메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 14, Issue 4, 2008, Pages 281-309

Exploring the proof paradoxes

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 77955258198     PISSN: 13523252     EISSN: 14698048     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S1352325208080117     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (91)

References (98)
  • 1
    • 85022419755 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Clarifying the Burden of Persuasion: What Bayesian Decision Rules Do and Do Not Do, 3 Evidence & Proof 1 D. Hamer, Probabilistic Standards of Proof, Their Complements, and the Errors That Are Expected to Flow from Them, 1 U. N. Eng. L.J. 71 (2004)
    • Good accounts include D.H. Kaye, Clarifying the Burden of Persuasion: What Bayesian Decision Rules Do and Do Not Do, 3 Evidence & Proof 1 (1999) D. Hamer, Probabilistic Standards of Proof, Their Complements, and the Errors That Are Expected to Flow from Them, 1 U. N. Eng. L.J. 71 (2004)
    • (1999) Good accounts include D.H. Kaye
  • 2
    • 0004266879 scopus 로고
    • ch. 5; R.J. Allen & S.A. Jehl, Burdens of Persuasion in Civil Cases: Algorithms v. Explanations, 4 Mich. St. L. Rev. 893 (2003)
    • See, e.g., L.J. Cohen, The Probable and the Provable (1977), ch. 5; R.J. Allen & S.A. Jehl, Burdens of Persuasion in Civil Cases: Algorithms v. Explanations, 4 Mich. St. L. Rev. 893 (2003)
    • (1977) The Probable and the Provable
    • Cohen, L.J.1
  • 3
    • 77950416760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Philosophy of Evidence Law: Justice in the Search for Truth, at
    • An excellent review of the literature is H.L. Ho, A Philosophy of Evidence Law: Justice in the Search for Truth (2008), at 135-143
    • (2008) An excellent review of the literature is H.L. Ho , pp. 135-143
  • 4
    • 85022398766 scopus 로고
    • Reasonable Doubt and Permissive Inferences: The Value of Complexity, 92 Harv. L. Rev. 1187
    • This example originates in C.R. Nesson, Reasonable Doubt and Permissive Inferences: The Value of Complexity, 92 Harv. L. Rev. 1187 (1979)
    • (1979) This example originates in C.R. Nesson
  • 5
    • 85022434271 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dangerousness and Citizenship, in Fundamentals of Sentencing Theory: Essays in Honour of Andrew von Hirsch (A. Ashworth & M. Wasik eds., )
    • The example is taken from R.A. Duff, Dangerousness and Citizenship, in Fundamentals of Sentencing Theory: Essays in Honour of Andrew von Hirsch (A. Ashworth & M. Wasik eds., 1998)
    • (1998) The example is taken from R.A. Duff
  • 6
    • 85022349169 scopus 로고
    • 33 Cal.2d 80, 199 P.2d 1. In the actual case, the court found both defendants liable. This version is taken from J.J. Thomson, Liability and Individualized Evidence, in Rights, Restitution and Risk: Essays in Moral Theory (W.A. Parent ed., 1986)
    • A variation on Summers v. Tice, 33 Cal.2d 80, 199 P.2d 1 (1948). In the actual case, the court found both defendants liable. This version is taken from J.J. Thomson, Liability and Individualized Evidence, in Rights, Restitution and Risk: Essays in Moral Theory (W.A. Parent ed., 1986)
    • (1948) A variation on Summers v. Tice
  • 7
    • 85022439095 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an introduction to the litigation, see A.J. Izenman, Introduction to Two Views on the Shonubi Case, in Statistical Science in the Courtroom (J.L. Gastwirth ed., )
    • The Shonubi case gave rise to a number of different judgments. For an introduction to the litigation, see A.J. Izenman, Introduction to Two Views on the Shonubi Case, in Statistical Science in the Courtroom (J.L. Gastwirth ed., 2000)
    • (2000) The Shonubi case gave rise to a number of different judgments
  • 9
    • 85022373978 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • When Do Courts Think Base Rate Statistics Are Relevant?, 42 Jurimetrics J. 373
    • A useful review of the case law is J.J. Koehler, When Do Courts Think Base Rate Statistics Are Relevant?, 42 Jurimetrics J. 373 (2002)
    • (2002) A useful review of the case law is J.J. Koehler
  • 10
    • 85022406957 scopus 로고
    • 469, 58 N.E.2d 754
    • Mass. 469, 58 N.E.2d 754 (1945)
    • (1945) Mass
  • 11
    • 33747040745 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 998 F.2d 84 (2d Cir. 1993); see also United States v. Shonubi, 103 F.3d 1085 (2d Cir. )
    • United States v. Shonubi, 998 F.2d 84 (2d Cir. 1993); see also United States v. Shonubi, 103 F.3d 1085 (2d Cir. 1997)
    • (1997) United States v. Shonubi
  • 14
    • 85022450162 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 998 F.2d at
    • See Shonubi, 998 F.2d at 89
    • Shonubi , pp. 89
  • 18
    • 85022372672 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see M. Redmayne, Objective Probability and the Law of Evidence, 2 Law, Probability & Risk 275 10.1093/lpr/2.4.275
    • For an overview, see M. Redmayne, Objective Probability and the Law of Evidence, 2 Law, Probability & Risk 275 (2003) 10.1093/lpr/2.4.275
    • (2003) For an overview
  • 22
    • 34249712324 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • it can be molded to fit other theories of probability, too, with the exception of the extreme subjectivism rejected above. See A. Hájek, The Reference Class Problem Is Your Problem Too, 156 Synthese
    • While the reference-class problem is generally associated with frequentist theories of probability, it can be molded to fit other theories of probability, too, with the exception of the extreme subjectivism rejected above. See A. Hájek, The Reference Class Problem Is Your Problem Too, 156 Synthese 563 (2007)
    • (2007) While the reference-class problem is generally associated with frequentist theories of probability , pp. 563
