메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 24, Issue 2, 1999, Pages 5-55

Is Anybody Still a Realist?

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0033442950     PISSN: 01622889     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1162/016228899560130     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (459)

References (260)
  • 1
    • 0031286827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Realist Paradigm and Degenerative vs. progressive Research Programs: An Appraisal of Neotraditional Research on Waltz's Balancing Proposition
    • December
    • We agree with much of the analysis in John Vasquez, "The Realist Paradigm and Degenerative vs. Progressive Research Programs: An Appraisal of Neotraditional Research on Waltz's Balancing Proposition," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 899-912. But we do not agree, among other things, that balancing behavior per se provides a strong test of realism or that realism is beyond redemption. On various criticisms, see also Francis Fukuyama, The End of History and the Last Man (New York: Free Press, 1992); Richard Ned Lebow and Thomas Risse-Kappen, eds., International Relations and the End of the Cold War (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995); and Paul W. Schroeder, "Historical Reality vs. Neorealist Theory," in Michael E. Brown, Sean M. Lynn-Jones, and Steven E. Miller, eds., The Perils of Anarchy: Contemporary Realism and International Security (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995), pp. 421-461; Peter J. Katzenstein, Robert O. Keohane, and Stephen D. Krasner, "International Organization and the Study of World Politics," International Organization, Vol. 52, No. 4 (Autumn 1998), pp. 670-674; and Benjamin Frankel, ed., Realism: Restatements and Renewal (London: Frank Cass, 1996), pp. xi-xii. For rejoinders, see Kenneth N. Waltz, "Evaluating Theories," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 913-918; Thomas J. Christensen and Jack Snyder, "Progressive Research and Degenerative Alliances," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 899-912; Colin Elman and Miriam Fendius Elman, "Correspondence: History vs. Neorealism: A Second Look," International Security, Vol. 20, No. 1 (Summer 1995), pp. 182-193; Elman and Elman, "Lakatos and Neorealism: A Reply to Vasquez," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 923-926; Randall L. Schweller, "New Realist Research on Alliances: Refining, not Refuting, Waltz's Balancing Proposition," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 927-930; and Stephen M. Walt, "The Progressive Power of Realism," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 931-935.
    • (1997) American Political Science Review , vol.91 , Issue.4 , pp. 899-912
    • Vasquez, J.1
  • 2
    • 0004255582 scopus 로고
    • New York: Free Press
    • We agree with much of the analysis in John Vasquez, "The Realist Paradigm and Degenerative vs. Progressive Research Programs: An Appraisal of Neotraditional Research on Waltz's Balancing Proposition," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 899-912. But we do not agree, among other things, that balancing behavior per se provides a strong test of realism or that realism is beyond redemption. On various criticisms, see also Francis Fukuyama, The End of History and the Last Man (New York: Free Press, 1992); Richard Ned Lebow and Thomas Risse-Kappen, eds., International Relations and the End of the Cold War (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995); and Paul W. Schroeder, "Historical Reality vs. Neorealist Theory," in Michael E. Brown, Sean M. Lynn-Jones, and Steven E. Miller, eds., The Perils of Anarchy: Contemporary Realism and International Security (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995), pp. 421-461; Peter J. Katzenstein, Robert O. Keohane, and Stephen D. Krasner, "International Organization and the Study of World Politics," International Organization, Vol. 52, No. 4 (Autumn 1998), pp. 670-674; and Benjamin Frankel, ed., Realism: Restatements and Renewal (London: Frank Cass, 1996), pp. xi-xii. For rejoinders, see Kenneth N. Waltz, "Evaluating Theories," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 913-918; Thomas J. Christensen and Jack Snyder, "Progressive Research and Degenerative Alliances," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 899-912; Colin Elman and Miriam Fendius Elman, "Correspondence: History vs. Neorealism: A Second Look," International Security, Vol. 20, No. 1 (Summer 1995), pp. 182-193; Elman and Elman, "Lakatos and Neorealism: A Reply to Vasquez," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 923-926; Randall L. Schweller, "New Realist Research on Alliances: Refining, not Refuting, Waltz's Balancing Proposition," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 927-930; and Stephen M. Walt, "The Progressive Power of Realism," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 931-935.
    • (1992) The End of History and the Last Man
    • Fukuyama, F.1
  • 3
    • 0004070640 scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • We agree with much of the analysis in John Vasquez, "The Realist Paradigm and Degenerative vs. Progressive Research Programs: An Appraisal of Neotraditional Research on Waltz's Balancing Proposition," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 899-912. But we do not agree, among other things, that balancing behavior per se provides a strong test of realism or that realism is beyond redemption. On various criticisms, see also Francis Fukuyama, The End of History and the Last Man (New York: Free Press, 1992); Richard Ned Lebow and Thomas Risse-Kappen, eds., International Relations and the End of the Cold War (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995); and Paul W. Schroeder, "Historical Reality vs. Neorealist Theory," in Michael E. Brown, Sean M. Lynn-Jones, and Steven E. Miller, eds., The Perils of Anarchy: Contemporary Realism and International Security (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995), pp. 421-461; Peter J. Katzenstein, Robert O. Keohane, and Stephen D. Krasner, "International Organization and the Study of World Politics," International Organization, Vol. 52, No. 4 (Autumn 1998), pp. 670-674; and Benjamin Frankel, ed., Realism: Restatements and Renewal (London: Frank Cass, 1996), pp. xi-xii. For rejoinders, see Kenneth N. Waltz, "Evaluating Theories," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 913-918; Thomas J. Christensen and Jack Snyder, "Progressive Research and Degenerative Alliances," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 899-912; Colin Elman and Miriam Fendius Elman, "Correspondence: History vs. Neorealism: A Second Look," International Security, Vol. 20, No. 1 (Summer 1995), pp. 182-193; Elman and Elman, "Lakatos and Neorealism: A Reply to Vasquez," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 923-926; Randall L. Schweller, "New Realist Research on Alliances: Refining, not Refuting, Waltz's Balancing Proposition," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 927-930; and Stephen M. Walt, "The Progressive Power of Realism," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 931-935.
    • (1995) International Relations and the End of the Cold War
    • Lebow, R.N.1    Risse-Kappen, T.2
  • 4
    • 29244461875 scopus 로고
    • Historical Reality vs. neorealist Theory
    • Michael E. Brown, Sean M. Lynn-Jones, and Steven E. Miller, eds., Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press
    • We agree with much of the analysis in John Vasquez, "The Realist Paradigm and Degenerative vs. Progressive Research Programs: An Appraisal of Neotraditional Research on Waltz's Balancing Proposition," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 899-912. But we do not agree, among other things, that balancing behavior per se provides a strong test of realism or that realism is beyond redemption. On various criticisms, see also Francis Fukuyama, The End of History and the Last Man (New York: Free Press, 1992); Richard Ned Lebow and Thomas Risse-Kappen, eds., International Relations and the End of the Cold War (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995); and Paul W. Schroeder, "Historical Reality vs. Neorealist Theory," in Michael E. Brown, Sean M. Lynn-Jones, and Steven E. Miller, eds., The Perils of Anarchy: Contemporary Realism and International Security (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995), pp. 421-461; Peter J. Katzenstein, Robert O. Keohane, and Stephen D. Krasner, "International Organization and the Study of World Politics," International Organization, Vol. 52, No. 4 (Autumn 1998), pp. 670-674; and Benjamin Frankel, ed., Realism: Restatements and Renewal (London: Frank Cass, 1996), pp. xi-xii. For rejoinders, see Kenneth N. Waltz, "Evaluating Theories," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 913-918; Thomas J. Christensen and Jack Snyder, "Progressive Research and Degenerative Alliances," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 899-912; Colin Elman and Miriam Fendius Elman, "Correspondence: History vs. Neorealism: A Second Look," International Security, Vol. 20, No. 1 (Summer 1995), pp. 182-193; Elman and Elman, "Lakatos and Neorealism: A Reply to Vasquez," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 923-926; Randall L. Schweller, "New Realist Research on Alliances: Refining, not Refuting, Waltz's Balancing Proposition," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 927-930; and Stephen M. Walt, "The Progressive Power of Realism," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 931-935.
    • (1995) The Perils of Anarchy: Contemporary Realism and International Security , pp. 421-461
    • Schroeder, P.W.1
  • 5
    • 0007021369 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • International Organization and the Study of World Politics
    • Autumn
    • We agree with much of the analysis in John Vasquez, "The Realist Paradigm and Degenerative vs. Progressive Research Programs: An Appraisal of Neotraditional Research on Waltz's Balancing Proposition," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 899-912. But we do not agree, among other things, that balancing behavior per se provides a strong test of realism or that realism is beyond redemption. On various criticisms, see also Francis Fukuyama, The End of History and the Last Man (New York: Free Press, 1992); Richard Ned Lebow and Thomas Risse-Kappen, eds., International Relations and the End of the Cold War (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995); and Paul W. Schroeder, "Historical Reality vs. Neorealist Theory," in Michael E. Brown, Sean M. Lynn-Jones, and Steven E. Miller, eds., The Perils of Anarchy: Contemporary Realism and International Security (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995), pp. 421-461; Peter J. Katzenstein, Robert O. Keohane, and Stephen D. Krasner, "International Organization and the Study of World Politics," International Organization, Vol. 52, No. 4 (Autumn 1998), pp. 670-674; and Benjamin Frankel, ed., Realism: Restatements and Renewal (London: Frank Cass, 1996), pp. xi-xii. For rejoinders, see Kenneth N. Waltz, "Evaluating Theories," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 913-918; Thomas J. Christensen and Jack Snyder, "Progressive Research and Degenerative Alliances," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 899-912; Colin Elman and Miriam Fendius Elman, "Correspondence: History vs. Neorealism: A Second Look," International Security, Vol. 20, No. 1 (Summer 1995), pp. 182-193; Elman and Elman, "Lakatos and Neorealism: A Reply to Vasquez," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 923-926; Randall L. Schweller, "New Realist Research on Alliances: Refining, not Refuting, Waltz's Balancing Proposition," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 927-930; and Stephen M. Walt, "The Progressive Power of Realism," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 931-935.
    • (1998) International Organization , vol.52 , Issue.4 , pp. 670-674
    • Katzenstein, P.J.1    Keohane, R.O.2    Krasner, S.D.3
  • 6
    • 0010871469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • London: Frank Cass
    • We agree with much of the analysis in John Vasquez, "The Realist Paradigm and Degenerative vs. Progressive Research Programs: An Appraisal of Neotraditional Research on Waltz's Balancing Proposition," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 899-912. But we do not agree, among other things, that balancing behavior per se provides a strong test of realism or that realism is beyond redemption. On various criticisms, see also Francis Fukuyama, The End of History and the Last Man (New York: Free Press, 1992); Richard Ned Lebow and Thomas Risse-Kappen, eds., International Relations and the End of the Cold War (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995); and Paul W. Schroeder, "Historical Reality vs. Neorealist Theory," in Michael E. Brown, Sean M. Lynn-Jones, and Steven E. Miller, eds., The Perils of Anarchy: Contemporary Realism and International Security (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995), pp. 421-461; Peter J. Katzenstein, Robert O. Keohane, and Stephen D. Krasner, "International Organization and the Study of World Politics," International Organization, Vol. 52, No. 4 (Autumn 1998), pp. 670-674; and Benjamin Frankel, ed., Realism: Restatements and Renewal (London: Frank Cass, 1996), pp. xi-xii. For rejoinders, see Kenneth N. Waltz, "Evaluating Theories," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 913-918; Thomas J. Christensen and Jack Snyder, "Progressive Research and Degenerative Alliances," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 899-912; Colin Elman and Miriam Fendius Elman, "Correspondence: History vs. Neorealism: A Second Look," International Security, Vol. 20, No. 1 (Summer 1995), pp. 182-193; Elman and Elman, "Lakatos and Neorealism: A Reply to Vasquez," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 923-926; Randall L. Schweller, "New Realist Research on Alliances: Refining, not Refuting, Waltz's Balancing Proposition," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 927-930; and Stephen M. Walt, "The Progressive Power of Realism," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 931-935.
    • (1996) Realism: Restatements and Renewal , pp. 11-12
    • Frankel, B.1
  • 7
    • 0031286825 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Evaluating Theories
    • December
    • We agree with much of the analysis in John Vasquez, "The Realist Paradigm and Degenerative vs. Progressive Research Programs: An Appraisal of Neotraditional Research on Waltz's Balancing Proposition," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 899-912. But we do not agree, among other things, that balancing behavior per se provides a strong test of realism or that realism is beyond redemption. On various criticisms, see also Francis Fukuyama, The End of History and the Last Man (New York: Free Press, 1992); Richard Ned Lebow and Thomas Risse-Kappen, eds., International Relations and the End of the Cold War (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995); and Paul W. Schroeder, "Historical Reality vs. Neorealist Theory," in Michael E. Brown, Sean M. Lynn-Jones, and Steven E. Miller, eds., The Perils of Anarchy: Contemporary Realism and International Security (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995), pp. 421-461; Peter J. Katzenstein, Robert O. Keohane, and Stephen D. Krasner, "International Organization and the Study of World Politics," International Organization, Vol. 52, No. 4 (Autumn 1998), pp. 670-674; and Benjamin Frankel, ed., Realism: Restatements and Renewal (London: Frank Cass, 1996), pp. xi-xii. For rejoinders, see Kenneth N. Waltz, "Evaluating Theories," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 913-918; Thomas J. Christensen and Jack Snyder, "Progressive Research and Degenerative Alliances," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 899-912; Colin Elman and Miriam Fendius Elman, "Correspondence: History vs. Neorealism: A Second Look," International Security, Vol. 20, No. 1 (Summer 1995), pp. 182-193; Elman and Elman, "Lakatos and Neorealism: A Reply to Vasquez," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 923-926; Randall L. Schweller, "New Realist Research on Alliances: Refining, not Refuting, Waltz's Balancing Proposition," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 927-930; and Stephen M. Walt, "The Progressive Power of Realism," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 931-935.
