메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 80, Issue 3, 2013, Pages 1079-1153

Unbundling constitutionality

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84886506110     PISSN: 00419494     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (28)

References (211)
  • 1
    • 33846289984 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Taking its proper place in the constitutional canon: Bolling v. Sharpe, Korematsu, and the equal protection component of fifth amendment due process
    • 1882-83
    • See Peter J. Rubin, Taking Its Proper Place in the Constitutional Canon: Bolling v. Sharpe, Korematsu, and the Equal Protection Component of Fifth Amendment Due Process, 92 Va L Rev 1879, 1882-83 (2006) (describing the reverse incorporation doctrine).
    • (2006) Va L Rev , vol.92 , pp. 1879
    • Rubin, P.J.1
  • 2
    • 84872671014 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Can the president appoint principal executive officers without a senate confirmation vote?
    • 942-44
    • Matthew C. Stephenson, Can the President Appoint Principal Executive Officers without a Senate Confirmation Vote?, 122 Yale L J 940, 942-44 (2013).
    • (2013) Yale L J , vol.122 , pp. 940
    • Stephenson, M.C.1
  • 4
    • 0003770529 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton
    • Sanford Levinson, Constitutional Faith 29 (Princeton 1988) (describing adherents to the "protestant" theory of constitutional textualism);
    • (1988) Constitutional Faith , pp. 29
    • Levinson, S.1
  • 5
    • 22744451175 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The eleventh amendment and the reading of precise constitutional texts
    • 1665
    • John F. Manning, The Eleventh Amendment and the Reading of Precise Constitutional Texts, 113 Yale L J 1663, 1665 (2004);
    • (2004) Yale L J , vol.113 , pp. 1663
    • Manning, J.F.1
  • 6
    • 0040755579 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The supreme court, 1999 term - Foreword: The document and the doctrine
    • 26-28
    • Akhil Reed Amar, The Supreme Court, 1999 Term - Foreword: The Document and the Doctrine, 114 Harv L Rev 26, 26-28 (2000).
    • (2000) Harv L Rev , vol.114 , pp. 26
    • Amar, A.R.1
  • 8
    • 0011659497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Do we have an unwritten constitution?
    • 710-11
    • Thomas C. Grey, Do We Have an Unwritten Constitution?, 27 Stan L Rev 703, 710-11 (1975).
    • (1975) Stan L Rev , vol.27 , pp. 703
    • Grey, T.C.1
  • 9
    • 32044457967 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What divides textualists from purposivists?
    • 73
    • John F. Manning, What Divides Textualists from Purposivists?, 106 Colum L Rev 70, 73 (2006);
    • (2006) Colum L Rev , vol.106 , pp. 70
    • Manning, J.F.1
  • 10
    • 84869650625 scopus 로고
    • The constitution as scripture
    • 1
    • Thomas C. Grey, The Constitution as Scripture, 37 Stan L Rev 1, 1 (1984).
    • (1984) Stan L Rev , vol.37 , pp. 1
    • Grey, T.C.1
  • 13
    • 79951690171 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Parchment and politics: The positive puzzle of constitutional commitment
    • 700
    • Daryl J. Levinson, Parchment and Politics: The Positive Puzzle of Constitutional Commitment, 124 Harv L Rev 657, 700 (2011).
    • (2011) Harv L Rev , vol.124 , pp. 657
    • Levinson, D.J.1
  • 16
    • 79952250443 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle Hafner (Kurt Von Fritz and Ernst Kapp, trans)
    • Aristotle, Constitution of Athens and Related Texts 83, 113-16 (Hafner 1950) (Kurt Von Fritz and Ernst Kapp, trans);
    • (1950) Constitution of Athens and Related Texts , vol.83 , pp. 113-116
  • 17
    • 84886550684 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 9)
    • Levinson, 124 Harv L Rev at 700 (cited in note 9).
    • Harv L Rev , vol.124 , pp. 700
    • Levinson1
  • 22
    • 37449001451 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The constitution outside the constitution
    • 414
    • Ernest A. Young, The Constitution outside the Constitution, 117 Yale L J 408, 414 (2007).
    • (2007) Yale L J , vol.117 , pp. 408
    • Young, E.A.1
  • 26
    • 84861370985 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Property as the law of things
    • 1691
    • See, for example, Henry E. Smith, Property as the Law of Things, 125 Harv L Rev 1691, 1691 (2012) (describing the bundle-of-sticks conception).
    • (2012) Harv L Rev , vol.125 , pp. 1691
    • Smith, H.E.1
  • 27
    • 0347419824 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Common law constitutional interpretation
    • 883
    • See, for example, David A. Strauss, Common Law Constitutional Interpretation, 63 U Chi L Rev 877, 883 (1996) ("It is the rare constitutional case in which the text plays any significant role.").
    • (1996) U Chi L Rev , vol.63 , pp. 877
    • Strauss, D.A.1
  • 30
    • 0002018204 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The constitution as an institution
    • 22
    • See, for example, K.N. Llewellyn, The Constitution as an Institution, 34 Colum L Rev 1, 22 (1934) (describing "highly probable permanence" as the "one essential criterion").
    • (1934) Colum L Rev , vol.34 , pp. 1
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 31
  • 32
    • 0038874371 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 12)
    • Bobbitt, Constitutional Fate at 29-37 (cited in note 12) (describing Justice Black's textualism as a response to a crisis precipitated by realist theories of judging);
    • Constitutional Fate , pp. 29-37
    • Bobbitt1
  • 34
    • 63849312562 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Limits of interpretivism
    • 164-67, 172
    • See Richard Primus, Limits of Interpretivism, 32 Harv J L & Pub Pol 159, 164-67, 172 (2009);
    • (2009) Harv J L & Pub Pol , vol.32 , pp. 159
    • Primus, R.1
  • 35
    • 84886540576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 15)
    • Strauss, 63 U Chi L Rev at 883 (cited in note 15).
    • U Chi L Rev , vol.63 , pp. 883
    • Strauss1
  • 37
    • 0039157069 scopus 로고
    • The proper scope of the commerce power
    • 1387-88
    • Richard A. Epstein, The Proper Scope of the Commerce Power, 73 Va L Rev 1387, 1387-88 (1987).
    • (1987) Va L Rev , vol.73 , pp. 1387
    • Epstein, R.A.1
  • 38
    • 18444417148 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What is textualism?
