메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 91, Issue 4, 2013, Pages 749-780

Legal realism untamed

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84875531427     PISSN: 00404411     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (60)

References (127)
  • 1
    • 0039567711 scopus 로고
    • Easy Cases
    • note
    • Frederick Schauer, Easy Cases, 58 S. Cal. L. Rev. 399, 407 (1985) [hereinafter, Schauer, Easy Cases].
    • (1985) S. Cal. L. Rev. , vol.58
    • Schauer, F.1
  • 4
    • 84936135622 scopus 로고
    • Legal Realism Now
    • note
    • Joseph William Singer, Legal Realism Now, 76 Calif. L. Rev. 465, 475-95 (1988) (reviewing Laura Kalman, Legal Realism at Yale: 1927-1960 (1986) and maintaining that Realism recognizes that, because the state defines transactional rules, law is implicated in every transaction). Others understand it as the ancestor of modern methodologically sophisticated empirical legal studies.
    • (1988) Calif. L. Rev. , vol.76
    • Singer, J.W.1
  • 5
    • 0001567226 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political Science and the New Legal Realism: A Case of Unfortunate Interdisciplinary Ignorance
    • note
    • See Frank B. Cross, Political Science and the New Legal Realism: A Case of Unfortunate Interdisciplinary Ignorance, 92 Nw. U. L. Rev. 251, 256-57 (1997) (noting the connection between Realism and the modern attitudinalist model of judicial decision making)
    • (1997) Nw. U. L. Rev. , vol.92
    • Cross, F.B.1
  • 6
    • 79955881983 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Toward a New Legal Realism
    • note
    • Daniel A. Farber, Toward a New Legal Realism, 68 U. Chi. L. Rev. 279, 302 (2001) (reviewing Behavioral Law and Economics (Cass R. Sunstein ed., 2000) (drawing the connection between Realism and contemporary law and economics)
    • (2001) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.68
    • Farber, D.A.1
  • 7
    • 79955881983 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Toward a New Legal Realism
    • note
    • Daniel A. Farber, Toward a New Legal Realism, 68 U. Chi. L. Rev. 279, 302 (2001) (reviewing Behavioral Law and Economics (Cass R. Sunstein ed., 2000) (drawing the connection between Realism and contemporary law and economics)
    • (2001) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.68
    • Farber, D.A.1
  • 8
    • 79955881983 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Toward a New Legal Realism
    • note
    • Daniel A. Farber, Toward a New Legal Realism, 68 U. Chi. L. Rev. 279, 302 (2001) (reviewing Behavioral Law and Economics (Cass R. Sunstein ed., 2000) (drawing the connection between Realism and contemporary law and economics)
    • (2001) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.68
    • Farber, D.A.1
  • 9
    • 0011322694 scopus 로고
    • A Realistic Jurisprudence-The Next Step
    • note
    • Karl N. Llewellyn, A Realistic Jurisprudence-The Next Step, 30 Colum. L. Rev. 431, 444-57 (1930) [hereinafter, Llewellyn, A Realistic Jurisprudence].
    • (1930) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.30
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 10
    • 84875537835 scopus 로고
    • Some Thoughts Suggested by the Restatements, Particularly of Contracts, Agency, and Trusts
    • note
    • See William Twining, Karl Llewellyn and the Realist Movement 32 (1973) (quoting a letter from Arthur Corbin observing that actual legal rules differed from the rules "in print"); see also Nathan Isaacs, Some Thoughts Suggested by the Restatements, Particularly of Contracts, Agency, and Trusts, 8 Am. L. Sch. Rev. 424, 428 (1936) (referring to "dry rules").
    • (1936) Am. L. Sch. Rev. , vol.8
    • Isaacs, N.1
  • 11
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • note
    • H.L.A. Hart accused the Realists of seeing rules solely as predictions and not as internalized guides or bases for criticism, H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law 137-38 (Penelope A. Bulloch & Joseph Raz eds., 2d ed. 1994).
    • (1994) The Concept of Law , pp. 137-138
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 12
    • 34547369602 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • People tend to believe their own descriptions of most things to be realistic. Consequently, the capitalization of Legal Realism designates a school of thought rather than an attribute. Moreover, the capitalization distinguishes Legal Realism as a school of thought about law from various perspectives characterized as realist in meta ethics, metaphysics, and other branches of philosophy. The distinction is important, because realism in philosophy identifies positions supporting the existence of mind-independent entities, and thus of mind-independent reality. See, e.g., Lynne Rudder Baker, The Metaphysics of Everyday Life: An Essay in Practical Realism (2007) (offering a realist position in metaphysics).