  • 23
    • 34047273943 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 36 J. Legal Stud. 107 (2007) M. Colyvan, H.M. Regan & S. Ferson, Is It a Crime to Belong to a Reference Class? 9 J. Pol. Phil. 168, reprinted in Probability Is the Very Guide of Life: The Philosophical Uses of Chance (H.E. Kyburg & M. Thalos eds., 2003)
    • R.J. Allen & M.S. Pardo, The Problematic Value of Mathematical Models of Evidence, 36 J. Legal Stud. 107 (2007) M. Colyvan, H.M. Regan & S. Ferson, Is It a Crime to Belong to a Reference Class? 9 J. Pol. Phil. 168 (2001), reprinted in Probability Is the Very Guide of Life: The Philosophical Uses of Chance (H.E. Kyburg & M. Thalos eds., 2003)
    • (2001) The Problematic Value of Mathematical Models of Evidence
    • Allen, R.J.1    Pardo, M.S.2
  • 24
    • 85022349785 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Problematic Value of Mathematical Models of Evidence note 24, at
    • Allen & Pardo, The Problematic Value of Mathematical Models of Evidence note 24, at 109
    • Allen & Pardo , pp. 109
  • 25
    • 85022364666 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Regan & Ferson, Allen & Pardo note 24, at
    • Colyvan, Regan & Ferson, Allen & Pardo note 24, at 172
    • Colyvan , pp. 172
  • 26
    • 85022350878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 11 Evidence & Proof 274, at 279, where the toll-collector argument is described as a “bad defence.” This is not as obvious in the original article
    • See M. Colyvan & H.M. Regan, Legal Decisions and the Reference Class Problem, 11 Evidence & Proof 274 (2007), at 279, where the toll-collector argument is described as a “bad defence.” This is not as obvious in the original article
    • (2007) Legal Decisions and the Reference Class Problem
    • Colyvan, M.1    Regan, H.M.2
  • 27
    • 85022349785 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legal Decisions and the Reference Class Problem note 24 at
    • Allen & Pardo, Legal Decisions and the Reference Class Problem note 24 at 109
    • Allen & Pardo , pp. 109
  • 29
    • 85022400704 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • it is not clear what this means, given that no human classes will ever be completely homogenous. In reality, there is some evidence to suggest that organized drug smugglers have little choice about the amount they smuggle, and this is likely to undermine the importance of factors personal to the smuggler in determining the amount swallowed; A.J. Izenman, Assessing the Statistical Evidence in the Shonubi Case, in Statistical Science in the Courtroom (J.L. Gastwirth ed., ), at
    • They appear to allow that the reference-class problem can be overcome if the reference class is “homogenous”; it is not clear what this means, given that no human classes will ever be completely homogenous. In reality, there is some evidence to suggest that organized drug smugglers have little choice about the amount they smuggle, and this is likely to undermine the importance of factors personal to the smuggler in determining the amount swallowed; A.J. Izenman, Assessing the Statistical Evidence in the Shonubi Case, in Statistical Science in the Courtroom (J.L. Gastwirth ed., 2000), at 423-424
    • (2000) They appear to allow that the reference-class problem can be overcome if the reference class is “homogenous”; , pp. 423-424
  • 31
    • 33845718912 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in Probability Is the Very Guide of Life: The Philosophical Uses of Chance (H.E. Kyburg & M. Thalos eds., )
    • See A. Hájek, Conditional Probability Is the Very Guide of Life, in Probability Is the Very Guide of Life: The Philosophical Uses of Chance (H.E. Kyburg & M. Thalos eds., 2003)
    • (2003) Conditional Probability Is the Very Guide of Life
    • Hájek, A.1
  • 32
    • 85022409926 scopus 로고
    • Much of the debate sparked by this work can be found in Probability and Inference in the Law of Evidence (P. Tillers & E. Green eds., 1988), which collects papers originally published at 66 B.U. L. Rev.
    • See, in particular, Cohen, Conditional Probability Is the Very Guide of Life note 2. Much of the debate sparked by this work can be found in Probability and Inference in the Law of Evidence (P. Tillers & E. Green eds., 1988), which collects papers originally published at 66 B.U. L. Rev. 377-952 (1986)
    • (1986) particular, Cohen, Conditional Probability Is the Very Guide of Life note 2 , pp. 377-952
  • 33
    • 85022350228 scopus 로고
    • (1986), ch. 3; see also the discussion, followed by commentary, in L.J. Cohen, Can Human Irrationality Be Experimentally Demonstrated?, 4 Behav. & Brain Sci. 317
    • See L.J. Cohen, The Dialogue of Reason: An Analysis of Analytical Philosophy (1986), ch. 3; see also the discussion, followed by commentary, in L.J. Cohen, Can Human Irrationality Be Experimentally Demonstrated?, 4 Behav. & Brain Sci. 317 (1981)
    • (1981) The Dialogue of Reason: An Analysis of Analytical Philosophy
    • Cohen, L.J.1
  • 34
    • 85022423580 scopus 로고
    • The Dialogue of Reason: An Analysis of Analytical Philosophy note 34, at 165-192. See also R.J. Allen, On the Significance of Batting Averages and Strikeout Totals, 65 Tul. L. Rev. 1093
    • See Cohen, Dialogue of Reason, The Dialogue of Reason: An Analysis of Analytical Philosophy note 34, at 165-192. See also R.J. Allen, On the Significance of Batting Averages and Strikeout Totals, 65 Tul. L. Rev. 1093 (1991)
    • (1991) Dialogue of Reason
    • Cohen1
  • 35
    • 85022359442 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dialogue of Reason note 34, at
    • Cohen, Dialogue of Reason, Dialogue of Reason note 34, at 165.