    • (1997) American Political Science Review , vol.91 , Issue.4 , pp. 913-918
    • Waltz, K.N.1
  • 8
    • 0031286827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Progressive Research and Degenerative Alliances
    • December
    • We agree with much of the analysis in John Vasquez, "The Realist Paradigm and Degenerative vs. Progressive Research Programs: An Appraisal of Neotraditional Research on Waltz's Balancing Proposition," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 899-912. But we do not agree, among other things, that balancing behavior per se provides a strong test of realism or that realism is beyond redemption. On various criticisms, see also Francis Fukuyama, The End of History and the Last Man (New York: Free Press, 1992); Richard Ned Lebow and Thomas Risse-Kappen, eds., International Relations and the End of the Cold War (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995); and Paul W. Schroeder, "Historical Reality vs. Neorealist Theory," in Michael E. Brown, Sean M. Lynn-Jones, and Steven E. Miller, eds., The Perils of Anarchy: Contemporary Realism and International Security (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995), pp. 421-461; Peter J. Katzenstein, Robert O. Keohane, and Stephen D. Krasner, "International Organization and the Study of World Politics," International Organization, Vol. 52, No. 4 (Autumn 1998), pp. 670-674; and Benjamin Frankel, ed., Realism: Restatements and Renewal (London: Frank Cass, 1996), pp. xi-xii. For rejoinders, see Kenneth N. Waltz, "Evaluating Theories," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 913-918; Thomas J. Christensen and Jack Snyder, "Progressive Research and Degenerative Alliances," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 899-912; Colin Elman and Miriam Fendius Elman, "Correspondence: History vs. Neorealism: A Second Look," International Security, Vol. 20, No. 1 (Summer 1995), pp. 182-193; Elman and Elman, "Lakatos and Neorealism: A Reply to Vasquez," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 923-926; Randall L. Schweller, "New Realist Research on Alliances: Refining, not Refuting, Waltz's Balancing Proposition," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 927-930; and Stephen M. Walt, "The Progressive Power of Realism," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 931-935.
    • (1997) American Political Science Review , vol.91 , Issue.4 , pp. 899-912
    • Christensen, T.J.1    Snyder, J.2
  • 9
    • 0000030571 scopus 로고
    • Correspondence: History vs. neorealism: A Second Look
    • Summer
    • We agree with much of the analysis in John Vasquez, "The Realist Paradigm and Degenerative vs. Progressive Research Programs: An Appraisal of Neotraditional Research on Waltz's Balancing Proposition," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 899-912. But we do not agree, among other things, that balancing behavior per se provides a strong test of realism or that realism is beyond redemption. On various criticisms, see also Francis Fukuyama, The End of History and the Last Man (New York: Free Press, 1992); Richard Ned Lebow and Thomas Risse-Kappen, eds., International Relations and the End of the Cold War (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995); and Paul W. Schroeder, "Historical Reality vs. Neorealist Theory," in Michael E. Brown, Sean M. Lynn-Jones, and Steven E. Miller, eds., The Perils of Anarchy: Contemporary Realism and International Security (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995), pp. 421-461; Peter J. Katzenstein, Robert O. Keohane, and Stephen D. Krasner, "International Organization and the Study of World Politics," International Organization, Vol. 52, No. 4 (Autumn 1998), pp. 670-674; and Benjamin Frankel, ed., Realism: Restatements and Renewal (London: Frank Cass, 1996), pp. xi-xii. For rejoinders, see Kenneth N. Waltz, "Evaluating Theories," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 913-918; Thomas J. Christensen and Jack Snyder, "Progressive Research and Degenerative Alliances," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 899-912; Colin Elman and Miriam Fendius Elman, "Correspondence: History vs. Neorealism: A Second Look," International Security, Vol. 20, No. 1 (Summer 1995), pp. 182-193; Elman and Elman, "Lakatos and Neorealism: A Reply to Vasquez," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 923-926; Randall L. Schweller, "New Realist Research on Alliances: Refining, not Refuting, Waltz's Balancing Proposition," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 927-930; and Stephen M. Walt, "The Progressive Power of Realism," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 931-935.
    • (1995) International Security , vol.20 , Issue.1 , pp. 182-193
    • Elman, E.1    Elman, M.F.2
  • 10
    • 0031286828 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lakatos and Neorealism: A Reply to Vasquez
    • December
    • We agree with much of the analysis in John Vasquez, "The Realist Paradigm and Degenerative vs. Progressive Research Programs: An Appraisal of Neotraditional Research on Waltz's Balancing Proposition," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 899-912. But we do not agree, among other things, that balancing behavior per se provides a strong test of realism or that realism is beyond redemption. On various criticisms, see also Francis Fukuyama, The End of History and the Last Man (New York: Free Press, 1992); Richard Ned Lebow and Thomas Risse-Kappen, eds., International Relations and the End of the Cold War (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995); and Paul W. Schroeder, "Historical Reality vs. Neorealist Theory," in Michael E. Brown, Sean M. Lynn-Jones, and Steven E. Miller, eds., The Perils of Anarchy: Contemporary Realism and International Security (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995), pp. 421-461; Peter J. Katzenstein, Robert O. Keohane, and Stephen D. Krasner, "International Organization and the Study of World Politics," International Organization, Vol. 52, No. 4 (Autumn 1998), pp. 670-674; and Benjamin Frankel, ed., Realism: Restatements and Renewal (London: Frank Cass, 1996), pp. xi-xii. For rejoinders, see Kenneth N. Waltz, "Evaluating Theories," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 913-918; Thomas J. Christensen and Jack Snyder, "Progressive Research and Degenerative Alliances," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 899-912; Colin Elman and Miriam Fendius Elman, "Correspondence: History vs. Neorealism: A Second Look," International Security, Vol. 20, No. 1 (Summer 1995), pp. 182-193; Elman and Elman, "Lakatos and Neorealism: A Reply to Vasquez," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 923-926; Randall L. Schweller, "New Realist Research on Alliances: Refining, not Refuting, Waltz's Balancing Proposition," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 927-930; and Stephen M. Walt, "The Progressive Power of Realism," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 931-935.
    • (1997) American Political Science Review , vol.91 , Issue.4 , pp. 923-926
    • Elman1    Elman2
  • 11
    • 0031286829 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New Realist Research on Alliances: Refining, not Refuting, Waltz's Balancing Proposition,
    • December
    • We agree with much of the analysis in John Vasquez, "The Realist Paradigm and Degenerative vs. Progressive Research Programs: An Appraisal of Neotraditional Research on Waltz's Balancing Proposition," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 899-912. But we do not agree, among other things, that balancing behavior per se provides a strong test of realism or that realism is beyond redemption. On various criticisms, see also Francis Fukuyama, The End of History and the Last Man (New York: Free Press, 1992); Richard Ned Lebow and Thomas Risse-Kappen, eds., International Relations and the End of the Cold War (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995); and Paul W. Schroeder, "Historical Reality vs. Neorealist Theory," in Michael E. Brown, Sean M. Lynn-Jones, and Steven E. Miller, eds., The Perils of Anarchy: Contemporary Realism and International Security (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995), pp. 421-461; Peter J. Katzenstein, Robert O. Keohane, and Stephen D. Krasner, "International Organization and the Study of World Politics," International Organization, Vol. 52, No. 4 (Autumn 1998), pp. 670-674; and Benjamin Frankel, ed., Realism: Restatements and Renewal (London: Frank Cass, 1996), pp. xi-xii. For rejoinders, see Kenneth N. Waltz, "Evaluating Theories," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 913-918; Thomas J. Christensen and Jack Snyder, "Progressive Research and Degenerative Alliances," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 899-912; Colin Elman and Miriam Fendius Elman, "Correspondence: History vs. Neorealism: A Second Look," International Security, Vol. 20, No. 1 (Summer 1995), pp. 182-193; Elman and Elman, "Lakatos and Neorealism: A Reply to Vasquez," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 923-926; Randall L. Schweller, "New Realist Research on Alliances: Refining, not Refuting, Waltz's Balancing Proposition," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 927-930; and Stephen M. Walt, "The Progressive Power of Realism," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 931-935.
    • (1997) American Political Science Review , vol.91 , Issue.4 , pp. 927-930
    • Schweller, R.L.1
  • 12
    • 0031286830 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Progressive Power of Realism
    • December
    • We agree with much of the analysis in John Vasquez, "The Realist Paradigm and Degenerative vs. Progressive Research Programs: An Appraisal of Neotraditional Research on Waltz's Balancing Proposition," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 899-912. But we do not agree, among other things, that balancing behavior per se provides a strong test of realism or that realism is beyond redemption. On various criticisms, see also Francis Fukuyama, The End of History and the Last Man (New York: Free Press, 1992); Richard Ned Lebow and Thomas Risse-Kappen, eds., International Relations and the End of the Cold War (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995); and Paul W. Schroeder, "Historical Reality vs. Neorealist Theory," in Michael E. Brown, Sean M. Lynn-Jones, and Steven E. Miller, eds., The Perils of Anarchy: Contemporary Realism and International Security (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995), pp. 421-461; Peter J. Katzenstein, Robert O. Keohane, and Stephen D. Krasner, "International Organization and the Study of World Politics," International Organization, Vol. 52, No. 4 (Autumn 1998), pp. 670-674; and Benjamin Frankel, ed., Realism: Restatements and Renewal (London: Frank Cass, 1996), pp. xi-xii. For rejoinders, see Kenneth N. Waltz, "Evaluating Theories," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 913-918; Thomas J. Christensen and Jack Snyder, "Progressive Research and Degenerative Alliances," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 899-912; Colin Elman and Miriam Fendius Elman, "Correspondence: History vs. Neorealism: A Second Look," International Security, Vol. 20, No. 1 (Summer 1995), pp. 182-193; Elman and Elman, "Lakatos and Neorealism: A Reply to Vasquez," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 923-926; Randall L. Schweller, "New Realist Research on Alliances: Refining, not Refuting, Waltz's Balancing Proposition," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 927-930; and Stephen M. Walt, "The Progressive Power of Realism," American Political Science Review, Vol. 91, No. 4 (December 1997), pp. 931-935.
    • (1997) American Political Science Review , vol.91 , Issue.4 , pp. 931-935
    • Walt, S.M.1
  • 13
    • 84972274409 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Concept Misinformation in Comparative Politics
    • December
    • Giovanni Sartori, "Concept Misinformation in Comparative Politics," American Political Science Review, Vol. 64, No. 4 (December 1970), pp. 1033-1053. This is another way in which our critique differs from that of Vasquez, who has also charged that the realist paradigm is degenerating. Vasquez argues that "there is no falsification before the emergence of better theory," and that alternative paradigms do not exist. We demonstrate that they do. Vasquez, "The Realist Paradigm," p. 910.
    • (1970) American Political Science Review , vol.64 , Issue.4 , pp. 1033-1053
    • Sartori, G.1
  • 14
    • 84972274409 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Giovanni Sartori, "Concept Misinformation in Comparative Politics," American Political Science Review, Vol. 64, No. 4 (December 1970), pp. 1033-1053. This is another way in which our critique differs from that of Vasquez, who has also charged that the realist paradigm is degenerating. Vasquez argues that "there is no falsification before the emergence of better theory," and that alternative paradigms do not exist. We demonstrate that they do. Vasquez, "The Realist Paradigm," p. 910.
    • The Realist Paradigm , pp. 910
    • Vasquez1
  • 15
    • 0043236441 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Vasquez, "The Realist Paradigm"; and David A. Lake and Robert Powell, eds., Strategic Choice and International Relations (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1999).
    • The Realist Paradigm
    • Vasquez1
  • 18
    • 0005699788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Restating the Realist Case
    • Frankel
    • Or a "basic theory," "research program," "school," or "approach." For similar usage, see Stephen Van Evera, cited in Benjamin Frankel, "Restating the Realist Case," in Frankel, Realism, p. xiii; and Walt, "The Progressive Power of Realism." We do not mean to imply more with the term "paradigm" than we state.
    • Realism , pp. 13
    • Van Evera, S.1    Frankel, B.2
  • 19
    • 0042735215 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Or a "basic theory," "research program," "school," or "approach." For similar usage, see Stephen Van Evera, cited in Benjamin Frankel, "Restating the Realist Case," in Frankel, Realism, p. xiii; and Walt, "The Progressive Power of Realism." We do not mean to imply more with the term "paradigm" than we state.
    • The Progressive Power of Realism
    • Walt1
  • 20
    • 0042735208 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Weatherhead Center for International Affairs Working Paper Series Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
    • For a fuller account of the desirable criteria, see Jeffrey Legro and Andrew Moravcsik, "Is Anybody Still a Realist?" Weatherhead Center for International Affairs Working Paper Series (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University, 1998). There we also employ these standards to reject paradigmatic definitions of realism based on ideal-typical outcomes (e.g., "pessimism" or "conflict"), vague concepts (e.g., "power and interest"), intellectual history, or outcomes predicted by more than one theory (e.g., "balancing").
    • (1998) Is Anybody Still a Realist?
    • Legro, J.1    Moravcsik, A.2
  • 21
    • 0042735215 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Our central criticism of recent realism is not that the realist paradigm is incoherent or indistinct simply because it generates various, even conflicting, theories and hypotheses. We do not believe that disagreement among realists per se is a sign of degeneration. See Walt, "The Progressive Power of Realism," pp. 932-933.
    • The Progressive Power of Realism , pp. 932-933
    • Walt1
  • 22
    • 0002479337 scopus 로고
    • Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programs
    • Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, eds., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See Imre Lakatos, "Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programs," in Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, eds., Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), pp. 131-132.
    • (1970) Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge , pp. 131-132
    • Lakatos, I.1
  • 23
    • 0003454816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Fundamental debates are always (at least) "three-cornered," pitting two (or more) theories against the data. See ibid., p. 115.
    • Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge , pp. 115
  • 24
    • 0004130918 scopus 로고
    • Boulder, Colo.: Westview
    • For a statement of core assumptions, see Robert O. Keohane, International Institutions and State Power (Boulder, Colo.: Westview, 1989); Stephen D. Krasner, ed., International Regimes (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1983); and Keohane, After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political Economy (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1984).