    • (2007) The Metaphysics of Everyday Life: An Essay in Practical Realism
    • Baker, L.R.1
  • 14
    • 84875483408 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In saying "logically entailed, " I refer not to deduction, the process by which particular outcomes are generated by a general rule, but to subsumption, pursuant to which decision makers decide whether a particular act or event is included within a rule. The judge or police officer deciding whether an automobile traveling at eighty miles per hour is violating the sixty-five-milesper-hour speed limit begins with the particular observation and then assesses whether the particular falls under-is subsumed by-the rule. She does not begin with the rule and then determine which particular outcomes might, in the abstract, be deduced from that rule.
  • 15
    • 85059272713 scopus 로고
    • Classification of Rights and Wrongs (Part I)
    • note
    • "Law, considered as a science, consists of certain principles or doctrines. To have such a mastery of these as to be able to apply them with constant facility and certainty to the ever-tangled skein of human affairs, is what constitutes a true lawyer.... " C.C. Langdell, A Selection of Cases on the Law of Contracts vi (1871). Langdell recognized, however, that the identification of such principles and doctrines was a matter of induction from particular decisions and not deduction from abstract generalities, see C.C. Langdell, Classification of Rights and Wrongs (Part I), 13 Harv. L. Rev. 537 (1900).
    • (1900) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.13 , pp. 537
    • Langdell, C.C.1
  • 16
    • 42549157941 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Irony of Judicial Elections
    • note
    • see also David E. Pozen, The Irony of Judicial Elections, 108 Colum. L. Rev. 265, 273 (2008) (describing traditional formalism as committed to judicial decisions based on "legal materials alone").
    • (2008) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.108
    • Pozen, D.E.1
  • 18
    • 0041920520 scopus 로고
    • The Artificial Reason of the Law or: What Lawyers Know
    • note
    • For explication of Coke's idea, see Charles Fried, The Artificial Reason of the Law or: What Lawyers Know, 60 Texas L. Rev. 35 (1981).
    • (1981) Texas L. Rev. , vol.60 , pp. 35
    • Fried, C.1
  • 19
    • 0005921984 scopus 로고
    • note
    • See, for example, Matthew Hale, The History of the Common Law of England (Charles M. Gray ed., 1971) (1713), although Hale was more receptive than Blackstone or Coke to the influence of nonlegal factors on legal decisions.
    • (1971) The History of the Common Law of England
    • Hale, M.1
  • 21
    • 84875524907 scopus 로고
    • German Legal Philosophy
    • note
    • John M. Zane, German Legal Philosophy, 16 Mich. L. Rev. 287, 338 (1918) ("Every judicial act resulting in a judgment consists of a pure deduction. ").
    • (1918) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.16
    • Zane, J.M.1
  • 23
    • 78650756127 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legal Formalism and Legal Realism: What Is the Issue?
    • note
    • Brian Leiter, Legal Formalism and Legal Realism: What Is the Issue?, 16 Legal Theory 111, 112 (2010) (stressing that Realism challenges even sophisticated versions of formalist accounts of adjudication).
    • (2010) Legal Theory , vol.16
    • Leiter, B.1
  • 24
    • 0040223919 scopus 로고
    • Remarks on the Theory of Appellate Decision and the Rules or Canons About How Statutes Are to Be Construed
    • note
    • Karl N. Llewellyn, Remarks on the Theory of Appellate Decision and the Rules or Canons About How Statutes Are to Be Construed, 3 Vand. L. Rev. 395, 395-96 (1950).
    • (1950) Vand. L. Rev. , vol.3 , pp. 395-396
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 25
    • 0003893980 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although Llewellyn had his particularistic and fact-and case-specific moments (see, e.g., Karl N. Llewellyn, The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals, 59-61, 121-25, 206-08 (1969) (discussing "Situation-Sense").
    • (1969) The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 26
    • 0039039964 scopus 로고
    • The Judgment Intuitive: The Function of the "Hunch" in Judicial Decision
    • note
    • See, e.g., Joseph C. Hutcheson, Jr., The Judgment Intuitive: The Function of the "Hunch" in Judicial Decision, 14 Cornell L.Q. 274, 284 (1929) (describing the fact-based nature of a judge's initial reaction to a case).
    • (1929) Cornell L.Q. , vol.14
    • Hutcheson Jr., J.C.1
  • 27
    • 80051484603 scopus 로고
    • The Psychologic Study of Judicial Opinions
    • Theodore Schroeder, The Psychologic Study of Judicial Opinions, 6 Calif. L. Rev. 89, 89 (1918).
