메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 123, Issue 5, 2010, Pages 1214-1246

Inducing moral deliberation: On the occasional virtues of fog

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 77955502667     PISSN: 0017811X     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (60)

References (136)
  • 2
    • 77955491571 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 64-66
    • See id. at 64-66.
  • 3
    • 77955493216 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 58
    • Id. at 58.
  • 4
    • 77955479377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id
    • id.
  • 5
    • 77955483964 scopus 로고
    • Of course, rules are not always simple to decipher. For instance, they may make reference to highly technical terms or to objective factors that are nonetheless difficult to discern, or, as is sometimes claimed about the rules of the tax code, they may be so voluminous as to stymie straightforward application, ("[S]tandards may be more transparent than more precise defaults."), 3 S. CAL. INTERDISC. LJ. 1
    • Of course, rules are not always simple to decipher. For instance, they may make reference to highly technical terms or to objective factors that are nonetheless difficult to discern, or, as is sometimes claimed about the rules of the tax code, they may be so voluminous as to stymie straightforward application. See Ian Ayres, Preliminary Thoughts on Optimal Tailoring of Contractual Rules, 3 S. CAL. INTERDISC. LJ. 1, 8 (1993) ("[S]tandards may be more transparent than more precise defaults.").
    • (1993) Preliminary Thoughts on Optimal Tailoring of Contractual Rules , vol.8
    • Ayres, I.1
  • 6
    • 77955496783 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Sullivan, supra note 1, at 62
    • See, e.g., Sullivan, supra note 1, at 62.
  • 9
    • 77955475843 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 79 OR. L. REV., 53-56, 58-59, (discussing the difficulties of the uncertainty that standards introduce but denying that standards should be altogether eschewed)
    • See, e.g., Russell B. Korobkin, Behavioral Analysis and Legal Form.: Rules vs. Standards Revisited, 79 OR. L. REV. 23, 37-38, 53-56, 58-59 (2000) (discussing the difficulties of the uncertainty that standards introduce but denying that standards should be altogether eschewed).
    • (2000) Behavioral Analysis and Legal Form.: Rules vs. Standards Revisited , vol.23 , pp. 37-38
    • Korobkin, R.B.1
  • 11
    • 77955478845 scopus 로고
    • 78 YALE LJ., (arguing that the vagueness of U.C.C. section 2-302 is necessary to address tensions in modern contract law)
    • See, e.g., M.P Ellinghaus, In Defense of Unconscionability, 78 YALE LJ. 757, 814-15 (1969) (arguing that the vagueness of U.C.C. section 2-302 is necessary to address tensions in modern contract law).
    • (1969) Defense of Unconscionability , vol.757 , pp. 814-815
    • Ellinghaus, M.P.1
  • 12
    • 77955488867 scopus 로고
    • 115 U. PA. L. REV., 504, 516, (criticizing U.C.C. section 2-302 for its reliance on subjective interpretation and application by judges, and the difficulty of determining whether a contract is invalid)
    • See, e.g., Arthur Allen Leff, Unconscionability and the Code - The Emperor's New Clause, 115 U. PA. L. REV. 485, 487, 504, 516 (1967) (criticizing U.C.C. section 2-302 for its reliance on subjective interpretation and application by judges, and the difficulty of determining whether a contract is invalid).
    • (1967) Unconscionability and the Code - The Emperor's New Clause , vol.485-487
    • Leff, A.A.1
  • 13
    • 77955498308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See State Farm Mut. Auto. Ins. Co. v. Campbell, 538 U.S. 408, 425 (2003) (finding that, as a matter of substantive due process, punitive damages generally should not exceed nine times the amount of compensatory damages)
    • See State Farm Mut. Auto. Ins. Co. v. Campbell, 538 U.S. 408, 425 (2003) (finding that, as a matter of substantive due process, punitive damages generally should not exceed nine times the amount of compensatory damages).
  • 14
    • 77955479750 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 417, 427
    • See id. at 417, 427.
  • 15
    • 77955474091 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 128 S. Ct. 2605 (2008)
    • 128 S. Ct. 2605 (2008).
  • 16
    • 77955479552 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 2627. The same passage fallaciously equated unpredictable awards with "eccentrically high" awards
    • Id. at 2627. The same passage fallaciously equated unpredictable awards with "eccentrically high" awards.
  • 17
    • 77955486274 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 18
    • 77955477530 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (citation omitted), 10 HARV. L. REV.
    • Id. (citation omitted) (citing Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., The Path of the Law, 10 HARV. L. REV. 457, 459 (1897)).
    • The Path of the Law , vol.457-459 , pp. 1897
    • Holmes Jr., O.W.1
  • 19
    • 77955487261 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 538 U.S. 408
    • 538 U.S. 408.
  • 20
    • 77955500284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 425
    • See id. at 425.
  • 21
    • 77955479551 scopus 로고
    • 97 YALE L.J., (discussing how the "indeterminacy" of some constitutional norms and their interpretation constructively interact with and feed both political movements and more informal but transformative forms of citizen engagement and dialogue)
    • See Frank Michelman, Law's Republic, 97 YALE L.J. 1493, 1528-1532 (1988) (discussing how the "indeterminacy" of some constitutional norms and their interpretation constructively interact with and feed both political movements and more informal but transformative forms of citizen engagement and dialogue).
    • (1988) Law's Republic , vol.1493 , pp. 1528-1532
    • Michelman, F.1
  • 22
    • 77955488680 scopus 로고
    • 100 HARV. L. REV., (discussing how balancing tests engage Justices in transparent forms of public reason and how open constitutional discourse by Justices engages the public)
    • Frank I. Michelman, The Supreme Court, 1985 Term-Foreword: Traces of Self-Government, 100 HARV. L. REV. 4, 34-36 (1986) (discussing how balancing tests engage Justices in transparent forms of public reason and how open constitutional discourse by Justices engages the public).