    • Dialogue of Reason , pp. 165
    • Cohen1
  • 36
    • 85022427328 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Allen & Pardo, Dialogue of Reason note 24); indeed, they would argue that the fundamental structure of proof is explanatory (see M.S. Pardo & R.J. Allen, Juridical Proof and the Best Explanation, 27 Law & Phil. 223 ). This line of argument is not explored here, because in this context it adds nothing to causal accounts of the paradoxes
    • Another way of making the point is that the factors are explanatory; explanation plays a significant role in Allen & Pardo's discussion of the reference-class problem. (Allen & Pardo, Dialogue of Reason note 24); indeed, they would argue that the fundamental structure of proof is explanatory (see M.S. Pardo & R.J. Allen, Juridical Proof and the Best Explanation, 27 Law & Phil. 223 (2008)). This line of argument is not explored here, because in this context it adds nothing to causal accounts of the paradoxes
    • (2008) Another way of making the point is that the factors are explanatory; explanation plays a significant role in Allen & Pardo's discussion of the reference-class problem
  • 37
    • 85022359442 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Another way of making the point is that the factors are explanatory; explanation plays a significant role in Allen & Pardo's discussion of the reference-class problem note 34, at
    • Cohen, Dialogue of Reason, Another way of making the point is that the factors are explanatory; explanation plays a significant role in Allen & Pardo's discussion of the reference-class problem note 34, at 167
    • Dialogue of Reason , pp. 167
    • Cohen1
  • 38
    • 85022416006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see id. at 166 for his “freshman” example; and discussion id. at 175, 177. But the precise point in the text is not explicitly discussed in Dialogue, where Cohen's emphasis is on psychological experiments that involve combining probabilities, and his argument is that one probability is more counterfactualizable than another and thus may rationally dominate calculations
    • Cohen comes close to accepting this: see id. at 166 for his “freshman” example; and discussion id. at 175, 177. But the precise point in the text is not explicitly discussed in Dialogue, where Cohen's emphasis is on psychological experiments that involve combining probabilities, and his argument is that one probability is more counterfactualizable than another and thus may rationally dominate calculations
    • Cohen comes close to accepting this
  • 39
    • 85022394326 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • When discussing experiments in which subjects see colored chips drawn from a bag and are asked to state the probability that the bag is the one in which chips of a particular color predominate, Cohen criticizes psychologists for presuming that subjects should think that the draws are random. Subjects, he argues, are right to “allow for the effect of any bias in how chips lie, or are drawable from, a particular bag,” and thus should let the prior probability of picking a bag containing mainly, e.g., red chips dominate their calculations, because “the drawing of the bag is stated to have been at random” (id. at 169). This is a rather gerrymandered argument: one can raise the same concerns about bias in how the bags lie or are chosen; and in any case, the possibility of bias in the bag does not tell us whether the bias will be towards red chips or blue chips (though there is presumably more likely to be a pocket of balls of the predominant color)
    • Cohen does argue that the noncounterfactualizability of this probability is significant. When discussing experiments in which subjects see colored chips drawn from a bag and are asked to state the probability that the bag is the one in which chips of a particular color predominate, Cohen criticizes psychologists for presuming that subjects should think that the draws are random. Subjects, he argues, are right to “allow for the effect of any bias in how chips lie, or are drawable from, a particular bag,” and thus should let the prior probability of picking a bag containing mainly, e.g., red chips dominate their calculations, because “the drawing of the bag is stated to have been at random” (id. at 169). This is a rather gerrymandered argument: one can raise the same concerns about bias in how the bags lie or are chosen; and in any case, the possibility of bias in the bag does not tell us whether the bias will be towards red chips or blue chips (though there is presumably more likely to be a pocket of balls of the predominant color)
    • Cohen does argue that the noncounterfactualizability of this probability is significant
  • 40
    • 85022444016 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in Probability Is the Very Guide of Life: The Philosophical Uses of Chance (H.E. Kyburg & M. Thalos eds., 2003); S. Campbell & J. Franklin, Randomness and the Justification of Induction, 138 Synthese 79 (2004) J.E. Adler, Belief's Own Ethics, at
    • See T. McGrew, Direct Inference and the Problem of Induction, in Probability Is the Very Guide of Life: The Philosophical Uses of Chance (H.E. Kyburg & M. Thalos eds., 2003); S. Campbell & J. Franklin, Randomness and the Justification of Induction, 138 Synthese 79 (2004) J.E. Adler, Belief's Own Ethics (2002), at 250-254
    • (2002) Direct Inference and the Problem of Induction , pp. 250-254
    • McGrew, T.1
  • 41
    • 85022369495 scopus 로고
    • (Cohen, Direct Inference and the Problem of Induction note 2), Cohen's discussion is in terms of weight, but by the time of An Introduction to the Philosophy of Induction and Probability, he suggests that weight can be analyzed in terms of counterfactualizability (L.J. Cohen, An Introduction to the Philosophy of Induction and Probability, at 109 n. 22)