    • (1918) Calif. L. Rev. , vol.6 , pp. 89
    • Schroeder, T.1
  • 29
    • 0002254318 scopus 로고
    • The Selection of Disputes for Litigation
    • note
    • The scholarship on the selection effect is vast, the canonical modern source being George L. Priest & Benjamin Klein, The Selection of Disputes for Litigation, 13 J. Legal Stud. 1 (1984).
    • (1984) J. Legal Stud. , vol.13 , pp. 1
    • Priest, G.L.1    Klein, B.2
  • 30
    • 0002254318 scopus 로고
    • The Selection of Disputes for Litigation
    • note
    • The scholarship on the selection effect is vast, the canonical modern source being George L. Priest & Benjamin Klein, The Selection of Disputes for Litigation, 13 J. Legal Stud. 1 (1984).
    • (1984) J. Legal Stud. , vol.13 , pp. 1
    • Priest, G.L.1    Klein, B.2
  • 31
    • 0040223920 scopus 로고
    • In Defense of an Unsystematic Science of Law
    • Max Radin, In Defense of an Unsystematic Science of Law, 51 Yale L.J. 1269, 1271 (1942).
    • (1942) Yale L.J. , vol.51
    • Radin, M.1
  • 32
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • note
    • H.L.A. Hart accused the Realists of seeing rules solely as predictions and not as internalized guides or bases for criticism, H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law 137-38 (Penelope A. Bulloch & Joseph Raz eds., 2d ed. 1994).
    • (1994) The Concept of Law , pp. 137-138
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 33
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • note
    • H.L.A. Hart accused the Realists of seeing rules solely as predictions and not as internalized guides or bases for criticism, H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law 137-38 (Penelope A. Bulloch & Joseph Raz eds., 2d ed. 1994).
    • (1994) The Concept of Law , pp. 137-138
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 34
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • note
    • H.L.A. Hart accused the Realists of seeing rules solely as predictions and not as internalized guides or bases for criticism, H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law 137-38 (Penelope A. Bulloch & Joseph Raz eds., 2d ed. 1994).
    • (1994) The Concept of Law , pp. 137-138
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 35
    • 33947096855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Court's Agenda-and the Nation's
    • note
    • And especially in the Supreme Court, where the ideological valence of the issues and the miniscule number of cases actually decided presents the selection effect at its acme. See generally Frederick Schauer, The Court's Agenda-and the Nation's, 120 Harv. L. Rev. 4 (2006) (analyzing the Supreme Court's decisional agenda).
    • (2006) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.120 , pp. 4
    • Schauer, F.1
  • 36
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • note
    • H.L.A. Hart accused the Realists of seeing rules solely as predictions and not as internalized guides or bases for criticism, H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law 137-38 (Penelope A. Bulloch & Joseph Raz eds., 2d ed. 1994).
    • (1994) The Concept of Law , pp. 137-138
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 37
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • note
    • H.L.A. Hart accused the Realists of seeing rules solely as predictions and not as internalized guides or bases for criticism, H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law 137-38 (Penelope A. Bulloch & Joseph Raz eds., 2d ed. 1994).
    • (1994) The Concept of Law , pp. 137-138
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 38
    • 0001567226 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political Science and the New Legal Realism: A Case of Unfortunate Interdisciplinary Ignorance
    • note
    • See Frank B. Cross, Political Science and the New Legal Realism: A Case of Unfortunate Interdisciplinary Ignorance, 92 Nw. U. L. Rev. 251, 256-57 (1997) (noting the connection between Realism and the modern attitudinalist model of judicial decision making)
    • (1997) Nw. U. L. Rev. , vol.92
    • Cross, F.B.1
  • 39
    • 84894870094 scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Edward Stevens Robinson, Law and the Lawyers 167-91 (1935) (arguing that the concepts of jurisprudence must be assessed under the lens of psychological and sociological analyses).
    • (1935) Law and the Lawyers , pp. 167-191
    • Robinson, E.S.1
  • 40
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • note
    • H.L.A. Hart accused the Realists of seeing rules solely as predictions and not as internalized guides or bases for criticism, H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law 137-38 (Penelope A. Bulloch & Joseph Raz eds., 2d ed. 1994).