    • 348
    • See, for example, Caleb Nelson, What is Textualism?, 91 Va L Rev 347, 348 (2005) ("[N]o 'textualist' favors isolating [] language from its surrounding context.").
    • (2005) Va L Rev , vol.91 , pp. 347
    • Nelson, C.1
  • 39
    • 77957375702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constitutional expectations
    • 97-98
    • Richard Primus, Constitutional Expectations, 109 Mich L Rev 91, 97-98 (2010).
    • (2010) Mich L Rev , vol.109 , pp. 91
    • Primus, R.1
  • 40
    • 0003825178 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 139-40 (cited in note 6)
    • See, for example, Scalia, A Matter of Interpretation at 129, 139-40 (cited in note 6) (describing the role of stare decisis).
    • A Matter of Interpretation , pp. 129
    • Scalia1
  • 41
    • 84861907967 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Judicial review, constitutional interpretation, and the democratic dilemma: Proposing a "Controlled activism" alternative
    • 1512
    • See Martin H. Redish and Matthew B. Arnould, Judicial Review, Constitutional Interpretation, and the Democratic Dilemma: Proposing a "Controlled Activism" Alternative, 64 Fla L Rev 1485, 1512 (2012) (describing nontextualism as a threat to "constitutional democracy").
    • (2012) Fla L Rev , vol.64 , pp. 1485
    • Redish, M.H.1    Arnould, M.B.2
  • 42
    • 0004083437 scopus 로고
    • Basic Books
    • A community can be mistaken about its own practices. But other things being equal, it is a virtue for a theory of a social practice to be consistent with the self-understandings of the participants in that practice. See Clifford Geertz, The Interpretation of Cultures 14-15 (Basic Books 1973).
    • (1973) The Interpretation of Cultures , pp. 14-15
    • Geertz, C.1
  • 43
    • 33645815488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The core of the case against judicial review
    • 1353
    • To be sure, one might count enabling judicial review as a liability: more than one important theorist has suggested that we would be better off without judicial review. See, for example, Jeremy Waldron, The Core of the Case against Judicial Review, 115 Yale L J 1346, 1353 (2006). But without taking the time necessary to argue the point all the way through, I will proceed on the premise that judicial review is, on balance, a net good within the system of American government. This is by no means to say that judicial review as it currently exists in the United States is the optimal form of judicial review. It is only to say, with full knowledge that the proposition would be very difficult to prove, that we are on balance better off with this institution as it exists than we would be if it did not exist at all.
    • (2006) Yale L J , vol.115 , pp. 1346
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 44
    • 79960817528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 12)
    • See, for example, Strauss, The Living Constitution at 115-17 (cited in note 12);
    • The Living Constitution , pp. 115-117
    • Strauss1
  • 47
    • 34249951655 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The living constitution
    • 1741-43
    • Bruce Ackerman, The Living Constitution, 120 Harv L Rev 1737, 1741-43 (2007) (describing processes of constitutional change other than Article V);
    • (2007) Harv L Rev , vol.120 , pp. 1737
    • Ackerman, B.1
  • 48
    • 0011659497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 7)
    • Grey, 27 Stan L Rev at 706-10 (cited in note 7) (arguing for nontextual sources of constitutional law);
    • Stan L Rev , vol.27 , pp. 706-710
    • Grey1
  • 49
    • 0002018204 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 16)
    • Llewellyn, 34 Colum L Rev at 3-4 (cited in note 16).
    • Colum L Rev , vol.34 , pp. 3-4
    • Llewellyn1
  • 50
    • 79952163066 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Grand Central
    • See Ron Paul, End the Fed 18-31 (Grand Central 2009) (arguing that the Federal Reserve is unconstitutional). But see McCulloch v Maryland, 17 US (4 Wheat) 316, 324-26 (1819) (upholding Congress's creation of the Bank of the United States).
    • (2009) End the Fed , pp. 18-31
    • Paul, R.1
  • 52
    • 84923210497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • S Ct 2312
    • See, for example, Federal Communications Commission v Fox Television Stations, Inc, 132 S Ct 2307, 2312 (2012). The idea that the First Amendment runs against the executive branch is not controversial. But the text of the First Amendment is addressed to "Congress." Many words in the Constitution are subject to multiple interpretations, but if pressed to identify something that the word "Congress" in the Constitution should not be read to mean, "President" seems like a safe choice. Unlike the extension of First Amendment norms to cover states, which is officially explained by the doctrine of incorporation, no official story exists to explain why a text written as a limitation on the power of Congress also works a limitation on the power of a different branch of the federal government. Much the same could be said of the idea that the guarantees of the First Amendment run against the federal courts.
    • (2012) Federal Communications Commission v Fox Television Stations, Inc , vol.132 , pp. 2307
  • 53
    • 84886511571 scopus 로고
    • F2d 466-67 5th Cir
    • See, for example, Bernard v Gulf Oil Co, 619 F2d 459, 466-67 (5th Cir 1980) (invalidating the district court's gag order as a violation of the First Amendment's guarantee of the freedom of speech). The judiciary, like the president, is not the Congress.
    • (1980) Bernard v Gulf Oil Co , vol.619 , pp. 459
  • 54
    • 18344368345 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • US 905
    • See Printz v United States, 521 US 898, 905 (1997) ("Because there is no constitutional text speaking to this precise question, the answer to the CLEOs' challenge must be sought in historical understanding and practice, in the structure of the Constitution, and in the jurisprudence of this Court."). Note, however, that constitutional discourse's tendency to seek textual homes for doctrines, see note 45, has fostered subsequent reformulations of the anticommandeering principle under which the rule might be understood to be an interpretation of the Necessary and Proper Clause.
    • (1997) Printz v United States , vol.521 , pp. 898
  • 55
    • 84861898203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A mandate for mandates: Is the individual health insurance case a slippery slope?
    • 89 & n 64
    • See, for example, Ilya Somin, A Mandate for Mandates: Is the Individual Health Insurance Case a Slippery Slope?, 75 L & Contemp Probs 75, 89 & n 64 (2012) (presenting the holding of Printz as an interpretation of the term "proper" in the Necessary and Proper Clause);
    • (2012) L & Contemp Probs , vol.75 , pp. 75
    • Somin, I.1
  • 56
    • 67649573353 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • *26-27 US Mar 27
    • *26-27 (US Mar 27, 2012) (available on Westlaw at 2012 WL 1017220) (Scalia) (characterizing the holdings of Printz and New York v United States as interpretations of the term "proper" in the Necessary and Proper Clause). 42 As the old joke has it, the legal authority for this constitutional proposition is the case of Lee v Grant.
