobedience
    • hereinafter Walzer, Obligation
    • Michael Walzer, The Obligation to Disobey, in Obligations: Essays on Disobedience, War, and Citizenship 3, 20 (1970) [hereinafter Walzer, Obligation].
    • (1970) War, and Citizenship , vol.3 , pp. 20
    • Walzer, M.1
  • 51
    • 84930244343 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 6, Disobedience , carried out covertly in the first instance to ensure that the act is successful may nonetheless be open and communicative when followed by an acknowledgment of the act and the reasons for taking it.”
    • Brownlee, Conscience and Conviction, supra note 6, at 23 (“Disobedience carried out covertly in the first instance to ensure that the act is successful may nonetheless be open and communicative when followed by an acknowledgment of the act and the reasons for taking it.”)
    • Conscience and Conviction , pp. 23
    • Brownlee1
  • 52
    • 84930254407 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz, supra note 6, at 265 (“[O]nly the fact that an act of disobedience occurred and... the nature of its motivation have to be made publicly known.”).
    • Raz, supra note 6, at 265 (“[O]nly the fact that an act of disobedience occurred and... the nature of its motivation have to be made publicly known.”).
  • 53
    • 84930242925 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • stating civil , disobedient must convey not only criticism “but also her desire for... a lasting change in law or policy”
    • Brownlee, Communicative Aspects, supra note 11, at 180 (stating civil disobedient must convey not only criticism “but also her desire for... a lasting change in law or policy”).
    • Communicative Aspects, Supra Note 11 , pp. 180
    • Brownlee1
  • 54
    • 84930254408 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • But cf. Raz, supra note 6, at 263–64 (arguing civil disobedience may be “designed either to contribute directly to a change of a law or of a public policy or to express one’s protest against, and [dissociation] from, a law or public policy,” but further noting all civil disobedience is designed “to have a political efect”). Although “[a]cts of civil disobedience often have focused and limited objectives,” Brownlee, Civil Disobedience, supra note 6, several commentators have recently called attention to variants that aspire to challenge political structures or stimulate democratic engagement more broadly. We discuss these variants infra notes 110, 253–257 and accompanying text. Note
  • 55
    • 84930254409 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz, supra note 6, at 264
    • Raz, supra note 6, at 264
  • 56
    • 84930254410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Singer, supra note 17, at 93 (noting conscientious objection “is undertaken in order to avoid taking part in the policies to which one objects, rather than in order to change those policies”)
    • Singer, supra note 17, at 93 (noting conscientious objection “is undertaken in order to avoid taking part in the policies to which one objects, rather than in order to change those policies”)
  • 57
    • 84930254411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Walzer, Obligation, supra note 20, at 12 (classifying conscientious objection as form of civil disobedience)
    • Walzer, Obligation, supra note 20, at 12 (classifying conscientious objection as form of civil disobedience)
  • 58
    • 84903437310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Administrative Origins of Modern Civil Liberties Law
    • 114, arguing World War I activists and administrators conceived of conscientious objection “not as a right to opt out of the warfare state, but rather as a right , to participate in... a particularistic manner
    • Jeremy K. Kessler, The Administrative Origins of Modern Civil Liberties Law, 114 Colum. L. Rev. 1083, 1090 (2014) (arguing World War I activists and administrators conceived of conscientious objection “not as a right to opt out of the warfare state, but rather as a right to participate in... a particularistic manner”).
    • (2014) Colum. L. Rev , vol.1083 , pp. 1090
    • Kessler, J.K.1
  • 59
    • 84930254412 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt, supra note 9, at 76–77 (asserting nonviolence is “generally , accepted necessary characteristic of civil disobedience”)
    •  Arendt, supra note 9, at 76–77 (asserting nonviolence is “generally accepted necessary characteristic of civil disobedience”)
  • 60
    • 84930254413 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bedau, On Civil Disobedience, supra note 6, at 656 (“The pun on ‘civil’ is essential; only nonviolent acts thus can qualify.”).
    • Bedau, On Civil Disobedience, supra note 6, at 656 (“The pun on ‘civil’ is essential; only nonviolent acts thus can qualify.”).
  • 61
    • 84930254414 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brownlee, Conscience and Conviction, supra note 6, at 21–23
    • Brownlee, Conscience and Conviction, supra note 6, at 21–23
  • 62
    • 84930254415 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (contesting “presumed incivility of violence”)
    • (contesting “presumed incivility of violence”)
  • 63
    • 84904628101 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 10, at, arguing “insistence on the absolute nonviolence of civil disobedience is... a little , disingenuous,” in light of violence and coercion risked by all legal disobedience)
    • Walzer, Civil Disobedience, supra note 10, at 25 (arguing “insistence on the absolute nonviolence of civil disobedience is... a little disingenuous,” in light of violence and coercion risked by all legal disobedience)
    • Civil Disobedience , pp. 25
    • Walzer1
  • 64
    • 84947634169 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Fallacy on Law and Order: That Civil Disobedience Must Be Absolutely Nonviolent
    • Howard Zinn, A Fallacy on Law and Order: That Civil Disobedience Must Be Absolutely Nonviolent, in Civil Disobedience and Violence 103, 111
    • In Civil Disobedience and Violence , vol.103 , pp. 111
    • Zinn, H.1
  • 65
    • 84930254416 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jefrie G. Murphy ed., 1971) (“[I]t would be foolish to rule out at the start, for all times and conditions, all of the vast range of possible tactics beyond strict nonviolence.”).
    • Jefrie G. Murphy ed., 1971) (“[I]t would be foolish to rule out at the start, for all times and conditions, all of the vast range of possible tactics beyond strict nonviolence.”).
  • 66
    • 84930254417 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz, supra note 6, at 267 (“[C]ertain non-violent acts, indeed some lawful acts, may well have much more severe consequences than many an act of violence: consider the possible efects of a strike by ambulance drivers.”)
    • Raz, supra note 6, at 267 (“[C]ertain non-violent acts, indeed some lawful acts, may well have much more severe consequences than many an act of violence: consider the possible efects of a strike by ambulance drivers.”)
  • 67
    • 84930254418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brownlee, Conscience and Conviction, supra note 6, at 21–22 (“[F]ocusing attention on violence draws attention away from the presumptively more salient issue of harm.”).
    • Brownlee, Conscience and Conviction, supra note 6, at 21–22 (“[F]ocusing attention on violence draws attention away from the presumptively more salient issue of harm.”).
  • 68
    • 84930254419 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Greenawalt, supra note 10, at 244–65 (arguing violence may sometimes be justified). Theorists have advanced additional criteria for distinguishing justified from unjustified civil disobedience.
    • Greenawalt, supra note 10, at 244–65 (arguing violence may sometimes be justified). Theorists have advanced additional criteria for distinguishing justified from unjustified civil disobedience.
  • 69
    • 84930254420 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    •  Rawls, supra note 6, at 371–77 (proposing civil disobedience should be limited to instances of clear and substantial injustice, used as last resort, and involve coordinated action among minority groups).
    •  Rawls, supra note 6, at 371–77 (proposing civil disobedience should be limited to instances of clear and substantial injustice, used as last resort, and involve coordinated action among minority groups).
  • 70
    • 84930254421 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Raz, supra note 6, at 275 (arguing such conditions represent attempt to “routinize” civil disobedience and “make it a regular form of political action to which all have a right,” when civil disobedience’s “exceptional character lies precisely... in the fact that it is (in liberal states) one type of political action to which one has no right”). Note
  • 71
    • 84930254422 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • As with nonviolence, however, some contend that willingness to accept punishment is not a definitional component of civil disobedience but rather a morally significant consideration for evaluating its practice. Note
  • 72
    • 84930254423 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz, supra note 6, at 265 (adopting this view). Others stress the insufficiency of willingness to accept punishment as a basis for legitimation.
    • Raz, supra note 6, at 265 (adopting this view). Others stress the insufficiency of willingness to accept punishment as a basis for legitimation.
  • 73
    • 84930254424 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cohen, supra note 9, at 214 (“It is mindless to suppose that murder, rape or arson would be justified if only one were willing to pay the penalty....”).
    • Cohen, supra note 9, at 214 (“It is mindless to suppose that murder, rape or arson would be justified if only one were willing to pay the penalty....”).
  • 74
    • 84930254425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Martin Luther King, Jr., Letter from Birmingham City Jail, in A Te stament of Hope 289, 294 (James Melvin Washington ed., 1986) (emphases omitted)
    • Martin Luther King, Jr., Letter from Birmingham City Jail, in A Te stament of Hope 289, 294 (James Melvin Washington ed., 1986) (emphases omitted)
  • 75
    • 84930254426 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (“[W]e would present our very bodies as a means of laying our case before the conscience of the local and national community.”). Drawing on King’s example, contemporary critics of Edward Snowden have insisted that his flight from prosecution disqualifies him from civil disobedient status.
    • (“[W]e would present our very bodies as a means of laying our case before the conscience of the local and national community.”). Drawing on King’s example, contemporary critics of Edward Snowden have insisted that his flight from prosecution disqualifies him from civil disobedient status.
  • 76
    • 84930254427 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • June 3, 9:00 AM), guest-post-snowden-obliged-accept-punishment (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (detailing and disputing this line of argument)
    • Michael J. Glennon, Is Snowden Obliged to Accept Punishment?, Just Security (June 3, 2014, 9:00 AM), http://justsecurity.org/11068/ guest-post-snowden-obliged-accept-punishment (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (detailing and disputing this line of argument).
    • (2014) Is Snowden Obliged
    • Glennon, M.J.1
  • 77
    • 84930254428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, supra note 6, at 366–67 (arguing “fidelity to law is expressed... by the willingness to accept the legal consequences of one’s conduct”)
    • Rawls, supra note 6, at 366–67 (arguing “fidelity to law is expressed... by the willingness to accept the legal consequences of one’s conduct”)
  • 78
    • 84930254429 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bedau, Personal Responsibility, supra note 10, at 51 (stating civil disobedience’s occurrence within framework of rule of law necessitates “willingness on the part of the disobedient to accept the legal consequences of his act”)
    • Bedau, Personal Responsibility, supra note 10, at 51 (stating civil disobedience’s occurrence within framework of rule of law necessitates “willingness on the part of the disobedient to accept the legal consequences of his act”)
  • 79
    • 84930254430 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 46–47, [Civil disobedience] respects , the legal norm at the very moment of resistance, and places itself under the sanction of that norm. If it resists the legal sanction that it brings upon itself, in truth it is no longer engaged in civil disobedience.”).
    • Bernard E. Harcourt, Political Disobedience, in Occupy: Three Inquiries in Disobedience 45, 46–47 (2013) (“[Civil disobedience] respects the legal norm at the very moment of resistance, and places itself under the sanction of that norm. If it resists the legal sanction that it brings upon itself, in truth it is no longer engaged in civil disobedience.”).
    • (2013) Political Disobedience, In , pp. 45
    • Harcourt, B.E.1
  • 80
    • 84930254431 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The possible application of multiple laws to “uncivil” behaviors is a focus of infra Part III.A.
    • The possible application of multiple laws to “uncivil” behaviors is a focus of infra Part III.A.
  • 81
    • 84930254432 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Local 702 Int’l Bhd. of Elec. Workers, AFL-CIO v. NLRB, 215 F. 3d 11, 14 (D.C. Cir. 2000) (considering work-to-rule action in which employees were “adhering strictly to all company safety and other rules; doing exactly and only what they were told
    • Local 702 Int’l Bhd. of Elec. Workers, AFL-CIO v. NLRB, 215 F. 3d 11, 14 (D.C. Cir. 2000) (considering work-to-rule action in which employees were “adhering strictly to all company safety and other rules; doing exactly and only what they were told
  • 82
    • 84930254433 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [and] reporting to work precisely on time” (internal quotation marks omitted))
    • [and] reporting to work precisely on time” (internal quotation marks omitted))
  • 83
    • 84930254434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [and] reporting to work precisely on time” (internal quotation marks omitted))Note
    • Direct Action: Solidarity and Sabotage, in We Are Everywhere: The Irresistible Rise of Global Anticapitalism 456, 457 (Notes from Nowhere ed., 2003) (“The notion of the work-to-rule is brilliantly simple—workers follow every rule, no matter how foolish, inefficient, or ill-advised. They break no laws, cause as much disruption as a strike, yet everyone still gets paid!”). William Simon has described work to rule as the practice of “bring[ing] an enterprise to a halt by refusing to cut the corners necessary for things to function smoothly” and cited it as a case of “scrupulous compliance with the law [that] is so burdensome and even disruptive that it occurs only as a form of protest.” William H. Simon, The Practice of Justice 90–91 (1998). Note
  • 84
    • 84930254435 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • As one commentator explained: If you ran your car like American Airlines has been running for the last two weeks[,] if your car was leaking oil on the drive, write it up. Windshield wipers streaking, write it up. Shocks squeaking, write it up. Car pulls slightly to the left, write it up.... A lot of systems in the morning sometimes just don’t come on line in the correct sequence. You’ll get a light or the thing won’t test so the fix is to power it down and then power it back up. Is a pilot authorized to do this[?] [N]o but we all used to do it so the flight could depart on time. Now if the same problem occurs guys are putting it in the log book and taking the delay. Note
  • 86
    • 33750855668 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nation (Mar. 8, 2010), [hereinafter Piven & Cloward, We ight of the Poor] (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (originally published May 2, 1966).
    • Frances Fox Piven & Richard Cloward, The Weight of the Poor: A Strategy to End Poverty, Nation (Mar. 8, 2010), http://www.thenation.com/article/weight-poor-strategy-end-poverty [hereinafter Piven & Cloward, We ight of the Poor] (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (originally published May 2, 1966).
    • The Weight of the Poor: A Strategy to End
    • Piven, F.F.1    Cloward, R.2
  • 87
    • 84930254438 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Cloward and Piven argued that maximizing welfare rolls would strain the “big-city Democratic coalition: the remaining white middle class, the white working-class ethnic groups and the growing minority poor.” Id. To preserve that coalition, and spurred by lobbying from mayors and governors rather than the poor themselves, “a national Democratic administration would be constrained to advance a federal solution to poverty that would override local welfare failures, local class and racial conflicts and local revenue dilemmas.” Id. Although never fully implemented, the Cloward–Piven proposal remains a canonical text for the welfare rights movement. Note
  • 88
    • 84930254439 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Frances Fox Piven & Richard Cloward, Poor People’s Movements 275–88 (1977) (discussing proposal).
    • Frances Fox Piven & Richard Cloward, Poor People’s Movements 275–88 (1977) (discussing proposal).
  • 89
    • 84930254440 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We explore some of the distinctive complexities raised by this category of examples infra Part II.B.4.
    • We explore some of the distinctive complexities raised by this category of examples infra Part II.B.4.
  • 90
    • 84930238522 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Medication Abortion Restrictions Burden
    • 16, summarizing these laws); Guttmacher Inst., State , Policies in Brief: Medication Abortion (2015, on file with the Columbia Law Review) (same
    • Heather D. Boonstra, Medication Abortion Restrictions Burden Women and Providers—and Threaten U.S. Trend To ward Very Early Abortion, 16 Guttmacher Pol’y Rev. 18, 21–22 (2013) (summarizing these laws); Guttmacher Inst., State Policies in Brief: Medication Abortion (2015), http://www.guttmacher.org/statecenter/spibs/spib_MA.pdf (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (same).
    • (2013) Guttmacher Pol’y Rev , vol.18 , pp. 21-22
    • Boonstra, H.D.1
  • 91
    • 84930254441 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Boonstra, supra note 37, at 19 (describing ways in which FDA-approved regimen has become “antiquated”)
    • Boonstra, supra note 37, at 19 (describing ways in which FDA-approved regimen has become “antiquated”)
  • 92
    • 84930243188 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Finer, The Accessibility of Abortion Services in the United States,
    • 35, & tbl.42003(finding eighty-three percent of medication , abortions performed in 2001 used a third of FDA-approved mifepristone dose).
    • Stanley K. Henshaw & Lawrence B. Finer, The Accessibility of Abortion Services in the United States, 2001, 35 Persps. on Sexual & Reprod. Health 16, 20–21 & tbl.4 (2003) (finding eighty-three percent of medication abortions performed in 2001 used a third of FDA-approved mifepristone dose).
    • (2001) Persps. On Sexual & , vol.16 , pp. 20-21
    • Henshaw, S.K.1    Lawrence, B.2
  • 93
    • 84930254442 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. infra notes 233–236 and accompanying text (explaining why strength of conviction needed to inspire uncivil obedience is likely to be weaker on average than whatis needed for civil disobedience).
    • Cf. infra notes 233–236 and accompanying text (explaining why strength of conviction needed to inspire uncivil obedience is likely to be weaker on average than what is needed for civil disobedience).