    • (1994) The Concept of Law , pp. 137-138
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 42
    • 85016690251 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Law, Morality, and the Guidance of Conduct
    • note
    • (see, e.g., Scott J. Shapiro, Law, Morality, and the Guidance of Conduct, 6 Legal Theory 127 (2000) (defending exclusive positivism), we understand law as a domain of sources and inputs substantially narrower than those otherwise accepted within the society for, say, moral or policy decisions (on the contours of that domain).
    • (2000) Legal Theory , vol.6 , pp. 127
    • Shapiro, S.J.1
  • 45
    • 0010002830 scopus 로고
    • Langdell's Orthodoxy
    • note
    • See Thomas C. Grey, Langdell's Orthodoxy, 45 U. Pitt. L. Rev. 1, 40-41 (1983) (discussing the use of conceptual order and formality in the classical legal system).
    • (1983) U. Pitt. L. Rev. , vol.45
    • Grey, T.C.1
  • 46
    • 0010002830 scopus 로고
    • Langdell's Orthodoxy
    • note
    • See Thomas C. Grey, Langdell's Orthodoxy, 45 U. Pitt. L. Rev. 1, 40-41 (1983) (discussing the use of conceptual order and formality in the classical legal system).
    • (1983) U. Pitt. L. Rev. , vol.45
    • Grey, T.C.1
  • 47
    • 0010002830 scopus 로고
    • Langdell's Orthodoxy
    • note
    • See Thomas C. Grey, Langdell's Orthodoxy, 45 U. Pitt. L. Rev. 1, 40-41 (1983) (discussing the use of conceptual order and formality in the classical legal system).
    • (1983) U. Pitt. L. Rev. , vol.45
    • Grey, T.C.1
  • 49
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • note
    • H.L.A. Hart accused the Realists of seeing rules solely as predictions and not as internalized guides or bases for criticism, H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law 137-38 (Penelope A. Bulloch & Joseph Raz eds., 2d ed. 1994).
    • (1994) The Concept of Law , pp. 137-138
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 51
    • 33748926618 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Ronald Dworkin, Justice in Robes 41-43 (2006) [hereinafter Dworkin, Justice in Robes].
    • (2006) Justice in Robes , pp. 41-43
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 52
    • 33748926618 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Ronald Dworkin, Justice in Robes 41-43 (2006) [hereinafter Dworkin, Justice in Robes].
    • (2006) Justice in Robes , pp. 41-43
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 53
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • note
    • H.L.A. Hart accused the Realists of seeing rules solely as predictions and not as internalized guides or bases for criticism, H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law 137-38 (Penelope A. Bulloch & Joseph Raz eds., 2d ed. 1994).
    • (1994) The Concept of Law , pp. 137-138
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 55
    • 77950669193 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The "Juristes Inquiets": Legal Classicism and Criticism in Early Twentieth-Century France
    • note
    • See Marie-Claire Belleau, The "Juristes Inquiets": Legal Classicism and Criticism in Early Twentieth-Century France, 1997 Utah L. Rev. 379, 393-94 (distinguishing Gény as critical of traditionalists who elevated legal constructs to the level of objective reality).
    • (1997) Utah L. Rev.
    • Belleau, M.-C.1
  • 56
    • 37949040759 scopus 로고
    • The German Free Law Movement as the Source of American Legal Realism
    • James E. Herget & Stephen Wallace, The German Free Law Movement as the Source of American Legal Realism, 73 Va. L. Rev. 399 (1987).
    • (1987) Va. L. Rev. , vol.73 , pp. 399
    • Herget, J.E.1    Wallace, S.2
  • 57
    • 37949040759 scopus 로고
    • The German Free Law Movement as the Source of American Legal Realism
    • James E. Herget & Stephen Wallace, The German Free Law Movement as the Source of American Legal Realism, 73 Va. L. Rev. 399 (1987).
    • (1987) Va. L. Rev. , vol.73 , pp. 399
    • Herget, J.E.1    Wallace, S.2
  • 58
    • 0004264409 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., The Common Law 1 (Mark D. Howe ed., Harv. Univ. Press 1963) (1st ed. 1881).
    • (1963) The Common Law , pp. 1
    • Holmes Jr., O.W.1
  • 59
    • 84875548546 scopus 로고
    • Introduction
    • note
    • This is not the occasion for extended analysis of legal technical meaning, but it is worth emphasizing that plain meaning is not necessarily ordinary meaning. There can be technical meanings widely understood in a specialized domain by members of a linguistic (sub)community. In that case the meanings would be plain, albeit technical. "Meson" has a plain meaning for physicists, and "gesso" for painters, although such terms do not appear in ordinary language. And the same holds true for law, where the plain meanings of "habeas corpus, " "quantum meruit, " "tying arrangement, " "curtesy, " and "interrogatory" are no part of ordinary language. On the relationship between ordinary and technical language in general, see Charles E. Caton, Introduction, in Philosophy and Ordinary Language v, vii-xi (Charles E. Caton ed., 1963).