    • (2012) Department of Health and Human Services V Florida
  • 57
    • 79952121244 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Multiplicity in federalism and the separation of powers
    • Book Review 1097 n 74-75
    • See, for example, Josh Chafetz, Book Review, Multiplicity in Federalism and the Separation of Powers, 120 Yale L J 1084, 1097 n 74-75 (2011).
    • (2011) Yale L J , vol.120 , pp. 1084
    • Chafetz, J.1
  • 58
    • 0004279652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 7)
    • See, for example, Ely, Democracy and Distrust at 32 (cited in note 7) (describing the reverse incorporation doctrine as "gibberish").
    • Democracy and Distrust , pp. 32
    • Ely1
  • 59
    • 84886536931 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 39) (collecting criticism of the doctrine)
    • See also Primus, 104 Colum L Rev at 977 n 7 (cited in note 39) (collecting criticism of the doctrine).
    • Colum L Rev , vol.104 , Issue.7 , pp. 977
    • Primus1
  • 60
    • 43549104222 scopus 로고
    • Understanding changed readings: Fidelity and theory
    • 408-10
    • See, for example, Lawrence Lessig, Understanding Changed Readings: Fidelity and Theory, 47 Stan L Rev 395, 408-10 (1995) (arguing that Bolling correctly recognized that Reconstruction had changed the meaning of "Due Process").
    • (1995) Stan L Rev , vol.47 , pp. 395
    • Lessig, L.1
  • 63
    • 84886577821 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 16)
    • Llewellyn, 34 Colum L Rev at 14 (cited in note 16).
    • Colum L Rev , vol.34 , pp. 14
    • Llewellyn1
  • 65
    • 0041920709 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The irrelevance of constitutional amendments
    • 1457-59
    • David A. Strauss, The Irrelevance of Constitutional Amendments, 114 Harv L Rev 1457, 1457-59 (2001);
    • (2001) Harv L Rev , vol.114 , pp. 1457
    • Strauss, D.A.1
  • 66
    • 84886486985 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 16)
    • Llewellyn, 34 Colum L Rev at 21-23 (cited in note 16).
    • Colum L Rev , vol.34 , pp. 21-23
    • Llewellyn1
  • 67
    • 0003770529 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 6)
    • See, for example, Levinson, Constitutional Faith at 30-37 (cited in note 6) (describing this view).
    • Constitutional Faith , pp. 30-37
    • Levinson1
  • 68
    • 84886507764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 25)
    • See, for example, Primus, 109 Mich L Rev at 99-100 (cited in note 25);
    • Mich L Rev , vol.109 , pp. 99-100
    • Primus1
  • 69
    • 84886522693 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 50)
    • Strauss, 114 Harv L Rev at 1462-63 (cited in note 50).
    • Harv L Rev , vol.114 , pp. 1462-1463
    • Strauss1
  • 70
    • 33749426712 scopus 로고
    • US 687-88
    • See Frontiero v Richardson, 411 US 677, 687-88 (1973) (discussing the relationship between questions of sex equality under the Fourteenth Amendment and the thenpending Equal Rights Amendment).
    • (1973) Frontiero v Richardson , vol.411 , pp. 677
  • 71
    • 78649932877 scopus 로고
    • US 30
    • See NLRB v Jones & Laughlin Steel Corp, 301 US 1, 30 (1937) (upholding provisions of the National Labor Relations Act as valid exercises of Congress's commerce power).
    • (1937) NLRB v Jones & Laughlin Steel Corp , vol.301 , pp. 1
  • 72
    • 72449204773 scopus 로고
    • US 391, 398-99
    • See West Coast Hotel Co v Parrish, 300 US 379, 391, 398-99 (1937) (upholding minimum wage legislation).
    • (1937) West Coast Hotel Co v Parrish , vol.300 , pp. 379
  • 73
    • 85037576959 scopus 로고
    • US 552
    • For a canonical example, contrast Colegrove v Green, 328 US 549, 552 (1946) (declaring nonjusticiable a challenge to an electoral districting plan),
    • (1946) Colegrove v Green , vol.328 , pp. 549
  • 74
    • 78649816227 scopus 로고
    • US 208-10
    • with Baker v Carr, 369 US 186, 208-10 (1962) (declaring such a challenge justiciable when presented as an equal protection claim rather than a Guarantee Clause claim).
    • (1962) Baker v Carr , vol.369 , pp. 186
  • 77
    • 0011659497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 7)
    • Grey, 27 Stan L Rev at 706-07 (cited in note 7);
    • Stan L Rev , vol.27 , pp. 706-707
    • Grey1
  • 78
    • 0002018204 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 16)
    • Llewellyn, 34 Colum L Rev at 3-5 (cited in note 16).
    • Colum L Rev , vol.34 , pp. 3-5
    • Llewellyn1
  • 79
    • 84886462057 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 8)
    • See, for example, Grey, 37 Stan L Rev at 1-3 (cited in note 8) (identifying non-textualists as "supplementers" because their position is that constitutional authority includes more than just the text).
    • Stan L Rev , vol.37 , pp. 1-3
    • Grey1
  • 80
    • 84886507479 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constitutional farce
    • William N. Eskridge Jr and Sanford Levinson, eds NYU
    • See generally Pamela S. Karlan and Daniel R. Ortiz, Constitutional Farce, in William N. Eskridge Jr and Sanford Levinson, eds, Constitutional Stupidities, Constitutional Tragedies 180 (NYU 1998) (arguing that the conventions of constitutional argument are sufficiently flexible so that it is always possible to articulate an interpretation that would avoid an unwanted outcome).
    • (1998) Constitutional Stupidities, Constitutional Tragedies , pp. 180
    • Karlan, P.S.1    Ortiz, D.R.2
  • 81
    • 84920752634 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • How the written constitution crowds out the extraconstitutional rule of recognition
    • Matthew D. Adler and Kenneth Einar Himma, eds 69-83, 86-87 Oxford
    • See Michael C. Dorf, How the Written Constitution Crowds Out the Extraconstitutional Rule of Recognition, in Matthew D. Adler and Kenneth Einar Himma, eds, The Rule of Recognition and the U.S. Constitution 69, 69-83, 86-87 (Oxford 2009) (discussing the tendency to shoehorn nontextual norms into arguments about the Constitution's text).