    • (1986) The Supreme Court, 1985 Term-Foreword: Traces of Self-Government , vol.4 , pp. 34-36
    • Michelman, F.I.1
  • 23
    • 77955493215 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sullivan, supra note 1, at 67-69
    • Sullivan, supra note 1, at 67-69.
  • 24
    • 77955488496 scopus 로고
    • 89 HARV. L. REV., 1764-66, 1771-73, (focusing on judges' and officials' applications of standards)
    • cf. Duncan Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, 89 HARV. L. REV. 1685, 1752-53, 1764-66, 1771-1773 (1976) (focusing on judges' and officials' applications of standards).
    • (1976) Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication , vol.1685 , pp. 1752-1753
    • Kennedy, D.1
  • 25
    • 0042704575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 106 YALE L.J., (presenting a nuanced discussion of and proposals for fashioning procedural directives and legal ethical norms in order to spark and reflect greater levels of democratic deliberation and dialogue about the form and timing of civil rights litigation, whether undertaken by individual litigants or by groups)
    • But cf. William B. Rubenstein, Divided We Litigate: Addressing Disputes Among Group Members and Lawyers in Civil Rights Campaigns, 106 YALE L.J. 1623, 1659, 1670-1675 (1997) (presenting a nuanced discussion of and proposals for fashioning procedural directives and legal ethical norms in order to spark and reflect greater levels of democratic deliberation and dialogue about the form and timing of civil rights litigation, whether undertaken by individual litigants or by groups).
    • (1997) Divided We Litigate: Addressing Disputes Among Group Members and Lawyers in Civil Rights Campaigns , vol.1623 , Issue.1659 , pp. 1670-1675
    • Rubenstein, W.B.1
  • 26
    • 21144449654 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 103 MICH. L. REV., 1811, (discussing William Muir's advocacy of self-conscious reflection by police officers and the ability of community policing programs to provide the public a role in stimulating police reflection)
    • David Alan Sklansky, Police and Democracy 103 MICH. L. REV. 1699, 1776, 1811 (2005) (discussing William Muir's advocacy of self-conscious reflection by police officers and the ability of community policing programs to provide the public a role in stimulating police reflection).
    • (2005) Police and Democracy , vol.1699 , pp. 1776
    • Sklansky, D.A.1
  • 27
    • 77955496083 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Harmful thoughts
    • 65-67, 69-73, (arguing that the vagueness of certain decision rules, such as those of duress, facilitates their fair application by judges while precluding their wrongful exploitation by citizens)
    • MEIR DAN-COHEN, Decision Rules and Conduct Rules: On Acoustic Separation in Criminal Law, in HARMFUL THOUGHTS 37, 48-49, 65-67, 69-73 (2002) (arguing that the vagueness of certain decision rules, such as those of duress, facilitates their fair application by judges while precluding their wrongful exploitation by citizens).
    • (2002) Decision Rules and Conduct Rules: On Acoustic Separation in Criminal Law , vol.37 , pp. 48-49
    • Dan-Cohen, M.1
  • 28
    • 33644600511 scopus 로고
    • 25-39, (discussing historical origins of the rules of the road and the effects of right-hand versus left-hand rules for various forms of traffic). Some evidence suggests "keep right" results in more deaths than "keep left." Peter Kincaid speculates that this may be partly because driving is safer for right-handed drivers if their right (dominant) eye is closer to the center of the road and because most drivers are right-handed)
    • PETER KINCAID, THE RULE OF THE ROAD: AN INTERNATIONAL GUIDE TO HISTORY AND PRACTICE 2-8, 25-39 (1986) (discussing historical origins of the rules of the road and the effects of right-hand versus left-hand rules for various forms of traffic). Some evidence suggests "keep right" results in more deaths than "keep left." Peter Kincaid speculates that this may be partly because driving is safer for right-handed drivers if their right (dominant) eye is closer to the center of the road and because most drivers are right-handed.
    • (1986) The Rule of the Road: An International Guide to History and Practice , pp. 2-8
    • Kincaid, P.1
  • 29
    • 77955507296 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 25-39
    • See id. at 25-39.
  • 30
    • 77955481287 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • describing the Shared Space movement's theory, method, and goals and evaluating its progress
    • See SABINE LUTZ, SHARED SPACE INST., SHARED SRACE - FINAL EVALUATION AND RESULTS 3-19 (2009), http://www.sharedspace.eu/en/publications/downloads/doc- download/20-shared-space-final-evaluation-long (describing the Shared Space movement's theory, method, and goals and evaluating its progress).
    • (2009) Shared Space Inst., Shared Srace - Final Evaluation and Results , pp. 3-19
    • Lutz, S.1
  • 33
    • 77955498137 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Shared Space Institute,(last visited Jan. 31, 2010)
    • Shared Space Institute, http://www.sharedspace.eu/en/home (last visited Jan. 31, 2010).
  • 34
    • 77955480614 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Hamilton-Baillie & Jones, supra note 2 2, at 44-45
    • See Hamilton-Baillie & Jones, supra note 2 2, at 44-45.
  • 35
    • 84902926356 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (quoting an interview with Monderman in Der Spiegel) (internal quotation marks omitted)
    • JEFF MAPES, PEDALING REVOLUTION: HOW CYCLISTS ARE CHANGING AMERICAN CITIES 71 n.i (2009) (quoting an interview with Monderman in Der Spiegel) (internal quotation marks omitted).
    • (2009) Pedaling Revolution: How Cyclists are Changing American Cities , vol.71 , Issue.1
    • Mapes, J.1
  • 36
    • 77955476947 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • CSS TRANSPORT FUTURES GROUP, TRAVEL IS GOOD 30 (2008)
    • CSS TRANSPORT FUTURES GROUP, TRAVEL IS GOOD 30 (2008).