    • In The Probable and the Provable (Cohen, Direct Inference and the Problem of Induction note 2), Cohen's discussion is in terms of weight, but by the time of An Introduction to the Philosophy of Induction and Probability, he suggests that weight can be analyzed in terms of counterfactualizability (L.J. Cohen, An Introduction to the Philosophy of Induction and Probability (1989), at 109 n. 22)
    • (1989) The Probable and the Provable
  • 44
    • 85022414670 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (2005), at 47-53. Duff discusses this theory of character in more detail in R.A. Duff, Criminal Attempts, at
    • See V. Tadros, Criminal Responsibility (2005), at 47-53. Duff discusses this theory of character in more detail in R.A. Duff, Criminal Attempts (1996), at 175-192
    • (1996) Criminal Responsibility , pp. 175-192
    • Tadros, V.1
  • 45
    • 85022449765 scopus 로고
    • at 155. In this context, the idea of a presumption of harmlessness seems to be due to J. Floud & W. Young, Dangerousness and Criminal Justice, at 43-45. While Floud and Young view the presumption as an important moral constraint on incapacitation, they see it as a restraint on practice (only those convicted of an offence should be considered for incapacitation on the basis of likely future offending) and do not discuss the issue considered here: whether the presumption should constrain the sort of evidence we use to judge dangerousness
    • Duff, Criminal Responsibility note 5, at 155. In this context, the idea of a presumption of harmlessness seems to be due to J. Floud & W. Young, Dangerousness and Criminal Justice (1981), at 43-45. While Floud and Young view the presumption as an important moral constraint on incapacitation, they see it as a restraint on practice (only those convicted of an offence should be considered for incapacitation on the basis of likely future offending) and do not discuss the issue considered here: whether the presumption should constrain the sort of evidence we use to judge dangerousness
    • (1981) Criminal Responsibility note 5
    • Duff1
  • 47
    • 85022413344 scopus 로고
    • in one sense lawbreakers are more autonomous than the (literally) heteronomous law-abiding, and there is a certain romantic view of crime under which offending is an expression of freedom. Lurking here, however, are difficult questions about the meaning of autonomy. On a Kantian view of autonomy, the opposite conclusion would be reached, for lawbreakers lack autonomy because they cannot will their crimes as universal law. On this account of autonomy, see O. O'Neill, Autonomy, Coherence and Independence, in Liberalism, Citizenship, and Autonomy (D. Milligan & W.W. Miller eds., ). It is clear from context, however, that neither Wasserman nor Duff are using “autonomy” in this Kantian sense. Nor is there any need to settle debates about the meaning of autonomy for the purposes of the present discussion; Kantians are free to replace references to autonomy in the text with references to some other concept, such as independence.
    • Indeed, in one sense lawbreakers are more autonomous than the (literally) heteronomous law-abiding, and there is a certain romantic view of crime under which offending is an expression of freedom. Lurking here, however, are difficult questions about the meaning of autonomy. On a Kantian view of autonomy, the opposite conclusion would be reached, for lawbreakers lack autonomy because they cannot will their crimes as universal law. On this account of autonomy, see O. O'Neill, Autonomy, Coherence and Independence, in Liberalism, Citizenship, and Autonomy (D. Milligan & W.W. Miller eds., 1992). It is clear from context, however, that neither Wasserman nor Duff are using “autonomy” in this Kantian sense. Nor is there any need to settle debates about the meaning of autonomy for the purposes of the present discussion; Kantians are free to replace references to autonomy in the text with references to some other concept, such as independence.
    • (1992) Indeed
  • 48
    • 0003956640 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (1986), at 155-156; Patricia Smith, Liberalism and Affirmative Obligation, at
    • See J. Raz, The Morality of Freedom (1986), at 155-156; Patricia Smith, Liberalism and Affirmative Obligation (1998), at 87-88
    • (1998) The Morality of Freedom , pp. 87-88
    • Raz, J.1
  • 49
    • 85022434450 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Regan & Ferson's claims, though he suggests a slightly different one. See P. Tillers, If Wishes Were Horses: Discursive Comments on Attempts to Prevent Individuals from Being Unfairly Burdened by Their Reference Classes, 4 Law, Probability & Risk
    • Peter Tillers also claims that a moral argument underlies Colyvan, Regan & Ferson's claims, though he suggests a slightly different one. See P. Tillers, If Wishes Were Horses: Discursive Comments on Attempts to Prevent Individuals from Being Unfairly Burdened by Their Reference Classes, 4 Law, Probability & Risk 33 (2005)
    • (2005) Peter Tillers also claims that a moral argument underlies Colyvan , pp. 33
  • 50
    • 85022448845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Colyvan, Regan & Ferson, Peter Tillers also claims that a moral argument underlies Colyvan note 24, at
    • As they acknowledge; Colyvan, Regan & Ferson, Peter Tillers also claims that a moral argument underlies Colyvan note 24, at 175
    • As they acknowledge , pp. 175
  • 51
    • 0003652116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (2005). Cf. D.C. Funder, Personality Judgment: A Realistic Approach to Person Perception
    • See, e.g., J.M. Doris, Lack of Character: Personality and Moral Behavior (2005). Cf. D.C. Funder, Personality Judgment: A Realistic Approach to Person Perception (1999)
    • (1999) Lack of Character: Personality and Moral Behavior
    • Doris, J.M.1
  • 52
    • 85022403229 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (3d ed. 2007), esp. ch. 2; P. Roberts & A. Zuckerman, Criminal Evidence (2004), esp. ch. 4; H.L. Ho, Justice in the Pursuit of Truth: A Moral Defence of the Similar Facts Rule, 35 Common L. World Rev. 51 (2006). Cf. L. Laudan, Truth, Error and Criminal Law: An Essay in Legal Epistemology, esp. chs.