    • (1989) International Institutions and State Power
    • Keohane, R.O.1
  • 25
    • 0004318696 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press
    • For a statement of core assumptions, see Robert O. Keohane, International Institutions and State Power (Boulder, Colo.: Westview, 1989); Stephen D. Krasner, ed., International Regimes (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1983); and Keohane, After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political Economy (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1984).
    • (1983) International Regimes
    • Krasner, S.D.1
  • 26
    • 84883967565 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press
    • For a statement of core assumptions, see Robert O. Keohane, International Institutions and State Power (Boulder, Colo.: Westview, 1989); Stephen D. Krasner, ed., International Regimes (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1983); and Keohane, After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political Economy (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1984).
    • (1984) After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political Economy
    • Keohane1
  • 27
    • 0000546136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Taking Preferences Seriously: A Liberal Theory of International Politics
    • Autumn
    • For a statement of core assumptions, see Andrew Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously: A Liberal Theory of International Politics," International Organization, Vol. 51, No. 4 (Autumn 1997), pp. 513-553. Helen V. Milner, "Rationalizing Politics: The Emerging Synthesis of International, American, and Comparative Politics," International Organization, Vol. 52, No. 4 (Autumn 1998), pp. 759-786; Robert O. Keohane and Joseph S. Nye, Power and Interdependence: World Politics in Transition (Boston: Little, Brown, 1977); Michael W. Doyle, "Liberalism and World Politics," American Political Science Review, Vol. 80, No. 4 (December 1986), pp. 1151-1169; Richard Cooper, The Economics of Interdependence: Economic Policy in the Atlantic Community (New York: Columbia University Press, 1968); and Elman and Elman, "Correspondence," p. 924, all concur that such theories are nonrealist.
    • (1997) International Organization , vol.51 , Issue.4 , pp. 513-553
    • Moravcsik, A.1
  • 28
    • 84990935518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rationalizing Politics: The Emerging Synthesis of International, American, and Comparative Politics
    • Autumn
    • For a statement of core assumptions, see Andrew Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously: A Liberal Theory of International Politics," International Organization, Vol. 51, No. 4 (Autumn 1997), pp. 513-553. Helen V. Milner, "Rationalizing Politics: The Emerging Synthesis of International, American, and Comparative Politics," International Organization, Vol. 52, No. 4 (Autumn 1998), pp. 759-786; Robert O. Keohane and Joseph S. Nye, Power and Interdependence: World Politics in Transition (Boston: Little, Brown, 1977); Michael W. Doyle, "Liberalism and World Politics," American Political Science Review, Vol. 80, No. 4 (December 1986), pp. 1151-1169; Richard Cooper, The Economics of Interdependence: Economic Policy in the Atlantic Community (New York: Columbia University Press, 1968); and Elman and Elman, "Correspondence," p. 924, all concur that such theories are nonrealist.
    • (1998) International Organization , vol.52 , Issue.4 , pp. 759-786
    • Milner, H.V.1
  • 29
    • 0000546136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Boston: Little, Brown
    • For a statement of core assumptions, see Andrew Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously: A Liberal Theory of International Politics," International Organization, Vol. 51, No. 4 (Autumn 1997), pp. 513-553. Helen V. Milner, "Rationalizing Politics: The Emerging Synthesis of International, American, and Comparative Politics," International Organization, Vol. 52, No. 4 (Autumn 1998), pp. 759-786; Robert O. Keohane and Joseph S. Nye, Power and Interdependence: World Politics in Transition (Boston: Little, Brown, 1977); Michael W. Doyle, "Liberalism and World Politics," American Political Science Review, Vol. 80, No. 4 (December 1986), pp. 1151-1169; Richard Cooper, The Economics of Interdependence: Economic Policy in the Atlantic Community (New York: Columbia University Press, 1968); and Elman and Elman, "Correspondence," p. 924, all concur that such theories are nonrealist.
    • (1977) Power and Interdependence: World Politics in Transition
    • Keohane, R.O.1    Nye, J.S.2
  • 30
    • 84973962290 scopus 로고
    • Liberalism and World Politics
    • December
    • For a statement of core assumptions, see Andrew Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously: A Liberal Theory of International Politics," International Organization, Vol. 51, No. 4 (Autumn 1997), pp. 513-553. Helen V. Milner, "Rationalizing Politics: The Emerging Synthesis of International, American, and Comparative Politics," International Organization, Vol. 52, No. 4 (Autumn 1998), pp. 759-786; Robert O. Keohane and Joseph S. Nye, Power and Interdependence: World Politics in Transition (Boston: Little, Brown, 1977); Michael W. Doyle, "Liberalism and World Politics," American Political Science Review, Vol. 80, No. 4 (December 1986), pp. 1151-1169; Richard Cooper, The Economics of Interdependence: Economic Policy in the Atlantic Community (New York: Columbia University Press, 1968); and Elman and Elman, "Correspondence," p. 924, all concur that such theories are nonrealist.
    • (1986) American Political Science Review , vol.80 , Issue.4 , pp. 1151-1169
    • Doyle, M.W.1
  • 31
    • 0000546136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • For a statement of core assumptions, see Andrew Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously: A Liberal Theory of International Politics," International Organization, Vol. 51, No. 4 (Autumn 1997), pp. 513-553. Helen V. Milner, "Rationalizing Politics: The Emerging Synthesis of International, American, and Comparative Politics," International Organization, Vol. 52, No. 4 (Autumn 1998), pp. 759-786; Robert O. Keohane and Joseph S. Nye, Power and Interdependence: World Politics in Transition (Boston: Little, Brown, 1977); Michael W. Doyle, "Liberalism and World Politics," American Political Science Review, Vol. 80, No. 4 (December 1986), pp. 1151-1169; Richard Cooper, The Economics of Interdependence: Economic Policy in the Atlantic Community (New York: Columbia University Press, 1968); and Elman and Elman, "Correspondence," p. 924, all concur that such theories are nonrealist.
    • (1968) The Economics of Interdependence: Economic Policy in the Atlantic Community
    • Cooper, R.1
  • 32
    • 0000546136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a statement of core assumptions, see Andrew Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously: A Liberal Theory of International Politics," International Organization, Vol. 51, No. 4 (Autumn 1997), pp. 513-553. Helen V. Milner, "Rationalizing Politics: The Emerging Synthesis of International, American, and Comparative Politics," International Organization, Vol. 52, No. 4 (Autumn 1998), pp. 759-786; Robert O. Keohane and Joseph S. Nye, Power and Interdependence: World Politics in Transition (Boston: Little, Brown, 1977); Michael W. Doyle, "Liberalism and World Politics," American Political Science Review, Vol. 80, No. 4 (December 1986), pp. 1151-1169; Richard Cooper, The Economics of Interdependence: Economic Policy in the Atlantic Community (New York: Columbia University Press, 1968); and Elman and Elman, "Correspondence," p. 924, all concur that such theories are nonrealist.
    • Correspondence , pp. 924
    • Elman1    Elman2
  • 33
    • 21144467098 scopus 로고
    • Territoriality and Beyond: Problematizing Modernity in International Relations
    • Winter
    • An "episteme" or "system of understanding" implies a collective mentality and should be distinguished from purely psychological approaches about individual perceptions and personality traits, although these may share similarities. Our use of the word seeks to situate the paradigm between deep constitutive connotations of "social episteme" in John G. Ruggie, "Territoriality and Beyond: Problematizing Modernity in International Relations," International Organization, Vol. 47, No. 4 (Winter 1993), p. 157, and interest-group focus of "epistemic community" in Peter M. Haas, "Introduction: Epistemic Communities and International Policy Coordination," International Organization, Vol. 46, No. 1 (Winter 1992), pp. 1-35.
    • (1993) International Organization , vol.47 , Issue.4 , pp. 157
    • Ruggie, J.G.1
  • 34
    • 84972264695 scopus 로고
    • Introduction: Epistemic Communities and International Policy Coordination
    • Winter
    • An "episteme" or "system of understanding" implies a collective mentality and should be distinguished from purely psychological approaches about individual perceptions and personality traits, although these may share similarities. Our use of the word seeks to situate the paradigm between deep constitutive connotations of "social episteme" in John G. Ruggie, "Territoriality and Beyond: Problematizing Modernity in International Relations," International Organization, Vol. 47, No. 4 (Winter 1993), p. 157, and interest-group focus of "epistemic community" in Peter M. Haas, "Introduction: Epistemic Communities and International Policy Coordination," International Organization, Vol. 46, No. 1 (Winter 1992), pp. 1-35.
    • (1992) International Organization , vol.46 , Issue.1 , pp. 1-35
    • Haas, P.M.1
  • 35
    • 0001844339 scopus 로고
    • Introduction
    • Elster, ed., New York: New York University Press
    • On the role of beliefs in rationalist theory see Jon Elster, "Introduction," in Elster, ed., Rational Choice (New York: New York University Press, 1986), pp. 1-33; and Arthur Denzau and Douglass North, "Shared Mental Models: Ideologies and Institutions," Kyklos, Vol. 47, No. 1 (Spring 1994), pp. 3-31.
    • (1986) Rational Choice , pp. 1-33
    • Elster, J.1
  • 36
    • 84980243564 scopus 로고
    • Shared Mental Models: Ideologies and Institutions
    • Spring
    • On the role of beliefs in rationalist theory see Jon Elster, "Introduction," in Elster, ed., Rational Choice (New York: New York University Press, 1986), pp. 1-33; and Arthur Denzau and Douglass North, "Shared Mental Models: Ideologies and Institutions," Kyklos, Vol. 47, No. 1 (Spring 1994), pp. 3-31.
    • (1994) Kyklos , vol.47 , Issue.1 , pp. 3-31
    • Denzau, A.1    North, D.2
  • 37
    • 0003837312 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press
    • John Odell, U.S. International Monetary Policy: Markets, Power, and Ideas as Sources of Change (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1982); Paul Egon Rohrlich, "Economic Culture and Foreign Policy," International Organization, Vol. 41, No. 1 (Winter 1987), pp. 61-92; Kathryn Sikkink, Ideas and Institutions: Developmentalism in Brazil and Argentina (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1991); Peter Hall, "Policy Paradigms, Social Learning, and the State," Comparative Politics, Vol. 25, No. 3 (April 1993), pp. 275-295; Judith Goldstein, Ideas, Interests, and American Trade Policy (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1993); Alastair lain Johnston, Cultural Realism: Strategic Culture and Grand Strategy in Chinese History (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1995); Jeffrey W. Legro, Cooperation under Fire: Anglo-German Restraint during World War II (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1995); Peter J. Katzenstein, ed., The Culture of National Security: Norms, Identity, and World Politics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996); Dan Reiter, Crucible of Beliefs (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1996); and Elizabeth Kier, Imagining War: French and British Military Doctrine between the Wars (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1997).
    • (1982) U.S. International Monetary Policy: Markets, Power, and Ideas as Sources of Change
    • Odell, J.1
  • 38
    • 84974132574 scopus 로고
    • Economic Culture and Foreign Policy
    • Winter
    • John Odell, U.S. International Monetary Policy: Markets, Power, and Ideas as Sources of Change (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1982); Paul Egon Rohrlich, "Economic Culture and Foreign Policy," International Organization, Vol. 41, No. 1 (Winter 1987), pp. 61-92; Kathryn Sikkink, Ideas and Institutions: Developmentalism in Brazil and Argentina (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1991); Peter Hall, "Policy Paradigms, Social Learning, and the State," Comparative Politics, Vol. 25, No. 3 (April 1993), pp. 275-295; Judith Goldstein, Ideas, Interests, and American Trade Policy (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1993); Alastair lain Johnston, Cultural Realism: Strategic Culture and Grand Strategy in Chinese History (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1995); Jeffrey W. Legro, Cooperation under Fire: Anglo-German Restraint during World War II (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1995); Peter J. Katzenstein, ed., The Culture of National Security: Norms, Identity, and World Politics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996); Dan Reiter, Crucible of Beliefs (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1996); and Elizabeth Kier, Imagining War: French and British Military Doctrine between the Wars (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1997).
    • (1987) International Organization , vol.41 , Issue.1 , pp. 61-92
    • Rohrlich, P.E.1
  • 39
    • 34249011226 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press
    • John Odell, U.S. International Monetary Policy: Markets, Power, and Ideas as Sources of Change (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1982); Paul Egon Rohrlich, "Economic Culture and Foreign Policy," International Organization, Vol. 41, No. 1 (Winter 1987), pp. 61-92; Kathryn Sikkink, Ideas and Institutions: Developmentalism in Brazil and Argentina (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1991); Peter Hall, "Policy Paradigms, Social Learning, and the State," Comparative Politics, Vol. 25, No. 3 (April 1993), pp. 275-295; Judith Goldstein, Ideas, Interests, and American Trade Policy (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1993); Alastair lain Johnston, Cultural Realism: Strategic Culture and Grand Strategy in Chinese History (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1995); Jeffrey W. Legro, Cooperation under Fire: Anglo-German Restraint during World War II (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1995); Peter J. Katzenstein, ed., The Culture of National Security: Norms, Identity, and World Politics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996); Dan Reiter, Crucible of Beliefs (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1996); and Elizabeth Kier, Imagining War: French and British Military Doctrine between the Wars (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1997).
    • (1991) Ideas and Institutions: Developmentalism in Brazil and Argentina
    • Sikkink, K.1
  • 40
    • 85055297421 scopus 로고
    • Policy Paradigms, Social Learning, and the State
    • April
    • John Odell, U.S. International Monetary Policy: Markets, Power, and Ideas as Sources of Change (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1982); Paul Egon Rohrlich, "Economic Culture and Foreign Policy," International Organization, Vol. 41, No. 1 (Winter 1987), pp. 61-92; Kathryn Sikkink, Ideas and Institutions: Developmentalism in Brazil and Argentina (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1991); Peter Hall, "Policy Paradigms, Social Learning, and the State," Comparative Politics, Vol. 25, No. 3 (April 1993), pp. 275-295; Judith Goldstein, Ideas, Interests, and American Trade Policy (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1993); Alastair lain Johnston, Cultural Realism: Strategic Culture and Grand Strategy in Chinese History (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1995); Jeffrey W. Legro, Cooperation under Fire: Anglo-German Restraint during World War II (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1995); Peter J. Katzenstein, ed., The Culture of National Security: Norms, Identity, and World Politics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996); Dan Reiter, Crucible of Beliefs (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1996); and Elizabeth Kier, Imagining War: French and British Military Doctrine between the Wars (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1997).