  • 40
    • 77955502995 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hamilton-Baillie, supra note 25, at 169-178
    • Hamilton-Baillie, supra note 25, at 169-178
  • 41
    • 77955479043 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hamilton-Baillie & Jones, supra note 22, at 46-47
    • Hamilton-Baillie & Jones, supra note 22, at 46-47.
  • 42
    • 77955474857 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • CAL. VEH, CODE § 23152(b) (West 2000)
    • CAL. VEH, CODE § 23152(b) (West 2000).
  • 43
    • 77955499173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF CONTRACTS § 208 (1981)
    • See, e.g., RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF CONTRACTS § 208 (1981).
  • 44
    • 77955499536 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also XJ.C.C. § 2-302(1) (2005)
    • See also XJ.C.C. § 2-302(1) (2005).
  • 45
    • 77955489821 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF CONTRACTS § 205
    • RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF CONTRACTS § 205.
  • 46
    • 77955490005 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also U.C.C. § 1-304
    • see also U.C.C. § 1-304.
  • 47
    • 77955493401 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FED. R. CIV. P. II(b)
    • FED. R. CIV. P. II(b).
  • 48
    • 77955481472 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although it is not my focus, some of my argument also applies, indirectly, to standards using nonevaluative terms. A standard requiring the use of "thick" roof materials rather than specifying a minimum width in inches or centimeters will require a contractor to consider the purposes of the roof, the stresses it will fall under, and, most importantly, what risks are reasonable for those housed underneath the roof to bear. A more specific rule is less likely to invite this form of deliberation
    • Although it is not my focus, some of my argument also applies, indirectly, to standards using nonevaluative terms. A standard requiring the use of "thick" roof materials rather than specifying a minimum width in inches or centimeters will require a contractor to consider the purposes of the roof, the stresses it will fall under, and, most importantly, what risks are reasonable for those housed underneath the roof to bear. A more specific rule is less likely to invite this form of deliberation.
  • 49
    • 77955483613 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Ayres, supra note 5, at 13 ("Simple standards needlessly interject ambiguity into the law")
    • See, e.g., Ayres, supra note 5, at 13 ("Simple standards needlessly interject ambiguity into the law").
  • 50
    • 77955478468 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • In a deep and reflective article discussing provisions of domestic and international law that prohibit "cruel," "inhuman," "inhumane," and "degrading" punishment, Jeremy Waldron celebrates the use of standards as opposed to rules because standards may improve the "quality of moral argument" by calling on us "to reflect upon and argue about whether a given practice is degrading or inhuman." Jeremy Waldron, Cruel, Inhuman, and Degrading Treatment: The Words Themselves 7-8 (N.Y. Univ. Sch. of Law Pub. Law & Legal Theory Research Paper Series, Working Paper No. 08-36, 2008). available at http://papers.ssrn.com/s0l3/papers.cfm?abstract-id=1278604. I am in utter agreement with him on this point. We may, however, part ways with respect to how the deliberation is to proceed or what its target is. He contends that we should consult "some shared sense of positive morality, some 'common conscience' we already share" rather than engaging our "own critical views on what counts as inhuman and degrading."
    • (2008) Cruel, Inhuman, and Degrading Treatment: The Words Themselves , pp. 7-8
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 51
    • 77955483781 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 42
    • Id. at 42.
  • 52
    • 77955500105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • In my view, when applying legal standards to a situation, whether for purposes of compliance, evaluation, or adjudication, we must not only consult the shared social interpretation of that standard, but we must also invoke our own critical understanding and ask what the proper moral interpretation of the standard is. Often no shared understanding has developed, and we must engage our critical capacities to begin to form one. But, in any case, what matters most is to identify the morally correct interpretation and, in time, strive to move the shared understanding so it squares with our critical sense of what we are actually committed to. We should investigate the shared understanding not because it settles the matter, but in order to calibrate the distance between it and our critical views for purposes of social evaluation, to develop a view of which interpretation is consistent with the current reasonable expectations of others, and to ensure our interpretation does not stray too far from where other aspects of our democratic commitments would situate us.
  • 53
    • 84872858817 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Immoral, conflicting, and redundant promises
    • I discuss the interest in being a particularized subject of respect and its connection to an under-discussed aspect of partiality in Seana Valentine Shiffrin, Rahul Kumar et al. eds., forthcoming, on file with the Harvard Law School Library
    • I discuss the interest in being a particularized subject of respect and its connection to an under-discussed aspect of partiality in Seana Valentine Shiffrin, Immoral, Conflicting, and Redundant Promises, in REASONS AND RECOGNITION: ESSAYS FOR T.M. SCANLON (Rahul Kumar et al. eds., forthcoming 2010) (on file with the Harvard Law School Library).
    • (2010) Reasons and Recognition: Essays for T.M. Scanlon
  • 55
    • 62649095907 scopus 로고
    • 82 CAL. L. REV., (remarking that a definitional dispute about a concept like art may "enrich[] the wider debate in which the disputed concept is deployed")
    • Cf. Jeremy Waldron, Vagueness in Law and Language: Some Philosophical Issues, 82 CAL. L. REV. 509, 531-532 (1994) (remarking that a definitional dispute about a concept like art may "enrich[] the wider debate in which the disputed concept is deployed").
    • (1994) Vagueness in Law and Language: Some Philosophical Issues , vol.509 , pp. 531-532
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 56
    • 84984685267 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am in substantial agreement with Mark Greenberg that legal pronouncements do not, ipso facto, determine the content of law, although they may have significant bearing on its content, 10 LEGAL THEORY, 190-197, (arguing that although law practices may contribute to the content of law, they cannot alone be fully determinative)
    • I am in substantial agreement with Mark Greenberg that legal pronouncements do not, ipso facto, determine the content of law, although they may have significant bearing on its content. See Mark Greenberg, How Facts Make Law, 10 LEGAL THEORY 157, 162-66, 190-197 (2004) (arguing that although law practices may contribute to the content of law, they cannot alone be fully determinative).