  • 94
    • 84930254443 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • For acts taken by groups, most of the individuals involved, or at least their leaders, must be properly motivated. Those members of the group who lack conscientiousness (or reformist intent) may not themselves be uncivil obedients, even if their collaborators and the act itself so qualify. Note
  • 95
    • 84930254444 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • We assume that most work-to-rule actions, like other labor protests, will involve a complicated and evolving mix of narrowly instrumental and broadly political motivations. As long as the latter set of motivations exerts substantial influence, we think it appropriate to characterize such actions as conscientious. Note
  • 96
    • 84930254445 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note, Note
    • As this discussion reflects, uncivil obedience by private citizens may require coordination on a significant scale—not just to be efective but even to be intelligible. One civil disobedient may be able to prick the conscience of the community by lying down in the middle of a busy street. One would-be uncivil obedient achieves nothing by driving at the speed limit. Note
  • 97
    • 84930254446 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • We say “generally” because, as with civil disobedience, certain forms of reasonably prompt ex post publicity may sufce where contemporaneous publicity would be exceedingly costly or self-defeating. Supra note 21 and accompanying text. Note
  • 98
    • 84930254447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Social meaning refers to “the attitudes and commitments that are communicated by words or actions” in context, which may not correspond to “the words that are actually being used.” Cass R. Sunstein, Social Norms and Big Government, 15 Quinnipiac L. Rev. 147, 154 (1995). Note
  • 99
    • 84930254448 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Reformist intent will often follow from conscientiousness, but not always, as when the actor has not formulated any prescriptive agenda or when the change she seeks is limited to her own case. More broadly, many controversial uses of law will fail to satisfy one or more of the elements above. For instance, tax gamesmanship and “strategic lawsuits against public participation” (lawsuits brought to silence critics by burdening them with the cost of a legal defense) will generally not be uncivil obedience because they are not conscientiously pursued for the reform of law or policy. But cf. infra notes 66–67 and accompanying text (discussing unusual case of tax gamesmanship that met these criteria). Note
  • 100
    • 84930254449 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • infra Part II.B.3
    • infra Part II.B.3
  • 101
    • 84930254450 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra notes 8–11 and accompanying text (describing direct–indirect distinction in civil disobedience literature).
    • supra notes 8–11 and accompanying text (describing direct–indirect distinction in civil disobedience literature).
  • 102
    • 84930254451 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Meyer, supra note 1 (“Their protest is aimed at getting Congress to repeal the federal speed limit law imposed during the Arab oil embargo in 1974 and to return such authority to the states.”)
    • Meyer, supra note 1 (“Their protest is aimed at getting Congress to repeal the federal speed limit law imposed during the Arab oil embargo in 1974 and to return such authority to the states.”)
  • 103
    • 84930254452 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Marks v. Mobil Oil Corp., 562 F. Supp. 759, 771–72 (E.D. Pa. 1983) (summarizing legislative history behind 1974 measure). Congress did in fact repeal the national speed limit two years later, in 1995, following a decline in the price of crude oil. National Highway System Designation Act of 1995, Pub. L. No. 104-59, § 205(d), 109 Stat. 568, 577.
    • Marks v. Mobil Oil Corp., 562 F. Supp. 759, 771–72 (E.D. Pa. 1983) (summarizing legislative history behind 1974 measure). Congress did in fact repeal the national speed limit two years later, in 1995, following a decline in the price of crude oil. National Highway System Designation Act of 1995, Pub. L. No. 104-59, § 205(d), 109 Stat. 568, 577.
  • 104
    • 84930254453 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the canonical exposition of the distinction between law in action (or the “real rules”) and law in books (or the “paper rules”)
    • For the canonical exposition of the distinction between law in action (or the “real rules”) and law in books (or the “paper rules”)
  • 105
    • 0002346629 scopus 로고
    • Law in Books and Law in Action
    • 44
    • Roscoe Pound, Law in Books and Law in Action, 44 Am. L. Rev. 12 (1910)
    • (1910) Am. L. Rev , pp. 12
    • Pound, R.1
  • 106
    • 84875531427 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legal Realism Untamed,
    • 91, nn.5–6, collecting other classic Legal Realist treatments of this distinction
    • Frederick Schauer, Legal Realism Untamed, 91 Tex. L. Rev. 749, 750–51 nn.5–6 (2013) (collecting other classic Legal Realist treatments of this distinction).
    • (2013) Tex. L. Rev , vol.749 , pp. 750-751
    • Schauer, F.1
  • 107
    • 84930254454 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Meyer, supra note 1 (quoting protester Al Allen).
    • Meyer, supra note 1 (quoting protester Al Allen).
  • 108
    • 84930254455 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Piven & Cloward, Weight of the Poor, supra note 34.
    • Piven & Cloward, Weight of the Poor, supra note 34.
  • 109
    • 84930254456 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Piven & Cloward, Weight of the Poor, supra note 34., Note
    • Accordingly, it is not uncivil obedience—although it may be civil disobedience— if a person violates local law X on the view that X is invalid because incompatible with a provision of “higher” positive law. Note
  • 110
    • 84930254457 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • In defining legality to require conformity with such privately as well as publicly generated obligations, we align ourselves with those who define civil disobedience in similarly expansive terms. Supra note 10. Note
  • 111
    • 84930254458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra notes 12–14 and accompanying text (noting this feature of civil disobedience).
    • supra notes 12–14 and accompanying text (noting this feature of civil disobedience).
  • 112
    • 84930254459 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Evasive behavior may not qualify as uncivil obedience for additional reasons, such as a lack of communicativeness or reformist intent.
    • Evasive behavior may not qualify as uncivil obedience for additional reasons, such as a lack of communicativeness or reformist intent.
  • 113
    • 84930254460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • infra Part III.C (considering informal regulation of uncivil obedience).
    • infra Part III.C (considering informal regulation of uncivil obedience).
  • 114
    • 34147099470 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Mark A. Edwards, Law and the Parameters of Acceptable Deviance, 97 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 49, 58 (2006) (“[T]he unacceptably compliant driver might find himself subject to sanctions such as tailgating, horn-blowing, headlight-flashing, and obscene gestures....”) Note
  • 115
    • 84930254462 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note, Note
    • Meyer, supra note 1 (describing angry responses by other drivers to National Motorists Association protest). As Mark Edwards observes more generally, while “[f]ormal institutions of enforcement are not well-equipped to punish normatively unacceptable legal behavior, because the acknowledged justification for their intervention—violation of formal law—is unavailable,” Edwards, supra, at 77, “[i]nformal social sanctions might be expected against behaviors that are formally compliant but normatively unacceptable,” Note
  • 116
    • 84930254463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Although beyond the scope of this study, it would be possible to extend the idea of uncivil obedience to wholly nonlegal, unwritten norms, as in exaggerated compliance with a rule of etiquette. Cf. infra notes 247–249 and accompanying text (discussing James Scott’s related concept of “critiques within the hegemony”). Note
  • 117
    • 84930254464 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note Note, Note
    • Legalism Definition, Webster’s Third New International Dictionary of English Language 1290 (3d ed. unabr. 1993) (defining “legalism” as “excessive reliance on legal principles and practices esp[ecially] as interpreted literally”). Most socially provocative behaviors that are lawful—from speaking in a loud voice to making outrageous claims to dressing like a chicken—are not provocative in the way they relate to law. Although inherently fuzzy at the margins, the distinction we are drawing between legally provocative behavior and otherwise provocative behavior is no more (or less) problematic than the well-established related distinction between legalistic behavior and otherwise lawful behavior. Note
  • 118
    • 84930254465 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Uncivil Definition, id. at 2485 (defining “uncivil” as, inter alia, “lacking in courtesy” or “not conducive to civic harmony and welfare”).
    • Cf. Uncivil Definition, id. at 2485 (defining “uncivil” as, inter alia, “lacking in courtesy” or “not conducive to civic harmony and welfare”).
  • 119
    • 84930254466 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Although we believe the “uncivil obedience” label to be the most felicitous for the way it highlights the ironic character of these practices and the comparison with civil disobedience, cf. supra note 3 (explaining sense in which we use “obedience”), we do not mean for the label itself to do any critical work. Acts of incivility may be fully justified under certain circumstances. In what one assumes was an efort to isolate the positive connotations of “civil disobedience,” the speed-limit protesters discussed in the main text dubbed their action National Civil Obedience Day. Meyer, supra note 1. Note
  • 120
    • 84930254467 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brownlee, Civil Disobedience, supra note 6 (describing civil disobedience as “invariably illegal,” without further explication). The civil disobedient, it is assumed, wants to be seen as violating an applicable positive law. While questions may arise as to whether her violation was justified by higher-law principles, there is typically no dispute as to whether a prima facie breach occurred.
    • Brownlee, Civil Disobedience, supra note 6 (describing civil disobedience as “invariably illegal,” without further explication). The civil disobedient, it is assumed, wants to be seen as violating an applicable positive law. While questions may arise as to whether her violation was justified by higher-law principles, there is typically no dispute as to whether a prima facie breach occurred.
  • 121
    • 84930254468 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • This “area” may be a physical domain, as in the case of a specific freeway or workplace, or it may be a regulatory domain, as in the case of a specific tax code or public benefits system. In either case, the uncivil obedient must defy practices or expectations that are widely followed or held among the community of persons bound by the law of the area. We mean for this formulation to be a bit loose. Just how widely followed or held a practice or expectation must be, and just how to mark the boundaries of a relevant area or community, are not in our view matters that can be specified ex ante with precision. Note
  • 122
    • 84930254469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Cf. Edwards, supra note 56, at 57 (observing existence of behaviors that are formally illegal but within socially constructed “parameters of acceptable deviance,” as well as behaviors that are formally legal but outside of these parameters). Note
  • 123
    • 84930254470 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • (explaining that in addition to “well-recognized gap between law-on-the-books, or formal law, and law-as-enforced,” there “is a parallel gap between law-on-the-books and law-as-behaved”) Note
  • 124
    • 84930254471 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 48 and accompanying text (noting distinction between “real” and “paper” rules).
    • supra note 48 and accompanying text (noting distinction between “real” and “paper” rules).
  • 125
    • 84930254472 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Jeremy Brecher, Strike! 251 (revised ed. 2014) (explaining work slowdowns and work-to-rule actions were common labor tactics in 1930s and were variously called “the conscious withdrawal of efficiency,” “striking on the job,” or “sabotage”). Note
  • 126
    • 69249183263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the constitutional context, Mark Tu shnet defines workarounds as situations where, “[f]inding some constitutional text obstructing our ability to reach a desired goal, we work around that text using other texts—and do so without (obviously) distorting the tools we use.” Mark Tu shnet, Constitutional Wo rkarounds, 87 Te x. L. Rev. 1499, 1503 (2009).
    • In the constitutional context, Mark Tu shnet defines workarounds as situations where, “[f]inding some constitutional text obstructing our ability to reach a desired goal, we work around that text using other texts—and do so without (obviously) distorting the tools we use.” Mark Tu shnet, Constitutional Wo rkarounds, 87 Te x. L. Rev. 1499, 1503 (2009).
  • 127
    • 0004798258 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • discussing Boyters’ protest and responses it elicited
    • Michael J. Graetz, The Decline (and Fall?) of the Income Ta x 35–39 (1997) (discussing Boyters’ protest and responses it elicited)
    • (1997) The Decline (And Fall?) of the Income Ta X , pp. 35-39
    • Graetz, M.J.1
  • 128
    • 84930254474 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jill Elaine Hasday, Family Law Reimagined 54 (2014) (same).
    • Jill Elaine Hasday, Family Law Reimagined 54 (2014) (same).
  • 129
    • 84930254475 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Recognizing that federal election law permitted him to express his wishes for the Super PAC as long as he communicated them publicly rather than privately, Colbert came prepared with a cardboard television set and broadcast his wishes from inside the set, all while sitting at Stewart’s desk. Katla McGlynn, Jon Stewart, Stephen Colbert Expose More Super PAC Loopholes Without “Coordinating,” Hufngton Post (Jan. 18, 2012, 9:01 AM),  , on file with the Columbia Law Review) (last updated Feb. , 23, 2012, 7:44 AM
    • Recognizing that federal election law permitted him to express his wishes for the Super PAC as long as he communicated them publicly rather than privately, Colbert came prepared with a cardboard television set and broadcast his wishes from inside the set, all while sitting at Stewart’s desk. Katla McGlynn, Jon Stewart, Stephen Colbert Expose More Super PAC Loopholes Without “Coordinating,” Hufngton Post (Jan. 18, 2012, 9:01 AM),  http://www.hufngtonpost.com/2012/01/18/jon-stewart-stephen-colbert-expose-super-pac-loopholes_n_1212670.html (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (last updated Feb. 23, 2012, 7:44 AM).
  • 130
    • 84930254476 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To hammer home the point, Colbert’s Super PAC, originally named “Americans for a Better Tomorrow, Tomorrow,” was unofcially renamed “The Definitely Not Coordinating with Stephen Colbert Super PAC” after Colbert put Stewart in charge. Under New Management!, Colbert Super PAC, on file with the Columbia Law Review) (last visited Mar. 16, 2015).
    • To hammer home the point, Colbert’s Super PAC, originally named “Americans for a Better Tomorrow, Tomorrow,” was unofcially renamed “The Definitely Not Coordinating with Stephen Colbert Super PAC” after Colbert put Stewart in charge. Under New Management!, Colbert Super PAC, http://www.colbertsuperpac.com/archive/ 011212a.html (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (last visited Mar. 16, 2015).
  • 131
    • 84930254477 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jan. 10, on file with the , Columbia Law Review). Although some might prefer to limit the concept of uncivil obedience to protests against government laws or policies, on our account at least some private codes of conduct may be targeted as well. Supra notes 51–52 and accompanying text.
    • Jane O’Grady, Elizabeth Anscombe, Guardian (Jan. 10, 2001), http://www.theguardian.com/news/2001/jan/11/guardianobituaries.highereducation (on file with the Columbia Law Review). Although some might prefer to limit the concept of uncivil obedience to protests against government laws or policies, on our account at least some private codes of conduct may be targeted as well. Supra notes 51–52 and accompanying text.
    • (2001) Elizabeth Anscombe, Guardian
    • O’Grady, J.1
  • 132
    • 84930254478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • May 19, 3:10 PM), (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (“[F]ed up Staten , Islanders disrupted trafic at the Ve rrazano Bridge toll booths for about 20 minutes yesterday by slowly paying the $10 toll in pennies to protest an imminent increase.”)
    • John Del Signore, Drivers Protest Verrazano Bridge Toll with Pennies, Gothamist (May 19, 2009, 3:10 PM), http://gothamist.com/2009/05/19/drivers_protest_verrazano_bridge_to.php (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (“[F]ed up Staten Islanders disrupted trafic at the Ve rrazano Bridge toll booths for about 20 minutes yesterday by slowly paying the $10 toll in pennies to protest an imminent increase.”)
    • (2009) Drivers Protest Verrazano Bridge Toll with Pennies,
    • Del Signore, J.1
  • 133
    • 84930254479 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Jim Shea, It’s Time to Eliminate the Dreadful Penny, Hartford Courant, Mar. 5, 2014, at D1 (“As for the penny being an instrument of protest, let’s face it, the paying of taxes or fines in pennies lacks originality to the point of now being lame.”). Note
  • 134
    • 84930254480 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Depending on the jurisdiction and on the manner in which these behaviors are executed, some variants may run afoul of separate legal prohibitions, such as a specific cap on the number of pennies that may be used in any given transaction or a general ban on disorderly conduct, and therefore would not qualify as uncivil obedience. infra Part III.A (explicating this point). Note
  • 135
    • 84930254481 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra notes 34–35 and accompanying text (summarizing Cloward–Piven plan). We will soon turn to a prominent set of contemporary examples, involving use of the quorum call, hold, and other procedural privileges by minority-party senators.
    • supra notes 34–35 and accompanying text (summarizing Cloward–Piven plan). We will soon turn to a prominent set of contemporary examples, involving use of the quorum call, hold, and other procedural privileges by minority-party senators.
  • 136
    • 84930254482 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • infra notes 96–102 and accompanying text.
    • infra notes 96–102 and accompanying text.
  • 137
    • 84930254483 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is the case across as well as within jurisdictions. For an example of administrative flooding from the United Kingdom
    • This is the case across as well as within jurisdictions. For an example of administrative flooding from the United Kingdom
  • 138
    • 84930250714 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oct. 11, 2006, 8:10 PM, (on file with the Columbia Law Review) , (describing wave of “mass lone protests,” as well as author’s own serial protests, in response to U.K. law requiring permit for all demonstrations near Houses of Parliament).