    • (1993) Comparative Politics , vol.25 , Issue.3 , pp. 275-295
    • Hall, P.1
  • 41
    • 0003673460 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press
    • John Odell, U.S. International Monetary Policy: Markets, Power, and Ideas as Sources of Change (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1982); Paul Egon Rohrlich, "Economic Culture and Foreign Policy," International Organization, Vol. 41, No. 1 (Winter 1987), pp. 61-92; Kathryn Sikkink, Ideas and Institutions: Developmentalism in Brazil and Argentina (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1991); Peter Hall, "Policy Paradigms, Social Learning, and the State," Comparative Politics, Vol. 25, No. 3 (April 1993), pp. 275-295; Judith Goldstein, Ideas, Interests, and American Trade Policy (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1993); Alastair lain Johnston, Cultural Realism: Strategic Culture and Grand Strategy in Chinese History (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1995); Jeffrey W. Legro, Cooperation under Fire: Anglo-German Restraint during World War II (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1995); Peter J. Katzenstein, ed., The Culture of National Security: Norms, Identity, and World Politics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996); Dan Reiter, Crucible of Beliefs (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1996); and Elizabeth Kier, Imagining War: French and British Military Doctrine between the Wars (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1997).
    • (1993) Ideas, Interests, and American Trade Policy
    • Goldstein, J.1
  • 42
    • 0004122666 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press
    • John Odell, U.S. International Monetary Policy: Markets, Power, and Ideas as Sources of Change (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1982); Paul Egon Rohrlich, "Economic Culture and Foreign Policy," International Organization, Vol. 41, No. 1 (Winter 1987), pp. 61-92; Kathryn Sikkink, Ideas and Institutions: Developmentalism in Brazil and Argentina (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1991); Peter Hall, "Policy Paradigms, Social Learning, and the State," Comparative Politics, Vol. 25, No. 3 (April 1993), pp. 275-295; Judith Goldstein, Ideas, Interests, and American Trade Policy (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1993); Alastair lain Johnston, Cultural Realism: Strategic Culture and Grand Strategy in Chinese History (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1995); Jeffrey W. Legro, Cooperation under Fire: Anglo-German Restraint during World War II (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1995); Peter J. Katzenstein, ed., The Culture of National Security: Norms, Identity, and World Politics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996); Dan Reiter, Crucible of Beliefs (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1996); and Elizabeth Kier, Imagining War: French and British Military Doctrine between the Wars (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1997).
    • (1995) Cultural Realism: Strategic Culture and Grand Strategy in Chinese History
    • Johnston, A.L.1
  • 43
    • 0003642697 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press
    • John Odell, U.S. International Monetary Policy: Markets, Power, and Ideas as Sources of Change (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1982); Paul Egon Rohrlich, "Economic Culture and Foreign Policy," International Organization, Vol. 41, No. 1 (Winter 1987), pp. 61-92; Kathryn Sikkink, Ideas and Institutions: Developmentalism in Brazil and Argentina (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1991); Peter Hall, "Policy Paradigms, Social Learning, and the State," Comparative Politics, Vol. 25, No. 3 (April 1993), pp. 275-295; Judith Goldstein, Ideas, Interests, and American Trade Policy (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1993); Alastair lain Johnston, Cultural Realism: Strategic Culture and Grand Strategy in Chinese History (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1995); Jeffrey W. Legro, Cooperation under Fire: Anglo-German Restraint during World War II (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1995); Peter J. Katzenstein, ed., The Culture of National Security: Norms, Identity, and World Politics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996); Dan Reiter, Crucible of Beliefs (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1996); and Elizabeth Kier, Imagining War: French and British Military Doctrine between the Wars (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1997).
    • (1995) Cooperation under Fire: Anglo-German Restraint during World War II
    • Legro, J.W.1
  • 44
    • 0003666718 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • John Odell, U.S. International Monetary Policy: Markets, Power, and Ideas as Sources of Change (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1982); Paul Egon Rohrlich, "Economic Culture and Foreign Policy," International Organization, Vol. 41, No. 1 (Winter 1987), pp. 61-92; Kathryn Sikkink, Ideas and Institutions: Developmentalism in Brazil and Argentina (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1991); Peter Hall, "Policy Paradigms, Social Learning, and the State," Comparative Politics, Vol. 25, No. 3 (April 1993), pp. 275-295; Judith Goldstein, Ideas, Interests, and American Trade Policy (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1993); Alastair lain Johnston, Cultural Realism: Strategic Culture and Grand Strategy in Chinese History (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1995); Jeffrey W. Legro, Cooperation under Fire: Anglo-German Restraint during World War II (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1995); Peter J. Katzenstein, ed., The Culture of National Security: Norms, Identity, and World Politics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996); Dan Reiter, Crucible of Beliefs (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1996); and Elizabeth Kier, Imagining War: French and British Military Doctrine between the Wars (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1997).
    • (1996) The Culture of National Security: Norms, Identity, and World Politics
    • Katzenstein, P.J.1
  • 45
    • 0003707216 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press
    • John Odell, U.S. International Monetary Policy: Markets, Power, and Ideas as Sources of Change (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1982); Paul Egon Rohrlich, "Economic Culture and Foreign Policy," International Organization, Vol. 41, No. 1 (Winter 1987), pp. 61-92; Kathryn Sikkink, Ideas and Institutions: Developmentalism in Brazil and Argentina (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1991); Peter Hall, "Policy Paradigms, Social Learning, and the State," Comparative Politics, Vol. 25, No. 3 (April 1993), pp. 275-295; Judith Goldstein, Ideas, Interests, and American Trade Policy (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1993); Alastair lain Johnston, Cultural Realism: Strategic Culture and Grand Strategy in Chinese History (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1995); Jeffrey W. Legro, Cooperation under Fire: Anglo-German Restraint during World War II (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1995); Peter J. Katzenstein, ed., The Culture of National Security: Norms, Identity, and World Politics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996); Dan Reiter, Crucible of Beliefs (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1996); and Elizabeth Kier, Imagining War: French and British Military Doctrine between the Wars (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1997).
    • (1996) Crucible of Beliefs
    • Reiter, D.1
  • 46
    • 0004098685 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press
    • John Odell, U.S. International Monetary Policy: Markets, Power, and Ideas as Sources of Change (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1982); Paul Egon Rohrlich, "Economic Culture and Foreign Policy," International Organization, Vol. 41, No. 1 (Winter 1987), pp. 61-92; Kathryn Sikkink, Ideas and Institutions: Developmentalism in Brazil and Argentina (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1991); Peter Hall, "Policy Paradigms, Social Learning, and the State," Comparative Politics, Vol. 25, No. 3 (April 1993), pp. 275-295; Judith Goldstein, Ideas, Interests, and American Trade Policy (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1993); Alastair lain Johnston, Cultural Realism: Strategic Culture and Grand Strategy in Chinese History (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1995); Jeffrey W. Legro, Cooperation under Fire: Anglo-German Restraint during World War II (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1995); Peter J. Katzenstein, ed., The Culture of National Security: Norms, Identity, and World Politics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996); Dan Reiter, Crucible of Beliefs (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1996); and Elizabeth Kier, Imagining War: French and British Military Doctrine between the Wars (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1997).
    • (1997) Imagining War: French and British Military Doctrine between the Wars
    • Kier, E.1
  • 48
    • 0031400090 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Tale of Two Realisms: Expanding the Institutions Debate
    • Randall L. Schweller and David Priess suggest this definition, although they neglect it in their midrange theorizing. Schweller and Priess, "A Tale of Two Realisms: Expanding the Institutions Debate," International Studies Review, Vol. 41, No. 1 (1997), pp. 1-32. Walt comes close in Walt, "The Progressive Power of Realism," p. 932. For an all-inclusive definition including many of these elements, see Frankel, "Restating the Realist Case."
    • (1997) International Studies Review , vol.41 , Issue.1 , pp. 1-32
    • Schweller1    Priess2
  • 49
    • 0042735215 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Randall L. Schweller and David Priess suggest this definition, although they neglect it in their midrange theorizing. Schweller and Priess, "A Tale of Two Realisms: Expanding the Institutions Debate," International Studies Review, Vol. 41, No. 1 (1997), pp. 1-32. Walt comes close in Walt, "The Progressive Power of Realism," p. 932. For an all-inclusive definition including many of these elements, see Frankel, "Restating the Realist Case."
    • The Progressive Power of Realism , pp. 932
    • Walt1
  • 50
    • 0043236442 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Randall L. Schweller and David Priess suggest this definition, although they neglect it in their midrange theorizing. Schweller and Priess, "A Tale of Two Realisms: Expanding the Institutions Debate," International Studies Review, Vol. 41, No. 1 (1997), pp. 1-32. Walt comes close in Walt, "The Progressive Power of Realism," p. 932. For an all-inclusive definition including many of these elements, see Frankel, "Restating the Realist Case."
    • Restating the Realist Case
    • Frankel1
  • 51
    • 0004205937 scopus 로고
    • Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley
    • Kenneth N. Waltz, Theory of International Politics (Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, 1979), p. 94; Stephen D. Krasner, Structural Conflict: The Third World against Global Liberalism (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1985), p. 28; Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1973), pp. 7-8; Robert Gilpin, "No One Loves a Political Realist," in Frankel, Realism, p. 7; and Robert O. Keohane, "Realism, Neorealism, and the Study of World Politics," in Keohane, ed., Neorealism and Its Critics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1986), pp. 1-26. This rationality can be bounded; the precise level of calculating ability is inessential to our purposes here, as long as miscalculations are random; if they are not, then other theories may take over.
    • (1979) Theory of International Politics , pp. 94
    • Waltz, K.N.1
  • 52
    • 84968164908 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley: University of California Press
    • Kenneth N. Waltz, Theory of International Politics (Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, 1979), p. 94; Stephen D. Krasner, Structural Conflict: The Third World against Global Liberalism (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1985), p. 28; Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1973), pp. 7-8; Robert Gilpin, "No One Loves a Political Realist," in Frankel, Realism, p. 7; and Robert O. Keohane, "Realism, Neorealism, and the Study of World Politics," in Keohane, ed., Neorealism and Its Critics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1986), pp. 1-26. This rationality can be bounded; the precise level of calculating ability is inessential to our purposes here, as long as miscalculations are random; if they are not, then other theories may take over.
    • (1985) Structural Conflict: The Third World Against Global Liberalism , pp. 28
    • Krasner, S.D.1
  • 53
    • 0004099967 scopus 로고
    • New York: Alfred A. Knopf
    • Kenneth N. Waltz, Theory of International Politics (Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, 1979), p. 94; Stephen D. Krasner, Structural Conflict: The Third World against Global Liberalism (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1985), p. 28; Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1973), pp. 7-8; Robert Gilpin, "No One Loves a Political Realist," in Frankel, Realism, p. 7; and Robert O. Keohane, "Realism, Neorealism, and the Study of World Politics," in Keohane, ed., Neorealism and Its Critics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1986), pp. 1-26. This rationality can be bounded; the precise level of calculating ability is inessential to our purposes here, as long as miscalculations are random; if they are not, then other theories may take over.
    • (1973) Politics among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace , pp. 7-8
    • Morgenthau, H.J.1
  • 54
    • 0040294185 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • No One Loves a Political Realist
    • Frankel
    • Kenneth N. Waltz, Theory of International Politics (Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, 1979), p. 94; Stephen D. Krasner, Structural Conflict: The Third World against Global Liberalism (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1985), p. 28; Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1973), pp. 7-8; Robert Gilpin, "No One Loves a Political Realist," in Frankel, Realism, p. 7; and Robert O. Keohane, "Realism, Neorealism, and the Study of World Politics," in Keohane, ed., Neorealism and Its Critics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1986), pp. 1-26. This rationality can be bounded; the precise level of calculating ability is inessential to our purposes here, as long as miscalculations are random; if they are not, then other theories may take over.
    • Realism , pp. 7
    • Gilpin, R.1
  • 55
    • 0002196730 scopus 로고
    • Realism, Neorealism, and the Study of World Politics
    • Keohane, ed., New York: Columbia University Press
    • Kenneth N. Waltz, Theory of International Politics (Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, 1979), p. 94; Stephen D. Krasner, Structural Conflict: The Third World against Global Liberalism (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1985), p. 28; Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1973), pp. 7-8; Robert Gilpin, "No One Loves a Political Realist," in Frankel, Realism, p. 7; and Robert O. Keohane, "Realism, Neorealism, and the Study of World Politics," in Keohane, ed., Neorealism and Its Critics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1986), pp. 1-26. This rationality can be bounded; the precise level of calculating ability is inessential to our purposes here, as long as miscalculations are random; if they are not, then other theories may take over.
    • (1986) Neorealism and Its Critics , pp. 1-26
    • Keohane, R.O.1
  • 56
    • 0042234229 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gilpin, "No One Loves a Political Realist"; and Kenneth N. Waltz, "Realist Thought and Neorealist Theory," in Robert L. Rothstein, ed., The Evolution of Theory in International Relations (Columbia: University of South Carolina Press, 1991), p. 37.
    • No One Loves a Political Realist
    • Gilpin1
  • 57
    • 0040098489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Realist Thought and Neorealist Theory
    • Robert L. Rothstein, ed., Columbia: University of South Carolina Press
    • Gilpin, "No One Loves a Political Realist"; and Kenneth N. Waltz, "Realist Thought and Neorealist Theory," in Robert L. Rothstein, ed., The Evolution of Theory in International Relations (Columbia: University of South Carolina Press, 1991), p. 37.
    • (1991) The Evolution of Theory in International Relations , pp. 37
    • Waltz, K.N.1
  • 58
    • 84971881632 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Anarchy in International Relations Theory: The Neorealist-Neoliberal Debate
    • Spring
    • Preferences should remain clearly distinct from strategies. State preferences are defined over states of the social world and are therefore "prestrategic," that is, they remain uninfluenced by shifts in the strategic environment, such as the distribution of power. Preferences are akin to "tastes" that states bring to the international bargaining table, although they themselves may of course result from forms of international interaction other than those being studied, as do national preferences resulting from economic interdependence. See Robert Powell, "Anarchy in International Relations Theory: The Neorealist-Neoliberal Debate," International Organization, Vol. 48, No. 2 (Spring 1994), pp. 313-344; and Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously."