    • (2004) How Facts Make Law , vol.157 , pp. 162-166
    • Greenberg, M.1
  • 57
    • 80055030062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (UCLA Sch. of Law Pub. Law & Legal Theory Research Paper Series, Research Paper No. 08-107), (describing how the legal significance of a statute or opinion may differ from what its explicit language says or connotes)
    • Mark Greenberg, The Standard Picture and Its Discontents 31-33 (UCLA Sch. of Law Pub. Law & Legal Theory Research Paper Series, Research Paper No. 08-107, 2008), available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract-id= 1103569 (describing how the legal significance of a statute or opinion may differ from what its explicit language says or connotes).
    • (2008) The Standard Picture and Its Discontents , pp. 31-33
    • Greenberg, M.1
  • 58
    • 77955486903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • My claim resides in a space similar to that occupied by many popular constitutionalists although my claim is both more modest in one respect and broader in others. It is more modest in that my position is weaker than that of some popular constitutionalists. My position is that popular interpretation makes a significant contribution to our understanding of law, but I do not make the stronger claim that it does or should completely or largely determine the content of law. My focus is broader in that I take the popular contribution to law to range over the entire domain of law (or at least that encapsulated or communicated by standards) and not solely over constitutional law
    • My claim resides in a space similar to that occupied by many popular constitutionalists although my claim is both more modest in one respect and broader in others. It is more modest in that my position is weaker than that of some popular constitutionalists. My position is that popular interpretation makes a significant contribution to our understanding of law, but I do not make the stronger claim that it does or should completely or largely determine the content of law. My focus is broader in that I take the popular contribution to law to range over the entire domain of law (or at least that encapsulated or communicated by standards) and not solely over constitutional law.
  • 59
    • 77955485366 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • This argument extends the claim often made about leaving interpretive room in legislative language to allow for agency delegation to the case of citizens and the law more generally. See, e.g., SCHAUER, supra note 6, at 194-96 (discussing the advantages of making room for the contributions and insights of future decisionmakers). In this respect, it resembles some of Charles Sabel's and others' arguments about delegating back to citizens, but my argument emphasizes the moral dimensions and advantages of such delegation, whereas he and his coauthors emphasize the prudential and cooperative benefits of delegation to smaller groups of citizens.
  • 62
    • 20744456588 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a longer discussion of the relationship between freedom of thought, thought development, and associations, 99 Nw. U. L. REV.
    • For a longer discussion of the relationship between freedom of thought, thought development, and associations, see Seana Valentine Shiffrin, Essay, What Is Really Wrong with Compelled Association?, 99 Nw. U. L. REV. 839 (2005).
    • (2005) Essay, What Is Really Wrong with Compelled Association? , pp. 839
    • Shiffrin, S.V.1
  • 63
    • 33846833905 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a related discussion, 120 HARV. L. REV., 747-748, which examines the application of moral norms to corporate behavior in the promissory context
    • For a related discussion, see Seana Valentine Shiffrin, The Divergence of Contract and Promise, 120 HARV. L. REV. 708, 747-748 (2007), which examines the application of moral norms to corporate behavior in the promissory context.
    • (2007) The Divergence of Contract and Promise , pp. 708
    • Shiffrin, S.V.1
  • 64
    • 6944228215 scopus 로고
    • Thus, I disagree with the sentiment that "[p]rivate citizens ⋯ are not fundamentally empowered by law; they are merely required to obey its commands.", 82 CAL. L. REV., 492
    • Thus, I disagree with the sentiment that "[p]rivate citizens ⋯ are not fundamentally empowered by law; they are merely required to obey its commands." Robert C. Post, Reconceptualizing Vagueness: Legal Rules and Social Orders, 82 CAL. L. REV. 491, 492 (1994).
    • (1994) Reconceptualizing Vagueness: Legal Rules and Social Orders , pp. 491
    • Post, R.C.1
  • 65
    • 77955475040 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 29 C.RR. § 1604.11(a) (2009)
    • 29 C.RR. § 1604.11(a) (2009).
  • 66
    • 77955475046 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The progress made through such consciousness-raising may sometimes be facilitated by the complementary assistance of rules and more concrete guidelines, especially in early days. Cf. infra p. 1240
    • The progress made through such consciousness-raising may sometimes be facilitated by the complementary assistance of rules and more concrete guidelines, especially in early days. Cf. infra p. 1240.
  • 67
    • 77955507981 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • emphasis omitted
    • THOMAS NAGEL, THE LAST WORD 19 (1997) (emphasis omitted).
    • (1997) The Last Word , vol.19
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 68
    • 77955476749 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed, this was Holmes's famous position: "[A] legal duty ⋯ is nothing but a prediction that if a man does or omits certain things he will be made to suffer in this or that way by judgment of the court⋯'' Holmes, supra note 15, at 458
    • Indeed, this was Holmes's famous position: "[A] legal duty ⋯ is nothing but a prediction that if a man does or omits certain things he will be made to suffer in this or that way by judgment of the court⋯'' Holmes, supra note 15, at 458.
  • 69
    • 77955498647 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The new palgrave dictionary of economics and the law
    • pag 587-588 (Peter Newman ed.), (using the examples of contra proferentem and penalty default rules)
    • See Ian Ayres, Default Rules for Incomplete Contracts, in I THE NEW PALGRAVE DICTIONARY OF ECONOMICS AND THE LAW 585, 587-588 (Peter Newman ed., 1998) (using the examples of contra proferentem and penalty default rules).
    • (1998) Default Rules for Incomplete Contracts , pp. 585
    • Ayres, I.1
  • 70
    • 77955498648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U.C.C. §2-305(1) (2005)
    • U.C.C. §2-305(1) (2005).
  • 71
    • 77955495361 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Ayres, supra note 47, at 587
    • See Ayres, supra note 47, at 587.