    • Mark Thomas, So Many Causes, So Little Time, Guardian (Oct. 11, 2006, 8:10 PM), http://www.theguardian.com/politics/2006/oct/12/houseofcommons.comment (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (describing wave of “mass lone protests,” as well as author’s own serial protests, in response to U.K. law requiring permit for all demonstrations near Houses of Parliament).
    • So Many Causes, So
    • Thomas, M.1
  • 139
    • 84930247658 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mar. 10, 2012), on file with the Columbia Law Review
    • Michelle Alexander, Op-Ed, Go to Trial: Crash the Justice System, N.Y. Times (Mar. 10, 2012), http://www.nytimes.com/2012/03/11/opinion/sunday/go-to-trial-crash-the-justice-system.html?_r=0 (on file with the Columbia Law Review).
    • Op-Ed, Go to Trial: Crash the Justice System, N.Y. Times
    • Alexander, M.1
  • 140
    • 84900989072 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Crashing the Misdemeanor System
    • exploring possible refinements to and extensions of Alexander’s proposal, focused on minor misdemeanors
    • Jenny Roberts, Crashing the Misdemeanor System, 70 Wash. & Lee L. Rev. 1089 (2013) (exploring possible refinements to and extensions of Alexander’s proposal, focused on minor misdemeanors).
    • (2013) Wash. & Lee L. Rev , vol.70 , pp. 1089
    • Roberts, J.1
  • 141
    • 84930254484 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oren Bar-Gill & Omri Ben-Shahar, The Prisoners’ (Plea Bargain) Dilemma, 1 J. Legal Analysis 737 (2009) (discussing collective-action problems faced by defendants).
    • Oren Bar-Gill & Omri Ben-Shahar, The Prisoners’ (Plea Bargain) Dilemma, 1 J. Legal Analysis 737 (2009) (discussing collective-action problems faced by defendants).
  • 142
    • 84930254485 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Henry T. Lummus, The Trial Judge 46 (1937) (“If all... defendants should combine to refuse to plead guilty, and should dare to hold out, they could break down the administration of justice in any state in the Union.”).
    • Henry T. Lummus, The Trial Judge 46 (1937) (“If all... defendants should combine to refuse to plead guilty, and should dare to hold out, they could break down the administration of justice in any state in the Union.”).
  • 143
    • 84930251085 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Defense Attorney’s Role in Plea Bargaining
    • 84, describing general strikes as “most spectacular form of bargaining , leverage that a public defender office can exert”)
    • Albert W. Alschuler, The Defense Attorney’s Role in Plea Bargaining, 84 Yale L.J. 1179, 1249 (1975) (describing general strikes as “most spectacular form of bargaining leverage that a public defender office can exert”).
    • Yale , vol.1179 , pp. 1249
    • Alschuler, A.W.1
  • 144
    • 84930254486 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Edwards, supra note 56, at 80 n.137 (“Either full enforcement or compliance would likely bring any functioning society to a crashing halt.”).
    • Cf. Edwards, supra note 56, at 80 n.137 (“Either full enforcement or compliance would likely bring any functioning society to a crashing halt.”).
  • 145
    • 67649624944 scopus 로고
    • July 17,, on file , with the Columbia Law Review)
    • Mr. Roosevelt Answers, N.Y. Times (July 17, 1895), http://query.nytimes.com/mem/archive-free/pdf?res=9C04E2DA103DE433A25754C1A9619C94649ED7CF (on file with the Columbia Law Review).
    • (1895) N.Y. Times
    • Answers, M.R.1
  • 146
    • 84930254487 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Doris Kearns Goodwin, The Bully Pulpit 209–10 (2013) (discussing Roosevelt’s strict enforcement policy). As a journalist observed at the time: [Roosevelt’s] reasoning had all the simplicity of originality. He was appointed to enforce the laws as they appeared on the statute books. He enforced them. That was originality; it rarely had been done before.... When prominent citizens and influential newspapers protested, he answered: “I am placed here to enforce the law as I find it. I shall enforce it. If you don’t like the law, repeal it.” Note
  • 147
  • 148
    • 84930254489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mar. 4, 1869), on file with the Columbia Law Review). More , recently, critics charged that the Administrator of President Reagan’s Environmental Protection Agency was interpreting the Clean Air Act in a “deliberately rigid fashion” so as to “prod Congress into reworking” the Act.
    • Ulysses S. Grant, First Inaugural Address (Mar. 4, 1869), available at http://avalon.law.yale.edu/19th_century/grant1.asp (on file with the Columbia Law Review). More recently, critics charged that the Administrator of President Reagan’s Environmental Protection Agency was interpreting the Clean Air Act in a “deliberately rigid fashion” so as to “prod Congress into reworking” the Act.
    • First Inaugural Address
    • Grant, U.S.1
  • 149
    • 84930254490 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Philip Shabecof, Mrs. Gorsuch as a Crusading Tiger? Critics Wonder Why, N.Y. Times (Dec. 26, 1982), on file with the , Columbia Law Review
    • Philip Shabecof, Mrs. Gorsuch as a Crusading Tiger? Critics Wonder Why, N.Y. Times (Dec. 26, 1982), http://www.nytimes.com/1982/12/26/weekinreview/mrs-gorsuch-as-a-crusading-tiger-critics-wonder-why. html (on file with the Columbia Law Review)
  • 150
    • 84930254491 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (“Mrs. Gorsuch said the imposition of sanctions would be ‘an unhealthy, regressive step.... But I always said I will fulfill my oath of office....’”).
    • (“Mrs. Gorsuch said the imposition of sanctions would be ‘an unhealthy, regressive step.... But I always said I will fulfill my oath of office....’”).
  • 151
    • 84930254492 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U.S. Const. art. II, § 3.
    • U.S. Const. art. II, § 3.
  • 152
    • 84930254493 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Presidential Authority to Decline to Execute Unconstitutional Statutes, 18 Op. O.L.C. 199 (1994) (defending this general proposition and suggesting factors that ought to bear on nonenforcement decisions).
    • Presidential Authority to Decline to Execute Unconstitutional Statutes, 18 Op. O.L.C. 199 (1994) (defending this general proposition and suggesting factors that ought to bear on nonenforcement decisions).
  • 153
    • 84930254494 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Andrew J. Parmenter, Note, Nullifying the Jury: “The Judicial Oligarchy” Declares War on Jury Nullification, 46 Washburn L.J. 379, 402–10 (2007) (cataloging eforts by U.S. judges to prevent and delegitimize jury nullification). Jury nullification occurs when a jury acquits a defendant it believes to be guilty “either because the jury wants to send a message about some social issue that is larger than the case itself or because the result dictated by law is contrary to the jury’s sense of justice, morality, or fairness.” Black’s Law Dictionary 989 (10th ed. 2014). In cases where the jurors’ reasoning, including their possible dissatisfaction with the law, remains opaque to the outside world, nullification would further fail the communicativeness requirement of uncivil obedience. Note
  • 154
    • 84930254495 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Parmenter, supra note 87, at 391 (listing Georgia, Indiana, and Maryland as having such constitutional provisions).
    • Parmenter, supra note 87, at 391 (listing Georgia, Indiana, and Maryland as having such constitutional provisions).
  • 155
    • 70349609478 scopus 로고
    • Racially Based Jury Nullification: Black Power in the Criminal
    • 105, proposing jury nullification as means to sub, vert racial oppression in criminal justice system and stimulate “implementation of certain noncriminal ways of addressing antisocial conduct
    • Paul Butler, Racially Based Jury Nullification: Black Power in the Criminal Justice System, 105 Yale L.J. 677, 680 (1995) (proposing jury nullification as means to subvert racial oppression in criminal justice system and stimulate “implementation of certain noncriminal ways of addressing antisocial conduct”).
    • (1995) Yale L.J , vol.677 , pp. 680
    • Butler, P.1
  • 156
    • 84878347297 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 113, 267, explaining, under “big waiver,” executive agencies claim statutory authority to decide whether policies adopted by Congress should be dispensed , with or replaced
    • David J. Barron & Todd D. Rakof, In Defense of Big Waiver, 113 Colum. L. Rev. 265, 267 (2013) (explaining, under “big waiver,” executive agencies claim statutory authority to decide whether policies adopted by Congress should be dispensed with or replaced).
    • (2013) In Defense of Big Waiver , pp. 265
    • Barron, D.J.1    Rakof, T.D.2
  • 157
    • 84930254496 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • No Child Left Behind Act of 2001, Pub. L. No. 107-110, § 9401(a), 115 Stat. 1425, 1972 (2002) (codified at 20 U.S.C. § 7861(a) (2012)).
    • No Child Left Behind Act of 2001, Pub. L. No. 107-110, § 9401(a), 115 Stat. 1425, 1972 (2002) (codified at 20 U.S.C. § 7861(a) (2012)).
  • 158
    • 84930254497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U.S. Dep’t of Educ., ESEA Flexibility,, on file with the Columbia Law Review) (last modified Feb. , 25, 2015) (indicating forty-three states have been granted waivers).
    • U.S. Dep’t of Educ., ESEA Flexibility, http://www2.ed.gov/policy/elsec/guid/esea-flexibility/index.html (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (last modified Feb. 25, 2015) (indicating forty-three states have been granted waivers).
  • 159
    • 84930254498 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Barron & Rakof, supra note 90, at 268. In the White House’s own words, because No Child Left Behind was “stand[ing] in the way” of state progress and Congress would not amend the law, the “Administration moved forward to ofer states flexibility within the law—as authorized by provisions in the law itself.” White House, Reforming No Child Left Behind, on file with the Columbia Law Review) (last visited Mar. 5, 2015). As a presidential , candidate, Mitt Romney pledged that he would dismantle the Afordable Care Act,lawfully, in a similar manner, although critics pointed out that only certain provisions ofthe Act were subject to waiver.
    • Barron & Rakof, supra note 90, at 268. In the White House’s own words, because No Child Left Behind was “stand[ing] in the way” of state progress and Congress would not amend the law, the “Administration moved forward to ofer states flexibility within the law—as authorized by provisions in the law itself.” White House, Reforming No Child Left Behind, http://www.whitehouse.gov/issues/education/k-12/reforming-no-child-left-behind (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (last visited Mar. 5, 2015). As a presidential candidate, Mitt Romney pledged that he would dismantle the Afordable Care Act, lawfully, in a similar manner, although critics pointed out that only certain provisions of the Act were subject to waiver.
  • 160
    • 84930254499 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oct. 30, 2012, 4:00 AM),, on file with the Columbia Law Review) (quoting , Romney as saying, “On day one of my administration, I’ll direct the secretary of Health and Human Services to grant a waiver from Obamacare to all 50 states
    • Julie Rovner, Can Mitt Romney Really Repeal Obamacare?, NPR (Oct. 30, 2012, 4:00 AM), http://www.npr.org/2012/10/30/163929221/can-romney-really-repeal-obamacare (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (quoting Romney as saying, “On day one of my administration, I’ll direct the secretary of Health and Human Services to grant a waiver from Obamacare to all 50 states”).
    • Can Mitt Romney Really Repeal
    • Rovner, J.1
  • 161
    • 84867723788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Victoria F. Nourse, A Decision Theory of Statutory Interpretation: Legislative History by the Rules, 122 Yale L.J. 70, 90 (2012) (explaining, in United States today, even self-identified purposivist interpreters always “begin with text”)
    • Cf. Victoria F. Nourse, A Decision Theory of Statutory Interpretation: Legislative History by the Rules, 122 Yale L.J. 70, 90 (2012) (explaining, in United States today, even self-identified purposivist interpreters always “begin with text”)
  • 162
    • 84930254501 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Andrew Tu tt, Fifty Shades of Te xtualism, 29 J.L. & Pol. 309, 309 (2014) (“‘We are all Te xtualists now’ has become such a popular refrain [among American commentators] it borders on cliché.”).
    • Andrew Tu tt, Fifty Shades of Te xtualism, 29 J.L. & Pol. 309, 309 (2014) (“‘We are all Te xtualists now’ has become such a popular refrain [among American commentators] it borders on cliché.”).
  • 163
    • 84930254502 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The inverse has happened: In a 2013 case, for example, Judge John Gleeson cited his “fundamental policy disagreement” with certain “excessively severe” drug-ofense sentencing guidelines in exercising his legal authority to impose a lighter sentence. United States v. Diaz, No. 11-821, 2013 WL 322243, at *1 (E.D.N.Y. Jan. 28, 2013). Bracing as Judge Gleeson’s arguments are, there is nothing particularly provocative as a legal matter about a judge’s utilization of an authority, clearly recognized in Supreme Court doctrine, to downward-depart from the guidelines based on policy disagreement. Note
  • 164
    • 84930254503 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dec. 18, 2009, 1:43 PM), on file with the Columbia Law Review) (noting, “senators usually waive” their right to have such bills read aloud on floor
    • Ricardo Alonso-Zaldivar, Republicans Threaten Health Care Read-a-Thon, Newsday (Dec. 18, 2009, 1:43 PM), http://www.newsday.com/business/republicans-threaten-health-care-read-a-thon-1.1660956 (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (noting “senators usually waive” their right to have such bills read aloud on floor).
    • Republicans Threaten Health Care Read-A-Thon,
    • Alonso-Zaldivar, R.1
  • 165
    • 84930254504 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Niels Lesniewski, Reid, Obama Call for Senate Rule Changes to Curb Filibusters, CQ To day (Oct. 28, 2010, 4:39 PM, on file with the Columbia Law Review
    • Niels Lesniewski, Reid, Obama Call for Senate Rule Changes to Curb Filibusters, CQ To day (Oct. 28, 2010, 4:39 PM), http://www.cq.com/doc/news-3756760?7&print=true (on file with the Columbia Law Review).
  • 167
    • 84930254506 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    •  (observing holds “are a more prominent feature of today’s Senate” and quoting one senator as lamenting that holds “have come into a form of reverence which was never to be”). The hold is an informal device through which individual senators or groups of senators, whose identities may be withheld from the public, inform party leaders that they do not want a particular measure to be taken up on the floor. Id. at 256. Note
  • 168
    • 84930254507 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oct. 5, 2013, on file with the Columbia Law , Review) (reviewing this campaign).
    • Sheryl Gay Stolberg & Mike McIntire, A Federal Budget Crisis Months in the Planning, N.Y. Times (Oct. 5, 2013), http://www. nytimes.com/2013/10/06/us/a-federal-budget-crisis-months-in-the-planning.html?pagewanted=all (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (reviewing this campaign).
    • A Federal Budget Crisis Months in The
    • Stolberg, S.G.1    McIntire, M.2
  • 169
    • 84908317454 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • David E. Pozen, Self-Help and the Separation of Powers, 124 Yale L.J. 2, 39– 46 (2014) [hereinafter Pozen, Self-Help] (discussing these tactics and pressure they have placed on separation-of-powers conventions). Conceivably, a President could retaliate against Congress through obstructionist uncivil obedience of her own, as by vetoing every bill that crosses her desk until Congress changes some preexisting law or policy. Note
  • 170
    • 84930254509 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • supra notes 8–11 and accompanying text (explaining civil disobedience is widely understood to include direct and indirect variants); supra notes 45–46 and accompanying text (extending this distinction to uncivil obedience). In late 2013, minority-party senators’ continual use of the filibuster precipitated filibuster reform, unintentionally generating the sort of change that direct uncivil obedience seeks. Note
  • 171
    • 84930254510 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nov. 21, 2013, on file with the Columbia Law Review) (explaining Senate Democrats voted , to end use of filibuster for executive branch nominees and non-Supreme-Court judicial branch nominees
    • Jeremy W. Peters, In Landmark Vote, Senate Limits Use of the Filibuster, N.Y. Times (Nov. 21, 2013), http://www.nytimes.com/2013/11/22/us/politics/reid-sets-in-motion-steps-to-limit-use-of-filibuster. html (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (explaining Senate Democrats voted to end use of filibuster for executive branch nominees and non-Supreme-Court judicial branch nominees).
    • In
    • Peters, J.W.1
  • 172
    • 84930254511 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • May 2, 2006, 4:00 AM, on file with the Columbia Law Review) (describing this protest as “nation’s largest coordinated demonstration since the war in Vietnam
    • Michael Cabanatuan et al., A Million Say: Let Us All Stay/Historic Day: Across the Nation, a Rallying Call for Immigrants, S.F. Gate (May 2, 2006, 4:00 AM), http://www.sfgate.com/news/article/a-million-say-let-us-all-stay-historic-day-2519475.php (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (describing this protest as “nation’s largest coordinated demonstration since the war in Vietnam”).