    • See, e.g., I.H. Dennis, The Law of Evidence (3d ed. 2007), esp. ch. 2; P. Roberts & A. Zuckerman, Criminal Evidence (2004), esp. ch. 4; H.L. Ho, Justice in the Pursuit of Truth: A Moral Defence of the Similar Facts Rule, 35 Common L. World Rev. 51 (2006). Cf. L. Laudan, Truth, Error and Criminal Law: An Essay in Legal Epistemology (2006), esp. chs. 7, 9
    • (2006) The Law of Evidence , vol.7 , pp. 9
    • Dennis, I.H.1
  • 54
    • 85022412143 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Responsibility, Risk, Probability, Naked Statistics, and Proof, 73 Iowa L. Rev. 1001, at
    • Cf. R.W. Wright, Causation, Responsibility, Risk, Probability, Naked Statistics, and Proof, 73 Iowa L. Rev. 1001 (1998), at 1059-1061
    • (1998) Causation , pp. 1059-1061
    • Wright, R.W.1
  • 55
    • 85022378526 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see discussion in the following subsection; and J. Greco, Knowledge as Credit for True Belief, in Intellectual Virtue: Perspectives from Ethics and Epistemology (M. DePaul & L. Zagzebski eds., )
    • Explaining just when a conclusion is due to luck is obviously difficult; see discussion in the following subsection; and J. Greco, Knowledge as Credit for True Belief, in Intellectual Virtue: Perspectives from Ethics and Epistemology (M. DePaul & L. Zagzebski eds., 2007)
    • (2007) Explaining just when a conclusion is due to luck is obviously difficult
  • 61
    • 84911160599 scopus 로고
    • 23 Analysis 121 (1963). A good discussion is L. Zagzebski, The Inescapability of Gettier Cases, 44 Phil. Q. 65
    • See E. Gettier, Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?, 23 Analysis 121 (1963). A good discussion is L. Zagzebski, The Inescapability of Gettier Cases, 44 Phil. Q. 65 (1994)
    • (1994) Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?
    • Gettier, E.1
  • 62
    • 85022438944 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (2007), at 89-91. For a skeptical response to this claim, see J.F. Beltrán, Legal Proof and Fact Finders’ Beliefs, 12 Legal Theory 293 at
    • See, e.g., R.A. Duff et al., The Trial on Trial: Volume Three: Towards a Normative Theory of the Criminal Trial (2007), at 89-91. For a skeptical response to this claim, see J.F. Beltrán, Legal Proof and Fact Finders’ Beliefs, 12 Legal Theory 293 (2006) at 301-303
    • (2006) The Trial on Trial: Volume Three: Towards a Normative Theory of the Criminal Trial , pp. 301-303
    • Duff, R.A.1
  • 64
    • 85022378187 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (id.) is suggestive, there are more complex examples of Gettier cases, and it is not clear that these raise antiliability intuitions. For a skeptical view on importing the Gettier requirement to verdicts, see Sorensen, The Field of Evidence and the Field of Knowledge note
    • While the example used by Pardo (id.) is suggestive, there are more complex examples of Gettier cases, and it is not clear that these raise antiliability intuitions. For a skeptical view on importing the Gettier requirement to verdicts, see Sorensen, The Field of Evidence and the Field of Knowledge note 59
    • While the example used by Pardo , pp. 59
  • 65
    • 85022351804 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beliefs can be more or less justified, but exactly how well justified does a belief have to be to count as knowledge? It is not easy to find a cutoff point, and some of the more radical analyses might allow something like weak knowledge that could be applied to civil cases; see S. Hetherington, Good Knowledge, Bad Knowledge: On Two Dogmas of Epistemology. Contextualists also admit of variable standards for knowledge; contextualism is discussed briefly below, but it is doubtful that contextualists would go so low as the balance of probabilities.
    • This does raise the question of how high the justification criterion for knowledge should be. Beliefs can be more or less justified, but exactly how well justified does a belief have to be to count as knowledge? It is not easy to find a cutoff point, and some of the more radical analyses might allow something like weak knowledge that could be applied to civil cases; see S. Hetherington, Good Knowledge, Bad Knowledge: On Two Dogmas of Epistemology (2001). Contextualists also admit of variable standards for knowledge; contextualism is discussed briefly below, but it is doubtful that contextualists would go so low as the balance of probabilities.