  • 72
    • 77955477519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ayres, supra note 5, at 11-12 (arguing that no default quantity would satisfy most parties)
    • Ayres, supra note 5, at 11-12 (arguing that no default quantity would satisfy most parties)
  • 74
    • 77955504042 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 9 Ex. 341, 156 Eng. Rep. 145 (1854)
    • 9 Ex. 341, 156 Eng. Rep. 145 (1854).
  • 75
    • 77955494299 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 151-152
    • Id. at 151-152.
  • 76
    • 77955506067 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ayres & Gertner, supra note 49, at 101-104 (discussing Hadley)
    • Ayres & Gertner, supra note 49, at 101-104 (discussing Hadley).
  • 78
    • 77955500283 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Penalty default standards could be used, however, to similar effect on the parties. See, e.g., Ayres, supra note 5, at 9-15. But depending on how hazy and open-ended the terms, their deployment might undermine one of the main motivations for using penalty defaults, namely, to save the judiciary from having to investigate and substitute judgment for the parties. One of the spurs to negotiate out of the penalty default rule is how clear it is that an untoward result will ensue if one does not.
  • 79
    • 77955506251 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Ayres & Gertner, supra note 49, at 97-100
    • See, e.g., Ayres & Gertner, supra note 49, at 97-100.
  • 80
    • 77955493578 scopus 로고
    • (Currin Shields ed., Library of Liberal Arts 1958), ("[As t]he first element of good government ⋯ being the virtue and intelligence of the human beings composing the community, the most important point of excellence which any form of government can possess is to promote the virtue and intelligence of the people ⋯")
    • See JOHN STUART MILL, CONSIDERATIONS ON REPRESENTATIVE GOVERNMENT 24-25 (Currin Shields ed., Library of Liberal Arts 1958) (1861) ("[As t]he first element of good government ⋯ being the virtue and intelligence of the human beings composing the community, the most important point of excellence which any form of government can possess is to promote the virtue and intelligence of the people ⋯").
    • (1861) Considerations on representative government , pp. 24-25
    • Mill, J.S.1
  • 82
    • 77955478266 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Shiffrin, supra note 41, at 714 (discussing a just society's dependence on a moral citizenry
    • Shiffrin, supra note 41, at 714 (discussing a just society's dependence on a moral citizenry).
  • 83
    • 77955498972 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Shiffrin, supra note 41 at, 710-719 (developing this position in greater depth)
    • See Shiffrin, supra note 41, at 710-719 (developing this position in greater depth).
  • 84
    • 0346403980 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 89 CAL. L. REV., 1251-52, 1269-70, 1285, (discussing use and effectiveness of persuasive techniques in recycling campaigns)
    • See Ann E. Carlson, Recycling Norms, 89 CAL. L. REV. 1231, 1251-52, 1269-70, 1285 (2001) (discussing use and effectiveness of persuasive techniques in recycling campaigns).
    • (2001) Recycling Norms , pp. 1231
    • Carlson, A.E.1
  • 85
    • 77955484468 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 319 U.S. 624 (1943)
    • 319 U.S. 624 (1943).
  • 86
    • 77955504215 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 430 U.S. 70s (1977)
    • 430 U.S. 70s (1977).
  • 88
    • 77955476040 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Shiffrin, supra note 40
    • see also Shiffrin, supra note 40.
  • 89
    • 77955482910 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This may seem like a strange claim given that these standards are legally enforceable: if one gets it wrong, a judge or jury may impose punishment or another remedy. True enough, but unlike pre-dictated content meant to be absorbed without deliberation, standards often allow for a range of acceptable alternative methods of compliance. Further, one may present one's reasons for one's interpretation to adjudicators who are open to persuasion
    • This may seem like a strange claim given that these standards are legally enforceable: if one gets it wrong, a judge or jury may impose punishment or another remedy. True enough, but unlike pre-dictated content meant to be absorbed without deliberation, standards often allow for a range of acceptable alternative methods of compliance. Further, one may present one's reasons for one's interpretation to adjudicators who are open to persuasion.
  • 90
    • 77955492123 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • This marks a related difference from the sort of deliberation induced by mandatory speech with opt-out provisions, such as the pledge (as well as similar provisions for prayer that have been struck down). One may think that all citizens should consider how they conceive of their relation to the state - whether that relation is one of fealty and whether it takes the same form as the state's conception of fealty. However, the pressure to deliberate feels objectionably coercive when it is exerted on these specified occasions in which one must register one's dissent in public, without much control over how that dissent is presented, and without any meaningful opportunity to discuss or explain one's position. Thus, I agree with Michael Seidman's criticism of the opt-out pledge, though I disagree that his criticism is properly targeted at Bamette's holding that the mandatory pledge is unconstitutional; rather, I think the criticism speaks in favor of taking Barnette further and treating the pledge in the same way that mandatory prayer has been handled.
  • 92
    • 77955504614 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Blasi & Shiffrin, supra note 60, at 449-53
    • see also Blasi & Shiffrin, supra note 60, at 449-53.
  • 93
    • 77955479548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 505 U.S. 833 (1992)
    • 505 U.S. 833 (1992).
  • 94
    • 77955505882 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 844
    • See id. at 844.
  • 95
    • 77955494478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., GA. CODE ANN. §§ 31-9A-3 to -4 (2009)
    • See, e.g., GA. CODE ANN. §§ 31-9A-3 to -4 (2009).
  • 96
    • 77955475458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LA. REV. STAT ANN. § 40:1299.35.6 (2008)
    • LA. REV. STAT ANN. § 40:1299.35.6 (2008).