    • (1963) Philosophy and Ordinary Language
    • Caton, C.E.1
  • 60
    • 84875548546 scopus 로고
    • Introduction
    • note
    • This is not the occasion for extended analysis of legal technical meaning, but it is worth emphasizing that plain meaning is not necessarily ordinary meaning. There can be technical meanings widely understood in a specialized domain by members of a linguistic (sub)community. In that case the meanings would be plain, albeit technical. "Meson" has a plain meaning for physicists, and "gesso" for painters, although such terms do not appear in ordinary language. And the same holds true for law, where the plain meanings of "habeas corpus, " "quantum meruit, " "tying arrangement, " "curtesy, " and "interrogatory" are no part of ordinary language. On the relationship between ordinary and technical language in general, see Charles E. Caton, Introduction, in Philosophy and Ordinary Language v, vii-xi (Charles E. Caton ed., 1963).
    • (1963) Philosophy and Ordinary Language
    • Caton, C.E.1
  • 61
    • 78650756127 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legal Formalism and Legal Realism: What Is the Issue?
    • note
    • Brian Leiter, Legal Formalism and Legal Realism: What Is the Issue?, 16 Legal Theory 111, 112 (2010) (stressing that Realism challenges even sophisticated versions of formalist accounts of adjudication).
    • (2010) Legal Theory , vol.16
    • Leiter, B.1
  • 62
    • 0002021491 scopus 로고
    • The Bill of Rights and the Fourteenth Amendment
    • note
    • Akhil Reed Amar, The Bill of Rights and the Fourteenth Amendment, 101 Yale L.J. 1193, 1233 (1992) (same).
    • (1992) Yale L.J. , vol.101
    • Amar, A.R.1
  • 63
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • note
    • H.L.A. Hart accused the Realists of seeing rules solely as predictions and not as internalized guides or bases for criticism, H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law 137-38 (Penelope A. Bulloch & Joseph Raz eds., 2d ed. 1994).
    • (1994) The Concept of Law , pp. 137-138
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 66
    • 84861882302 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • "No person shall be elected to the office of the President more than twice, and no person who has held the office of President, or acted as President, for more than two years of a term to which some other person was elected President shall be elected to the office of the President more than once. " U.S. Const. amend. XXII, § 1.
    • U.S. Const. amend
  • 67
    • 84861882302 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • "No person shall be elected to the office of the President more than twice, and no person who has held the office of President, or acted as President, for more than two years of a term to which some other person was elected President shall be elected to the office of the President more than once. " U.S. Const. amend. XXII, § 1.
    • U.S. Const. amend
  • 70
    • 78650756127 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legal Formalism and Legal Realism: What Is the Issue?
    • note
    • Brian Leiter, Legal Formalism and Legal Realism: What Is the Issue?, 16 Legal Theory 111, 112 (2010) (stressing that Realism challenges even sophisticated versions of formalist accounts of adjudication).
    • (2010) Legal Theory , vol.16
    • Leiter, B.1
  • 71
    • 0003893980 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although Llewellyn had his particularistic and fact-and case-specific moments (see, e.g., Karl N. Llewellyn, The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals, 59-61, 121-25, 206-08 (1969) (discussing "Situation-Sense").
    • (1969) The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 72
    • 0003893980 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although Llewellyn had his particularistic and fact-and case-specific moments (see, e.g., Karl N. Llewellyn, The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals, 59-61, 121-25, 206-08 (1969) (discussing "Situation-Sense").
    • (1969) The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 73
    • 0001567226 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political Science and the New Legal Realism: A Case of Unfortunate Interdisciplinary Ignorance
    • note
    • See Frank B. Cross, Political Science and the New Legal Realism: A Case of Unfortunate Interdisciplinary Ignorance, 92 Nw. U. L. Rev. 251, 256-57 (1997) (noting the connection between Realism and the modern attitudinalist model of judicial decision making)
    • (1997) Nw. U. L. Rev. , vol.92
    • Cross, F.B.1
  • 74
    • 0039039964 scopus 로고
    • The Judgment Intuitive: The Function of the "Hunch" in Judicial Decision
    • note
    • See, e.g., Joseph C. Hutcheson, Jr., The Judgment Intuitive: The Function of the "Hunch" in Judicial Decision, 14 Cornell L.Q. 274, 284 (1929) (describing the fact-based nature of a judge's initial reaction to a case).