    • (2001) This does raise the question of how high the justification criterion for knowledge should be
  • 66
    • 85184718697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Knowledge, and Rationality, 109 Phil. Rev. 373 (2000). Nelkin's article also points to another way of analyzing the proof paradoxes. Nelkin draws parallels between Lottery and a similar paradox that involves belief rather than knowledge: you hold a ticket in a large lottery; it is initially plausible to suppose that you believe that the ticket will not win, as it is very improbable that it will. But you should then be prepared to form the same belief about any ticket in the lottery; the conjunction of your beliefs then entails that you believe that no ticket will win, hence the paradox. Nelkin resolves the belief version of the Lottery paradox by arguing that you do not in fact believe that your ticket will lose because, again, of the missing causal element. One might then argue that what is required for verdicts is belief rather than knowledge and that it is belief that is missing in the proof paradoxes. This possibility is not pursued at length here, largely because Nelkin's argument about the lack of belief in the belief version of the Lottery paradox has received little support. See, further, D. Christensen, Putting Logic in Its Place: Formal Constraints on Rational Belief. For a skeptical view of a belief requirement for verdicts, see Beltrán, This does raise the question of how high the justification criterion for knowledge should be note
    • D.K. Nelkin, The Lottery Paradox, Knowledge, and Rationality, 109 Phil. Rev. 373 (2000). Nelkin's article also points to another way of analyzing the proof paradoxes. Nelkin draws parallels between Lottery and a similar paradox that involves belief rather than knowledge: you hold a ticket in a large lottery; it is initially plausible to suppose that you believe that the ticket will not win, as it is very improbable that it will. But you should then be prepared to form the same belief about any ticket in the lottery; the conjunction of your beliefs then entails that you believe that no ticket will win, hence the paradox. Nelkin resolves the belief version of the Lottery paradox by arguing that you do not in fact believe that your ticket will lose because, again, of the missing causal element. One might then argue that what is required for verdicts is belief rather than knowledge and that it is belief that is missing in the proof paradoxes. This possibility is not pursued at length here, largely because Nelkin's argument about the lack of belief in the belief version of the Lottery paradox has received little support. See, further, D. Christensen, Putting Logic in Its Place: Formal Constraints on Rational Belief (2004). For a skeptical view of a belief requirement for verdicts, see Beltrán, This does raise the question of how high the justification criterion for knowledge should be note 70
    • (2004) The Lottery Paradox , pp. 70
    • Nelkin, D.K.1
  • 67
    • 84945657680 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also the discussion in Duncan Pritchard, Knowledge, Luck and Lotteries, in New Waves in Epistemology (D. Pritchard & V. Hendricks eds., 2008)
    • Duncan Pritchard, Epistemic Luck (2005). See also the discussion in Duncan Pritchard, Knowledge, Luck and Lotteries, in New Waves in Epistemology (D. Pritchard & V. Hendricks eds., 2008)
    • (2005) Epistemic Luck
    • Pritchard, D.1
  • 68
    • 34748812482 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see A. Hiller & R. Neta, Safety and Epistemic Luck, 158 Synthese 303 (2007) J. Comesaña, Unsafe Knowledge, 146 Synthese 395 (2005) J. Lackey, Pritchard's Epistemic Luck, 56 Phil. Q. 284
    • For objections to this account, see A. Hiller & R. Neta, Safety and Epistemic Luck, 158 Synthese 303 (2007) J. Comesaña, Unsafe Knowledge, 146 Synthese 395 (2005) J. Lackey, Pritchard's Epistemic Luck, 56 Phil. Q. 284 (2006)
    • (2006) For objections to this account
  • 69
    • 85022397723 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pritchard also suggests that I do not know that I will not be able to afford the expensive house if I own a lottery ticket. It is unclear whether Pritchard would stand by his claim in respect of Heart Attack if, for example, I have a history of sudden heart attacks in my family
    • See Pritchard, Knowledge, Luck and Lotteries, For objections to this account note 75, at 46-48. Pritchard also suggests that I do not know that I will not be able to afford the expensive house if I own a lottery ticket. It is unclear whether Pritchard would stand by his claim in respect of Heart Attack if, for example, I have a history of sudden heart attacks in my family
    • Pritchard, Knowledge, Luck and Lotteries, For objections to this account note 75, at 46-48
  • 70
    • 85022413323 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see R v. Smith, Court of Appeal Criminal Division (UK), 8 February
    • For an actual example, see R v. Smith, Court of Appeal Criminal Division (UK), 8 February 2000
    • (2000) For an actual example
  • 71
    • 85022420334 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an actual example note
    • See Hiller & Neta, For an actual example note 76
    • Hiller & Neta , pp. 76
  • 72
    • 0012211679 scopus 로고
    • at 65-73; R. Nozick, Invariances: The Structure of the Objective World (2001), at
    • See D. Nute, Topics in Conditional Logic (1980), at 65-73; R. Nozick, Invariances: The Structure of the Objective World (2001), at 148-155