    • (1994) International Organization , vol.48 , Issue.2 , pp. 313-344
    • Powell, R.1
  • 59
    • 84971881632 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Preferences should remain clearly distinct from strategies. State preferences are defined over states of the social world and are therefore "prestrategic," that is, they remain uninfluenced by shifts in the strategic environment, such as the distribution of power. Preferences are akin to "tastes" that states bring to the international bargaining table, although they themselves may of course result from forms of international interaction other than those being studied, as do national preferences resulting from economic interdependence. See Robert Powell, "Anarchy in International Relations Theory: The Neorealist-Neoliberal Debate," International Organization, Vol. 48, No. 2 (Spring 1994), pp. 313-344; and Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously."
    • Taking Preferences Seriously
    • Moravcsik1
  • 60
    • 84873840682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Morgenthau, Politics among Nations, pp. 2-12; Waltz, Theory of International Politics, pp. 18-37; and Waltz, "Realist Thought and Neorealist Theory," pp. 21-37.
    • Politics among Nations , pp. 2-12
    • Morgenthau1
  • 61
    • 84874353575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Morgenthau, Politics among Nations, pp. 2-12; Waltz, Theory of International Politics, pp. 18-37; and Waltz, "Realist Thought and Neorealist Theory," pp. 21-37.
    • Theory of International Politics , pp. 18-37
    • Waltz1
  • 62
    • 0040098489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Morgenthau, Politics among Nations, pp. 2-12; Waltz, Theory of International Politics, pp. 18-37; and Waltz, "Realist Thought and Neorealist Theory," pp. 21-37.
    • Realist Thought and Neorealist Theory , pp. 21-37
    • Waltz1
  • 64
    • 0039831231 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Powell, "Anarchy in International Relations Theory," p. 315; Alexander Wendt, "Social Theory of International Politics," unpublished manuscript, Dartmouth College, 1998, p. 309; Randall L. Schweller, "Neorealism's Status-Quo Bias: What Security Dilemma?" in Frankel, Realism; Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously"; Jeffrey W. Legro, "Culture and Preferences in the International Cooperation Two-step," American Political Science Review, Vol. 90, No. 1 (March 1996), pp. 118-137; Barry Buzan, Charles Jones, and Richard Little, The Logic of Anarchy: Neorealism to Structural Realism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993); and John Gerard Ruggie, "International Regimes, Transactions, and Change: Embedded Liberalism in the Postwar Economic Order," in Krasner, International Regimes.
    • Anarchy in International Relations Theory , pp. 315
    • Powell1
  • 65
    • 0004061150 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • unpublished manuscript, Dartmouth College
    • Powell, "Anarchy in International Relations Theory," p. 315; Alexander Wendt, "Social Theory of International Politics," unpublished manuscript, Dartmouth College, 1998, p. 309; Randall L. Schweller, "Neorealism's Status-Quo Bias: What Security Dilemma?" in Frankel, Realism; Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously"; Jeffrey W. Legro, "Culture and Preferences in the International Cooperation Two-step," American Political Science Review, Vol. 90, No. 1 (March 1996), pp. 118-137; Barry Buzan, Charles Jones, and Richard Little, The Logic of Anarchy: Neorealism to Structural Realism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993); and John Gerard Ruggie, "International Regimes, Transactions, and Change: Embedded Liberalism in the Postwar Economic Order," in Krasner, International Regimes.
    • (1998) Social Theory of International Politics , pp. 309
    • Wendt, A.1
  • 66
    • 0040098487 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Neorealism's Status-Quo Bias: What Security Dilemma?
    • Frankel
    • Powell, "Anarchy in International Relations Theory," p. 315; Alexander Wendt, "Social Theory of International Politics," unpublished manuscript, Dartmouth College, 1998, p. 309; Randall L. Schweller, "Neorealism's Status-Quo Bias: What Security Dilemma?" in Frankel, Realism; Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously"; Jeffrey W. Legro, "Culture and Preferences in the International Cooperation Two-step," American Political Science Review, Vol. 90, No. 1 (March 1996), pp. 118-137; Barry Buzan, Charles Jones, and Richard Little, The Logic of Anarchy: Neorealism to Structural Realism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993); and John Gerard Ruggie, "International Regimes, Transactions, and Change: Embedded Liberalism in the Postwar Economic Order," in Krasner, International Regimes.
    • Realism
    • Schweller, R.L.1
  • 67
    • 0043236447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Powell, "Anarchy in International Relations Theory," p. 315; Alexander Wendt, "Social Theory of International Politics," unpublished manuscript, Dartmouth College, 1998, p. 309; Randall L. Schweller, "Neorealism's Status-Quo Bias: What Security Dilemma?" in Frankel, Realism; Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously"; Jeffrey W. Legro, "Culture and Preferences in the International Cooperation Two-step," American Political Science Review, Vol. 90, No. 1 (March 1996), pp. 118-137; Barry Buzan, Charles Jones, and Richard Little, The Logic of Anarchy: Neorealism to Structural Realism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993); and John Gerard Ruggie, "International Regimes, Transactions, and Change: Embedded Liberalism in the Postwar Economic Order," in Krasner, International Regimes.
    • Taking Preferences Seriously
    • Moravcsik1
  • 68
    • 0030306699 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Culture and Preferences in the International Cooperation Two-step
    • March
    • Powell, "Anarchy in International Relations Theory," p. 315; Alexander Wendt, "Social Theory of International Politics," unpublished manuscript, Dartmouth College, 1998, p. 309; Randall L. Schweller, "Neorealism's Status-Quo Bias: What Security Dilemma?" in Frankel, Realism; Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously"; Jeffrey W. Legro, "Culture and Preferences in the International Cooperation Two-step," American Political Science Review, Vol. 90, No. 1 (March 1996), pp. 118-137; Barry Buzan, Charles Jones, and Richard Little, The Logic of Anarchy: Neorealism to Structural Realism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993); and John Gerard Ruggie, "International Regimes, Transactions, and Change: Embedded Liberalism in the Postwar Economic Order," in Krasner, International Regimes.
    • (1996) American Political Science Review , vol.90 , Issue.1 , pp. 118-137
    • Legro, J.W.1
  • 69
    • 0041733839 scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • Powell, "Anarchy in International Relations Theory," p. 315; Alexander Wendt, "Social Theory of International Politics," unpublished manuscript, Dartmouth College, 1998, p. 309; Randall L. Schweller, "Neorealism's Status-Quo Bias: What Security Dilemma?" in Frankel, Realism; Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously"; Jeffrey W. Legro, "Culture and Preferences in the International Cooperation Two-step," American Political Science Review, Vol. 90, No. 1 (March 1996), pp. 118-137; Barry Buzan, Charles Jones, and Richard Little, The Logic of Anarchy: Neorealism to Structural Realism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993); and John Gerard Ruggie, "International Regimes, Transactions, and Change: Embedded Liberalism in the Postwar Economic Order," in Krasner, International Regimes.
    • (1993) Charles Jones, and Richard Little, the Logic of Anarchy: Neorealism to Structural Realism
    • Buzan, B.1
  • 70
    • 0001842576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • International Regimes, Transactions, and Change: Embedded Liberalism in the Postwar Economic Order
    • Krasner
    • Powell, "Anarchy in International Relations Theory," p. 315; Alexander Wendt, "Social Theory of International Politics," unpublished manuscript, Dartmouth College, 1998, p. 309; Randall L. Schweller, "Neorealism's Status-Quo Bias: What Security Dilemma?" in Frankel, Realism; Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously"; Jeffrey W. Legro, "Culture and Preferences in the International Cooperation Two-step," American Political Science Review, Vol. 90, No. 1 (March 1996), pp. 118-137; Barry Buzan, Charles Jones, and Richard Little, The Logic of Anarchy: Neorealism to Structural Realism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993); and John Gerard Ruggie, "International Regimes, Transactions, and Change: Embedded Liberalism in the Postwar Economic Order," in Krasner, International Regimes.
    • International Regimes
    • Ruggie, J.G.1
  • 71
    • 84880654215 scopus 로고
    • Back to the Future: Instability in Europe after the Cold War
    • Summer
    • John J. Mearsheimer, "Back to the Future: Instability in Europe after the Cold War," International Security, Vol. 15, No. 1 (Summer 1990), pp. 5-56; and Joseph M. Grieco, "Anarchy and the Limits of Cooperation: A Realist Critique of the Newest Liberal Institutionalism," International Organization, Vol. 42, No. 3 (Summer 1988), pp. 485-507. Grieco maintains that states seek both absolute and relative gains. The relative importance of relative gains is given by the coefficient k. The higher the value of k, Grieco maintains, the stronger the incentives for relative-gains seeking and the more pronounced the tendency to engage in "defensive positionalist" realist behavior. For a more detailed analysis, see pp. 25-27 below.
    • (1990) International Security , vol.15 , Issue.1 , pp. 5-56
    • Mearsheimer, J.J.1
  • 72
    • 84972468435 scopus 로고
    • Anarchy and the Limits of Cooperation: A Realist Critique of the Newest Liberal Institutionalism
    • Summer
    • John J. Mearsheimer, "Back to the Future: Instability in Europe after the Cold War," International Security, Vol. 15, No. 1 (Summer 1990), pp. 5-56; and Joseph M. Grieco, "Anarchy and the Limits of Cooperation: A Realist Critique of the Newest Liberal Institutionalism," International Organization, Vol. 42, No. 3 (Summer 1988), pp. 485-507. Grieco maintains that states seek both absolute and relative gains. The relative importance of relative gains is given by the coefficient k. The higher the value of k, Grieco maintains, the stronger the incentives for relative-gains seeking and the more pronounced the tendency to engage in "defensive positionalist" realist behavior. For a more detailed analysis, see pp. 25-27 below.
    • (1988) International Organization , vol.42 , Issue.3 , pp. 485-507
    • Grieco, J.M.1
  • 73
    • 0040098487 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schweller puts this well: "If states are assumed to seek nothing more than their own survival, why would they feel threatened? . . . Anarchy and self-preservation alone are not sufficient. . . . Predatory states motivated by expansion and absolute gains, not security and the fear of relative losses, are the prime movers of neo-realist theory. Without some possibility for their existence, the security dilemma melts away, as do most concepts associated with contemporary realism." Schweller, "Neorealism's Status-Quo Bias," pp. 91, 119. Somewhat perversely for a realist, he cites Fukuyama, The End of History, pp. 254-255. See also Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously"; Charles L. Glaser, "Realists as Optimists: Cooperation as Self-Help," in Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller, The Perils of Anarchy; and Andrew Kydd, "Sheep in Sheep's Clothing: Why Security Seekers Do Not Fight Each Other," Security Studies, Vol. 7, No. 1 (Autumn 1997), pp. 153-154.
    • Neorealism's Status-Quo Bias , pp. 91
    • Schweller1
  • 74
    • 0004175957 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schweller puts this well: "If states are assumed to seek nothing more than their own survival, why would they feel threatened? . . . Anarchy and self-preservation alone are not sufficient. . . . Predatory states motivated by expansion and absolute gains, not security and the fear of relative losses, are the prime movers of neo-realist theory. Without some possibility for their existence, the security dilemma melts away, as do most concepts associated with contemporary realism." Schweller, "Neorealism's Status-Quo Bias," pp. 91, 119. Somewhat perversely for a realist, he cites Fukuyama, The End of History, pp. 254-255. See also Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously"; Charles L. Glaser, "Realists as Optimists: Cooperation as Self-Help," in Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller, The Perils of Anarchy; and Andrew Kydd, "Sheep in Sheep's Clothing: Why Security Seekers Do Not Fight Each Other," Security Studies, Vol. 7, No. 1 (Autumn 1997), pp. 153-154.
    • The End of History , pp. 254-255
    • Fukuyama1
  • 75
    • 0043236447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schweller puts this well: "If states are assumed to seek nothing more than their own survival, why would they feel threatened? . . . Anarchy and self-preservation alone are not sufficient. . . . Predatory states motivated by expansion and absolute gains, not security and the fear of relative losses, are the prime movers of neo-realist theory. Without some possibility for their existence, the security dilemma melts away, as do most concepts associated with contemporary realism." Schweller, "Neorealism's Status-Quo Bias," pp. 91, 119. Somewhat perversely for a realist, he cites Fukuyama, The End of History, pp. 254-255. See also Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously"; Charles L. Glaser, "Realists as Optimists: Cooperation as Self-Help," in Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller, The Perils of Anarchy; and Andrew Kydd, "Sheep in Sheep's Clothing: Why Security Seekers Do Not Fight Each Other," Security Studies, Vol. 7, No. 1 (Autumn 1997), pp. 153-154.
    • Taking Preferences Seriously
    • Moravcsik1
  • 76
    • 0039315517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Realists as Optimists: Cooperation as Self-Help
    • Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller
    • Schweller puts this well: "If states are assumed to seek nothing more than their own survival, why would they feel threatened? . . . Anarchy and self-preservation alone are not sufficient. . . . Predatory states motivated by expansion and absolute gains, not security and the fear of relative losses, are the prime movers of neo-realist theory. Without some possibility for their existence, the security dilemma melts away, as do most concepts associated with contemporary realism." Schweller, "Neorealism's Status-Quo Bias," pp. 91, 119. Somewhat perversely for a realist, he cites Fukuyama, The End of History, pp. 254-255. See also Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously"; Charles L. Glaser, "Realists as Optimists: Cooperation as Self-Help," in Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller, The Perils of Anarchy; and Andrew Kydd, "Sheep in Sheep's Clothing: Why Security Seekers Do Not Fight Each Other," Security Studies, Vol. 7, No. 1 (Autumn 1997), pp. 153-154.