    • (1929) Cornell L.Q. , vol.14
    • Hutcheson Jr., J.C.1
  • 76
    • 0003893980 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although Llewellyn had his particularistic and fact-and case-specific moments (see, e.g., Karl N. Llewellyn, The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals, 59-61, 121-25, 206-08 (1969) (discussing "Situation-Sense").
    • (1969) The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 78
    • 0003893980 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although Llewellyn had his particularistic and fact-and case-specific moments (see, e.g., Karl N. Llewellyn, The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals, 59-61, 121-25, 206-08 (1969) (discussing "Situation-Sense").
    • (1969) The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 79
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • note
    • H.L.A. Hart accused the Realists of seeing rules solely as predictions and not as internalized guides or bases for criticism, H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law 137-38 (Penelope A. Bulloch & Joseph Raz eds., 2d ed. 1994).
    • (1994) The Concept of Law , pp. 137-138
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 80
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • note
    • H.L.A. Hart accused the Realists of seeing rules solely as predictions and not as internalized guides or bases for criticism, H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law 137-38 (Penelope A. Bulloch & Joseph Raz eds., 2d ed. 1994).
    • (1994) The Concept of Law , pp. 137-138
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 81
    • 0003893980 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although Llewellyn had his particularistic and fact-and case-specific moments (see, e.g., Karl N. Llewellyn, The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals, 59-61, 121-25, 206-08 (1969) (discussing "Situation-Sense").
    • (1969) The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 82
    • 0003893980 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although Llewellyn had his particularistic and fact-and case-specific moments (see, e.g., Karl N. Llewellyn, The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals, 59-61, 121-25, 206-08 (1969) (discussing "Situation-Sense").
    • (1969) The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 83
    • 0346278481 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Descending Trail: Holmes' Path of the Law One Hundred Years Later
    • note
    • Kansas even makes it quasi-official. Kan. Stat. Ann. § 8-1560d (2010). On the divergence between posted and real speed limits as exemplifying the gap between law on the books and law in action, see Albert W. Alschuler, The Descending Trail: Holmes' Path of the Law One Hundred Years Later, 49 Fla. L. Rev. 353, 367-68 (1997) (noting a five-mile-per-hour divergence).
    • (1997) Fla. L. Rev. , vol.49
    • Alschuler, A.W.1
  • 84
    • 0346617081 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Doing Without Speed Limits
    • Robert E. King & Cass R. Sunstein, Doing Without Speed Limits, 79 B.U. L. Rev. 155 (1999).
    • (1999) B.U. L. Rev. , vol.79 , pp. 155
    • King, R.E.1    Sunstein, C.R.2
  • 85
    • 0003893980 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although Llewellyn had his particularistic and fact-and case-specific moments (see, e.g., Karl N. Llewellyn, The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals, 59-61, 121-25, 206-08 (1969) (discussing "Situation-Sense").
    • (1969) The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 86
    • 0003893980 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although Llewellyn had his particularistic and fact-and case-specific moments (see, e.g., Karl N. Llewellyn, The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals, 59-61, 121-25, 206-08 (1969) (discussing "Situation-Sense").
    • (1969) The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 87
    • 0003893980 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although Llewellyn had his particularistic and fact-and case-specific moments (see, e.g., Karl N. Llewellyn, The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals, 59-61, 121-25, 206-08 (1969) (discussing "Situation-Sense").
    • (1969) The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 88
    • 0346617081 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Doing Without Speed Limits
    • Robert E. King & Cass R. Sunstein, Doing Without Speed Limits, 79 B.U. L. Rev. 155 (1999).
    • (1999) B.U. L. Rev. , vol.79 , pp. 155
    • King, R.E.1    Sunstein, C.R.2
  • 91
    • 84875483734 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • 15 U.S.C. §§ 77a-i (2010).
    • (2010) U.S.C. , vol.15
  • 92
    • 84875509207 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See 17 C.F.R. § 230.461 (2012) (allowing for acceleration of the effective date of registration by written request).
    • (2012) C.F.R. , vol.17
  • 93
    • 0006227418 scopus 로고
    • Vicarious Liability for Fraud on Securities Markets: Theory and Evidence
    • note
    • See Jennifer H. Arlen & William J. Carney, Vicarious Liability for Fraud on Securities Markets: Theory and Evidence, 1992 U. Ill. L. Rev. 691, 711 n.94 (describing non-acceleration where indemnification is guaranteed).