    • A Million Say: Let Us All Stay/Historic Day: Across the Nation, a Rallying Call for Immigrants, S.F. Gate
    • Cabanatuan, M.1
  • 173
    • 84909118367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • May 1, 2006, (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (discussing protest’s economic impacts).
    • Anita Hamilton, A Day Without Immigrants: Making a Statement, Time (May 1, 2006), http://content.time.com/time/nation/article/0,8599,1189899,00.html (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (discussing protest’s economic impacts).
    • A Day without Immigrants: Making a Statement,
    • Hamilton, A.1
  • 174
    • 84930254513 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • This performance of law-following, however, was itself an admission of systematic law-breaking. Undocumented workers were not truly complying with laws prohibiting their employment, or they would not have held jobs in the first place. It is necessary to isolate the one-day protest as the relevant time period, then, to appreciate its character as direct uncivil obedience. Note
  • 175
    • 84930254514 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • supra note 11 and accompanying text (noting potential blurriness of this distinction in civil disobedience context). We speculate that extreme indirectness is more likely to occur with civil disobedience than with uncivil obedience. The idea that law-breaking can be an expressive, reformist tactic is fairly well understood. The idea of law-following as such a tactic is less familiar. For those who seek to protest a certain law or policy by assiduously adhering to a distant law or policy, there is an added risk that the novelty of their approach will distract from, rather than amplify, their critical message. Lying down in the middle of traffic (unlawfully) and driving fifty-five miles per hour on the freeway (lawfully) are both extremely indirect means to protest a war. Only the latter tactic, however, seems not just attenuated but incoherent, implausible. Note
  • 176
    • 84930254515 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra notes 74–79 and accompanying text (discussing these proposals).
    • supra notes 74–79 and accompanying text (discussing these proposals).
  • 177
    • 84930254516 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brownlee, Civil Disobedience, supra note 6.
    • Brownlee, Civil Disobedience, supra note 6.
  • 178
    • 84860992860 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • David Fontana & Donald Braman, Judicial Backlash or Just Backlash? Evidence from a National Experiment, 112 Colum. L. Rev. 731, 747 n.53 (2012) (“The hierarchical-individualist worldview tends to be associated with the Republican Party and with those self-identifying as ‘conservative’ Note
  • 179
    • 77950333010 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The egalitarian-communitarian worldview with the Democratic Party and with those self-identifying as ‘liberal.’” (citing Dan M. Kahan, Culture, Cognition, and Consent: Who Perceives What, and Why, in Acquaintance-Rape Cases, 158 U. Pa. L. Rev. 729, 784–85 & fig.7 (2010))). Note
  • 180
    • 84930254519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Comprehensive uncivil obedience of this sort can be contrasted with the phenomenon that Bernard Harcourt calls “political disobedience.” Harcourt, supra note 30, at 47. Responding to the Occupy Wall Street movement, Harcourt recently proposed this term to capture a species of disobedience that resists not just a condemned law or policy but “the very way in which we are governed.” Id. Political disobedience rejects “the structure of partisan politics, the demand for policy reforms, the call for party identification.... It turns its back on the political institutions and actors who govern us.”Note
  • 181
    • 84930254520 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • We find it difficult to envision uncivil obedience operating on such a model, if for no other reason than its painstaking concern for legal detail. Uncivil obedience’s strategic adherence to and reliance on the formal legal system implies that its rejection of existing political structures will never be quite so profound or so radical. Political disobedience “refuses to play the game.” Id. at 59. Uncivil obedience, even on a comprehensive scale, plays it with extreme dexterity. Note
  • 182
    • 84930254521 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The horizontal separation of powers across the branches of the federal government is much less fecund in this regard. Although it is possible to imagine Congress responding to a disagreeable Supreme Court ruling by passing new legislation that technically comports with the terms of the ruling but is widely understood as an efort to subvert its substance, actual cases of such legislative uncivil obedience appear to be rare at best. Note
  • 184
    • 84889631706 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Partisan Federalism
    • Jessica Bulman-Pozen, Partisan Federalism, 127 Harv. L. Rev. 1077 (2014)
    • (2014) Harv. L. Rev , vol.127 , pp. 1077
    • Bulman-Pozen, J.1
  • 185
    • 79851503317 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Supreme Court, 2009 Term—Foreword: Federalism All the Way Down
    • Heather K. Gerken, The Supreme Court, 2009 Term—Foreword: Federalism All the Way Down, 124 Harv. L. Rev. 4 (2010)
    • (2010) Harv. L. Rev , vol.124 , pp. 4
    • Gerken, H.K.1
  • 186
    • 34247498788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Against Preemption:
    • Roderick M. Hills, Against Preemption: How Federalism Can Improve the National Legislative Process, 82 N.Y. U. L. Rev. 1 (2007)
    • (2007) N.Y. U. L. Rev , vol.82 , pp. 1
    • Hills, R.M.1
  • 187
    • 38849153183 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Significance of the Local in Immigration Regulation
    • Cristina M. Rodríguez, The Significance of the Local in Immigration Regulation, 106 Mich. L. Rev. 567 (2008).
    • (2008) Mich. L. Rev , vol.106 , pp. 567
    • Rodríguez, C.M.1
  • 188
    • 84898618414 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • From Sovereignty and Process to
    • 1920
    • Jessica Bulman-Pozen, From Sovereignty and Process to Administration and Politics: The Afterlife of American Federalism, 123 Yale L.J. 1920 (2014).
    • (2014) Yale L.J , vol.123
    • Bulman-Pozen, J.1
  • 189
    • 70349257377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Uncooperative Federalism
    • 1278–80, arguing certain state responses to USA PATRIOT Act were , “akin to civil disobedience”
    • Jessica Bulman-Pozen & Heather K. Gerken, Uncooperative Federalism, 118 Yale L.J. 1256, 1278–80 (2009) (arguing certain state responses to USA PATRIOT Act were “akin to civil disobedience”).
    • (2009) Yale L.J , vol.118 , pp. 1256
    • Bulman-Pozen, J.1    Gerken, H.K.2
  • 190
    • 84930254523 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra notes 36–38 and accompanying text.
    • supra notes 36–38 and accompanying text.
  • 191
    • 84930254524 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oklahoma’s Abortion Battle Goes National,
    • Oct. 30, on file with the Columbia Law Review) (describing these five state laws as “part of , the larger cascade of abortion restrictions that have swept the country in the past three years
    • Amelia Thomson-DeVeaux, Oklahoma’s Abortion Battle Goes National, Am. Prospect (Oct. 30, 2013), http://prospect.org/article/oklahomas-abortion-battle-goes-national (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (describing these five state laws as “part of the larger cascade of abortion restrictions that have swept the country in the past three years”).
    • (2013) Am.
    • Thomson-Deveaux, A.1
  • 192
    • 84930254525 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Boonstra, supra note 37, at 18–21.
    • Boonstra, supra note 37, at 18–21.
  • 193
    • 84930254526 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    •  (“These restrictions are profered, although exclusively by abortion opponents, in the purported interest of protecting women’s health and safety. According to antiabortion activists, undergoing an abortion using a protocol other than that approved by the FDA... is a ‘prescription for disaster.’”).
    •  (“These restrictions are profered, although exclusively by abortion opponents, in the purported interest of protecting women’s health and safety. According to antiabortion activists, undergoing an abortion using a protocol other than that approved by the FDA... is a ‘prescription for disaster.’”).
  • 194
    • 84930254527 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brief for Petitioners at 14–15, Arizona v. United States, 132 S. Ct. 2492 (2012) (No. 11-182), 2012 WL 416748 (“Throughout the legislative process..., S.B. 1070 was revised to clarify and reinforce its express adoption of federal immigration standards, and the necessity that it be enforced in conformity with those standards.”).
    • Brief for Petitioners at 14–15, Arizona v. United States, 132 S. Ct. 2492 (2012) (No. 11-182), 2012 WL 416748 (“Throughout the legislative process..., S.B. 1070 was revised to clarify and reinforce its express adoption of federal immigration standards, and the necessity that it be enforced in conformity with those standards.”).
  • 195
    • 84930254528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arizona, 132 S. Ct. at 2497–98 (describing S.B. 1070).
    • Arizona, 132 S. Ct. at 2497–98 (describing S.B. 1070).
  • 196
    • 82855172557 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Federalism as a Safeguard of the Separation of Powers
    • 490–91, explaining Arizona’s contention “that the federal executive is betraying Congress by underenforcing the federal immigration laws
    • Jessica Bulman-Pozen, Federalism as a Safeguard of the Separation of Powers, 112 Colum. L. Rev. 459, 490–91 (2012) (explaining Arizona’s contention “that the federal executive is betraying Congress by underenforcing the federal immigration laws”).
    • (2012) Colum. L. Rev , vol.112 , pp. 459
    • Bulman-Pozen, J.1
  • 197
    • 84930254529 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This argument against preemption became known as the “mirror-image theory.”
    • This argument against preemption became known as the “mirror-image theory.”
  • 198
    • 84930254530 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Margaret Hu, Reverse-Commandeering, 46 U.C. Davis L. Rev. 535, 539 n.7 (2012). The theory’s basic claim, in the words of its architect, is that “[s]tate governments possess the authority to criminalize particular conduct concerning illegal immigration, provided that they do so in a way that mirrors the terms of federal law.” Kris W. Kobach, Reinforcing the Rule of Law: What States Can and Should Do to Reduce Illegal Immigration, 22 Geo. Immigr. L.J. 459, 475 (2008).
    • Margaret Hu, Reverse-Commandeering, 46 U.C. Davis L. Rev. 535, 539 n.7 (2012). The theory’s basic claim, in the words of its architect, is that “[s]tate governments possess the authority to criminalize particular conduct concerning illegal immigration, provided that they do so in a way that mirrors the terms of federal law.” Kris W. Kobach, Reinforcing the Rule of Law: What States Can and Should Do to Reduce Illegal Immigration, 22 Geo. Immigr. L.J. 459, 475 (2008).
  • 199
    • 84930254531 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • July 27, 2014) (unpublished manuscript, on file with the Columbia Law Review) , (cataloging tactics used to burden navigators
    • Katherine T. Vukadin, Obamacare Interrupted: Obstructive Federalism and the Consumer Information Blockade 26–29 (July 27, 2014) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=2472594 (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (cataloging tactics used to burden navigators)
    • Obamacare Interrupted: Obstructive Federalism And , pp. 26-29
    • Vukadin, K.T.1
  • 200
    • 84930254532 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Obamacare’s Hidden
    • Aug. 9, 5:00 AM, on , file with the Columbia Law Review) (“At least sixteen states have passed navigator laws since 2012....
    • Nicholas Kusnetz, Obamacare’s Hidden Battle: Insurance Agents Push State Regulation of Guides to New Marketplaces, Ctr. for Pub. Integrity (Aug. 9, 2013, 5:00 AM), http://www.publicintegrity.org/2013/08/09/13144/obamacares-hidden-battle-insurance-agents-push-state-regulation-guides-new (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (“At least sixteen states have passed navigator laws since 2012....”).
    • (2013) Ctr. For
    • Kusnetz, N.1
  • 201
    • 84930254533 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Kusnetz, supra note 123 (quoting numerous state sponsors who stress “[i]nsurance has long been the realm of the states” and who “maintain that these laws simply establish state oversight and ensure that consumers will be protected from unscrupulous or uninformed navigators”). Note
  • 202
    • 84930254534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • In a similar fashion, state legislatures have challenged women’s exercise of abortion rights by enacting TRAP (Targeted Regulation of Abortion Providers) laws that impose onerous licensing requirements on abortion facilities. States mandate specific physical dimensions for procedure rooms, hallways, and janitors’ closets; require hands-free sinks and complex ventilation systems; and impose design standards for parking lots and covered entrances. Note
  • 203
    • 84930254535 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Rachel Benson Gold & Elizabeth Nash, TRAP Laws Gain Political Traction While Abortion Clinics—and the Women They Serve—Pay the Price, Guttmacher Pol’y Rev., Spring 2013, at 7 (summarizing and criticizing this trend). These laws are justified by proponents as health and safety regulations of the sort the Supreme Court has upheld, Note
  • 204
    • 84930254536 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Mazurek v. Armstrong, 520 U.S. 968 (1997) (per curiam) (upholding state law requiring that abortions be performed by licensed physicians), even though the requirements imposed on abortion providers are significantly more exacting than those imposed on other medical facilities and the laws are widely understood to undermine and signal opposition to—without directly flouting—the constitutional right to abortion. Note
  • 205
    • 84930254537 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Editorial, Virginia’s Abortion Assault Claims a Victim, Wash. Post (Apr. 26, 2013), http://wapo.st/183RdOT (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (characterizing Virginia’s TRAP law as anti-abortion “ideological crusade masquerading as concern for public health”). Note
  • 206
    • 84930254538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Cf. supra notes 53–54 and accompanying text (explaining evasion cannot constitute uncivil obedience). Note
  • 207
    • 84930254539 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 877–78 (1992) (joint opinion of O’Connor, Kennedy & Souter, JJ.).
    • Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 877–78 (1992) (joint opinion of O’Connor, Kennedy & Souter, JJ.).
  • 208
    • 84930254540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • At this writing, Oklahoma’s medication-abortion law has been enjoined, while Ohio’s, North Dakota’s, and Texas’s have been upheld and a challenge to Arizona’s is pending. Planned Parenthood of Greater Te x. Surgical Health Servs. v. Abbott, 748 F. 3d 583, 605 (5th Cir. 2014)
    • At this writing, Oklahoma’s medication-abortion law has been enjoined, while Ohio’s, North Dakota’s, and Texas’s have been upheld and a challenge to Arizona’s is pending. Planned Parenthood of Greater Te x. Surgical Health Servs. v. Abbott, 748 F. 3d 583, 605 (5th Cir. 2014)
  • 209
    • 84930254541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Planned Parenthood Sw. Ohio Region v. DeWine, 696 F. 3d 490, 516–18 (6th Cir. 2012)
    • Planned Parenthood Sw. Ohio Region v. DeWine, 696 F. 3d 490, 516–18 (6th Cir. 2012)
  • 210
    • 84930254542 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MKB Mgmt. Corp. v. Burdick, 855 N.W.2d 31, 32 (N.D. 2014); Cline v. Okla. Coal. for Reprod. Justice, 313 P.3d 253, 262 (Okla. 2013)
    • MKB Mgmt. Corp. v. Burdick, 855 N.W.2d 31, 32 (N.D. 2014); Cline v. Okla. Coal. for Reprod. Justice, 313 P.3d 253, 262 (Okla. 2013)
  • 211
    • 84930254543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Planned Parenthood Ariz., Inc. v. Humble, 753 F. 3d 905, 918 (9th Cir. 2014) (instructing districtcourt to preliminarily enjoin Arizona’s law). The Fifth Circuit recently upheld Te xas’s TRAP law.
    • Planned Parenthood Ariz., Inc. v. Humble, 753 F. 3d 905, 918 (9th Cir. 2014) (instructing district court to preliminarily enjoin Arizona’s law). The Fifth Circuit recently upheld Te xas’s TRAP law.
  • 212
    • 84930254544 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Planned Parenthood of Greater Te x. Surgical Health Servs., 748 F. 3d at 590–600 (upholding admitting privileges requirement).
    • Planned Parenthood of Greater Te x. Surgical Health Servs., 748 F. 3d at 590–600 (upholding admitting privileges requirement).
  • 213
    • 84930254545 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arizona v. United States, 132 S. Ct. 2492 (2012). We return to the Arizona case infra notes 191–200 and accompanying text.
    • Arizona v. United States, 132 S. Ct. 2492 (2012). We return to the Arizona case infra notes 191–200 and accompanying text.
  • 214
    • 84930254546 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra notes 12–14, 51–54 and accompanying text (explaining these points).
    • supra notes 12–14, 51–54 and accompanying text (explaining these points).
  • 215
    • 33846647656 scopus 로고
    • The Supreme Court, 1991 Te rm—Foreword: The Justices of Rules and Standards
    • Kathleen M. Sullivan, The Supreme Court, 1991 Te rm—Foreword: The Justices of Rules and Standards, 106 Harv. L. Rev. 22, 58 (1992).
    • (1992) Harv. L. Rev , vol.106 , pp. 58
    • Sullivan, K.M.1
  • 216
    • 79955744308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Complexity of Jurisdictional Clarity
    • 1, using similar speed-limit examples to illustrate rules–standards distinction
    • Scott Dodson, The Complexity of Jurisdictional Clarity, 97 Va. L. Rev. 1, 16 (2011) (using similar speed-limit examples to illustrate rules–standards distinction)
    • (2011) Va. L. Rev , vol.97 , pp. 16
    • Dodson, S.1
  • 217
    • 21144468370 scopus 로고
    • Rules Versus Standards: An Economic Analysis
    • 560, same
    • Louis Kaplow, Rules Versus Standards: An Economic Analysis, 42 Duke L.J. 557, 560 (1993) (same)
    • (1993) Duke L.J , vol.42 , pp. 557
    • Kaplow, L.1
  • 218
    • 31544465066 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Behavior Analysis and Legal Form: Rules vs.