    • The Perils of Anarchy
    • Glaser, C.L.1
  • 77
    • 0039907879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sheep in Sheep's Clothing: Why Security Seekers Do Not Fight Each Other
    • Autumn
    • Schweller puts this well: "If states are assumed to seek nothing more than their own survival, why would they feel threatened? . . . Anarchy and self-preservation alone are not sufficient. . . . Predatory states motivated by expansion and absolute gains, not security and the fear of relative losses, are the prime movers of neo-realist theory. Without some possibility for their existence, the security dilemma melts away, as do most concepts associated with contemporary realism." Schweller, "Neorealism's Status-Quo Bias," pp. 91, 119. Somewhat perversely for a realist, he cites Fukuyama, The End of History, pp. 254-255. See also Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously"; Charles L. Glaser, "Realists as Optimists: Cooperation as Self-Help," in Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller, The Perils of Anarchy; and Andrew Kydd, "Sheep in Sheep's Clothing: Why Security Seekers Do Not Fight Each Other," Security Studies, Vol. 7, No. 1 (Autumn 1997), pp. 153-154.
    • (1997) Security Studies , vol.7 , Issue.1 , pp. 153-154
    • Kydd, A.1
  • 78
    • 5644255699 scopus 로고
    • The Emerging Structure of International Politics
    • Fall
    • Kenneth N. Waltz, "The Emerging Structure of International Politics," International Security, Vol. 18, No. 2 (Fall 1993), p. 57; Waltz, Theory of International Politics; Robert Gilpin, War and Change in World Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981); and Michael Mastanduno, "Do Relative Gains Matter? America's Response to Japanese Industrial Policy," in David A. Baldwin, ed., Neorealism and Neoliberalism: The Contemporary Debate (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993).
    • (1993) International Security , vol.18 , Issue.2 , pp. 57
    • Waltz, K.N.1
  • 79
    • 0042735210 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Kenneth N. Waltz, "The Emerging Structure of International Politics," International Security, Vol. 18, No. 2 (Fall 1993), p. 57; Waltz, Theory of International Politics; Robert Gilpin, War and Change in World Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981); and Michael Mastanduno, "Do Relative Gains Matter? America's Response to Japanese Industrial Policy," in David A. Baldwin, ed., Neorealism and Neoliberalism: The Contemporary Debate (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993).
    • (1981) Theory of International Politics; Robert Gilpin, War and Change in World Politics
    • Waltz1
  • 80
    • 0042735209 scopus 로고
    • Do Relative Gains Matter? America's Response to Japanese Industrial Policy
    • David A. Baldwin, ed., New York: Columbia University Press
    • Kenneth N. Waltz, "The Emerging Structure of International Politics," International Security, Vol. 18, No. 2 (Fall 1993), p. 57; Waltz, Theory of International Politics; Robert Gilpin, War and Change in World Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981); and Michael Mastanduno, "Do Relative Gains Matter? America's Response to Japanese Industrial Policy," in David A. Baldwin, ed., Neorealism and Neoliberalism: The Contemporary Debate (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993).
    • (1993) Neorealism and Neoliberalism: The Contemporary Debate
    • Mastanduno, M.1
  • 81
    • 0004259310 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • Disaggregating the interactions between two may be empirically and theoretically challenging, but the conceptual distinction between the two dimensions of preferences remains unavoidable. Howard Raiffa, The Art and Science of Negotiation (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1982); James D. Morrow, "Social Choice and System Structure in World Politics," World Politics, Vol. 41, No. 1 (October 1988), pp. 75-97; and Stephen D. Krasner, "Global Communications and National Power: Life on the Pareto Frontier," in Baldwin, Neorealism and Neoliberalism, pp. 234-249. These theorists do not, of course, concede to a theory based on material resources the sole ability to explain the outcome of conflict-prevailing beliefs; asymmetrical interdependence or preference intensity, institutional context, and various process-level theories may also play a role.
    • (1982) The Art and Science of Negotiation
    • Raiffa, H.1
  • 82
    • 84971851162 scopus 로고
    • Social Choice and System Structure in World Politics
    • October
    • Disaggregating the interactions between two may be empirically and theoretically challenging, but the conceptual distinction between the two dimensions of preferences remains unavoidable. Howard Raiffa, The Art and Science of Negotiation (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1982); James D. Morrow, "Social Choice and System Structure in World Politics," World Politics, Vol. 41, No. 1 (October 1988), pp. 75-97; and Stephen D. Krasner, "Global Communications and National Power: Life on the Pareto Frontier," in Baldwin, Neorealism and Neoliberalism, pp. 234-249. These theorists do not, of course, concede to a theory based on material resources the sole ability to explain the outcome of conflict-prevailing beliefs; asymmetrical interdependence or preference intensity, institutional context, and various process-level theories may also play a role.
    • (1988) World Politics , vol.41 , Issue.1 , pp. 75-97
    • Morrow, J.D.1
  • 83
    • 0039240707 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Global Communications and National Power: Life on the Pareto Frontier
    • Baldwin
    • Disaggregating the interactions between two may be empirically and theoretically challenging, but the conceptual distinction between the two dimensions of preferences remains unavoidable. Howard Raiffa, The Art and Science of Negotiation (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1982); James D. Morrow, "Social Choice and System Structure in World Politics," World Politics, Vol. 41, No. 1 (October 1988), pp. 75-97; and Stephen D. Krasner, "Global Communications and National Power: Life on the Pareto Frontier," in Baldwin, Neorealism and Neoliberalism, pp. 234-249. These theorists do not, of course, concede to a theory based on material resources the sole ability to explain the outcome of conflict-prevailing beliefs; asymmetrical interdependence or preference intensity, institutional context, and various process-level theories may also play a role.
    • Neorealism and Neoliberalism , pp. 234-249
    • Krasner, S.D.1
  • 84
    • 0039173716 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The False Promise of International Institutions
    • Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller
    • John J. Mearsheimer, "The False Promise of International Institutions," in Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller, The Perils of Anarchy, p. 337; Eric Labs, "Beyond Victory: Offensive Realism and the Expansion of War Aims," Security Studies, Vol. 6, No. 4 (Summer 1997), pp. 1-49; and Robert Gilpin, "The Richness of the Tradition of Political Realism," in Keohane, Neorealism and Its Critics.
    • The Perils of Anarchy , pp. 337
    • Mearsheimer, J.J.1
  • 85
    • 0009944670 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beyond Victory: Offensive Realism and the Expansion of War Aims
    • Summer
    • John J. Mearsheimer, "The False Promise of International Institutions," in Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller, The Perils of Anarchy, p. 337; Eric Labs, "Beyond Victory: Offensive Realism and the Expansion of War Aims," Security Studies, Vol. 6, No. 4 (Summer 1997), pp. 1-49; and Robert Gilpin, "The Richness of the Tradition of Political Realism," in Keohane, Neorealism and Its Critics.
    • (1997) Security Studies , vol.6 , Issue.4 , pp. 1-49
    • Labs, E.1
  • 86
    • 0003330502 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Richness of the Tradition of Political Realism
    • Keohane
    • John J. Mearsheimer, "The False Promise of International Institutions," in Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller, The Perils of Anarchy, p. 337; Eric Labs, "Beyond Victory: Offensive Realism and the Expansion of War Aims," Security Studies, Vol. 6, No. 4 (Summer 1997), pp. 1-49; and Robert Gilpin, "The Richness of the Tradition of Political Realism," in Keohane, Neorealism and Its Critics.
    • Neorealism and Its Critics
    • Gilpin, R.1
  • 87
    • 84871475956 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Coleman argues that coercion - "where the superordinate agrees to withhold an action that would make the subordinate worse off in exchange for the subordinate's obeying the superordinate" - is a "somewhat special" case of exchange. Coleman, Foundations of Social Theory, p. 29; and Kenneth A. Oye, Economic Discrimination and Political Exchange: World Political Economy in the 1930s and 1980s (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1992).
    • Foundations of Social Theory , pp. 29
    • Coleman1
  • 88
    • 0003698871 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press
    • Coleman argues that coercion - "where the superordinate agrees to withhold an action that would make the subordinate worse off in exchange for the subordinate's obeying the superordinate" - is a "somewhat special" case of exchange. Coleman, Foundations of Social Theory, p. 29; and Kenneth A. Oye, Economic Discrimination and Political Exchange: World Political Economy in the 1930s and 1980s (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1992).
    • (1992) Economic Discrimination and Political Exchange: World Political Economy in the 1930s and 1980s
    • Oye, K.A.1
  • 89
    • 84873840682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The language in Morgenthau, Politics among Nations, p. 5, is echoed almost verbatim in Waltz, Theory of International Politics. On Weber, see Michael Joseph Smith, Realist Thought from Weber to Kissinger (Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press, 1986).
    • Politics among Nations , pp. 5
    • Morgenthau1
  • 90
    • 84874353575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The language in Morgenthau, Politics among Nations, p. 5, is echoed almost verbatim in Waltz, Theory of International Politics. On Weber, see Michael Joseph Smith, Realist Thought from Weber to Kissinger (Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press, 1986).
    • Theory of International Politics
    • Waltz1
  • 91
    • 0004039689 scopus 로고
    • Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press
    • The language in Morgenthau, Politics among Nations, p. 5, is echoed almost verbatim in Waltz, Theory of International Politics. On Weber, see Michael Joseph Smith, Realist Thought from Weber to Kissinger (Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press, 1986).
    • (1986) Realist Thought from Weber to Kissinger
    • Smith, M.J.1
  • 95
    • 84972091498 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • State Power and the Structure of Foreign Trade
    • April
    • Stephen D. Krasner, "State Power and the Structure of Foreign Trade," World Politics, Vol. 28, No. 3 (April 1976), pp. 317-347; Gilpin, War and Change in World Politics; David A. Lake, Power, Protection, and Free Trade: International Sources of U.S. Commercial Policy (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1988); and Lake, "Leadership, Hegemony, and the International Economy: Naked Emperor or Tattered Monarch with Potential?" International Studies Quarterly, Vol. 37 No 4 (December 1993), pp. 459-489.
    • (1976) World Politics , vol.28 , Issue.3 , pp. 317-347
    • Krasner, S.D.1
  • 96
    • 84972091498 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stephen D. Krasner, "State Power and the Structure of Foreign Trade," World Politics, Vol. 28, No. 3 (April 1976), pp. 317-347; Gilpin, War and Change in World Politics; David A. Lake, Power, Protection, and Free Trade: International Sources of U.S. Commercial Policy (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1988); and Lake, "Leadership, Hegemony, and the International Economy: Naked Emperor or Tattered Monarch with Potential?" International Studies Quarterly, Vol. 37 No 4 (December 1993), pp. 459-489.
    • War and Change in World Politics
    • Gilpin1
  • 97
    • 84972091498 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press
    • Stephen D. Krasner, "State Power and the Structure of Foreign Trade," World Politics, Vol. 28, No. 3 (April 1976), pp. 317-347; Gilpin, War and Change in World Politics; David A. Lake, Power, Protection, and Free Trade: International Sources of U.S. Commercial Policy (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1988); and Lake, "Leadership, Hegemony, and the International Economy: Naked Emperor or Tattered Monarch with Potential?" International Studies Quarterly, Vol. 37 No 4 (December 1993), pp. 459-489.
    • (1988) Power, Protection, and Free Trade: International Sources of U.S. Commercial Policy
    • Lake, D.A.1
  • 98
    • 84972091498 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leadership, Hegemony, and the International Economy: Naked Emperor or Tattered Monarch with Potential?
    • December
    • Stephen D. Krasner, "State Power and the Structure of Foreign Trade," World Politics, Vol. 28, No. 3 (April 1976), pp. 317-347; Gilpin, War and Change in World Politics; David A. Lake, Power, Protection, and Free Trade: International Sources of U.S. Commercial Policy (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1988); and Lake, "Leadership, Hegemony, and the International Economy: Naked Emperor or Tattered Monarch with Potential?" International Studies Quarterly, Vol. 37 No 4 (December 1993), pp. 459-489.
    • (1993) International Studies Quarterly , vol.37 , Issue.4 , pp. 459-489
    • Lake1
  • 102
    • 85034121822 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, forthcoming)
    • Dale Copeland, Anticipating Power: Dynamic Realism and the Origins of Major War (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, forthcoming); and Christopher Layne, "Kant or Cant: The Myth of the Democratic Peace," in Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller, The Perils of Anarchy, pp. 287-331.
    • Anticipating Power: Dynamic Realism and the Origins of Major War
    • Copeland, D.1
  • 103
    • 0345387493 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant or Cant: The Myth of the Democratic Peace
    • Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller
    • Dale Copeland, Anticipating Power: Dynamic Realism and the Origins of Major War (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, forthcoming); and Christopher Layne, "Kant or Cant: The Myth of the Democratic Peace," in Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller, The Perils of Anarchy, pp. 287-331.
    • The Perils of Anarchy , pp. 287-331
    • Layne, C.1
  • 104
    • 84971748261 scopus 로고
    • Absolute and Relative Gains in International Relations Theory
    • December
    • Robert Powell, "Absolute and Relative Gains in International Relations Theory," American Political Science Review, Vol. 85, No. 4 (December 1991), pp. 701-726; and Barry R. Posen, The Sources of Military Doctrine: France, Britain, and Germany between the Wars (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1984), pp. 69, 229.
    • (1991) American Political Science Review , vol.85 , Issue.4 , pp. 701-726
    • Powell, R.1
  • 105
    • 84971748261 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press
    • Robert Powell, "Absolute and Relative Gains in International Relations Theory," American Political Science Review, Vol. 85, No. 4 (December 1991), pp. 701-726; and Barry R. Posen, The Sources of Military Doctrine: France, Britain, and Germany between the Wars (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1984), pp. 69, 229.
    • (1984) The Sources of Military Doctrine: France, Britain, and Germany between the Wars , pp. 69
    • Posen, B.R.1
  • 106
    • 0040888385 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Realist International Theory and the Study of World Politics
    • Michael W. Doyle and G. John Ikenberry, eds., Boulder, Colo.: Westview, is most explicit
    • Joseph M. Grieco, "Realist International Theory and the Study of World Politics," in Michael W. Doyle and G. John Ikenberry, eds., New Thinking in International Relations Theory (Boulder, Colo.: Westview, 1997), pp. 166-168, is most explicit.
    • (1997) New Thinking in International Relations Theory , pp. 166-168
    • Grieco, J.M.1
  • 107
    • 84974186329 scopus 로고
    • The Assumption of Anarchy in International Relations Theory
    • January
    • The transmethodological consensus on this point is near universal. In addition to Wendt, Powell, Moravcsik, Legro, and Schweller, cited above in n. 22, see Helen V. Milner, "The Assumption of Anarchy in International Relations Theory," Review of International Studies, Vol. 17, No. 1 (January 1991), pp. 67-85.