    • (1992) U. Ill. L. Rev. , Issue.94
    • Arlen, J.H.1    Carney, W.J.2
  • 94
    • 84875545625 scopus 로고
    • 354 U.S. 467 (1964).
    • (1964) U.S. , vol.354 , pp. 467
  • 96
    • 84978886622 scopus 로고
    • 465 U.S. 330 (1984).
    • (1984) U.S. , vol.465 , pp. 330
  • 97
    • 84978886622 scopus 로고
    • 465 U.S. 330 (1984).
    • (1984) U.S. , vol.465 , pp. 330
  • 98
    • 16544374531 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cheap Smokes: State and Federal Responses to Tobacco Tax Evasion over the Internet
    • note
    • See Christopher Banthin, Cheap Smokes: State and Federal Responses to Tobacco Tax Evasion over the Internet, 14 Health Matrix 325, 335 (2004) (arguing that practical and legal obstacles to enforcement inhibit collection of use taxes on out-of-state purchases).
    • (2004) Health Matrix , vol.14
    • Banthin, C.1
  • 99
    • 0009400594 scopus 로고
    • Balls, Strikes, and Norms: Rule Violations and Normative Rules Among Baseball Umpires
    • note
    • And elsewhere. Those fond of legal examples from sports and games may recognize the exact phenomenon under discussion in the so-called phantom tag in baseball, where umpires genuinely internalize and apply a rule about tagging a runner that differs from the rule on the books. So too with the former distinction between American and National League strike zones, a distinction nowhere to be found in the official rules of baseball. See David W. Rainey & Janet D. Larsen, Balls, Strikes, and Norms: Rule Violations and Normative Rules Among Baseball Umpires, 10 J. Sport & Exercise Psych. 75, 77, 79 (1988) (stating that umpires routinely called the strike zone more than two inches lower than the definition in the official rules in spite of the fact that 94% of those surveyed knew the official definition).
    • (1988) J. Sport & Exercise Psych. , vol.10
    • Rainey, D.W.1    Larsen, J.D.2
  • 101
    • 0003993772 scopus 로고
    • note
    • At least on the assumption that the United States is an especially nonformal legal environment. See P.S. Atiyah & Robert S. Summers, Form and Substance in AngloAmerican Law (1987) (maintaining that the American legal system is more substantive than formal).
    • (1987) Form and Substance in AngloAmerican Law
    • Atiyah, P.S.1    Summers, R.S.2
  • 102
    • 33645300021 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Aharon Barak, Purposive Interpretation in Law 88 (Sari Bashi trans., 2005) (defining purposive interpretation and arguing for its pervasive use).
    • (2005) Purposive Interpretation in Law , pp. 88
    • Barak, A.1
  • 103
    • 78649559545 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Below the Surface: Comparing Legislative History Usage by the House of Lords and the Supreme Court
    • note
    • See James J. Brudney, Below the Surface: Comparing Legislative History Usage by the House of Lords and the Supreme Court, 85 Wash. U. L. Rev. 1 passim (2007) (contrasting American and British uses of legislative proceedings in statutory interpretation).
    • (2007) Wash. U. L. Rev. , vol.85 , pp. 1
    • Brudney, J.J.1
  • 104
    • 82855164333 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Caleb Nelson, Statutory Interpretation 108-226 (2011) (surveying and explaining traditional canons of statutory interpretation); 2A Norman J. Singer & J.D. Shambie Singer, Sutherland's Statutes and Statutory Construction § 45:13 (7th ed. 2007) (providing an introduction to canons and aids of statutory construction).
    • (2011) Statutory Interpretation , pp. 108-226
    • Nelson, C.1
  • 105
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • note
    • H.L.A. Hart accused the Realists of seeing rules solely as predictions and not as internalized guides or bases for criticism, H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law 137-38 (Penelope A. Bulloch & Joseph Raz eds., 2d ed. 1994).
    • (1994) The Concept of Law , pp. 137-138
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 107
  • 108
    • 0001567226 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political Science and the New Legal Realism: A Case of Unfortunate Interdisciplinary Ignorance
    • note
    • See Frank B. Cross, Political Science and the New Legal Realism: A Case of Unfortunate Interdisciplinary Ignorance, 92 Nw. U. L. Rev. 251, 256-57 (1997) (noting the connection between Realism and the modern attitudinalist model of judicial decision making)
    • (1997) Nw. U. L. Rev. , vol.92
    • Cross, F.B.1
  • 109
    • 0010184932 scopus 로고
    • On the distinction between the logic of decision and the logic of justification, see Richard A. Wasserstrom, The Judicial Decision 26-31 (1961).