    • (1980) Topics in Conditional Logic , pp. 148-155
    • Nute, D.1
  • 73
    • 85022412678 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Topics in Conditional Logic note 63 E. Sosa, Relevant Alternatives, Contextualism Included, 119 Phil. Stud. 35
    • See, e.g., Hawthorne, Topics in Conditional Logic note 63 E. Sosa, Relevant Alternatives, Contextualism Included, 119 Phil. Stud. 35 (2004)
    • (2004) Hawthorne
  • 74
    • 85022398307 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There have been no surveys of the responses of the general public to Lottery cases. Cf. J.M. Weinberg, S. Nichols & S. Stich, Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions, 29 Phil. Topics
    • Or at least, the responses of the philosophically literate. There have been no surveys of the responses of the general public to Lottery cases. Cf. J.M. Weinberg, S. Nichols & S. Stich, Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions, 29 Phil. Topics 429 (2001)
    • (2001) Or at least, the responses of the philosophically literate , pp. 429
  • 75
    • 84945654770 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (2005); B. Weatherson, Questioning Contextualism, in Aspects of Knowing: Philosophical Essays (S. Hetherington ed., 2006); W.A. Davies, Knowledge Claims and Context: Loose Use, 132 Phil. Stud
    • See, e.g., J. Stanley, Knowledge and Practical Interests (2005); B. Weatherson, Questioning Contextualism, in Aspects of Knowing: Philosophical Essays (S. Hetherington ed., 2006); W.A. Davies, Knowledge Claims and Context: Loose Use, 132 Phil. Stud 395 (2007)
    • (2007) Knowledge and Practical Interests , pp. 395
    • Stanley, J.1
  • 76
    • 85022450791 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Context and the Agent's Point of View, in Contextualism in Philosophy (G. Preyer & G. Peters eds., 2005); T. Williamson, Contextualism, Context-Sensitive Invariantism, and Knowledge of Knowledge, 55 Phil. Q. 213
    • T. Williamson, Knowledge, Context and the Agent's Point of View, in Contextualism in Philosophy (G. Preyer & G. Peters eds., 2005); T. Williamson, Contextualism, Context-Sensitive Invariantism, and Knowledge of Knowledge, 55 Phil. Q. 213 (2005)
    • (2005) Knowledge
    • Williamson, T.1
  • 77
    • 85022399853 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see, e.g., R v. Watters, Court of Appeal Criminal Division (UK), 19 October. It may be that quantification alone makes doubt seem more vivid, and that particular forms of quantification (as in Blue Bus) have effects over and above this
    • That said, quantification does sometimes seem to cause courts to refuse to convict even when the evidence is very strong: see, e.g., R v. Watters, Court of Appeal Criminal Division (UK), 19 October 2000. It may be that quantification alone makes doubt seem more vivid, and that particular forms of quantification (as in Blue Bus) have effects over and above this
    • (2000) That said, quantification does sometimes seem to cause courts to refuse to convict even when the evidence is very strong
  • 81
    • 33746885600 scopus 로고
    • in Philosophical Papers (3d ed., J.O. Urmson & G.J. Warnock ed., ). It is not really accurate to describe Austin's account as a theory of knowledge; it hardly aims at completeness and is developed in the context of the problem of knowledge of other minds. However, Mark Kaplan is currently filling out the Austinian account. See M. Kaplan, If You Know You Can't be Wrong, in Epistemology Futures (S. Hetherington ed., 2006)
    • J.L. Austin, Other Minds, in Philosophical Papers (3d ed., J.O. Urmson & G.J. Warnock ed., 1979). It is not really accurate to describe Austin's account as a theory of knowledge; it hardly aims at completeness and is developed in the context of the problem of knowledge of other minds. However, Mark Kaplan is currently filling out the Austinian account. See M. Kaplan, If You Know You Can't be Wrong, in Epistemology Futures (S. Hetherington ed., 2006)
    • (1979) Other Minds
    • Austin, J.L.1
  • 83
    • 84922265051 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • “A belief is epistemically justified for knowledge, according to the “criminal” standard that we endorse, when one has strong reasons in support of it, no undefeated epistemic reason to doubt it, and no undefeated epistemic reason to believe that one's evidence for it is unreliable”; E. Conee & R. Feldman, Evidentialism: Essays in Epistemology, at 296. However, this does not really give us a clear answer to the puzzles that concern us: in Prisoners, what makes the slim possibility of the prisoner being innocent a defeater, when the same slim possibility of an eyewitness mistake is not?
    • One stream in the epistemological literature picks up on this insight and takes the nonexistence of “defeaters” as a condition for knowledge. Most tantalizingly, for our purposes, we find this comment: “A belief is epistemically justified for knowledge, according to the “criminal” standard that we endorse, when one has strong reasons in support of it, no undefeated epistemic reason to doubt it, and no undefeated epistemic reason to believe that one's evidence for it is unreliable”; E. Conee & R. Feldman, Evidentialism: Essays in Epistemology (2004), at 296. However, this does not really give us a clear answer to the puzzles that concern us: in Prisoners, what makes the slim possibility of the prisoner being innocent a defeater, when the same slim possibility of an eyewitness mistake is not?