    • 23, same
    • Russell B. Korobkin, Behavior Analysis and Legal Form: Rules vs. Standards Revisited, 79 Or. L. Rev. 23, 23 (2000) (same).
    • (2000) Or. L. Rev. , vol.79 , pp. 23
    • Korobkin, R.B.1
  • 219
    • 84930254547 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sullivan, supra note 131, at 58 n.231 (citing Margaret Jane Radin, Presumptive Positivism and Tr ivial Cases, 14 Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol’y 823, 828–32 (1991))
    • Sullivan, supra note 131, at 58 n.231 (citing Margaret Jane Radin, Presumptive Positivism and Tr ivial Cases, 14 Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol’y 823, 828–32 (1991))
  • 220
    • 0042440459 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Rule of Law” as a Concept in Constitutional Discourse
    • 1, [A]s is well recognized, ‘rules’ and ‘standards’ do not so , much define a dichotomy as reflect ranges along a continuum.
    • Richard H. Fallon, “The Rule of Law” as a Concept in Constitutional Discourse, 97 Colum. L. Rev. 1, 49 (1997) (“[A]s is well recognized, ‘rules’ and ‘standards’ do not so much define a dichotomy as reflect ranges along a continuum.”).
    • (1997) Colum. L. Rev , vol.97 , pp. 49
    • Fallon, R.H.1
  • 221
    • 84930254548 scopus 로고
    • Sunstein, Problems with Rules
    • 83
    • Cass R. Sunstein, Problems with Rules, 83 Calif. L. Rev. 953, 992 (1995).
    • (1995) Calif. L. Rev , vol.953 , pp. 992
    • Cass, R.1
  • 222
    • 84930254549 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dodson, supra note 133, at 17.
    • Dodson, supra note 133, at 17.
  • 223
    • 84930254550 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra notes 32–33, 65 and accompanying text (explaining work to rule)
    • supra notes 32–33, 65 and accompanying text (explaining work to rule)
  • 224
    • 84930254551 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • David Luban, Misplaced Fidelity, 90 Te x. L. Rev. 673, 688 (2012) (book review) (observing work to rule is efective “because in the real world we expect people to make the innumerable minor adjustments that rules cannot capture”). In this sense, the use of the word “rule” in the label “work to rule” is entirely appropriate.
    • David Luban, Misplaced Fidelity, 90 Te x. L. Rev. 673, 688 (2012) (book review) (observing work to rule is efective “because in the real world we expect people to make the innumerable minor adjustments that rules cannot capture”). In this sense, the use of the word “rule” in the label “work to rule” is entirely appropriate.
  • 225
    • 84930254552 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 67 and accompanying text (describing Boyters’ protest against marriage tax penalty).
    • supra note 67 and accompanying text (describing Boyters’ protest against marriage tax penalty).
  • 226
    • 84930254553 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra notes 96–102 and accompanying text (considering systematic Senate obstructionism as form of uncivil obedience).
    • supra notes 96–102 and accompanying text (considering systematic Senate obstructionism as form of uncivil obedience).
  • 227
    • 84930254554 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra notes 1–4, 47–48 and accompanying text (discussing this protest).
    • supra notes 1–4, 47–48 and accompanying text (discussing this protest).
  • 228
    • 77955502667 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Inducing Moral Deliberation: On the Occasional
    • 1214
    • Seana Valentine Shifrin, Inducing Moral Deliberation: On the Occasional Virtues of Fog, 123 Harv. L. Rev. 1214, 1217 (2010).
    • (2010) Harv. L. Rev , vol.123 , pp. 1217
    • Shifrin, S.V.1
  • 229
    • 84930254555 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (arguing relatively opaque and moralistic idiom of standards induces deliberation).
    • (arguing relatively opaque and moralistic idiom of standards induces deliberation).
  • 230
    • 84859851443 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Eric A. Posner, Deference to the Executive in the United States After September 11: Congress, the Courts, and the Office of Legal Counsel, 35 Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol’y 213, 220 (2012) (“The legal landscape is a complex mix of rules and standards, which often overlap. Drivers must obey both traffic rules like the speed limit and trafic standards like laws against reckless driving and tort norms against negligent driving.”). On the potential role of “abuse of right” as a super-standard proscribing incivility
    • Cf. Eric A. Posner, Deference to the Executive in the United States After September 11: Congress, the Courts, and the Office of Legal Counsel, 35 Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol’y 213, 220 (2012) (“The legal landscape is a complex mix of rules and standards, which often overlap. Drivers must obey both traffic rules like the speed limit and trafic standards like laws against reckless driving and tort norms against negligent driving.”). On the potential role of “abuse of right” as a super-standard proscribing incivility
  • 231
    • 84930254557 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • infra Part III.B.1.
    • infra Part III.B.1.
  • 232
    • 84930254558 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Minn. Stat. Ann. § 609.74(2) (West 2009) (defining public nuisance to include intentionally “interfer[ing] with” or “obstruct[ing]” “any public highway or right-of-way”)
    • Minn. Stat. Ann. § 609.74(2) (West 2009) (defining public nuisance to include intentionally “interfer[ing] with” or “obstruct[ing]” “any public highway or right-of-way”)
  • 233
    • 84930254559 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Utah Code Ann. § 76-9-102(1)(b)(iv) (LexisNexis 2013 & Supp. 2014) (defining disorderly conduct to include “obstruct[ing] vehicular or pedestrian trafic” with “inten[t]to cause public inconvenience, annoyance, or alarm”). Other jurisdictions, in contrast, limit the ofenses of disorderly conduct and public nuisance to a distinct set of enumerated behaviors or to the creation of hazardous conditions.
    • Utah Code Ann. § 76-9-102(1)(b)(iv) (LexisNexis 2013 & Supp. 2014) (defining disorderly conduct to include “obstruct[ing] vehicular or pedestrian trafic” with “inten[t] to cause public inconvenience, annoyance, or alarm”). Other jurisdictions, in contrast, limit the ofenses of disorderly conduct and public nuisance to a distinct set of enumerated behaviors or to the creation of hazardous conditions.
  • 234
    • 84930254560 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tex. Penal Code Ann. § 42.01 (West 2013 & Supp. 2014) (restricting definition of “[d]isorderly [c]onduct” to enumerated behaviors)
    • Tex. Penal Code Ann. § 42.01 (West 2013 & Supp. 2014) (restricting definition of “[d]isorderly [c]onduct” to enumerated behaviors)
  • 235
    • 84930254561 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Tex. Civ. Prac. & Rem. Code Ann. §§ 125.062–.063 (West 2011) (limiting “public nuisance” to “continuously or regularly associat[ing] in gang activities” or habitually using particular location “for engaging in gang activity”). In a much-publicized 2011 incident, a Utah man who paid a disputed bill in pennies was cited for disorderly conduct—although reportedly for dumping thousands of coins over the counter and floor rather than for using pennies per se. Note
  • 236
    • 84930254562 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • June 6, 2011, 1:01 PM, on file with the Columbia Law Review
    • Eoin O’Carroll, 2,500 Pennies: Is It Legal to Pay a Bill in Pennies?, CSMonitor.com (June 6, 2011, 1:01 PM), http://www.csmonitor.com/Business/2011/0606/2-500-pennies-Is-it-legal-to-pay-a-bill-in-pennies (on file with the Columbia Law Review).
    • 2,500 Pennies:
    • O’Carroll, E.1
  • 237
    • 84930254563 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Just consider the potential costs to personal freedom and public discourse of maintaining an open-ended (though not unconstitutionally vague) prohibition on disorderly conduct.
    • Just consider the potential costs to personal freedom and public discourse of maintaining an open-ended (though not unconstitutionally vague) prohibition on disorderly conduct.
  • 238
    • 33749481102 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Convergence of Rules and Standards
    • [hereinafter Schauer, Convergence] (cataloging “rule-avoidance strat, egies”).
    • Frederick Schauer, The Convergence of Rules and Standards, 2003 N.Z. L. Rev. 303, 312–15 [hereinafter Schauer, Convergence] (cataloging “rule-avoidance strategies”).
    • (2003) N.Z. L. , pp. 303
    • Schauer, F.1
  • 239
    • 84930254564 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lenox Educ. Ass’n v. Labor Relations Comm’n, 471 N.E.2d 81, 82–83 (Mass. 1984) (holding “concerted refusal by public school teachers to perform services
    • Lenox Educ. Ass’n v. Labor Relations Comm’n, 471 N.E.2d 81, 82–83 (Mass. 1984) (holding “concerted refusal by public school teachers to perform services
  • 240
    • 84930254565 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • customarily performed by teachers generally, but not expressly described in their most recent collective bargaining agreement,” constituted unprotected strike)
    • customarily performed by teachers generally, but not expressly described in their most recent collective bargaining agreement,” constituted unprotected strike)
  • 241
    • 84930254566 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jeld We n Corp., Case 9-CA-28831, 1992 WL 83506, at *1–*2 (NLRB Office of Gen. Counsel Feb. 4, 1992) (finding work-to-rule action, in which employees “strictly adher[ed] to Employer instructions,” constituted unprotected slowdown).
    • Jeld We n Corp., Case 9-CA-28831, 1992 WL 83506, at *1–*2 (NLRB Office of Gen. Counsel Feb. 4, 1992) (finding work-to-rule action, in which employees “strictly adher[ed] to Employer instructions,” constituted unprotected slowdown).
  • 242
    • 84930254567 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Riverside Cement Co., 296 N.L.R.B. 840, 841 (1989) (stating, in decision for employees who alleged unlawful retaliation for engaging in work to rule, “[w]here an action is voluntary, the concerted refusal by employees to perform that action is a protected concerted activity and does not constitute an unlawful partial strike”).
    • Riverside Cement Co., 296 N.L.R.B. 840, 841 (1989) (stating, in decision for employees who alleged unlawful retaliation for engaging in work to rule, “[w]here an action is voluntary, the concerted refusal by employees to perform that action is a protected concerted activity and does not constitute an unlawful partial strike”).
  • 243
    • 84930254568 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Boyter v. Comm’r, 668 F. 2d 1382, 1388 (4th Cir. 1981). Without expressing a view on the merits, the panel remanded the case to the tax court “to determine whether the divorces, even if valid under Maryland law, are nonetheless shams and should be disregarded for federal income tax purposes for the years in question.” Id. When this happened, the Boyters divorced for a final time without remarrying, vowing to remain divorced until the law was changed. Graetz, supra note 67, at 37. Note
  • 244
    • 84930254569 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schauer, Convergence, supra note 146, at 311–21 (hypothesizing general tendency for rules and standards to converge)
    • Schauer, Convergence, supra note 146, at 311–21 (hypothesizing general tendency for rules and standards to converge)
  • 245
    • 84930254570 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Pierre Schlag, Rules and Standards, 33 UCLA L. Rev. 379, 428–29 (1985) (noting “tendency of rules to evolve or degenerate... into standards, and standards to evolve or degenerate into rules”). When standards become “rulified” over time through the eforts of interpreters and enforcers to provide more concrete guidance—so that, for example, motorists come to learn that driving under sixty-five miles per hour in dry weather will be deemed to comply with a directive to “drive safely”—opportunities for uncivil obedience may reemerge. Note
  • 246
    • 84930254571 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Coinage Act, 1971, c. 24, § 2(1d) (U.K.). For similar rules, see, for example, Currency Act 1965 (Cth) s 16(1) (Austl.) (restricting ability to tender payment using coins of various denominations); Currency Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. C-52, § 8 (Can.) (same). The United States Senate’s new limitations on the filibuster provide another example of a more fine-grained set of rules adopted to counteract uncivilly obedient uses of the prior regulations. See supra note 102 (describing this development). Note
  • 247
    • 84930254572 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Dodson, supra note 133, at 16 (summarizing literature). Conversely, standards are often praised for, among other things, being easier to craft and fairer as applied to particular cases. Id. at 17. Note
  • 248
    • 84930254573 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The United Kingdom’s bar on payments in bronze coins exceeding twenty pence, for example, knocks out not only disruptive tax protests but also innocent attempts by children to empty their piggy banks at the candy store. Note
  • 249
    • 84930254574 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Vaughan Lowe, The Politics of Law-Making: Are the Method and Character of Norm Creation Changing?, in The Role of Law in International Politics 207, 212–21 (Michael Byers ed., 2000) (defining “interstitial norms” as norms that lack “independent normative charge of their own” but instead “direct the manner in which competing or conflicting norms that do have their own normativity should interact in practice,” and citing abuse of right as prominent example). Note
  • 250
    • 84930254575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For useful surveys
    • For useful surveys
  • 251
    • 84930254576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Council of Europe, Abuse of Rights and Equivalent Concepts (1990), and Michael Byers, Abuse of Rights: An Old Principle, A New Age, 47 McGill L.J. 389 (2002). The doctrine has been substantially codified in European domestic systems but remains largely uncodified in international law. Note
  • 253
    • 84930254577 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The term “abuse of right” is thus misleadingly narrow insofar as it suggests that only Hohfeldian rights are implicated. Cf. Joseph M. Perillo, Abuse of Rights: A Pervasive Legal Concept, 27 Pac. L.J. 37, 54 n.76 (1995) (invoking Hohfeld and noting “term ‘abuse of rights,’” as used by author and countless others, “encompasses rights, powers, privileges, immunities, etc.”). There is a long-running debate over whether the term is more deeply misleading because conduct found to be an abuse of right is best understood as never having been within the scope of the right, rather than as a genuine exercise of the right that loses protection because of its abusive character. Note
  • 254
    • 84930254578 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Marcel Planiol, Tr eatise on the Civil Law no. 871 (La. State Law Inst. Trans., 11th ed. 1939) (insisting “the right ceases where the abuse commences”)
    • Marcel Planiol, Tr eatise on the Civil Law no. 871 (La. State Law Inst. Trans., 11th ed. 1939) (insisting “the right ceases where the abuse commences”)
  • 255
    • 84925971161 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Frederick Schauer, Can Rights Be Abused?, 31 Phil. Q. 225, 225–27 (1981) (exploring this puzzle).
    • Frederick Schauer, Can Rights Be Abused?, 31 Phil. Q. 225, 225–27 (1981) (exploring this puzzle).
  • 256
    • 84876353379 scopus 로고
    • Civil Liability for Abuse of Right: Something Old, Something New
    • 1173
    • A.N. Yiannopoulos, Civil Liability for Abuse of Right: Something Old, Something New..., 54 La. L. Rev. 1173, 1195 (1994)
    • (1994) La. L. Rev , vol.54 , pp. 1195
    • Yiannopoulos, A.N.1
  • 257
    • 84930254580 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Joseph Voyame et al., Abuse of Rights in Comparative Law, in Abuse of Rights and Equivalent Concepts, supra note 154, at 23, 23 (describing abuse of right as “legal mechanism designed to ease the inflexibility of the legal relationships derived from statutory, judicial or treaty rules”). Note
  • 258
    • 84930254581 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Byers, supra note 154, at 393–94 (listing Germany, Italy, and Austria as examples of legal systems that conceive of abuse of right in these terms)
    • Byers, supra note 154, at 393–94 (listing Germany, Italy, and Austria as examples of legal systems that conceive of abuse of right in these terms)
  • 259
    • 84930254582 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Voyame et al., supra note 157, at 28–31 (listing Italy, Austria, and Liechtenstein as countries that continue to employ “extremely narrow” approach of making “malicious intent... the sole essential element of the abuse”). The German Civil Code, for example, provides that “‘[t]he exercise of a right is unlawful, if its purpose can only be to cause damage to another.’” Byers, supra note 154, at 393 (quoting Bürgerliches Gesetzbuch [BGB] [Civil Code] art. 226 (Ger.), translated in The German Civil Code (Simon L. Goren trans., 1994)). Note
  • 260
    • 77950639123 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Abuse of Rights: The Continental Drug and the Common
    • 691, identifying this as “classical textbook example” of , abuse of right).
    • Anna di Robilant, Abuse of Rights: The Continental Drug and the Common Law, 61 Hastings L.J. 687, 691 (2010) (identifying this as “classical textbook example” of abuse of right).
    • (2010) Hastings L.J , vol.61 , pp. 687
    • Di Robilant, A.1
  • 261
    • 84930254583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Voyame et al., supra note 157, at 31–35 (discussing countries that “define any harmful act perpetrated in the absence of legitimate interest as an abuse”).