    • (1991) Review of International Studies , vol.17 , Issue.1 , pp. 67-85
    • Milner, H.V.1
  • 108
    • 0042234232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • define the realist hard core as rational, strategic states in anarchy seeking survival with limited resources
    • This is true also of some more unwieldy definitions. Elman and Elman, "Lakatos and Neorealism," p. 923, define the realist hard core as rational, strategic states in anarchy seeking survival with limited resources. Ashley Tellis, "Reconstructing Political Realism: The Long March to Scientific Theory," Security Studies, Vol. 5, No. 2 (Winter 1995-1996), p. 3, describes "political actions aimed at enhancing security" as the "minimum realist program." Sean M. Lynn-Jones and Steven E. Miller, "Preface," in Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller, The Perils of Anarchy, pp. ix-x, focus on rationality, anarchy, and power, but make no assumption that underlying goals conflict and limit their definition to the use of military force. We see a similar move in Buzan, Jones, and Little, The Logic of Anarchy, which seeks to integrate interdependence, preferences, information, and institutions into a "realist" theory tied together only by the fact that it is systemic.
    • Lakatos and Neorealism , pp. 923
    • Elman1    Elman2
  • 109
    • 0041733842 scopus 로고
    • Reconstructing Political Realism: The Long March to Scientific Theory
    • Winter describes "political actions aimed at enhancing security" as the "minimum realist program."
    • This is true also of some more unwieldy definitions. Elman and Elman, "Lakatos and Neorealism," p. 923, define the realist hard core as rational, strategic states in anarchy seeking survival with limited resources. Ashley Tellis, "Reconstructing Political Realism: The Long March to Scientific Theory," Security Studies, Vol. 5, No. 2 (Winter 1995-1996), p. 3, describes "political actions aimed at enhancing security" as the "minimum realist program." Sean M. Lynn-Jones and Steven E. Miller, "Preface," in Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller, The Perils of Anarchy, pp. ix-x, focus on rationality, anarchy, and power, but make no assumption that underlying goals conflict and limit their definition to the use of military force. We see a similar move in Buzan, Jones, and Little, The Logic of Anarchy, which seeks to integrate interdependence, preferences, information, and institutions into a "realist" theory tied together only by the fact that it is systemic.
    • (1995) Security Studies , vol.5 , Issue.2 , pp. 3
    • Tellis, A.1
  • 110
    • 0040933969 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Preface
    • Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller
    • This is true also of some more unwieldy definitions. Elman and Elman, "Lakatos and Neorealism," p. 923, define the realist hard core as rational, strategic states in anarchy seeking survival with limited resources. Ashley Tellis, "Reconstructing Political Realism: The Long March to Scientific Theory," Security Studies, Vol. 5, No. 2 (Winter 1995-1996), p. 3, describes "political actions aimed at enhancing security" as the "minimum realist program." Sean M. Lynn-Jones and Steven E. Miller, "Preface," in Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller, The Perils of Anarchy, pp. ix-x, focus on rationality, anarchy, and power, but make no assumption that underlying goals conflict and limit their definition to the use of military force. We see a similar move in Buzan, Jones, and Little, The Logic of Anarchy, which seeks to integrate interdependence, preferences, information, and institutions into a "realist" theory tied together only by the fact that it is systemic.
    • The Perils of Anarchy , pp. 9-10
    • Lynn-Jones, S.M.1    Miller, S.E.2
  • 111
    • 0004186904 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • which seeks to integrate interdependence, preferences, information, and institutions into a "realist" theory tied together only by the fact that it is systemic
    • This is true also of some more unwieldy definitions. Elman and Elman, "Lakatos and Neorealism," p. 923, define the realist hard core as rational, strategic states in anarchy seeking survival with limited resources. Ashley Tellis, "Reconstructing Political Realism: The Long March to Scientific Theory," Security Studies, Vol. 5, No. 2 (Winter 1995-1996), p. 3, describes "political actions aimed at enhancing security" as the "minimum realist program." Sean M. Lynn-Jones and Steven E. Miller, "Preface," in Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller, The Perils of Anarchy, pp. ix-x, focus on rationality, anarchy, and power, but make no assumption that underlying goals conflict and limit their definition to the use of military force. We see a similar move in Buzan, Jones, and Little, The Logic of Anarchy, which seeks to integrate interdependence, preferences, information, and institutions into a "realist" theory tied together only by the fact that it is systemic.
    • The Logic of Anarchy
    • Buzan1    Jones2    Little3
  • 112
    • 0003781092 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press
    • Some sociological theories take the somewhat different view that actors behave according to a noninstrumental "logic of appropriateness," whereby actors conform to internalized rules imposed by society. See Martha Finnemore, National Interests in International Society (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1996), pp. 28-31; and James March and Johan Olsen, Rediscovering Institutions: The Organizational Basis of Politics (New York: Free Press, 1989).
    • (1996) National Interests in International Society , pp. 28-31
    • Finnemore, M.1
  • 113
    • 0003713160 scopus 로고
    • New York: Free Press
    • Some sociological theories take the somewhat different view that actors behave according to a noninstrumental "logic of appropriateness," whereby actors conform to internalized rules imposed by society. See Martha Finnemore, National Interests in International Society (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1996), pp. 28-31; and James March and Johan Olsen, Rediscovering Institutions: The Organizational Basis of Politics (New York: Free Press, 1989).
    • (1989) Rediscovering Institutions: The Organizational Basis of Politics
    • March, J.1    Olsen, J.2
  • 114
    • 0003650879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Routledge
    • Stefano Guzzini's assessment goes to the heart of the matter: "The closest we can get to . . . a single . . . assumption that would demarcate realism is the idea of anarchy . . . [But] traditional defenders of collective security [as well as 'democratic peace' liberals] have the same starting point. Rather than setting Realism apart from other international theories, the assumption of anarchy sets International Relations apart from other disciplines." Guzzini, Realism in International Relations and International Political Economy: The Continuing Story of a Death Foretold (New York: Routledge, 1998), pp. viii-ix. See also Helen V. Milner, "The Assumption of Anarchy in International Relations"; and Keohane, "Introduction," After Hegemony.
    • (1998) Realism in International Relations and International Political Economy: The Continuing Story of a Death Foretold , pp. 8-9
    • Guzzini1
  • 115
    • 0010195507 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stefano Guzzini's assessment goes to the heart of the matter: "The closest we can get to . . . a single . . . assumption that would demarcate realism is the idea of anarchy . . . [But] traditional defenders of collective security [as well as 'democratic peace' liberals] have the same starting point. Rather than setting Realism apart from other international theories, the assumption of anarchy sets International Relations apart from other disciplines." Guzzini, Realism in International Relations and International Political Economy: The Continuing Story of a Death Foretold (New York: Routledge, 1998), pp. viii-ix. See also Helen V. Milner, "The Assumption of Anarchy in International Relations"; and Keohane, "Introduction," After Hegemony.
    • The Assumption of Anarchy in International Relations
    • Milner, H.V.1
  • 116
    • 85034141403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Introduction
    • Stefano Guzzini's assessment goes to the heart of the matter: "The closest we can get to . . . a single . . . assumption that would demarcate realism is the idea of anarchy . . . [But] traditional defenders of collective security [as well as 'democratic peace' liberals] have the same starting point. Rather than setting Realism apart from other international theories, the assumption of anarchy sets International Relations apart from other disciplines." Guzzini, Realism in International Relations and International Political Economy: The Continuing Story of a Death Foretold (New York: Routledge, 1998), pp. viii-ix. See also Helen V. Milner, "The Assumption of Anarchy in International Relations"; and Keohane, "Introduction," After Hegemony.
    • After Hegemony
    • Keohane1
  • 117
    • 84873840682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Morgenthau speaks for nearly all realists in arguing that realism must "guard against two popular fallacies: the concern with motives and the concern with ideological preferences. . . . History shows no exact and necessary correlation between the quality of motives and the quality of foreign policy." Morgenthau, Politics among Nations, pp. 5-7; Waltz, Theory of International Politics, p. 29, see also pp. 65-66, 79, 90, 108-112, 196-198, 271; and Grieco, "Realist International Theory," p. 165.
    • Politics among Nations , pp. 5-7
    • Morgenthau1
  • 118
    • 84874353575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Morgenthau speaks for nearly all realists in arguing that realism must "guard against two popular fallacies: the concern with motives and the concern with ideological preferences. . . . History shows no exact and necessary correlation between the quality of motives and the quality of foreign policy." Morgenthau, Politics among Nations, pp. 5-7; Waltz, Theory of International Politics, p. 29, see also pp. 65-66, 79, 90, 108-112, 196-198, 271; and Grieco, "Realist International Theory," p. 165.
    • Theory of International Politics , pp. 29
    • Waltz1
  • 119
    • 85034144305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Morgenthau speaks for nearly all realists in arguing that realism must "guard against two popular fallacies: the concern with motives and the concern with ideological preferences. . . . History shows no exact and necessary correlation between the quality of motives and the quality of foreign policy." Morgenthau, Politics among Nations, pp. 5-7; Waltz, Theory of International Politics, p. 29, see also pp. 65-66, 79, 90, 108-112, 196-198, 271; and Grieco, "Realist International Theory," p. 165.
    • Realist International Theory , pp. 165
    • Grieco1
  • 120
    • 0003717499 scopus 로고
    • New York: Random House
    • Morgenthau's use of the term "power" can be ill-defined and overly expansive. See Inis L. Claude, Power and International Relations (New York: Random House, 1962), pp. 25-37.
    • (1962) Power and International Relations , pp. 25-37
    • Claude, I.L.1
  • 121
    • 84874353575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Waltz, Theory of International Politics, pp. 118, 126. Fareed Zakaria speaks for most contemporary realists when he terms Waltz's writings on such questions "confused and contradictory." Zakaria, From Wealth to Power: The Unusual Origins of America's World Role (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1998), pp. 26-28.
    • Theory of International Politics , pp. 118
    • Waltz1
  • 122
    • 0003623776 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press
    • Waltz, Theory of International Politics, pp. 118, 126. Fareed Zakaria speaks for most contemporary realists when he terms Waltz's writings on such questions "confused and contradictory." Zakaria, From Wealth to Power: The Unusual Origins of America's World Role (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1998), pp. 26-28.
    • (1998) From Wealth to Power: The Unusual Origins of America's World Role , pp. 26-28
    • Zakaria1
  • 123
    • 0041733800 scopus 로고
    • The Pole of Power and the Pole of Indifference
    • Wolfers, ed., Baltimore, Md.: Johns Hopkins University Press
    • Arnold Wolfers, "The Pole of Power and the Pole of Indifference," in Wolfers, ed., Discord and Collaboration: Essays in International Politics (Baltimore, Md.: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1962), p. 42, see also pp. 86, 156, 160. Even in Waltz, Theory of International Politics, we encounter only the assertion, rather than the derivation, of the primacy of systemic concerns.
    • (1962) Discord and Collaboration: Essays in International Politics , pp. 42
    • Wolfers, A.1
  • 124
    • 84874353575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arnold Wolfers, "The Pole of Power and the Pole of Indifference," in Wolfers, ed., Discord and Collaboration: Essays in International Politics (Baltimore, Md.: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1962), p. 42, see also pp. 86, 156, 160. Even in Waltz, Theory of International Politics, we encounter only the assertion, rather than the derivation, of the primacy of systemic concerns.
    • Theory of International Politics
    • Waltz1
  • 127
    • 0041094898 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Realism and Domestic Politics: A Review Essay
    • Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller
    • Fareed Zakaria, "Realism and Domestic Politics: A Review Essay," in Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller, The Perils of Anarchy, quote on p. 463, and Zakaria, From Wealth to Power, pp. 32-33, 181-183. We do not endorse all of Zakaria's criticisms of Snyder.
    • The Perils of Anarchy , pp. 463
    • Zakaria, F.1
  • 128
    • 0038078220 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fareed Zakaria, "Realism and Domestic Politics: A Review Essay," in Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller, The Perils of Anarchy, quote on p. 463, and Zakaria, From Wealth to Power, pp. 32-33, 181-183. We do not endorse all of Zakaria's criticisms of Snyder.
    • From Wealth to Power , pp. 32-33
    • Zakaria1
  • 129
    • 0040559435 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Anarchy and the Limits of Cooperation: A Realist Critique of the Newest Liberal Institutionalism
    • Baldwin
    • Joseph M. Grieco, "Anarchy and the Limits of Cooperation: A Realist Critique of the Newest Liberal Institutionalism," in Baldwin, Neorealism and Neoliberalism, p. 138; and Powell, "Absolute and Relative Gains in International Relations Theory."
    • Neorealism and Neoliberalism , pp. 138
    • Grieco, J.M.1
  • 133
    • 0003430827 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press
    • Bruce M. Russett, Grasping the Democratic Pence: Principles for a Post-Cold War World (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1993); Robert Jervis, "Security Regimes," International Organization, Vol. 36, No. 2 (Spring 1982), pp. 357-378; Jack Snyder, "Averting Anarchy in the New Europe," International Security, Vol. 14, No. 4 (Spring 1990), pp. 5-41; and George Downs and Keisuke Iida, "Assessing the Theoretical Case against Collective Security," in Downs, ed., Collective Security beyond the Cold War (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1994), pp. 17-39.
    • (1993) Grasping the Democratic Pence: Principles for a Post-Cold War World
    • Russett, B.M.1
  • 134
    • 84972029004 scopus 로고
    • Security Regimes
    • Spring
    • Bruce M. Russett, Grasping the Democratic Pence: Principles for a Post-Cold War World (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1993); Robert Jervis, "Security Regimes," International Organization, Vol. 36, No. 2 (Spring 1982), pp. 357-378; Jack Snyder, "Averting Anarchy in the New Europe," International Security, Vol. 14, No. 4 (Spring 1990), pp. 5-41; and George Downs and Keisuke Iida, "Assessing the Theoretical Case against Collective Security," in Downs, ed., Collective Security beyond the Cold War (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1994), pp. 17-39.