  • 97
    • 77955495174 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MISS. CODE ANN. §§ 41-41-133, -35 (2009). A comprehensive list of the thirty-four states that impose mandatory counseling and the twenty-five states that impose a waiting period appears in GUTTMACHER INSTITUTE, available at
    • MISS. CODE ANN. §§ 41-41-133, -35 (2009). A comprehensive list of the thirty-four states that impose mandatory counseling and the twenty-five states that impose a waiting period appears in GUTTMACHER INSTITUTE, STATE POLICIES IN BRIEF: COUNSELING AND WAITING PERIODS FOR ABORTION (2010), available at http://www.guttmacher.org/statecenter/spibs/ spib-MWPA.pdf.
    • State Policies in Brief: Counseling and Waiting Periods for Abortion , vol.2010
  • 98
    • 77955485012 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although it is not aimed to encourage moral deliberation in particular, I have in mind the quite different design of the Federal Trade Commission's "Cooling Off" rule, which permits buyers in a door-to-door sales transaction (that is, buyers who have not sought out the sale and may, reasonably, be unfamiliar with the product) three business days to rescind the transaction in case, upon reflection, the transaction seems undesirable. See 16 C.F.R. § 429 (2009). Although buyers are afforded time to reconsider, they are neither required to wait three days to transact nor to take affirmative action to complete the transaction after three days
    • Although it is not aimed to encourage moral deliberation in particular, I have in mind the quite different design of the Federal Trade Commission's "Cooling Off" rule, which permits buyers in a door-to-door sales transaction (that is, buyers who have not sought out the sale and may, reasonably, be unfamiliar with the product) three business days to rescind the transaction in case, upon reflection, the transaction seems undesirable. See 16 C.F.R. § 429 (2009). Although buyers are afforded time to reconsider, they are neither required to wait three days to transact nor to take affirmative action to complete the transaction after three days.
  • 99
    • 77955492130 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 100
    • 77955495362 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Brief for Petitioners and Cross-Respondents, Casey, 505 U.S. 833 (Nos. 91-744, 91-902), 1992 WL 551419, at *16, *39~40
    • See Brief for Petitioners and Cross-Respondents, Casey, 505 U.S. 833 (Nos. 91-744, 91-902), 1992 WL 551419, at *16, *39~40.
  • 101
    • 0027019040 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sylvia A. Law, Abortion Compromise - Inevitable and Impossible, 1992 U. ILL. L. REV. 921, 940 (listing burdens of requirement)
    • Sylvia A. Law, Abortion Compromise - Inevitable and Impossible, 1992 U. ILL. L. REV. 921, 940 (listing burdens of requirement).
  • 102
    • 77955501541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Law, supra note 67, at 940 (noting that the requirements made false assumptions about women's decisionmaking processes)
    • See Law, supra note 67, at 940 (noting that the requirements made false assumptions about women's decisionmaking processes).
  • 103
    • 0026793285 scopus 로고
    • Evidence suggests that even minors take the decision whether to abort seriously and deliberate beforehand, 24 FAM. PLAN. PERSP., 205, (observing that in their study of 1500 abortion decisions by minors in states without parental notification requirements, "[a]ll minors reported that at least one person - a relative, a friend or a professional - had taken part in the decision process or had helped them arrange the abortion")
    • Evidence suggests that even minors take the decision whether to abort seriously and deliberate beforehand. See Stanley K. Henshaw & Kathryn Kost, Parental Involvement in Minors' Abortion Decisions, 24 FAM. PLAN. PERSP. 196, 205 (1992) (observing that in their study of 1500 abortion decisions by minors in states without parental notification requirements, "[a]ll minors reported that at least one person - a relative, a friend or a professional - had taken part in the decision process or had helped them arrange the abortion").
    • (1992) Kathryn Kost, Parental Involvement in Minors' Abortion Decisions , pp. 196
    • Henshaw, S.K.1
  • 104
    • 77955507816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • See Brief for Amicus Curiae American Psychological Ass'n in Support of Petitioners, Casey, 505 U.S. 833 (Nos. 91-744, 91-902), 1992 WL 12006 399, at *I8-20. It is not always inappropriate for the government to discourage the exercise of a right. For instance, the government might appropriately discourage protected racist speech, even in public fora. But discouragement of the exercise of a right is a delicate matter and must be done in ways that do not harass, imply repercussions for resisting the discouragement, or insult citizens who resist the discouragement by, for instance, suggesting they are incompetent or disloyal. It is one thing to discourage racist speech through general education campaigns or calls for tolerance; it is another thing to demand authors undergo racial sensitivity training on the eve of the publication of their racist book. I hope it is evident that I do not regard the parallel between having an abortion and engaging in racist speech as extending any further than the fact that both involve the exercise of a fundamental right in a way disfavored by many.
  • 105
    • 77955483780 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 497 U.S. 261 (1990)
    • 497 U.S. 261 (1990).
  • 106
    • 0027620521 scopus 로고
    • LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS., Summer, 219-220 (arguing that the Missouri law and other similar laws are penalty default rules because polls suggest that most people would prefer termination rather than life support in a variety of end-of-life situations)
    • See, e.g., James Lindgren, Death by Default, LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS., Summer 1993, at 185, 219-220 (arguing that the Missouri law and other similar laws are penalty default rules because polls suggest that most people would prefer termination rather than life support in a variety of end-of-life situations).
    • (1993) Death by Default , pp. 185
    • Lindgren, J.1
  • 107
    • 77955503161 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Cruzan, 497 U.S. at 282-283
    • See Cruzan, 497 U.S. at 282-283.
  • 108
    • 1842861892 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 59 SOC. SCI. & MED., (discussing some elderly patients' resistance to advance care directives because they prefer a nonstatic, dynamic decisionmaking procedure that more actively involves family members and more nuanced forms of trust in medical professionals)
    • See, e.g., Jane Seymour et al., Planning for the End of Life: The Views of Older People About Advance Care Statements, 59 SOC. SCI. & MED. 57, 63-66 (2004) (discussing some elderly patients' resistance to advance care directives because they prefer a nonstatic, dynamic decisionmaking procedure that more actively involves family members and more nuanced forms of trust in medical professionals).