    • Voyame et al., supra note 157, at 31–35 (discussing countries that “define any harmful act perpetrated in the absence of legitimate interest as an abuse”).
  • 262
    • 84930254584 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Di Robilant, supra note 159, at 691–92
    • Di Robilant, supra note 159, at 691–92
  • 263
    • 84255166642 scopus 로고
    • The French Concept of Abuse of Rights
    • 1, When the right is , being abused, the actor is technically or mechanically within the formal limits of the right accorded, and may also be acting carefully. But he is not employing the right in conformity with its nature and purpose....
    • John H. Crabb, The French Concept of Abuse of Rights, 6 Inter-Am. L. Rev. 1, 9 (1964) (“When the right is being abused, the actor is technically or mechanically within the formal limits of the right accorded, and may also be acting carefully. But he is not employing the right in conformity with its nature and purpose....”).
    • (1964) Inter-Am. L. Rev , vol.6 , pp. 9
    • Crabb, J.H.1
  • 264
    • 84922407093 scopus 로고
    • The Role of the Abuse of Right Doctrine in Japan
    • 1037
    • Kazuaki Sono & Yasuhiro Fujioka, The Role of the Abuse of Right Doctrine in Japan, 35 La. L. Rev. 1037, 1037 (1975).
    • (1975) La. L. Rev , vol.35 , pp. 1037
    • Sono, K.1    Fujioka, Y.2
  • 265
    • 84930254585 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Byers, supra note 154, at 395 (quoting BW art. 13(2) (Neth.), translated in New Netherlands Civil Code (P.P.C. Haanappel & Ejan Mackaay trans., 1990)).
    • Byers, supra note 154, at 395 (quoting BW art. 13(2) (Neth.), translated in New Netherlands Civil Code (P.P.C. Haanappel & Ejan Mackaay trans., 1990)).
  • 266
    • 84930254586 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Voyame et al., supra note 157, at 35 (summarizing approach of countries that “apply an objective conception of abuse of rights”).
    • Voyame et al., supra note 157, at 35 (summarizing approach of countries that “apply an objective conception of abuse of rights”).
  • 267
    • 84930254587 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (quoting Louis Josserand, “the father” of modern French abuse-of-right theory).
    • (quoting Louis Josserand, “the father” of modern French abuse-of-right theory).
  • 268
    • 84930254588 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • di Robilant, supra note 159, at 691–92 (“At the height of nineteenth-century industrial struggles [in Europe], unions were found to abuse their right to strike when their action departed from the right’s ‘normal function.’”).
    • di Robilant, supra note 159, at 691–92 (“At the height of nineteenth-century industrial struggles [in Europe], unions were found to abuse their right to strike when their action departed from the right’s ‘normal function.’”).
  • 269
    • 84930254589 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • supra notes 96–102 and accompanying text (describing these Senate behaviors). At present, the doctrine of abuse of right “is rarely mentioned in constitutional law,” although some influential European jurists have begun to urge this change. András Sajó, Abuse of Fundamental Rights or the Difficulties of Purposiveness, in Abuse: The Dark Side of Fundamental Rights 29, 33 (András Sajó ed., 2006). Abuse of right has been “neglected” in public law, according to Sajó, because of the prominence of concepts such as “discretionary power and legislative sovereignty” and the privileging of “categorical” (rather than balancing) approaches to rights. Id. at 34. Note
  • 270
    • 84930254590 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the notorious vagueness of abuse of right, see, for example, Robert Krieps, General Report, in Abuse of Rights and Equivalent Concepts, supra note 154, at 166, 173 (“[E]ven an experienced jurist... would be hard put to say precisely what was the criterion that determined that a right had been abused....”)
    • On the notorious vagueness of abuse of right, see, for example, Robert Krieps, General Report, in Abuse of Rights and Equivalent Concepts, supra note 154, at 166, 173 (“[E]ven an experienced jurist... would be hard put to say precisely what was the criterion that determined that a right had been abused....”)
  • 271
    • 84930254591 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Voyame et al., supra note 157, at 23 (“[W]ithin most countries, there is no unanimous agreement as to the scope of the prohibition of abuse of rights; doctrinal disputes and contradictory judgments are commonplace.”).
    • Voyame et al., supra note 157, at 23 (“[W]ithin most countries, there is no unanimous agreement as to the scope of the prohibition of abuse of rights; doctrinal disputes and contradictory judgments are commonplace.”).
  • 272
    • 84930254592 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Yiannopoulos, supra note 157 (reviewing history of abuse of right in Louisiana law).
    • Yiannopoulos, supra note 157 (reviewing history of abuse of right in Louisiana law).
  • 273
    • 84930254593 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [1895] A.C. 587 (H.L.) 594 (appeal taken from Eng.).
    • [1895] A.C. 587 (H.L.) 594 (appeal taken from Eng.).
  • 274
    • 84930254594 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Perillo, supra note 156, at 40
    • Perillo, supra note 156, at 40
  • 275
    • 84930254595 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • D.J. Devine, Some Comparative Aspects of the Doctrine of Abuse of Rights, 1964 Acta Juridica 148, 164 (“Despite the lack of any general principle of abuse of right,... in some particular instances, English Law does admit what amounts to [such] a doctrine.... These instances occur mainly in thelaw of nuisance, conspiracy, abuse of process and qualified privilege in defamation.”)
    • D.J. Devine, Some Comparative Aspects of the Doctrine of Abuse of Rights, 1964 Acta Juridica 148, 164 (“Despite the lack of any general principle of abuse of right,... in some particular instances, English Law does admit what amounts to [such] a doctrine.... These instances occur mainly in the law of nuisance, conspiracy, abuse of process and qualified privilege in defamation.”)
  • 276
    • 84930254596 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • di Robilant, supra note 159, at 696 (arguing abuse of right “was silently at work” in English and especially American private law during late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, through “functional equivalents” such as “‘malice’ tests and ‘reasonable user’ rules”).
    • di Robilant, supra note 159, at 696 (arguing abuse of right “was silently at work” in English and especially American private law during late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, through “functional equivalents” such as “‘malice’ tests and ‘reasonable user’ rules”).
  • 277
    • 84930254597 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But cf. Perillo, supra note 156, at 69–77 (emphasizing haziness surrounding idea of good faith in American contract law and arguing abuse-of-right framework would be clearer and more constraining).
    • But cf. Perillo, supra note 156, at 69–77 (emphasizing haziness surrounding idea of good faith in American contract law and arguing abuse-of-right framework would be clearer and more constraining).
  • 278
    • 84930254598 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Email from Jody S. Kraus, Patricia D. & R. Paul Yetter Professor of Law and Professor of Philosophy, Columbia Law Sch., to authors (Sept. 8, 2014, 3:26 PM EDT) (on file with the Columbia Law Review).
    • Email from Jody S. Kraus, Patricia D. & R. Paul Yetter Professor of Law and Professor of Philosophy, Columbia Law Sch., to authors (Sept. 8, 2014, 3:26 PM EDT) (on file with the Columbia Law Review).
  • 279
    • 84859826480 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oct. 22, 2010, unpublished manuscript, on file with the Columbia Law Review). For a similar theory , of the duty of good faith in civilian contract law
    • Henry E. Smith, An Economic Analysis of Law Ve rsus Equity (Oct. 22, 2010) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://www.law.yale.edu/documents/pdf/LEO/HSmith_LawVersusEquity7.pdf (on file with the Columbia Law Review). For a similar theory of the duty of good faith in civilian contract law
    • An Economic Analysis of Law Ve Rsus Equity
    • Smith, H.E.1
  • 280
    • 84930254599 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • unpublished manuscript, on file with the Columbia Law Review) (arguing good faith , supplies “residual concept with which to fashion new remedies [for opportunism] where no existing one is appropriate”
    • Ejan Mackaay, The Economics of Civil Law Contract and of Good Faith 15 (2009) (unpublished manuscript), available at https://papyrus.bib.umontreal.ca/xmlui/bitstream/handle/1866/3016/Mackaay_Trebilc ock-Symposium%20_3_.pdf (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (arguing good faith supplies “residual concept with which to fashion new remedies [for opportunism] where no existing one is appropriate”).
    • (2009) The Economics of Civil , pp. 15
    • Mackaay, E.1
  • 281
    • 84930254600 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, supra note 174, at 33.
    • Smith, supra note 174, at 33.
  • 283
    • 84941051964 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Paul MacMahon, Good Faith and Fair Dealing as an Underenforced Legal Norm, 99 Minn. L. Rev. (forthcoming 2015) (manuscript at 38–49) (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (detailing “underenforcement” of duty of good faith in American contract law). Note
  • 284
    • 0034396337 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Bitter with the Sweet: Tr adition, History, and
    • 1292, “It did not take long after Professor Chayes celebrated the ‘triumph of equity’ in public law litigation to recognize that the announcement was premature.... (quoting , Abram Chayes, The Role of the Judge in Public Law Litigation, 89 Harv. L. Rev. 1281, 1292 (1976)))
    • Stephen B. Burbank, The Bitter with the Sweet: Tr adition, History, and Limitations on Federal Judicial Power—A Case Study, 75 Notre Dame L. Rev. 1291, 1292 (2000) (“It did not take long after Professor Chayes celebrated the ‘triumph of equity’ in public law litigation to recognize that the announcement was premature.... (quoting Abram Chayes, The Role of the Judge in Public Law Litigation, 89 Harv. L. Rev. 1281, 1292 (1976)))
    • (2000) Notre Dame L. Rev , vol.75 , pp. 1291
    • Burbank, S.B.1
  • 285
    • 0042608704 scopus 로고
    • No Final Victories: The Incompleteness of Equity’s
    • Summer, 105, reviewing cases “demonstrating the limited nature of equity’s ‘triumph’ in federal public , law” and modern Supreme Court’s “hostility toward the spirit of equity” in this area
    • Thomas D. Rowe No Final Victories: The Incompleteness of Equity’s Triumph in Federal Public Law, 56 Law & Contemp. Probs., Summer 1993, at 105, 105 (reviewing cases “demonstrating the limited nature of equity’s ‘triumph’ in federal public law” and modern Supreme Court’s “hostility toward the spirit of equity” in this area)
    • (1993) Law & Contemp. Probs. , vol.56 , pp. 105
    • Rowe, T.D.1
  • 286
    • 84958092516 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constitutional Bad Faith
    • forthcoming 2016) , (manuscript at 8–19) (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (documenting margin-alization of principle of good faith in American constitutional law)
    • David E. Pozen, Constitutional Bad Faith, 129 Harv. L. Rev. (forthcoming 2016) (manuscript at 8–19) (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (documenting margin-alization of principle of good faith in American constitutional law)
    • Harv. L. Rev , vol.129
    • Pozen, D.E.1
  • 287
    • 79953709925 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • May God Protect Us from the Equity of Parlements”: Comparative Reflections on
    • 1292, [Historically,] English equity was confined to private law. It had little or no public-law dimension or , application....”). Abuse of right has been similarly sidelined in European countries’ domestic public law. Supra note 167.
    • Vernon Va lentine Palmer, “May God Protect Us from the Equity of Parlements”: Comparative Reflections on English and French Equity Power, 73 Tul. L. Rev. 1287, 1292 (1999) (“[Historically,] English equity was confined to private law. It had little or no public-law dimension or application....”). Abuse of right has been similarly sidelined in European countries’ domestic public law. Supra note 167.
    • (1999) Tul. L. Rev , vol.73 , pp. 1287
    • Palmer, V.V.1
  • 289
    • 84930254603 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, supra note 174, at 9.
    • Smith, supra note 174, at 9.
  • 290
    • 84930254604 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 148 and accompanying text (discussing this litigation).
    • supra note 148 and accompanying text (discussing this litigation).
  • 291
    • 84930254605 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 147 and accompanying text (noting mixed case law in this area).
    • supra note 147 and accompanying text (noting mixed case law in this area).
  • 293
    • 84930254606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The empirical and methodological challenges would be formidable, but researchers could conceivably perform interjurisdictional comparisons of rates of work-to-rule actions, tax payments in coins, eforts to flood the courts, and so forth. At a minimum, surveys and laboratory experiments could be used to test perceptions of various kinds of uncivil obedience across common-law and civil-law subjects. Note
  • 294
    • 77950640888 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Cf. H.C. Gutteridge, Abuse of Rights, 5 Cambridge L.J. 22, 22 (1933) (asserting “theory of the abuse of rights... has been rejected by our [Anglo-American] law” in favor of “theory of the extent of individual rights which can only be described as the consecration of the spirit of unrestricted egoism”). Note
  • 295
    • 84930254608 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra Part II.B.4.
    • supra Part II.B.4.
  • 296
    • 84930254609 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fla. Lime & Avocado Growers, Inc. v. Paul, 373 U.S. 132, 142–43 (1963).
    • Fla. Lime & Avocado Growers, Inc. v. Paul, 373 U.S. 132, 142–43 (1963).
  • 297
    • 84930254610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hines v. Davidowitz, 312 U.S. 52, 67 (1941).
    • Hines v. Davidowitz, 312 U.S. 52, 67 (1941).
  • 298
    • 84930254611 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Crosby v. Nat’l Foreign Trade Council, 530 U.S. 363, 373 (2000) (“What is a sufficient obstacle is a matter of judgment, to be informed by examining the federal statute as a whole and identifying its purpose and intended effects.”). Note
  • 299
    • 84930254612 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • S. Ct. 2492 (2012)
    • S. Ct. 2492 (2012)
  • 300
    • 84930254613 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra notes 119–122 and accompanying text (describing Arizona’s challenged immigration law).
    • supra notes 119–122 and accompanying text (describing Arizona’s challenged immigration law).
  • 301
    • 84930254614 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 122 and accompanying text (explaining “mirror-image theory”).
    • supra note 122 and accompanying text (explaining “mirror-image theory”).
  • 302
    • 84930254615 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arizona, 132 S. Ct. at 2522 (Scalia, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part)
    • Arizona, 132 S. Ct. at 2522 (Scalia, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part)
  • 303
    • 84930254616 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (“[T]o say, as the Court does, that Arizona contradicts federal law by enforcing applications of the Immigration Act that the President declines to enforce boggles the mind.”).
    • (“[T]o say, as the Court does, that Arizona contradicts federal law by enforcing applications of the Immigration Act that the President declines to enforce boggles the mind.”).
  • 304
    • 84930254617 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (“Arizona law would interfere with the careful balance struck by Congress with respect to unauthorized employment of aliens.”).
    • (“Arizona law would interfere with the careful balance struck by Congress with respect to unauthorized employment of aliens.”).
  • 305
    • 84930254618 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • State laws touching on immigration and foreign afairs have been invalidated on grounds of field, as well as conflict, preemption. In Arizona, the Supreme Court invoked both field and conflict preemption, even, oddly enough, with regard to the same provision of the state law.
    • State laws touching on immigration and foreign afairs have been invalidated on grounds of field, as well as conflict, preemption. In Arizona, the Supreme Court invoked both field and conflict preemption, even, oddly enough, with regard to the same provision of the state law.
  • 306
    • 84930254619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (noting certain “specific conflicts between state and federal law simply underscore the reason for field preemption”).
    • (noting certain “specific conflicts between state and federal law simply underscore the reason for field preemption”).
  • 307
    • 84930254620 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 121 and accompanying text (reviewing Arizona’s argument).
    • supra note 121 and accompanying text (reviewing Arizona’s argument).
  • 308
    • 84930254621 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Adam B. Cox, Enforcement Redundancy and the Future of Immigration Law, 2012 Sup. Ct. Rev. 31, 33 (arguing Arizona “endors[es] the idea that immigration law is centrally the product of executive ‘lawmaking’ that bears little relation to immigration law on the books”). Similar reasoning appeared in Buckman Co. v. Plaintifs’ Legal Committee with respect to state tort law. 531 U.S. 341 (2001). The Buckman Court emphasized that “the federal statutory scheme amply empowers the FDA to punish and deter fraud against the Administration,” and held that the FDA’s discretion in exercising this authority amounted to part of the federal law bearing preemptive effect. Id. at 348. Note
  • 309
    • 84930254622 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Wyeth v. Levine, 555 U.S. 555, 583 (2009) (Thomas, J., concurring in the judgment) (“I have become increasingly skeptical of this Court’s ‘purposes and objectives’ pre-emption jurisprudence. Under this approach, the Court routinely invalidates state laws based on perceived conflicts with broad federal policy objectives, legislative history, or generalized notions of congressional purposes that are not embodied within the text of federal law.”) Note
  • 310
    • 49749139380 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ernest A. Young, Executive Preemption, 102 Nw. U. L. Rev. 869, 871 (2008) (contending preemption based on agency activity “seem[s] to shift preemptive authority from Congress to the agency—a result that contravenes both the text of the Supremacy Clause and the structural safeguards of federalism and separation of powers”).