    • (2009) The Rule of Recognition and the U.S. Constitution , pp. 69
    • Dorf, M.C.1
  • 82
    • 40749084517 scopus 로고
    • US 511
    • See, for example, United States v Gaudin, 515 US 506, 511 (1995).
    • (1995) United States v Gaudin , vol.515 , pp. 506
  • 83
    • 84886518812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • F Supp 2d 980 ND Ill (bench trial)
    • See, for example, United States v Hanjuan Jin, 833 F Supp 2d 977, 980 (ND Ill 2012) (bench trial);
    • (2012) United States v Hanjuan Jin , vol.833 , pp. 977
  • 84
    • 84886457469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • F Supp 2d 17 DDC
    • United States v Weaks, 840 F Supp 2d 12, 17 (DDC 2012) (bench trial).
    • (2012) United States v Weaks , vol.840 , pp. 12
  • 85
    • 84886534482 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Acontextual judicial review
    • 1153-54 & n 47
    • I thank Louis Seidman for pointing out this example to me. See Louis Michael Seidman, Acontextual Judicial Review, 32 Cardozo L Rev 1143, 1153-54 & n 47 (2011).
    • (2011) Cardozo L Rev , vol.32 , pp. 1143
    • Seidman, L.M.1
  • 86
    • 77958149431 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Burying the "Continuing body" theory of the senate
    • See generally Aaron-Andrew P. Bruhl, Burying the "Continuing Body" Theory of the Senate, 95 Iowa L Rev 1401 (2010) (describing and criticizing this conception).
    • (2010) Iowa L Rev , vol.95 , pp. 1401
    • Bruhl, A.-A.P.1
  • 87
    • 56849096736 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the origin of rules (with apologies to darwin): A comment on antonin scalia's the rule of law as a law of rules
    • 1006
    • See, for example, David A. Strauss, On the Origin of Rules (with Apologies to Darwin): A Comment on Antonin Scalia's The Rule of Law as a Law of Rules, 75 U Chi L Rev 997, 1006 (2008): There are provisions of the Constitution that do prescribe rules or, in any event, that do not leave much room for discretion. There are provisions that use numbers, for example - for the minimum ages of federal officials, for those officials' terms in office, for the number of senators per state, and for how often a census is to be conducted - and at least the numerical aspects of those rules, read naturally, do not permit the exercise of much discretion.
    • (2008) U Chi L Rev , vol.75 , pp. 997
    • Strauss, D.A.1
  • 88
    • 84886515493 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • P3d 523 Wyo
    • Early litigation under the Eleventh Amendment brought this issue to the Supreme Court, which conspicuously failed to provide a textual explanation for the practice. In Hollingsworth v Virginia, 3 US 378 (1798), one of the claims the Court confronted was precisely that the Eleventh Amendment was invalid because it had not complied with the presentment requirement. Justice Samuel Chase provided the Court's sole response to this contention as follows: "There can, surely, be no necessity to answer that argument. The negative of the President applies only to the ordinary cases of legislation: He has nothing to do with the proposition, or adoption, of amendments to the Constitution." Id at 381. Justice Chase's dictum states the operative supreme law perfectly, and it makes not the slightest gesture toward explaining how the text could be read to accord with that supreme law. More recently, the Supreme Court of Wyoming has interpreted the language of the Wyoming Constitution's presentment requirement, whose wording is in relevant part identical to that of Article V, to invalidate a proposed amendment that was not presented to the governor. See Geringer v Bebout, 10 P3d 514, 523 (Wyo 2000). The Supreme Court of Wyoming charitably described the US Supreme Court's reasoning in Hollingsworth as "not contained in that Court's decision." Id.
    • (2000) Geringer v Bebout , vol.10 , pp. 514
  • 89
    • 84928458858 scopus 로고
    • As many as six impossible things before breakfast
    • 629
    • Don Herzog, As Many as Six Impossible Things before Breakfast, 75 Cal L Rev 609, 629 (1987).
    • (1987) Cal L Rev , vol.75 , pp. 609
    • Herzog, D.1
  • 90
    • 0037984044 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • Here are some examples: (1) One might deny that Article III makes jury trial mandatory in criminal cases by mobilizing the word "right" in the language of the Sixth Amendment, which guarantees criminal defendants "the right to a speedy and public trial, by an impartial jury of the State and district wherein the crime shall have been committed." This use of the term "right," the textualist might say, indicates that the accused has the option of a trial. To be sure, the term "right" does not always describe an option, see generally Richard A. Primus, The American Language of Rights (Cambridge 1999), but the term does bear that meaning often enough to make such a reading of the Sixth Amendment plausible as a prima facie matter. One could then privilege that interpretation of the Sixth Amendment over the apparent plain meaning of Article III in either of two ways. First, one could say that the Sixth Amendment overrides Article III wherever the two conflict because the Sixth Amendment was adopted two years later.
    • (1999) The American Language of Rights
    • Primus, R.A.1
  • 91
    • 84886558186 scopus 로고
    • US 68-69
    • See Schick v United States, 195 US 65, 68-69 (1904) (endorsing this reading in dicta). Alternatively, one could say that the two clauses should be read to reflect the same basic idea, that any conflict between them should be resolved by giving each clause a reasonable rather than a literal meaning, and that the apparently inflexible language of Article III is reasonably read just as a way of emphasizing the importance of the jury trial right. As I have described elsewhere, we can think of these two reconciliations as reflecting hard-textualist and soft-textualist approaches, respectively, where the hard textualist insists on a close reading Article V states its own conditions for the validity of measures enacted thereunder. If those conditions are exclusive, the presentment requirement of Article I would not apply. One problem with this argument, though, is that the language of Article I seems totalizing. It provides that "Every" measure to which both Houses must agree must be presented. Note too that congressional enactments under all other articles of the Constitution - not just those enacted under Article I - are treated as if the Presentment Clause meant what it says. Congressional reorganizations of the judiciary under Article III must be presented to the president, as must measures exercising the various powers given to Congress in Article IV (that is, the power to prescribe interstate comity under the Full Faith and Credit Clause, the power to admit new states, and the power to make rules governing federal territory and disposing of federal property). Statutes adopted under the enforcement clauses of the Thirteenth, Fourteenth, Fifteenth, Nineteenth, Twenty-Fourth, and Twenty-Sixth Amendments are treated as subject to the presentment requirements of Article I, as is the exercise of the substantive congressional powers conferred in the Sixteenth, Twentieth, Twenty-Third, and Twenty-Fifth Amendments. (The joker in the deck is congressional confirmations as specified in the Twenty-Fifth Amendment, namely the confirmation of a new vice president and the decision as to whether a disabled president is fit to resume office; to date, there is scant practice under these provisions, and it is easy to imagine presidents skipping signatures in both situations.) Considered in this context, a claim that Article V is exempt resembles special pleading - which, again, does not mean that the argument would not be persuasive to a motivated audience.