    • (2004) One stream in the epistemological literature picks up on this insight and takes the nonexistence of “defeaters” as a condition for knowledge. Most tantalizingly, for our purposes, we find this comment
  • 85
    • 85022413466 scopus 로고
    • at 2; S. Haack, One stream in the epistemological literature picks up on this insight and takes the nonexistence of “defeaters” as a condition for knowledge. Most tantalizingly, for our purposes, we find this comment note 90 note 66, at
    • See E. Craig, Knowledge and the State of Nature (1990), at 2; S. Haack, One stream in the epistemological literature picks up on this insight and takes the nonexistence of “defeaters” as a condition for knowledge. Most tantalizingly, for our purposes, we find this comment note 90 note 66, at 7
    • (1990) Knowledge and the State of Nature , pp. 7
    • Craig, E.1
  • 87
    • 85022430579 scopus 로고
    • For actual cases that obviously call for conviction but where the evidence seems unchallengeable in the sense explored here, see R v. Straffen, [1952] 2 Q.B. 911; R v. Smith 11 Cr. App. R. 229; United States v. Veysey, 334 F.3d 600 (7th Cir. 2003). There are obvious connections here with Alex Stein's account of legal proof, though Stein arrives at the significance of challengeability by a different route; see A. Stein, Foundations of Evidence Law (2005); cf. M. Redmayne, The Structure of Evidence Law, 26 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 805 (2006) D.A Nance, Allocating the Risk of Error, 13 Legal Theory 129 (2007)
    • D can, of course, challenge the facts that he was near the crime scene, that the thread matched, and so on, but likewise, the blue bus company can challenge the fact that 60 percent of buses are blue. For actual cases that obviously call for conviction but where the evidence seems unchallengeable in the sense explored here, see R v. Straffen, [1952] 2 Q.B. 911; R v. Smith (1916) 11 Cr. App. R. 229; United States v. Veysey, 334 F.3d 600 (7th Cir. 2003). There are obvious connections here with Alex Stein's account of legal proof, though Stein arrives at the significance of challengeability by a different route; see A. Stein, Foundations of Evidence Law (2005); cf. M. Redmayne, The Structure of Evidence Law, 26 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 805 (2006) D.A Nance, Allocating the Risk of Error, 13 Legal Theory 129 (2007)
    • (1916) D can, of course, challenge the facts that he was near the crime scene, that the thread matched, and so on, but likewise, the blue bus company can challenge the fact that 60 percent of buses are blue
  • 89
    • 0003942296 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (2d ed. ), at 13-15; Haack, The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding note 66, at 7; Kaplan, The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding note
    • See J.L. Pollock & J. Cruz, Contemporary Theories of Knowledge (2d ed. 1999), at 13-15; Haack, The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding note 66, at 7; Kaplan, The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding note 95
    • (1999) Contemporary Theories of Knowledge , pp. 95
    • Pollock, J.L.1    Cruz, J.2
  • 90
    • 85022418775 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Contemporary Theories of Knowledge note 98, at
    • Pollock & Cruz, Contemporary Theories of Knowledge note 98, at 14
    • Pollock & Cruz , pp. 14
  • 91
    • 85022371767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • our knowledge that the ticket lost may be less certain than our justified true belief that it did
    • And note that (see note 64 Pollock & Cruz), our knowledge that the ticket lost may be less certain than our justified true belief that it did
    • note that (see note 64 Pollock & Cruz)
  • 92
    • 85022416009 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note that (see note 64 Pollock & Cruz) note
    • Cf. Weinberg, Nichols & Stich, note that (see note 64 Pollock & Cruz) note 82
    • Nichols & Stich , pp. 82
    • Weinberg1
  • 93
    • 85022446576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in Epistemology Futures (S. Hetherington ed., 2006), at 165 n. 22. Hetherington, Nichols & Stich note 73, at 104, describes the lottery proposition as “excellent, but not perfect, knowledge.” Olsson suggests that Isaac Levi is committed to the view that there is knowledge in Lottery, though he himself states that “our lack of knowledge [in Lottery] is as clear a part of common sense as any other claim I can think of”; E.J. Olsson, Levi and the Lottery, in Knowledge and Inquiry: Essays on the Pragmatism of Isaac Levi (E.J. Olsson ed., ), at
    • See, e.g., W. Lycan, On the Gettier Problem Problem, in Epistemology Futures (S. Hetherington ed., 2006), at 165 n. 22. Hetherington, Nichols & Stich note 73, at 104, describes the lottery proposition as “excellent, but not perfect, knowledge.” Olsson suggests that Isaac Levi is committed to the view that there is knowledge in Lottery, though he himself states that “our lack of knowledge [in Lottery] is as clear a part of common sense as any other claim I can think of”; E.J. Olsson, Levi and the Lottery, in Knowledge and Inquiry: Essays on the Pragmatism of Isaac Levi (E.J. Olsson ed., 2006), at 174
    • (2006) On the Gettier Problem Problem , pp. 174
    • Lycan, W.1
  • 96
    • 60949361920 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 72 Phil. & Phenomenological Res. 366 (2006) B. Weatherson, What Good Are Counterexamples?, 115 Phil. Stud
    • See also F. Spicer, Epistemic Intuitions and Epistemic Contextualism, 72 Phil. & Phenomenological Res. 366 (2006) B. Weatherson, What Good Are Counterexamples?, 115 Phil. Stud 1 (2003)
    • (2003) Epistemic Intuitions and Epistemic Contextualism , pp. 1
    • Spicer, F.1
  • 97
    • 85022452495 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • for example, David Lewis's response to Unger in D. Lewis, Illusory Innocence? in Papers Ethics & Soc. Phil. (2000); and Barbara Fried's to Sunstein in B. Fried, Moral Heuristics and the Means/End Distinction, 28 Behav. & Brain Sci. 549
    • Thus note, for example, David Lewis's response to Unger in D. Lewis, Illusory Innocence? in Papers Ethics & Soc. Phil. (2000); and Barbara Fried's to Sunstein in B. Fried, Moral Heuristics and the Means/End Distinction, 28 Behav. & Brain Sci. 549 (2005)
    • (2005) Thus note
  • 98
    • 85022382741 scopus 로고
    • Statistical Probability Evidence and the Appearance of Justice, 103 Harv. L. Rev. 530, at
    • A similar point is made in D. Shaviro, Statistical Probability Evidence and the Appearance of Justice, 103 Harv. L. Rev. 530 (1989), at 543
    • (1989) A similar point is made in D. Shaviro , pp. 543


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.