    • Ernest A. Young, Executive Preemption, 102 Nw. U. L. Rev. 869, 871 (2008) (contending preemption based on agency activity “seem[s] to shift preemptive authority from Congress to the agency—a result that contravenes both the text of the Supremacy Clause and the structural safeguards of federalism and separation of powers”).
  • 311
    • 84930254624 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As a growing literature emphasizes, there are many reasons one might welcome state dissent from federal policy and accordingly be wary of “civilizing” reforms.
    • As a growing literature emphasizes, there are many reasons one might welcome state dissent from federal policy and accordingly be wary of “civilizing” reforms.
  • 312
    • 84930254625 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bulman-Pozen & Gerken, supra note 114, at 1284–94 (identifying potential benefits of “uncooperative federalism”)
    • Bulman-Pozen & Gerken, supra note 114, at 1284–94 (identifying potential benefits of “uncooperative federalism”)
  • 313
    • 84930254626 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hills, supra note 112, at 4 (proposing “often competitive interaction between the levels of government” can make “Congress a more honest and democratically accountable regulator of conduct throughout the nation”)
    • Hills, supra note 112, at 4 (proposing “often competitive interaction between the levels of government” can make “Congress a more honest and democratically accountable regulator of conduct throughout the nation”)
  • 314
    • 11144271345 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1, arguing , limiting federal preemption of state law would advance values such as citizen participation and deliberation
    • Ernest A. Young, The Rehnquist Court’s Two Federalisms, 83 Te x. L. Rev. 1, 130–34 (2004) (arguing limiting federal preemption of state law would advance values such as citizen participation and deliberation).
    • (2004) The Rehnquist Court’s Two Federalisms , vol.83 , pp. 130-134
    • Young, E.A.1
  • 315
    • 84930254627 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. supra note 62 (discussing diferent types of environments in which uncivil obedience may occur).
    • Cf. supra note 62 (discussing diferent types of environments in which uncivil obedience may occur).
  • 316
    • 84930254628 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Robert C. Ellickson, Order Without Law 167–78 (1991) (defining close-knit groups as ones in which “informal power is broadly distributed among group members and the information pertinent to informal control circulates easily among them,” and arguing their members will tend to develop and maintain welfare-enhancing norms of cooperation)
    • Robert C. Ellickson, Order Without Law 167–78 (1991) (defining close-knit groups as ones in which “informal power is broadly distributed among group members and the information pertinent to informal control circulates easily among them,” and arguing their members will tend to develop and maintain welfare-enhancing norms of cooperation)
  • 317
    • 84930246784 scopus 로고
    • Opting Out of the Legal System: Extralegal
    • 115, discussing importance of “geographical concentration, ethnic homogeneity, and repeat , dealing” for emergence of reputational norms).
    • Lisa Bernstein, Opting Out of the Legal System: Extralegal Contractual Relations in the Diamond Industry, 21 J. Legal Stud. 115, 140 (1992) (discussing importance of “geographical concentration, ethnic homogeneity, and repeat dealing” for emergence of reputational norms).
    • (1992) J. Legal Stud , vol.21 , pp. 140
    • Bernstein, L.1
  • 318
    • 0037412588 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • passim & 365 , n.31, exploring conditions under which cooperative norms can arise in non-close- , knit settings and positing that members’ ability to monitor noncooperation and communicate about each other’s reputations matters more than group size per se).
    • Lior Jacob Strahilevitz, Social Norms from Close-Knit Groups to Loose-Knit Groups, 70 U. Chi. L. Rev. 359, passim & 365 n.31 (2003) (exploring conditions under which cooperative norms can arise in non-close- knit settings and positing that members’ ability to monitor noncooperation and communicate about each other’s reputations matters more than group size per se).
    • (2003) Social , vol.70 , pp. 359
    • Strahilevitz, L.J.1
  • 319
    • 84930254629 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ellickson, supra note 202, at 4 (“Neighbors in fact are strongly inclined to cooperate, but they achieve cooperative outcomes not by bargaining from legally established entitlements,... but rather by developing and enforcing adaptive norms or neighborliness that trump formal legal entitlements.”)
    • Ellickson, supra note 202, at 4 (“Neighbors in fact are strongly inclined to cooperate, but they achieve cooperative outcomes not by bargaining from legally established entitlements,... but rather by developing and enforcing adaptive norms or neighborliness that trump formal legal entitlements.”)
  • 320
    • 84930254630 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Eric A. Posner, Law and Social Norms 12 (2002) (“[T]hat people do not rely on the law to solve day-to-day cooperative problems is clear from both formal research... and casual empiricism.”).
    • Eric A. Posner, Law and Social Norms 12 (2002) (“[T]hat people do not rely on the law to solve day-to-day cooperative problems is clear from both formal research... and casual empiricism.”).
  • 321
    • 84930254631 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra notes 34–35, 67, 74–79 and accompanying text (presenting these examples)
    • supra notes 34–35, 67, 74–79 and accompanying text (presenting these examples).
  • 322
    • 84930244053 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U.S. Senate, (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (last visited Mar. 25, 2015) (crediting William S. White’s 1957 book The Citadel with “populariz[ing] the idea of the Senate as a , ‘gentlemen’s club’”).
    • U.S. Senate, Citadel, https://www.senate.gov/reference/reference:item/Citadel.htm (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (last visited Mar. 25, 2015) (crediting William S. White’s 1957 book The Citadel with “populariz[ing] the idea of the Senate as a ‘gentlemen’s club’”).
    • Citadel
  • 323
    • 84857870452 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Through the Looking Glass, Darkly: What Has Become of the
    • Dec, art. 2, at 1, 1.
    • Sarah Binder, Through the Looking Glass, Darkly: What Has Become of the Senate?, Forum: J. Applied Res. Contemp. Pol., Dec. 2011, art. 2, at 1, 1.
    • (2011) Applied Res. Contemp. Pol.,
    • Binder, S.1
  • 324
    • 84930254633 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (discussing breakdown of comity in Senate).
    •  (discussing breakdown of comity in Senate).
  • 325
    • 84930254634 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra notes 96–102 and accompanying text (discussing senatorial uncivil obedience).
    • supra notes 96–102 and accompanying text (discussing senatorial uncivil obedience).
  • 326
    • 84930254635 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra notes 53–56 and accompanying text (noting possible formal and informal responses to uncivil obedience).
    • supra notes 53–56 and accompanying text (noting possible formal and informal responses to uncivil obedience).
  • 327
    • 84930254636 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the varieties of informal sanctions that may be applied
    • On the varieties of informal sanctions that may be applied
  • 328
    • 0000449743 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Creating and Enforcing Norms, with Special
    • 369, cataloging “sanctions , that enforce [social] norms”).
    • Richard A. Posner & Eric B. Rasmusen, Creating and Enforcing Norms, with Special Reference to Sanctions, 19 Int’l Rev. L. & Econ. 369, 370–72 (1999) (cataloging “sanctions that enforce [social] norms”).
    • (1999) Int’l Rev. L. & Econ , vol.19 , pp. 370-372
    • Posner, R.A.1    Rasmusen, E.B.2
  • 329
    • 84930254637 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Caterpillar, Inc., 322 N.L.R.B. 674 (1996) (discussing supervisor’s informal and formal retaliation against employees for engaging in protected work-to-rulebehaviors).
    • Caterpillar, Inc., 322 N.L.R.B. 674 (1996) (discussing supervisor’s informal and formal retaliation against employees for engaging in protected work-to-rule behaviors).
  • 330
    • 0003168621 scopus 로고
    • Shame, Culture, and American Criminal Law
    • 18801916, Informal sanctions appear to work best within relatively , bounded, close-knit communities, whose members ‘don’t mind their own business’ and who rely on each other.”).
    • Toni M. Massaro, Shame, Culture, and American Criminal Law, 89 Mich. L. Rev. 1880, 1916 (1991) (“Informal sanctions appear to work best within relatively bounded, close-knit communities, whose members ‘don’t mind their own business’ and who rely on each other.”).
    • (1991) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.89
    • Massaro, T.M.1
  • 331
    • 84930254638 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • “Inclusive,” “soft,” or “incorporationist” positivism, in contrast, holds that the existence and content of law may depend on moral principles insofar as they are explicitly or implicitly incorporated into a society’s rule of recognition.
    • “Inclusive,” “soft,” or “incorporationist” positivism, in contrast, holds that the existence and content of law may depend on moral principles insofar as they are explicitly or implicitly incorporated into a society’s rule of recognition.
  • 332
    • 37949034425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Exclusive Legal Positivism
    • Jules L. Coleman & Scott Shapiro eds., 2002) (comparing exclusive and inclusive legal positivism
    • Andrei Marmor, Exclusive Legal Positivism, in The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law 104 (Jules L. Coleman & Scott Shapiro eds., 2002) (comparing exclusive and inclusive legal positivism)
    • In the Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence And
    • Marmor, A.1
  • 333
    • 84930254640 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Frederick Schauer, Formalism, 97 Yale L.J. 509, 510 (1988) (defining formalism as decision making constrained by “specific linguistic formulation of a rule”). Our aim in this paragraph and the next is to convey the basic sense in which uncivil obedience may be facilitated by legal formalism and positivism. There are countless jurisprudential nuances that we gloss over in the effort to offer a succinct statement of the issue.
    • Frederick Schauer, Formalism, 97 Yale L.J. 509, 510 (1988) (defining formalism as decision making constrained by “specific linguistic formulation of a rule”). Our aim in this paragraph and the next is to convey the basic sense in which uncivil obedience may be facilitated by legal formalism and positivism. There are countless jurisprudential nuances that we gloss over in the effort to offer a succinct statement of the issue.
  • 334
    • 84930254641 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Simon, supra note 32, at 79–85 (proposing “substantivism” as umbrella term for all conceptions of law that reject core premises of positivism). Dworkin’s notion of “law as integrity” is developed in Ronald Dworkin, Law’s Empire 176–224 (1986).
    • Simon, supra note 32, at 79–85 (proposing “substantivism” as umbrella term for all conceptions of law that reject core premises of positivism). Dworkin’s notion of “law as integrity” is developed in Ronald Dworkin, Law’s Empire 176–224 (1986).
  • 335
    • 84930254642 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This proposition is vigorously disputed by numerous philosophers.
    • This proposition is vigorously disputed by numerous philosophers.
  • 336
    • 84894300025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Frederick Schauer, Official Obedience and the Politics of Defining “Law,” 86 S. Cal. L. Rev. 1165, 1167 n.10 (2013) (collecting sources).
    • Frederick Schauer, Official Obedience and the Politics of Defining “Law,” 86 S. Cal. L. Rev. 1165, 1167 n.10 (2013) (collecting sources).
  • 337
    • 84930254644 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Markovits, supra note 9, at 1898–901 (reviewing prominent eforts to “determine[] the metes and bounds of justified liberal disobedience”).
    • Markovits, supra note 9, at 1898–901 (reviewing prominent eforts to “determine[] the metes and bounds of justified liberal disobedience”).
  • 338
    • 84930254645 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, supra note 6, at 364.
    • Rawls, supra note 6, at 364.
  • 339
    • 84930254646 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cass R. Sunstein, Why Societies Need Dissent (2003) (arguing dissent performs variety of valuable social functions).
    • Cass R. Sunstein, Why Societies Need Dissent (2003) (arguing dissent performs variety of valuable social functions).
  • 340
    • 84930254647 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Russell Kirk, The Conservative Mind: From Burke to Elliot 38 (7th rev. ed. 2001) (reading Burke to teach “even the most intelligent of men cannot hope to understand all the secrets of traditional morals and social arrangements; but we may be sure that Providence, acting through the medium of human trial and error, has developed every hoary habit for some important purpose”). Note
  • 341
    • 84930254648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • supra notes 96–102 and accompanying text (describing these transformations). Those who believe that unwritten “constitutional conventions” tend to promote stability, ef ciency, or fairness in a political system might be similarly concerned about such intragovernmental uncivil obedience. Note
  • 342
    • 84930254649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pozen, Self-Help, supra note 101, at 27–48 (explaining constitutional conventions and their application to U.S. context).
    • Pozen, Self-Help, supra note 101, at 27–48 (explaining constitutional conventions and their application to U.S. context).
  • 343
    • 84930254650 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra Part III.B.1 (exploring relationship between abuse of right and uncivil obedience).
    • supra Part III.B.1 (exploring relationship between abuse of right and uncivil obedience).
  • 344
    • 84930254651 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • We say “presumptive” because in any given case a wide range of factors, including the justness of the uncivil obedient’s cause, may overcome any such qualms about her tactics. Note
  • 345
    • 84930254652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • By “public law values,” we mean to invoke values such as “openness, fairness, participation, impartiality, accountability, honesty and rationality” that are widely understood to reinforce the rule of law and to reflect core goals of constitutional and administrative regulation. Michael Taggart, The Province of Administrative Law Determined?, in The Province of Administrative Law 1, 3 (Michael Taggart ed., 1997). Note
  • 346
    • 84930254653 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra Parts III.A–B (examining possible legal responses to uncivil obedience).
    • supra Parts III.A–B (examining possible legal responses to uncivil obedience).
  • 347
    • 84930254654 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. supra notes 42–44 and accompanying text (discussing relationship between communicativeness and candor in practice of uncivil obedience).
    • Cf. supra notes 42–44 and accompanying text (discussing relationship between communicativeness and candor in practice of uncivil obedience).
  • 348
    • 84930254655 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra Part II.B.3 (explaining direct–indirect distinction).
    • supra Part II.B.3 (explaining direct–indirect distinction).
  • 349
    • 84930254656 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Baker, supra note 83, at 30.
    • Baker, supra note 83, at 30.
  • 350
    • 84886289373 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dissenting from Within: Why and How Public Officials
    • 650, Overt resistance is likely to be better , than covert resistance at promoting dialogue and debate....
    • Adam Shinar, Dissenting from Within: Why and How Public Officials Resist the Law, 40 Fla. St. U. L. Rev. 601, 650 (2013) (“Overt resistance is likely to be better than covert resistance at promoting dialogue and debate....”).
    • (2013) Fla. St. U. L. Rev , vol.40 , pp. 601
    • Shinar, A.1
  • 351
    • 84926117878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dyzenhaus expressly ties his idea of grey holes to executive officials, but the , central insights can be generalized to other actors.
    • David Dyzenhaus, The Constitution of Law: Legality in a Time of Emergency 42 (2006). Dyzenhaus expressly ties his idea of grey holes to executive officials, but the central insights can be generalized to other actors.
    • (2006) The Constitution of Law: Legality in a Time of Emergency , pp. 42
    • Dyzenhaus, D.1
  • 352
    • 84930254657 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • David Dyzenhaus, Schmitt v. Dicey: Are States of Emergency Inside or
    • David Dyzenhaus, Schmitt v. Dicey: Are States of Emergency Inside or
  • 353
    • 84930254658 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Outside the Legal Order?, 27 Cardozo L. Rev. 2005, 2026 (2006) (arguing “grey holes are more harmful to the rule of law than [are] black holes” because only former mask their “lack of substance”).
    • Outside the Legal Order?, 27 Cardozo L. Rev. 2005, 2026 (2006) (arguing “grey holes are more harmful to the rule of law than [are] black holes” because only former mask their “lack of substance”).
  • 354
    • 84930254659 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra notes 28–30 and accompanying text (discussing these accounts of civil disobedience).
    • supra notes 28–30 and accompanying text (discussing these accounts of civil disobedience).
  • 355
    • 84930254660 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra notes 53–54 and accompanying text (noting possibility of finding of illegality, notwithstanding uncivil obedient’s genuine, well-founded belief in legality of her conduct).
    • supra notes 53–54 and accompanying text (noting possibility of finding of illegality, notwithstanding uncivil obedient’s genuine, well-founded belief in legality of her conduct).
  • 356
    • 84930254661 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra Part III.C (discussing informal regulation of uncivil obedience).
    • supra Part III.C (discussing informal regulation of uncivil obedience).
  • 357
    • 84930254662 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Cf. Brownlee, Communicative Aspects, supra note 11, at 181 (“[T]he legal protester will not be called upon by the law to defend her decision to protest. This means that whatever conscientious intentions underpin her protest need not meet the same standards as those that distinguish serious civil disobedients from ordinary ofenders.”). Note
  • 358
    • 84930254663 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Brownlee, Civil Disobedience, supra note 6 (noting one harm “usually identified with civil disobedience” is that it “can encourage more than just other civil disobedience; it can encourage a general disrespect for the law”). Note
  • 359
    • 84930254664 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra Parts II.B.2, II.B.4 (describing uncivil obedience by government of-cials and institutions).