    • (1904) Schick v United States , vol.195 , pp. 65
  • 92
    • 70350006219 scopus 로고
    • US 159-61
    • See Duncan v Louisiana, 391 US 145, 159-61 (1968).
    • (1968) Duncan v Louisiana , vol.391 , pp. 145
  • 93
    • 77954979256 scopus 로고
    • US 655-57
    • Contrast, for example, Mapp v Ohio, 367 US 643, 655-57 (1961) (excluding evidence gathered in warrantless search),
    • (1961) Mapp v Ohio , vol.367 , pp. 643
  • 94
    • 84873127951 scopus 로고
    • US 33
    • with Wolf v Colorado, 338 US 25, 33 (1949) (permitting the admission of such evidence).
    • (1949) Wolf v Colorado , vol.338 , pp. 25
  • 95
    • 84886491468 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Belknap
    • Or at least it never has so far; one can generate far-flung hypothetical circumstances in which such change might be possible. To date, however, it does describe American constitutional practice well to say that the text itself changes only with formal amendments. One might also add the caveat that whether the Constitution has been formally amended as prescribed in Article V is itself sometimes a contestable question. See, for example, Bruce Ackerman, 2 We the People: Transformations 197-98 (Belknap 1998) (raising doubts about whether the Fourteenth Amendment was adopted in accordance with Article V's requirements);
    • (1998) We the People: Transformations , vol.2 , pp. 197-198
    • Ackerman, B.1
  • 96
    • 68949155246 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • Laurence H. Tribe, The Invisible Constitution xix-xx (Oxford 2008) (describing controversy over whether the Twenty-Seventh Amendment was validly adopted).
    • (2008) The Invisible Constitution
    • Tribe, L.H.1
  • 97
    • 79952157516 scopus 로고
    • US 42
    • See Luther v Borden, 48 US 1, 42 (1849). As noted earlier, statements about what courts will not do are limited by our inability to foresee all the ways in which the future might be different from the past. See Part I.A.4. Perhaps under some future circumstance a court would in fact enforce the Guarantee Clause. What we can say now is that prevailing doctrine includes a principle against the judicial enforcement of that Clause and that courts to date have conformed, at least officially, to that doctrine.
    • (1849) Luther v Borden , vol.48 , pp. 1
  • 98
    • 84886461135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Parl Deb, HC (6th ser) 621
    • See, for example, Fixed-Term Parliaments Bill, 515 Parl Deb, HC (6th ser) 621 (2010);
    • (2010) Fixed-Term Parliaments Bill , pp. 515
  • 100
    • 84886465548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BBC News Sept 14 (visited Sept 114, 2013)
    • Peers End Deadlock over Fixed Term Parliaments (BBC News Sept 14, 2011), online at http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/uk-politics-14924982 (visited Sept 114, 2013).
    • (2011) Peers end Deadlock Over Fixed Term Parliaments
  • 101
    • 84886565466 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The GOP's electoral college scheme
    • Dec 17 (visited Sept 11, 2013)
    • In recent years, a few legislators have entertained the idea of splitting their states' electoral votes in proportion to the statewide popular vote, rather than awarding the entire electoral slate to the winner of the popular vote. The motivations for this idea are understood to be partisan: the proposal surfaces in states where the partisan preference of the legislature differs from the expected partisan preference of the state's presidential electorate, such that splitting the electoral vote proportionally would probably capture more votes for the legislature's preferred candidate than a winner-take-all system would. See, for example, Reid Wilson, The GOP's Electoral College Scheme, Natl J (Dec 17, 2012), online at http://www.nationaljournal.com/columns/on-the-trail/ the-gop-s-electoral-college-scheme-20121217 (visited Sept 11, 2013). Today, Maine and Nebraska already operate on something other than a winner-take-all basis. Accordingly, it is not the case that the winner-take-all system functions as supreme law. What functions as supreme law is the principle that the electors must be awarded pursuant to the popular vote. There is more than one way to translate a popular-vote result into a slate of electors, but no state considers skipping the popular vote and letting the legislature pick electors directly.
    • (2012) Natl J
    • Wilson, R.1
  • 103
    • 77951785725 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The irrelevance of writtenness in constitutional interpretation
    • 1085
    • See Andrew B. Coan, The Irrelevance of Writtenness in Constitutional Interpretation, 158 U Pa L Rev 1025, 1085 (2010) (noting "that the First Amendment bars President Obama from forcibly shutting down Fox News ⋯ is uncontroversially true, given the contemporary state of American constitutional law").
    • (2010) U Pa L Rev , vol.158 , pp. 1025
    • Coan, A.B.1
  • 105
    • 84886539148 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bloomberg Feb 8 (visited Sept 11, 2013)
    • Some commentators may think this general scenario is already not so far away, albeit applied to constitutional rights other than religious free exercise. See, for example, Noah Feldman, Obama's Drone Attack on Your Due Process (Bloomberg Feb 8, 2013), online at http://www.bloomberg.com/news/2013- 02-08/obama-s-drone-attack-on-your-due-process.html (visited Sept 11, 2013) (describing an administration white paper on the use of drone strikes as an evisceration of the constitutional guarantee of due process).
    • (2013) Obama's Drone Attack on Your Due Process
    • Feldman, N.1
  • 106
    • 78149354083 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Public consensus as constitutional authority
    • 1220-21, 1227-28
    • See Richard Primus, Public Consensus as Constitutional Authority, 78 Geo Wash L Rev 1207, 1220-21, 1227-28 (2010) (explaining that public consensus can act as an independent source of authority in constitutional interpretation).
    • (2010) Geo Wash L Rev , vol.78 , pp. 1207
    • Primus, R.1
  • 107
    • 84886522693 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 50)
    • See Strauss, 114 Harv L Rev at 1462-63 (cited in note 50). It also sometimes happens that the decisionmaking class's collective support for the merits of an idea still does not yield the view that the Constitution can be read to embody that idea. The Twentieth, Twenty-First, and Twenty-Second Amendments - among others - are probably best understood in that vein.