    • (2004) Planning for the End of Life: The Views of Older People About Advance Care Statements , vol.57 , pp. 63-66
    • Seymour, J.1
  • 109
    • 0031020918 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 38 PSYCHOSOMATICS, (discussing literature on death denial and reporting a study in which seriously ill patients and their doctors largely lacked advance directives and failed to remember conversations about terminal care preferences)
    • See Lewis M. Cohen et al., Denying the Dying: Advance Directives and Dialysis Discontinuation, 38 PSYCHOSOMATICS 27, 29-31 (1997) (discussing literature on death denial and reporting a study in which seriously ill patients and their doctors largely lacked advance directives and failed to remember conversations about terminal care preferences).
    • (1997) Denying the Dying: Advance Directives and Dialysis Discontinuation , vol.27 , pp. 29-31
    • Cohen, L.M.1
  • 110
    • 0027183020 scopus 로고
    • 34 PSYCHOSOMATICS, (discussing denial phenomena even among those aware of the opportunity for advance directives and concluding "it may be unrealistic to expect healthy or chronically ill individuals to render binding agreements regarding life support," id. at 399)
    • Lewis M. Cohen et al., Patient Attitudes and Psychological Considerations in Dialysis Discontinuation, 34 PSYCHOSOMATICS 395, 398-399 (1993) (discussing denial phenomena even among those aware of the opportunity for advance directives and concluding "it may be unrealistic to expect healthy or chronically ill individuals to render binding agreements regarding life support," id. at 399).
    • (1993) Patient Attitudes and Psychological Considerations in Dialysis Discontinuation , vol.395 , pp. 398-399
    • Cohen, L.M.1
  • 112
    • 77955481863 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Seymour et al., supra note 74, at 63-66 (identifying factors other than denial that may account for reluctance to write advance care directives, including concern that one's views may change)
    • But see Seymour et al., supra note 74, at 63-66 (identifying factors other than denial that may account for reluctance to write advance care directives, including concern that one's views may change).
  • 113
    • 33947601737 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 29 SOC. HEALTH & ILLNESS, (critiquing methodology of some studies on denial and advance directives for apparently equating denial with failure to write advance directives rather than showing a causal relationship)
    • Camilla Zimmermann, Death Denial: Obstacle or Instrument for Palliative Care? An Analysis of Clinical Literature, 29 SOC. HEALTH & ILLNESS 297, 302-303 (2007) (critiquing methodology of some studies on denial and advance directives for apparently equating denial with failure to write advance directives rather than showing a causal relationship).
    • (2007) Death Denial: Obstacle or Instrument for Palliative Care? An Analysis of Clinical Literature , vol.297 , pp. 302-303
    • Zimmermann, C.1
  • 115
    • 0012547380 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I recognize this is complicated ground. Whether and to what degree sexual activity between adults and minors is harmful may depend upon the age difference, the gender of the participants, and the cultural setting, (2d ed.), Possibly, some relations for some minors in particular settings may be consensual and not harmful, but for many others these encounters may be psychologically traumatic and may also have long-lasting physical, social, and personal effects, for example those incurred from teen pregnancy
    • I recognize this is complicated ground. Whether and to what degree sexual activity between adults and minors is harmful may depend upon the age difference, the gender of the participants, and the cultural setting. See WILLIAM N. ESKRIDGE, JR. & NAN D. HUNTER, SEXUALITY, GENDER, AND THE LAW 158-163 (2d ed. 2004). Possibly, some relations for some minors in particular settings may be consensual and not harmful, but for many others these encounters may be psychologically traumatic and may also have long-lasting physical, social, and personal effects, for example those incurred from teen pregnancy.
    • (2004) Sexuality, Gender, and The Law , pp. 158-163
    • Eskridge Jr., W.N.1    Hunter, N.D.2
  • 116
    • 77955507286 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Oberman, supra note 76, at 704-706, 705 nn.6-9 (discussing literature on the risks of adolescent sexual activity). These harms are substantial enough to justify even those rule-like formulations that may preclude or deter less deleterious encounters among the willing
    • See Oberman, supra note 76, at 704-706, 705 nn.6-9 (discussing literature on the risks of adolescent sexual activity). These harms are substantial enough to justify even those rule-like formulations that may preclude or deter less deleterious encounters among the willing.
  • 117
    • 77955504450 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There may, however, be grounds for adjudicators or enforcement officers to apply a more standard-like norm (or decision "rule") when assessing guilt, level of culpability, or excuse. See DAN-COHEN, supra note 20, at 42-43, 58-62
    • There may, however, be grounds for adjudicators or enforcement officers to apply a more standard-like norm (or decision "rule") when assessing guilt, level of culpability, or excuse. See DAN-COHEN, supra note 20, at 42-43, 58-62.
  • 118
    • 0000444999 scopus 로고
    • 3 J. LEGAL STUD., (discussing the advantage of a clear, numerical speeding rule coupled with officer discretion to waive a ticket when the speeding driver is responding to an emergency)
    • see also Isaac Ehrlich & Richard A. Posner, An Economic Analysis of Legal Rulemaking, 3 J. LEGAL STUD. 257, 268 (1974) (discussing the advantage of a clear, numerical speeding rule coupled with officer discretion to waive a ticket when the speeding driver is responding to an emergency).
    • (1974) An Economic Analysis of Legal Rulemaking , vol.257 , pp. 268
    • Ehrlich, I.1    Posner, R.A.2
  • 119
    • 47349121009 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 121 HARV. L. REV. 1969, 2039, (discussing German legal doctrine that permits the general defense that even if the elements of a crime are satisfied, the conduct "was not sufficiently 'wrongful' to merit punishment")
    • See William J. Stuntz, Unequal Justice, 121 HARV. L. REV. 1969, 2039 (2008) (discussing German legal doctrine that permits the general defense that even if the elements of a crime are satisfied, the conduct "was not sufficiently 'wrongful' to merit punishment").