    • supra Parts II.B.2, II.B.4 (describing uncivil obedience by government of-cials and institutions).
  • 360
    • 84930254665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, supra note 6, at 373.
    • Rawls, supra note 6, at 373.
  • 361
    • 84930254666 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Markovits, supra note 9, at 1899–901 (highlighting this feature of traditional civil disobedience and citing American civil rights movement as “most prominent” example) Note
  • 362
    • 84930254667 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Brownlee, Civil Disobedience, supra note 6 (“The historical paradigms of Gandhi, King, the sufragettes, and Mandela are representative of that kind of civil disobedience which aims to guarantee legal protection for the basic rights of a specific constituency.”). Note
  • 363
    • 84887865560 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Presidential Power, Historical
    • 1140, noting “pervasive , existence of public ‘law talk’” in United States, in which government officials “almost always endeavor[] to argue that [their] actions are lawful”).
    • Curtis A. Bradley & Trevor W. Morrison, Presidential Power, Historical Practice, and Legal Constraint, 113 Colum. L. Rev. 1097, 1140 (2013) (noting “pervasive existence of public ‘law talk’” in United States, in which government officials “almost always endeavor[] to argue that [their] actions are lawful”).
    • (2013) Colum. L. Rev , vol.113 , pp. 1097
    • Bradley, C.A.1    Morrison, T.W.2
  • 364
    • 84930254668 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 99 and accompanying text (noting role of “holds” in recent senatorial uncivil obedience).
    • supra note 99 and accompanying text (noting role of “holds” in recent senatorial uncivil obedience).
  • 365
    • 84930254669 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra Part II.B.4 (considering these examples).
    • supra Part II.B.4 (considering these examples).
  • 366
    • 84930254670 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. supra notes 154–155 and accompanying text (describing related concept of abuse of right in international law).
    • Cf. supra notes 154–155 and accompanying text (describing related concept of abuse of right in international law).
  • 367
    • 84930254671 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Recent legal scholarship has complicated this association in other respects.
    • Recent legal scholarship has complicated this association in other respects.
  • 368
    • 33645991780 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dissenting by Deciding
    • (arguing, disaggregated institutions enable minorities to constitute local majorities and thereby dissent through governance decisions)
    • Heather K. Gerken, Dissenting by Deciding, 57 Stan. L. Rev. 1745 (2005) (arguing disaggregated institutions enable minorities to constitute local majorities and thereby dissent through governance decisions)
    • (2005) Stan. L. Rev , vol.57 , pp. 1745
    • Gerken, H.K.1
  • 369
    • 84930254672 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Shinar, supra note 228 (exploring resistance by government officials to laws and policies they are responsible for implementing).
    • Shinar, supra note 228 (exploring resistance by government officials to laws and policies they are responsible for implementing).
  • 370
    • 84930254673 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra notes 233–236 and accompanying text (discussing limited liability that attends uncivil obedience).
    • supra notes 233–236 and accompanying text (discussing limited liability that attends uncivil obedience).
  • 371
    • 84930254674 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • James C. Scott, Domination and the Arts of Resistance 105 (1990) [hereinafter Scott, Arts of Resistance].
    • James C. Scott, Domination and the Arts of Resistance 105 (1990) [hereinafter Scott, Arts of Resistance].
  • 372
    • 84930254675 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • James C. Scott, Weapons of the Weak 26 (1985) (suggesting in some cases “symbolic compliance” with despised norm may be maximized in order to minimize “actual” compliance).
    • James C. Scott, Weapons of the Weak 26 (1985) (suggesting in some cases “symbolic compliance” with despised norm may be maximized in order to minimize “actual” compliance).
  • 373
    • 84930254676 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scott, Arts of Resistance, supra note 247, at 105
    • Scott, Arts of Resistance, supra note 247, at 105
  • 374
    • 84930254677 scopus 로고
    • “The fourth rule [of power , tactics] is: Make the enemy live up to their own book of rules. You can kill them with this, for they can no more obey their own rules than the Christian church can live up to Christianity.”
    • Saul D. Alinsky, Rules for Radicals: A Practical Primer for Realistic Radicals 128 (1971) (“The fourth rule [of power tactics] is: Make the enemy live up to their own book of rules. You can kill them with this, for they can no more obey their own rules than the Christian church can live up to Christianity.”).
    • (1971) Rules For , pp. 128
    • Alinsky, S.D.1
  • 375
    • 80455163077 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Evolution and Ideology of Global Constitutionalism
    • 1163
    • David S. Law & Mila Versteeg, The Evolution and Ideology of Global Constitutionalism, 99 Calif. L. Rev. 1163, 1191 (2011).
    • (2011) Calif. L. Rev , vol.99 , pp. 1191
    • Law, D.S.1    Versteeg, M.2
  • 376
    • 84930254678 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We bracket here many complexities regarding the precise boundaries of, and relationships between, the “first-generation” and “second-generation” concepts
    • We bracket here many complexities regarding the precise boundaries of, and relationships between, the “first-generation” and “second-generation” concepts
  • 377
    • 84858265399 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • observing these , “two sets of rights can neither logically nor practically be separated in watertight compartments”
    • Philip Alston & Ryan Goodman, International Human Rights 285 (2012) (observing these “two sets of rights can neither logically nor practically be separated in watertight compartments”).
    • (2012) International Human Rights , pp. 285
    • Alston, P.1    Goodman, R.2
  • 378
    • 84930254679 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra notes 32–35 and accompanying text (setting out these examples).
    • supra notes 32–35 and accompanying text (setting out these examples).
  • 379
    • 84930254680 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Markovits, supra note 9. Markovits’s essay, which was inspired by the antiglobal-ization protests of the mid-2000s, presciently anticipated the Occupy Wall Street movement. (speculating about “growing prominence” of disobedience concerned more with democratic legitimacy and accountability than with liberal rights).
    • Markovits, supra note 9. Markovits’s essay, which was inspired by the antiglobal-ization protests of the mid-2000s, presciently anticipated the Occupy Wall Street movement. (speculating about “growing prominence” of disobedience concerned more with democratic legitimacy and accountability than with liberal rights).
  • 380
    • 84930254681 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • More specifically, democratic disobedience, “when it is justified, pursues processes rather than outcomes, employs coercion only in destabilizing ways, and serves momentary coalitions rather than entrenched constituencies.”
    • More specifically, democratic disobedience, “when it is justified, pursues processes rather than outcomes, employs coercion only in destabilizing ways, and serves momentary coalitions rather than entrenched constituencies.”
  • 381
    • 84930254682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Piven & Cloward, Weight of the Poor, supra note 34 (suggesting each of these objectives).
    • Piven & Cloward, Weight of the Poor, supra note 34 (suggesting each of these objectives).
  • 382
    • 84930254683 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Soc’y for Personality & Soc. Psychol., Are Conservatives More Obedient and Agreeable than Their Liberal Counterparts?, ScienceDaily (June 27, 2014), on file with the Columbia , Law Review) (“Historically, conservatives are viewed as being more obedient and more respectful of leadership. Whereas, liberals tend to be associated with protests and blatant acts of rebellion.”).
    • Soc’y for Personality & Soc. Psychol., Are Conservatives More Obedient and Agreeable than Their Liberal Counterparts?, ScienceDaily (June 27, 2014), http://www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2014/06/140627113048.htm (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (“Historically, conservatives are viewed as being more obedient and more respectful of leadership. Whereas, liberals tend to be associated with protests and blatant acts of rebellion.”).
  • 384
    • 84930254684 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • reviewing evidence that “right-wing authoritarians,” who tend to be conservative, exhibit high degree of submission to established authorities
    • reviewing evidence that “right-wing authoritarians,” who tend to be conservative, exhibit high degree of submission to established authorities
  • 385
    • 84930245841 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2d ed. 2002) (arguing conservatives have “strict father” , morality while liberals have “nurturant parent” morality)
    • George Lakof, Moral Politics: How Liberals and Conservatives Think 65–140 (2d ed. 2002) (arguing conservatives have “strict father” morality while liberals have “nurturant parent” morality)
    • Moral Politics: How Liberals , pp. 65-140
    • Lakof, G.1
  • 386
    • 84930248575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Basic
    • 421, finding people who endorse values of conformity and tradi, tion tend to be conservative).
    • Shalom H. Schwartz et al., Basic Personal Values, Core Political Values, and Voting: A Longitudinal Analysis, 31 Pol. Psychol. 421, 444–46 (2010) (finding people who endorse values of conformity and tradition tend to be conservative).
    • (2010) Pol. , vol.31 , pp. 444-446
    • Schwartz, S.H.1
  • 387
    • 34248997229 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Jonathan Haidt, The New Synthesis in Moral Psychology, 316 Science 998, 1001 (2007). According to Haidt: The current triggers of the Authority/subversion foundation... include anything that is construed as an act of obedience, disobedience, respect, disrespect, submission, or rebellion, with regard to authorities perceived to be legitimate.... [I]t is much easier for the political right to build on this foundation than it is for the left, which often defines itself in part by its opposition to hierarchy, inequality, and power. Note
  • 388
    • 84930254686 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jonathan Haidt, The Righteous Mind: Why Good People Are Divided by Politics and
    • Jonathan Haidt, The Righteous Mind: Why Good People Are Divided by Politics and
  • 389
    • 84930254687 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Religion 168 (2013) [hereinafter Haidt, Righteous Mind].
    • Religion 168 (2013) [hereinafter Haidt, Righteous Mind].
  • 390
    • 84930254688 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • 261Katherine Beckett & Theodore Sasson, The Politics of Injustice 48 (2d ed. 2004) (“Conservatives [in the 1960s] identified the civil rights movement—and, in particular, the philosophy of civil disobedience—as a leading cause of crime.”) Note
  • 391
    • 84930254689 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Wil Mara, Civil Unrest in the 1960s: Riots and Their Aftermath 47 (2010) (“[Conservatives] have little patience for those who practice civil disobedience. In their minds breaking the law is breaking the law....”); Russell Hittinger, Resisting the Sovereign, 3 Te x. Rev. L. & Pol. Note
  • 392
    • 84930254690 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (“[T]here is almost nothing favorable to be said about civil disobedience from conservative quarters....”)
    • (“[T]here is almost nothing favorable to be said about civil disobedience from conservative quarters....”)
  • 393
    • 84930242138 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dec. 1990) (unpublished manuscript, on file with the Columbia Law Review) , (stating civil disobedience “has rarely been used by conservative social movements”
    • Abigail A. Fuller, Conflict Resolution and Conservative Ideology: The Use of Civil Disobedience by Operation Rescue (Dec. 1990) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://www.colorado.edu/conflict/full_text_search/AllCRCDocs/90-1.htm (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (stating civil disobedience “has rarely been used by conservative social movements”).
    • Conflict
    • Fuller, A.A.1
  • 394
    • 84972011394 scopus 로고
    • ofering examples of civil disobedience undertaken by , conservatives).
    • Lynn Robert Buzzard & Paula Campbell, Holy Disobedience: When Christians Must Resist the State 1–20 (1984) (ofering examples of civil disobedience undertaken by conservatives).
    • (1984) Holy Disobedience: When Christians Must , pp. 1-20
    • Buzzard, L.R.1    Campbell, P.2
  • 395
    • 0042059167 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Past as Authority and as Social Critic: Stabilizing and
    • 352Terrence J. McDonald ed., 1996) (observing reform tactics that exploit legal system’s need for formality and generality and “employ the norms and procedures of , the system against itself” may be seen as accepting, at deeper level, “ideological legitimacy of the system as a whole”
    • Cf. Robert W. Gordon, The Past as Authority and as Social Critic: Stabilizing and Destabilizing Functions of History in Legal Argument, in The Historic Turn in the Human Sciences 339, 352 (Terrence J. McDonald ed., 1996) (observing reform tactics that exploit legal system’s need for formality and generality and “employ the norms and procedures of the system against itself” may be seen as accepting, at deeper level, “ideological legitimacy of the system as a whole”).
    • In the Historic Turn in the Human , pp. 339
    • Gordon, C.F.1
  • 396
    • 84930254693 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Haidt, Righteous Mind, supra note 260, at 86
    • Haidt, Righteous Mind, supra note 260, at 86
  • 397
    • 67649207602 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mysteries of Morality
    • (discussing significance , of third-party moral condemnation)
    • Peter DeScioli & Robert Kurzban, Mysteries of Morality, 112 Cognition 281 (2009) (discussing significance of third-party moral condemnation)
    • (2009) Cognition , vol.112 , pp. 281
    • Descioli, P.1    Kurzban, R.2
  • 398
    • 84868153786 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral Reputation:
    • discussing evolutionary and cognitive bases of humans’ desire to secure good moral reputation).
    • Dan Sperber & Nicolas Baumard, Moral Reputation: An Evolutionary and Cognitive Perspective, 27 Mind & Language 495 (2012) (discussing evolutionary and cognitive bases of humans’ desire to secure good moral reputation).
    • (2012) Mind & Language , vol.27 , pp. 495
    • Sperber, D.1    Baumard, N.2
  • 399
    • 84930254694 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This hypothesis may break down at the extreme right end of the ideological spectrum, where individuals are deeply alienated from the prevailing legal order and lesslikely to accept law’s claim to legitimate authority.
    • This hypothesis may break down at the extreme right end of the ideological spectrum, where individuals are deeply alienated from the prevailing legal order and less likely to accept law’s claim to legitimate authority.
  • 400
    • 84930254695 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • While much of the social-psychological literature on morality addresses liberals and conservatives rather than Democrats and Republicans, the contemporary correlations of liberal–Democrat and conservative–Republican are sufficiently strong to apply the literature’s insights to party politics. Note
  • 401
    • 84930254696 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Alan I. Abramowitz, The Disappearing Center 139 (2010) (“The overwhelming majority of House and Senate Democrats are liberals, and the overwhelming majority of House and Senate Republicans are conservatives.”) Note
  • 402
    • 84930254697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Robert S. Erikson et al., Public Opinion in the States: A Quarter Century of Change and Stability, in Public Opinion in State Politics 229, 238 (Jefrey E. Cohen ed., 2006) (“It is approaching common knowledge that the United States is becoming increasingly polarized in terms of the party-ideology connection.”). Note
  • 403
    • 84930254698 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra Part II.B.4, notes 96–102 and accompanying text (exploring these developments).
    • supra Part II.B.4, notes 96–102 and accompanying text (exploring these developments).
  • 404
    • 84930254699 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Other examples of uncivil obedience that we have discussed, such as the speed-limit protest, are not readily identifiable in partisan or ideological terms.
    • Other examples of uncivil obedience that we have discussed, such as the speed-limit protest, are not readily identifiable in partisan or ideological terms.
  • 405
    • 84930243656 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • When the Law Is Not One’s Own: A Case for
    • 317, discussing “historical elements that have led to civil disobedience’s undoing in the United States
    • Barbara B. LaBossiere, When the Law Is Not One’s Own: A Case for Violent Civil Disobedience, 19 Pub. Af. Q. 317, 317 (2005) (discussing “historical elements that have led to civil disobedience’s undoing in the United States”)
    • (2005) Pub. Af. Q. , vol.19 , pp. 317
    • Labossiere, B.B.1
  • 406
    • 84930240247 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note, at 85, 85 (“The most striking characteristic of civil disobedience is its irrelevance to the , problems of today.”).
    • Herbert J. Storing, The Case Against Civil Disobedience, in Civil Disobedience in Focus, supra note 10, at 85, 85 (“The most striking characteristic of civil disobedience is its irrelevance to the problems of today.”).
    • The Case against Civil Disobedience, in Civil Disobedience in Focus , pp. 10
    • Storing, H.J.1
  • 407
    • 84930254700 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brownlee, P Civil Disobedience, supra note 6
    • Brownlee, P Civil Disobedience, supra note 6
  • 408
    • 84930254701 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • “Some theorists maintain that civil disobedience is an outdated, overanalysed notion that little reflects current forms of political activism....”).
    • “Some theorists maintain that civil disobedience is an outdated, overanalysed notion that little reflects current forms of political activism....”).
  • 409
    • 84930254702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Cf. Markovits, supra note 9, at 1901 (“The civil rights movement—and the rights revolution more generally—represented the heyday of liberal disobedience.”). Note
  • 410
    • 84930254703 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    •  Developing this argument and citing protests against Vietnam War, nuclear weapons, and globalization as examples of issues not amenable to liberal disobedience Note
  • 411
    • 84930254704 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Brownlee, Civil Disobedience, supra note 6 (citing environment, animal rights, nuclear disarmament, globalization, and foreign policy as issues at fore of contemporary activist agenda that do not focus on individuals’ basic rights). Note


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.