    • Harv L Rev , vol.114 , pp. 1462-1463
    • Strauss1
  • 111
    • 79960817528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 12)
    • See Strauss, The Living Constitution at 32-49 (cited in note 12) (describing the common-law system of judicial review where cases are decided based on precedent, and the Constitution plays "at most, a ceremonial role").
    • The Living Constitution , pp. 32-49
    • Strauss1
  • 112
    • 84886580766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • US 66
    • See, for example, Hillside Dairy Inc v Lyons, 539 US 59, 66 (2003);
    • (2003) Hillside Dairy Inc v Lyons , vol.539 , pp. 59
  • 113
    • 84886501193 scopus 로고
    • US 138
    • Maine v Taylor, 477 US 131, 138 (1986).
    • (1986) Maine v Taylor , vol.477 , pp. 131
  • 115
    • 79960817528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 12)
    • See notes 9 and 11. See also Strauss, The Living Constitution at 34-35 (cited in note 12).
    • The Living Constitution , pp. 34-35
    • Strauss1
  • 118
    • 84886501091 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 11)
    • Young, 117 Yale L J at 414 (cited in note 11).
    • Yale L J , vol.117 , pp. 414
    • Young1
  • 119
    • 79960817528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 12)
    • The work of Professors David Strauss and Thomas Grey provides examples. See generally Strauss, The Living Constitution (cited in note 12).
    • The Living Constitution
    • Strauss1
  • 120
    • 0011659497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 7)
    • See also Grey, 27 Stan L Rev at 706-10 (cited in note 7).
    • Stan L Rev , vol.27 , pp. 706-710
    • Grey1
  • 121
    • 84886555597 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 50)
    • There are also important exceptions: sometimes small-c theory aims to explain why certain rules that have been thought constitutional should in fact not be enforced through judicial review. See, for example, Ackerman, 1 We the People: Foundations at 131-33 (cited in note 50);
    • We the People: Foundations , vol.1 , pp. 131-133
    • Ackerman1
  • 122
    • 84886577229 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 16)
    • Llewellyn, 34 Colum L Rev at 40 (cited in note 16).
    • Colum L Rev , vol.34 , pp. 40
    • Llewellyn1
  • 124
  • 125
    • 0003770529 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 6)
    • See, for example, Levinson, Constitutional Faith at 29 (cited in note 6) (describing the core of the difference between big-C and small-c perspectives as being the exclusivity, vel non, of the text);
    • Constitutional Faith , pp. 29
    • Levinson1
  • 128
    • 84886497512 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 15)
    • Strauss, 63 U Chi L Rev at 904 (cited in note 15).
    • U Chi L Rev , vol.63 , pp. 904
    • Strauss1
  • 129
    • 84886467744 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 11)
    • See, for example, Young, 117 Yale L J at 415-16 (cited in note 11);
    • Yale L J , vol.117 , pp. 415-416
    • Young1
  • 132
    • 0012224294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle 113-16 (cited in note 10)
    • Aristotle, Constitution of Athens at 83, 113-16 (cited in note 10);
    • Constitution of Athens , pp. 83
  • 133
    • 84886495799 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 16)
    • Llewellyn, 34 Colum L Rev at 31 (cited in note 16).
    • Colum L Rev , vol.34 , pp. 31
    • Llewellyn1
  • 135
    • 84886524000 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 50)
    • Strauss, 114 Harv L Rev at 1459-60 (cited in note 50).
    • Harv L Rev , vol.114 , pp. 1459-1460
    • Strauss1
  • 136
    • 77951825411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • America's statutory "constitution"
    • 12
    • See William N. Eskridge Jr, America's Statutory "constitution", 41 UC Davis L Rev 1, 12 (2007).
    • (2007) UC Davis L Rev , vol.41 , pp. 1
    • Eskridge Jr., W.N.1
  • 137
    • 84886550684 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 9)
    • See Levinson, 124 Harv L Rev at 700 (cited in note 9).
    • Harv L Rev , vol.124 , pp. 700
    • Levinson1
  • 138
    • 67650553143 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Federalism and the generality problem in constitutional interpretation
    • 2039-40
    • See, for example, John F. Manning, Federalism and the Generality Problem in Constitutional Interpretation, 122 Harv L Rev 2003, 2039-40 (2009) (arguing against the practice of recognizing constitutional structure apart from constitutional text).
    • (2009) Harv L Rev , vol.122 , pp. 2003
    • Manning, J.F.1
  • 139
    • 77950490430 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The constitutional legitimacy of freestanding federalism
    • 103-05
    • See, for example, Gillian E. Metzger, The Constitutional Legitimacy of Freestanding Federalism, 122 Harv L Rev F 98, 103-05 (2009).
    • (2009) Harv L Rev F , vol.122 , pp. 98
    • Metzger, G.E.1
  • 140
    • 0040563670 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 22-23 (cited in note 32)
    • Black, Structure and Relationship at 12-13, 22-23 (cited in note 32). To be sure, Black often seemed to have an expansive conception of structure, as well as a heightened sense of how clearly that structure - or a particular view of that structure - would resolve a given question.
    • Structure and Relationship , pp. 12-13
    • Black1
  • 141
    • 84946917014 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • US 375
    • See, for example, Central Virginia Community College v Katz, 546 US 356, 375 (2006) ("[W]e have understood the Eleventh Amendment to stand not so much for what it says, but for the presupposition of our constitutional structure which it confirms.") (brackets in original),
    • (2006) Central Virginia Community College v Katz , vol.546 , pp. 356
  • 143
    • 18344368345 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • US 905
    • Printz v United States, 521 US 898, 905 (1997) (Scalia) ("Because there is no constitutional text speaking to this precise question, the answer to the CLEOs' challenge must be sought in historical understanding and practice, in the structure of the Constitution, and in the jurisprudence of this Court."). To be sure, justices also sometimes deny the validity of putative structural rules on the grounds that the text does not support them.
    • (1997) Printz v United States , vol.521 , pp. 898
  • 144
    • 84886466510 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • US 361
    • See, for example, Department of Revenue of Kentucky v Davis, 553 US 328, 361 (2008) (Thomas concurring) (rejecting dormant commerce doctrine as having "no basis in the Constitution").