    • Unequal Justice , pp. 2008
    • Stuntz, W.J.1
  • 122
    • 77955474848 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Introduction to german law
    • Mathias Reimann & Joachim Zekoll eds., 2d ed.
    • Heribert Schumann, Criminal Law, in INTRODUCTION TO GERMAN LAW 387, 394-397 (Mathias Reimann & Joachim Zekoll eds., 2d ed. 2005).
    • (2005) Criminal Law , vol.387 , pp. 394-397
    • Schumann, H.1
  • 123
    • 77955490516 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Ehrlich & Posner, supra note 78, at 267-271
    • See Ehrlich & Posner, supra note 78, at 267-271.
  • 124
    • 77955489041 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kennedy, supra note 18, at 1694-1699
    • Kennedy, supra note 18, at 1694-1699.
  • 125
    • 77955479747 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kennedy, supra note 18, at 1695 (noting "the mechanical arbitrariness of rules and the biased arbitrariness of standards")
    • See Kennedy, supra note 18, at 1695 (noting "the mechanical arbitrariness of rules and the biased arbitrariness of standards").
  • 126
    • 77955503707 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • criticizing the idea that potential criminals have any additional claim to predictability of punishment over and above more general claims to be treated fairly and with proportionality
    • See ANDREI MARMOR, LAW IN THE AGE OF PLURALISM 190-191 (2007) (criticizing the idea that potential criminals have any additional claim to predictability of punishment over and above more general claims to be treated fairly and with proportionality).
    • (2007) Law in the Age of Pluralism , pp. 190-191
    • Marmor, A.1
  • 127
    • 77955494471 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kennedy, supra note 18, at 1695-1696 (noting that rules facilitate gaming behavior by the bad man and that uncertainty may provoke moral behavior by making people cautious in order to avoid crossing a line they cannot discern)
    • Kennedy, supra note 18, at 1695-1696 (noting that rules facilitate gaming behavior by the bad man and that uncertainty may provoke moral behavior by making people cautious in order to avoid crossing a line they cannot discern).
  • 128
    • 77955494642 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Waldron, supra note 36, at 535 ("The citizen needs to know what the law requires of him, but that is not necessarily the same as needing to know exactly how far he can go before his behavior becomes an infraction.")
    • See Waldron, supra note 36, at 535 ("The citizen needs to know what the law requires of him, but that is not necessarily the same as needing to know exactly how far he can go before his behavior becomes an infraction.").
  • 129
    • 77955499893 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There may be social interests in ensuring that remedies are sufficiently predictable to allow for the underwriting and availability of insurance. These interests may be served, however, through insurers' setting policy limits based on frequency of occurrence rather than solely through precise rules
    • There may be social interests in ensuring that remedies are sufficiently predictable to allow for the underwriting and availability of insurance. These interests may be served, however, through insurers' setting policy limits based on frequency of occurrence rather than solely through precise rules.
  • 130
    • 77955489443 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stuntz, supra note 79, at 2034-2039
    • Stuntz, supra note 79, at 2034-2039.
  • 131
    • 77955493734 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Kennedy, supra note 18, at 1705-07, 1771-1777 (discussing how standards may empower adjudicators and offer an avenue for resisting dominant, but flawed, ideology)
    • See also Kennedy, supra note 18, at 1705-07, 1771-1777 (discussing how standards may empower adjudicators and offer an avenue for resisting dominant, but flawed, ideology).
  • 132
    • 77955493732 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That is, the opportunity to consult with moral agents and to predict their judgments may suffice to provide adequate notice for the inveterate amoralist. Nonetheless, as I argue above, an individual's habitual practice will be insufficient for understanding the law and for compliance with its spirit. A general, widespread, social approach of this sort will fail to provide determinate content and to achieve compliance with its letter as well. See supra p. 1228
    • That is, the opportunity to consult with moral agents and to predict their judgments may suffice to provide adequate notice for the inveterate amoralist. Nonetheless, as I argue above, an individual's habitual practice will be insufficient for understanding the law and for compliance with its spirit. A general, widespread, social approach of this sort will fail to provide determinate content and to achieve compliance with its letter as well. See supra p. 1228.
  • 133
    • 77955474085 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See SCHAUER, supra note 6, at 192 (discussing specificity of provisions in the South African Constitution as reflecting an understandable reluctance "to grant discretion to mostly the same police officers, prosecutors, and judges who had been in power during apartheid")
    • See SCHAUER, supra note 6, at 192 (discussing specificity of provisions in the South African Constitution as reflecting an understandable reluctance "to grant discretion to mostly the same police officers, prosecutors, and judges who had been in power during apartheid").
  • 134
    • 77955488861 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kennedy, supra note 18, at 1706 (making a similar point about the judiciary's introduction of rules to control the executive)
    • Kennedy, supra note 18, at 1706 (making a similar point about the judiciary's introduction of rules to control the executive).
  • 135
    • 77955504978 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kennedy, supra note 18, at 1702-1705 (discussing the role of rules in areas of "moral flux," id. at 1704)
    • See Kennedy, supra note 18, at 1702-1705 (discussing the role of rules in areas of "moral flux," id. at 1704).
  • 136
    • 77955477520 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Joshua Cohen, Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy, in DELIBERATIVE DEMOCRACY 67, 79 (James Bohman & William Rehg eds., 1007) (arguing that "[i]nstitutions in a deliberative democracy do not serve simply to implement the results of deliberation," but also to establish the conditions to "make deliberation possible" (emphasis omitted))
    • See Joshua Cohen, Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy, in DELIBERATIVE DEMOCRACY 67, 79 (James Bohman & William Rehg eds., 1007) (arguing that "[i]nstitutions in a deliberative democracy do not serve simply to implement the results of deliberation," but also to establish the conditions to "make deliberation possible" (emphasis omitted)).


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.