    • (1961) The Judicial Decision , pp. 26-31
    • Wasserstrom, R.A.1
  • 110
    • 0003893980 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although Llewellyn had his particularistic and fact-and case-specific moments (see, e.g., Karl N. Llewellyn, The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals, 59-61, 121-25, 206-08 (1969) (discussing "Situation-Sense").
    • (1969) The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 111
    • 0003893980 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although Llewellyn had his particularistic and fact-and case-specific moments (see, e.g., Karl N. Llewellyn, The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals, 59-61, 121-25, 206-08 (1969) (discussing "Situation-Sense").
    • (1969) The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 112
    • 0003893980 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although Llewellyn had his particularistic and fact-and case-specific moments (see, e.g., Karl N. Llewellyn, The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals, 59-61, 121-25, 206-08 (1969) (discussing "Situation-Sense").
    • (1969) The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 113
    • 0003893980 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although Llewellyn had his particularistic and fact-and case-specific moments (see, e.g., Karl N. Llewellyn, The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals, 59-61, 121-25, 206-08 (1969) (discussing "Situation-Sense").
    • (1969) The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 115
    • 33748926618 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Ronald Dworkin, Justice in Robes 41-43 (2006) [hereinafter Dworkin, Justice in Robes].
    • (2006) Justice in Robes , pp. 41-43
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 116
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • note
    • H.L.A. Hart accused the Realists of seeing rules solely as predictions and not as internalized guides or bases for criticism, H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law 137-38 (Penelope A. Bulloch & Joseph Raz eds., 2d ed. 1994).
    • (1994) The Concept of Law , pp. 137-138
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 117
    • 84875529728 scopus 로고
    • Desuetude, Due Process, and the Scarlet Letter Revisited
    • note
    • Corey R. Chivers, Desuetude, Due Process, and the Scarlet Letter Revisited, 1992 Utah L. Rev. 449, 451 (noting that the doctrine of desuetude voids a statute).
    • (1992) Utah L. Rev.
    • Chivers, C.R.1
  • 118
    • 77951918389 scopus 로고
    • Bacchus Imports, Ltd. v. Dias
    • note
    • See Bacchus Imports, Ltd. v. Dias, 468 U.S. 263, 276 (1984) (rejecting as unconstitutionally protectionist Hawaii's understandable attempt to assist the pineapple wine industry by exempting it from otherwise applicable taxes).
    • (1984) U.S. , vol.468
  • 121
    • 84875524030 scopus 로고
    • United States v. Locke
    • note
    • E.g., United States v. Locke, 471 U.S. 84, 96 (1985) (enforcing the exact literal meaning of a "prior to December 31" filing deadline).
    • (1985) U.S. , vol.471
  • 122
    • 84863469193 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ring v. Arizona
    • note
    • E.g., Ring v. Arizona, 536 U.S. 584, 613 (2002).
    • (2002) U.S. , vol.536
  • 123
    • 33748926618 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Ronald Dworkin, Justice in Robes 41-43 (2006) [hereinafter Dworkin, Justice in Robes].
    • (2006) Justice in Robes , pp. 41-43
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 124
    • 33748926618 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Ronald Dworkin, Justice in Robes 41-43 (2006) [hereinafter Dworkin, Justice in Robes].
    • (2006) Justice in Robes , pp. 41-43
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 125
    • 0001417422 scopus 로고
    • The Path of the Law
    • note
    • Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457, 461 (1897) (stressing the importance of "[t]he prophecies of what the courts will do in fact").
    • (1897) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.10
    • Holmes Jr., O.W.1
  • 126
    • 0001417422 scopus 로고
    • The Path of the Law
    • note
    • Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457, 461 (1897) (stressing the importance of "[t]he prophecies of what the courts will do in fact").
    • (1897) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.10
    • Holmes Jr., O.W.1
  • 127
    • 0000565909 scopus 로고
    • Bargaining in the Shadow of the Law: The Case of Divorce
    • note
    • Cf. Robert H. Mnookin & Lewis Kornhauser, Bargaining in the Shadow of the Law: The Case of Divorce, 88 Yale L.J. 950 (1979) (discussing the effects of divorce law on formal and informal bargaining between the parties occurring outside of the courtroom).
    • (1979) Yale L.J. , vol.88 , pp. 950
    • Mnookin, R.H.1    Kornhauser, L.2


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.