    • (2008) Department of Revenue of Kentucky v Davis , vol.553 , pp. 328
  • 145
    • 44849128099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The core of an uneasy case for judicial review
    • 1699-1700
    • An argument in favor of recognizing some structural principle as a constitutional rule might have a formal basis if the argument were essentially originalst. That is, one might argue that the principle in question is an authoritative constitutional rule because the Founders intended, expected, or understood it to be so, thus implicitly enacting it when they ratified the Constitution. In such an argument, the fact that the rule in question is structural is incidental to its status as a constitutional rule. What qualifies the rule as constitutional is the authority of an original understanding. The argument about the Eleventh Amendment put forth in Katz and Blatchford is officially of this variety. See note 137. 139 See, for example, Richard H. Fallon Jr, The Core of an Uneasy Case for Judicial Review, 121 Harv L Rev 1693, 1699-1700 (2008) (offering such an argument).
    • (2008) Harv L Rev , vol.121 , pp. 1693
    • Fallon Jr., R.H.1
  • 146
    • 0040563670 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 32)
    • Professor Charles Black put the point in the following unsubtle way: "I do not think I am suggesting that precision be supplanted by wide-open speculation. The precision of textual explication is nothing but specious in the areas that matter." Black, Structure and Relationship at 29 (cited in note 32). One need not condemn all textual explication as specious in order to recognize the strength of the basic point that practitioners confronting structural issues are quite capable of disagreeing even where there are texts on point.
    • Structure and Relationship , pp. 29
    • Black1
  • 148
    • 0011659497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 7)
    • See, for example, Grey, 27 Stan L Rev at 706 (cited in note 7).
    • Stan L Rev , vol.27 , pp. 706
    • Grey1
  • 149
    • 84886561764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 891-94 (cited in note 15)
    • See, for example, Strauss, 63 U Chi L Rev at 879, 891-94 (cited in note 15) (describing the idea of "rational traditionalism").
    • U Chi L Rev , vol.63 , pp. 879
    • Strauss1
  • 150
    • 0038874371 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 12)
    • See Bobbitt, Constitutional Fate at 93-119 (cited in note 12). My use of the term is indebted to, but broader than, Professor Bobbitt's. Professor Bobbitt uses "ethos" not just to name the generic idea that a conception of the values of the American polity can give rise to constitutional rules but to identify one particular value that he sees as generating such rules: limited government. See, for example, id at 230. For small-c theorists other than Professor Bobbitt, however, principles other than limited government may be as important to the American constitutional ethos as limited government is in Professor Bobbitt's view. In my attempt to capture the conception of small-c constitutionalism broadly, therefore, I use the idea of ethos generically, to capture constitutional rules that follow from any prevailing ideas about who we are as a people and what we therefore would or would not do through our political institutions, rather than only those arising from the specific conception of ethos that Professor Bobbitt proposes.
    • Constitutional Fate , pp. 93-119
    • Bobbitt1
  • 151
    • 32144459811 scopus 로고
    • US 447-49
    • See, for example, Brandenburg v Ohio, 395 US 444, 447-49 (1969) (applying free speech protection against a state government).
    • (1969) Brandenburg v Ohio , vol.395 , pp. 444
  • 154
    • 57649096450 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dead or alive: Originalism as popular constitutionalism in heller
    • 194-95
    • See, for example, Reva B. Siegel, Dead or Alive: Originalism as Popular Constitutionalism in Heller, 122 Harv L Rev 191, 194-95 (2008).
    • (2008) Harv L Rev , vol.122 , pp. 191
    • Siegel, R.B.1
  • 155
    • 84886509883 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 00:24-00:33 Oyez Project (visited Sept 11, 2013)
    • See Dickerson v United States (No. 99-5525) - Opinion Announcement at 00:24-00:33 (Oyez Project 2013), online at http://www.oyez.org/cases/1990-1999/ 1999/1999-99-5525/opinion (visited Sept 11, 2013) (Chief Justice Rehnquist explaining, when announcing Dickerson, that the Miranda warnings "have echoed through police stations and on television screens in the thirty-four years since we decided the case of Miranda versus Arizona").
    • (2013) Dickerson V United States (No. 99-5525) - Opinion Announcement
  • 157
    • 84886541633 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 898 (cited in note 15)
    • See Strauss, 63 U Chi L Rev at 887, 898 (cited in note 15).
    • U Chi L Rev , vol.63 , pp. 887
    • Strauss1
  • 159
    • 84886574398 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 70)
    • Seidman, 32 Cardozo L Rev at 1154 (cited in note 70).
    • Cardozo L Rev , vol.32 , pp. 1154
    • Seidman1
  • 160
    • 0003770529 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 6)
    • These instances contrast with a different and perhaps more common attitude among people who recognize nontextual bases for constitutional law, which is to regard all of the text as supreme law, albeit without being exhaustive of the supreme law. See Levinson, Constitutional Faith at 29 (cited in note 6).
    • Constitutional Faith , pp. 29
    • Levinson1
  • 163
    • 84886451212 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited note 157)
    • Eskridge and Ferejohn, 50 Duke L J at 1217 (cited note 157).
    • Duke L J , vol.50 , pp. 1217
    • Eskridge1    Ferejohn2
  • 165
    • 84886544961 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 70)
    • See, for example, Seidman, 32 Cardozo L Rev at 1147-48 (cited in note 70);
    • Cardozo L Rev , vol.32 , pp. 1147-1148
    • Seidman1
  • 166
    • 84886565922 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 16)
    • Llewellyn, 34 Colum L Rev at 22 (cited in note 16).
    • Colum L Rev , vol.34 , pp. 22
    • Llewellyn1
  • 168
    • 84886489284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 16)
    • See, for example, Llewellyn, 34 Colum L Rev at 26-27 (cited in note 16).
    • Colum L Rev , vol.34 , pp. 26-27
    • Llewellyn1
  • 172
    • 84886463692 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 70)
    • See, for example, Seidman, 32 Cardozo L Rev at 1148 (cited in note 70);
    • Cardozo L Rev , vol.32 , pp. 1148
    • Seidman1
  • 173
    • 84886572433 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 16)
    • Llewellyn, 34 Colum L Rev at 30 (cited in note 16).
    • Colum L Rev , vol.34 , pp. 30
    • Llewellyn1
  • 174
    • 84886470062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 9)
    • See Levinson, 124 Harv L Rev at 707 (cited in note 9).
    • Harv L Rev , vol.124 , pp. 707
    • Levinson1
  • 175
  • 176
    • 0011659497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 7) (ethos)
    • Grey, 27 Stan L Rev at 706 (cited in note 7) (ethos);
    • Stan L Rev , vol.27 , pp. 706
    • Grey1
  • 177
    • 0038874371 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 12) (both)
    • Bobbitt, Constitutional Fate at 93-96 (cited in note 12) (both).
    • Constitutional Fate , pp. 93-96
    • Bobbitt1
  • 180
    • 0040563670 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 32)
    • See, for example, Black, Structure and Relationship at 31 (cited in note 32) (suggesting that structural interpretation "be brought more clearly into the conscious field"); Grey, 27 Stan L Rev at 706 (cited in note 7) (lamenting the tendency of judges to hide their nontextual reasoning).
    • Structure and Relationship , pp. 31
    • Black1
  • 181
    • 0004279652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 7)
    • See Ely, Democracy and Distrust at 43-72 (cited in note 7) (criticizing nontexual judicial review).
    • Democracy and Distrust , pp. 43-72
    • Ely1
  • 182
    • 84886486985 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 16)
    • To be sure, some leading small-c thinkers have had the opposite project: Professors Karl Llewellyn and Bruce Ackerman have both advanced theories of constitutionality arguing for the disentrenchment of norms that would otherwise be considered formally entrenched and eligible for judicial protection. Professor Llewellyn's The Constitution as an Institution, published in 1934, was an argument for letting the elected branches make far-reaching changes in federal governance without judicial interference, and Professor Ackerman's We the People is in large part a defense of the judges' having gotten out of the way of that reform program. See Llewellyn, 34 Colum L Rev at 21-23 (cited in note 16);
    • Colum L Rev , vol.34 , pp. 21-23
    • Llewellyn1
  • 185
    • 0011659497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 7)
    • See Grey, 27 Stan L Rev at 706 (cited in note 7).
    • Stan L Rev , vol.27 , pp. 706
    • Grey1
  • 186
  • 188
    • 0003374013 scopus 로고
    • Neutral principles and some first amendment problems
    • 1
    • Robert H. Bork, Neutral Principles and Some First Amendment Problems, 47 Ind L J 1, 1 (1971).
    • (1971) Ind L J , vol.47 , pp. 1
    • Bork, R.H.1
  • 189
    • 0004279652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 7)
    • See also Ely, Democracy and Distrust at 43-72 (cited in note 7) (recognizing the limits of pure textualism but criticizing the idea that judicial review should enforce nontextual fundamental values).
    • Democracy and Distrust , pp. 43-72
    • Ely1
  • 190
    • 84886492714 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 47-49, 67-82, 163 (cited in note 11)
    • See Tiedeman, The Unwritten Constitution at 42-44, 47-49, 67-82, 163 (cited in note 11). Professor Tiedeman knew nothing of the Warren Court, of course. For him, a leading example of sound judicial review without textual warrant was the Court's decision in Slaughter-House. See id at 102-09.
    • The Unwritten Constitution , pp. 42-44
    • Tiedeman1
  • 192
    • 0038874371 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 12)
    • Professor Bobbitt's narrative of the rising influence of Justice Hugo Black as a response to the apparent nontextual judging of the midcentury Court offers an exemplary illustration. In Professor Bobbitt's telling, it was precisely the worry that the midcentury Court lacked firm and objective bases for its exercises of judicial review that make Justice Black's endorsement of simple textualism seem so compelling. See Bobbitt, Constitutional Fate at 29-33 (cited in note 12).
    • Constitutional Fate , pp. 29-33
    • Bobbitt1
  • 196
    • 84886532965 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 9)
    • Pub L No 79-404, ch 324, 60 Stat 237 (1946), codified as amended in various sections of Title 5. See also Eskridge and Ferejohn, A Republic of Statutes at 10-11 (cited in note 9).
    • A Republic of Statutes , pp. 10-11
    • Eskridge1    Ferejohn2
  • 197
    • 84886532965 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 9)
    • Pub L No 89-110, 79 Stat 437 (1965), codified as amended at 42 USC § 1971 et seq. See also Eskridge and Ferejohn, A Republic of Statutes at 88-89 (cited in note 9).
    • A Republic of Statutes , pp. 88-89
    • Eskridge1    Ferejohn2
  • 198
    • 84886532965 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 9)
    • Clean Air Act of 1963, Pub L No 88-206, 77 Stat 392, codified at 42 USC § 7401 et seq. See also Eskridge and Ferejohn, A Republic of Statutes at 256 (cited in note 9).
    • A Republic of Statutes , pp. 256
    • Eskridge1    Ferejohn2
  • 199
    • 84886532965 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 9)
    • Federal Water Pollution Control Act Amendments of 1972, Pub L No 92-500, 86 Stat 816, codified at 33 USC § 1251 et seq. See Eskridge and Ferejohn, A Republic of Statutes at 256 (cited in note 9).
    • A Republic of Statutes , pp. 256
    • Eskridge1    Ferejohn2
  • 201
    • 84886574162 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 132)
    • See, for example, Eskridge, 41 UC Davis L Rev at 5-6 (cited in note 132).
    • UC Davis L Rev , vol.41 , pp. 5-6
    • Eskridge1
  • 204
    • 84886536460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 50)
    • Strauss, 114 Harv L Rev at 1458-59 (cited in note 50);
    • Harv L Rev , vol.114 , pp. 1458-1459
    • Strauss1
  • 205
    • 84886534872 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 15)
    • Strauss, 63 U Chi L Rev at 877-79 (cited in note 15).
    • U Chi L Rev , vol.63 , pp. 877-879
    • Strauss1
  • 206
    • 84886534872 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 15)
    • See, for example, Strauss, 63 U Chi L Rev at 877 (cited in note 15).
    • U Chi L Rev , vol.63 , pp. 877
    • Strauss1
  • 207
    • 0041920709 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 50)
    • See Strauss, 114 Harv L Rev at 1457-58 (cited in note 50).
    • Harv L Rev , vol.114 , pp. 1457-1458
    • Strauss1
  • 208
    • 84886567844 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 15)
    • See, for example, Strauss, 63 U Chi L Rev at 929 (cited in note 15).
    • U Chi L Rev , vol.63 , pp. 929
    • Strauss1
  • 210
    • 84886524000 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cited in note 50)
    • Strauss, 114 Harv L Rev at 1459 (cited in note 50).
    • Harv L Rev , vol.114 , pp. 1459
    • Strauss1
  • 211
    • 84886561764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 886-87 (cited in note 15)
    • Strauss, 63 U Chi L Rev at 879, 886-87 (cited in note 15).
    • U Chi L Rev , vol.63 , pp. 879
    • Strauss1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.