    • (1982) International Organization , vol.36 , Issue.2 , pp. 357-378
    • Jervis, R.1
  • 135
    • 84929227242 scopus 로고
    • Averting Anarchy in the New Europe
    • Spring
    • Bruce M. Russett, Grasping the Democratic Pence: Principles for a Post-Cold War World (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1993); Robert Jervis, "Security Regimes," International Organization, Vol. 36, No. 2 (Spring 1982), pp. 357-378; Jack Snyder, "Averting Anarchy in the New Europe," International Security, Vol. 14, No. 4 (Spring 1990), pp. 5-41; and George Downs and Keisuke Iida, "Assessing the Theoretical Case against Collective Security," in Downs, ed., Collective Security beyond the Cold War (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1994), pp. 17-39.
    • (1990) International Security , vol.14 , Issue.4 , pp. 5-41
    • Snyder, J.1
  • 136
    • 0042234184 scopus 로고
    • Assessing the Theoretical Case against Collective Security
    • Downs, ed., Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press
    • Bruce M. Russett, Grasping the Democratic Pence: Principles for a Post-Cold War World (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1993); Robert Jervis, "Security Regimes," International Organization, Vol. 36, No. 2 (Spring 1982), pp. 357-378; Jack Snyder, "Averting Anarchy in the New Europe," International Security, Vol. 14, No. 4 (Spring 1990), pp. 5-41; and George Downs and Keisuke Iida, "Assessing the Theoretical Case against Collective Security," in Downs, ed., Collective Security beyond the Cold War (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1994), pp. 17-39.
    • (1994) Collective Security Beyond the Cold War , pp. 17-39
    • Downs, G.1    Iida, K.2
  • 137
    • 84972159336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Krasner, Structural Conflict; Mastanduno, "Do Relative Gains Matter?"; James D. Fearon, "Rationalist Explanations for War," International Organization, Vol. 49, No. 3 (Summer 1995), pp. 379- 414; and Lake, "Leadership, Hegemony, and the International Economy."
    • Structural Conflict
    • Krasner1
  • 138
    • 84972159336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Krasner, Structural Conflict; Mastanduno, "Do Relative Gains Matter?"; James D. Fearon, "Rationalist Explanations for War," International Organization, Vol. 49, No. 3 (Summer 1995), pp. 379- 414; and Lake, "Leadership, Hegemony, and the International Economy."
    • Do Relative Gains Matter?
    • Mastanduno1
  • 139
    • 84972159336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rationalist Explanations for War
    • Summer
    • Krasner, Structural Conflict; Mastanduno, "Do Relative Gains Matter?"; James D. Fearon, "Rationalist Explanations for War," International Organization, Vol. 49, No. 3 (Summer 1995), pp. 379-414; and Lake, "Leadership, Hegemony, and the International Economy."
    • (1995) International Organization , vol.49 , Issue.3 , pp. 379-414
    • Fearon, J.D.1
  • 140
    • 84972159336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Krasner, Structural Conflict; Mastanduno, "Do Relative Gains Matter?"; James D. Fearon, "Rationalist Explanations for War," International Organization, Vol. 49, No. 3 (Summer 1995), pp. 379- 414; and Lake, "Leadership, Hegemony, and the International Economy."
    • Leadership, Hegemony, and the International Economy
    • Lake1
  • 141
    • 0030518596 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Trading with the Enemy: Security and Relative Economic Gains
    • Summer
    • Peter Liberman, "Trading with the Enemy: Security and Relative Economic Gains," International Security, Vol. 21, No. 1 (Summer 1996), pp. 155-158; Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously," pp. 538-540; and Robert O. Keohane, "Institutionalist Theory and the Realist Challenge after the Cold War," in Baldwin, Neorealism and Neoliberalism, p. 280ff.
    • (1996) International Security , vol.21 , Issue.1 , pp. 155-158
    • Liberman, P.1
  • 142
    • 0030518596 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Peter Liberman, "Trading with the Enemy: Security and Relative Economic Gains," International Security, Vol. 21, No. 1 (Summer 1996), pp. 155-158; Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously," pp. 538-540; and Robert O. Keohane, "Institutionalist Theory and the Realist Challenge after the Cold War," in Baldwin, Neorealism and Neoliberalism, p. 280ff.
    • Taking Preferences Seriously , pp. 538-540
    • Moravcsik1
  • 143
    • 0030518596 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Institutionalist Theory and the Realist Challenge after the Cold War
    • Baldwin
    • Peter Liberman, "Trading with the Enemy: Security and Relative Economic Gains," International Security, Vol. 21, No. 1 (Summer 1996), pp. 155-158; Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously," pp. 538-540; and Robert O. Keohane, "Institutionalist Theory and the Realist Challenge after the Cold War," in Baldwin, Neorealism and Neoliberalism, p. 280ff.
    • Neorealism and Neoliberalism
    • Keohane, R.O.1
  • 144
    • 0039173716 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Because k cannot be observed directly and it is difficult to differentiate security from power seeking-hence the security dilemma - it is difficult to know how this theory could be tested, absent a theory of the determinants of k. There has been, to our knowledge, no attempt to measure k independently of state behavior. Cf. Mearsheimer, "The False Promise of International Institutions," pp. 347-348.
    • The False Promise of International Institutions , pp. 347-348
    • Mearsheimer1
  • 145
    • 77649127632 scopus 로고
    • Realist Theory and the Problem of International Cooperation
    • August
    • See Joseph M. Grieco, "Realist Theory and the Problem of International Cooperation," Journal of Politics, Vol. 50, No. 3 (August 1988), pp. 610-612; and Grieco, Cooperation among Nations: Europe, America, and Non-Tariff Barriers to Trade (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1990), pp. 45-47.
    • (1988) Journal of Politics , vol.50 , Issue.3 , pp. 610-612
    • Grieco, J.M.1
  • 146
    • 0003993070 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press
    • See Joseph M. Grieco, "Realist Theory and the Problem of International Cooperation," Journal of Politics, Vol. 50, No. 3 (August 1988), pp. 610-612; and Grieco, Cooperation among Nations: Europe, America, and Non-Tariff Barriers to Trade (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1990), pp. 45-47.
    • (1990) Cooperation among Nations: Europe, America, and Non-Tariff Barriers to Trade , pp. 45-47
    • Grieco1
  • 147
    • 24744461933 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Political Economy of International Trade: Enduring Puzzles and an Agenda for Inquiry
    • December
    • For a review of this literature, James E. Alt, Jeffry Frieden, Michael J. Gilligan, Dani Rodrik, and Ronald Rogowski, "The Political Economy of International Trade: Enduring Puzzles and an Agenda for Inquiry," Comparative Political Studies, Vol. 29, No. 6 (December 1996), pp. 689-717.
    • (1996) Comparative Political Studies , vol.29 , Issue.6 , pp. 689-717
    • Alt, J.E.1    Frieden, J.2    Gilligan, M.J.3    Rodrik, D.4    Rogowski, R.5
  • 148
    • 0039240707 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Krasner, "Global Communications and National Power"; and Keohane, "Institutionalist Theory and the Realist Challenge." If such bargaining failure cannot be attributed to concerns about ex post cheating, Grieco argues, it confirms realist claims. Yet Grieco concedes the existence of a competing liberal explanation in a long footnote, but then drops the point. Grieco, "Anarchy and the Limits of Cooperation," pp. 486-488.
    • Global Communications and National Power
    • Krasner1
  • 149
    • 85034148000 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Krasner, "Global Communications and National Power"; and Keohane, "Institutionalist Theory and the Realist Challenge." If such bargaining failure cannot be attributed to concerns about ex post cheating, Grieco argues, it confirms realist claims. Yet Grieco concedes the existence of a competing liberal explanation in a long footnote, but then drops the point. Grieco, "Anarchy and the Limits of Cooperation," pp. 486-488.
    • Institutionalist Theory and the Realist Challenge
    • Keohane1
  • 150
    • 0040559435 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Krasner, "Global Communications and National Power"; and Keohane, "Institutionalist Theory and the Realist Challenge." If such bargaining failure cannot be attributed to concerns about ex post cheating, Grieco argues, it confirms realist claims. Yet Grieco concedes the existence of a competing liberal explanation in a long footnote, but then drops the point. Grieco, "Anarchy and the Limits of Cooperation," pp. 486-488.
    • Anarchy and the Limits of Cooperation , pp. 486-488
    • Grieco1
  • 151
    • 0031757208 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Neoclassical Realism and Theories of Foreign Policy
    • October
    • Gideon Rose, "Neoclassical Realism and Theories of Foreign Policy," World Politics Vol. 51, No. 1 (October 1998), pp. 144-172.
    • (1998) World Politics , vol.51 , Issue.1 , pp. 144-172
    • Rose, G.1
  • 152
    • 0031757208 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid. Rose seeks to make a virtue of this, citing Aristotle for the proposition that domestic politics is simply too complex a subject about which to generalize. This claim must come as a surprise not only to scholars of comparative and U.S. politics, but to those who study the democratic peace, economic interdependence, aggressive ideologies, and other domestic determinants of security policy. In any case, no more recent support for the assumption is provided.
    • (1998) World Politics , vol.51 , Issue.1 , pp. 144-172
  • 156
    • 84873840682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 9
    • Zakaria cites Otto Hintze and Morgenthau in his defense. Yet Hintze viewed state structure as a product of international circumstances, not the reverse. Morgenthau, we shall see, did not believe that his claims about moral restraint were realist. Vague though Morgenthau's notion of "power" may be, he firmly rejects appeals to public opinion. "The government," he wrote, "must realize that it is the leader and not the slave of public opinion. [Public opinion is] continuously created and recreated by informed and responsible leadership." Morgenthau, Politics among Nations, pp. 133-135, 205, chap. 9.
    • Politics among Nations , pp. 133-135
    • Morgenthau1
  • 159
    • 85034145577 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 22; and Randall L. Schweller, "Bandwagoning for Profit: Bringing the Revisionist State Back In," in Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller, The Perils of Anarchy, pp. 255-257. Andrew Kydd terms this view "motivational realism." Kydd, "Sheep in Sheep's Clothing." This, it should be noted, violates Rose's explicit definition of NCR, which assumes that systemic factors remain empirically more important.
    • Deadly Imbalances: Tripolarity and Hitler's Strategy of World Conquest , pp. 22
  • 160
    • 84909243746 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bandwagoning for Profit: Bringing the Revisionist State Back In
    • Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller
    • Ibid., p. 22; and Randall L. Schweller, "Bandwagoning for Profit: Bringing the Revisionist State Back In," in Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller, The Perils of Anarchy, pp. 255-257. Andrew Kydd terms this view "motivational realism." Kydd, "Sheep in Sheep's Clothing." This, it should be noted, violates Rose's explicit definition of NCR, which assumes that systemic factors remain empirically more important.
    • The Perils of Anarchy , pp. 255-257
    • Schweller, R.L.1
  • 161
    • 0038914087 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 22; and Randall L. Schweller, "Bandwagoning for Profit: Bringing the Revisionist State Back In," in Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller, The Perils of Anarchy, pp. 255-257. Andrew Kydd terms this view "motivational realism." Kydd, "Sheep in Sheep's Clothing." This, it should be noted, violates Rose's explicit definition of NCR, which assumes that systemic factors remain empirically more important.
    • Sheep in Sheep's Clothing
    • Kydd1
  • 162
    • 0003810914 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Schweller, Deadly Imbalances, pp. 84-89; and Schweller, "New Realist Research on Alliances," pp. 928-929.
    • Deadly Imbalances , pp. 84-89
    • Schweller1
  • 166
    • 85034149122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This confusing situation can arise because Schweller, like other contemporary realists, tests his theory against neorealism but ignores nonrealist alternatives.
  • 167
    • 85034126380 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 20
    • Ibid., p. 20.
  • 168
    • 0003409521 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: W.W. Norton
    • Those with concerns other than social scientific explanation may legitimately see indeterminacy and richness as a virtue. Michael W. Doyle concludes a recent study of realism by warning that if we "want to retain the range of insight embodied in the works of Thucydides, Machiavelli, Hobbes, and Rousseau . . . we need to reject a monolithic conception of a Realist model." Doyle, Ways of War and Peace: Realism, Liberalism, and Socialism (New York: W.W. Norton, 1997), p. 195; see also pp. 137-160.
    • (1997) Ways of War and Peace: Realism, Liberalism, and Socialism , pp. 195
    • Doyle1
  • 169
    • 84873840682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Morgenthau distinguishes consistently and explicitly between realist and nonrealist elements. The realist elements rest on "the concept of interest defined in terms of power," which "sets politics as [a] . . . sphere of action and understanding" independent of law, morality, or economics. Morgenthau, Politics among Nations, pp. 5, 7-8, 12. He explicitly sets off sections on norms and institutions with an introduction presenting them as alternatives to the initial realist theory. Ibid., p. 227. E.H. Carr's classic realist statement contains similarly self-conscious dichotomies. Carr, The Twenty-Years' Crisis, 1919-1939 (New York: Harper and Row, 1964), pp. 93-94.
    • Politics among Nations , pp. 5
    • Morgenthau1
  • 170
    • 84873840682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Morgenthau distinguishes consistently and explicitly between realist and nonrealist elements. The realist elements rest on "the concept of interest defined in terms of power," which "sets politics as [a] . . . sphere of action and understanding" independent of law, morality, or economics. Morgenthau, Politics among Nations, pp. 5, 7-8, 12. He explicitly sets off sections on norms and institutions with an introduction presenting them as alternatives to the initial realist theory. Ibid., p. 227. E.H. Carr's classic realist statement contains similarly self-conscious dichotomies. Carr, The Twenty-Years' Crisis, 1919-1939 (New York: Harper and Row, 1964), pp. 93-94.
    • Politics among Nations , pp. 227
  • 171
    • 0003959434 scopus 로고
    • New York: Harper and Row
    • For example, Morgenthau distinguishes consistently and explicitly between realist and nonrealist elements. The realist elements rest on "the concept of interest defined in terms of power," which "sets politics as [a] . . . sphere of action and understanding" independent of law, morality, or economics. Morgenthau, Politics among Nations, pp. 5, 7-8, 12. He explicitly sets off sections on norms and institutions with an introduction presenting them as alternatives to the initial realist theory. Ibid., p. 227. E.H. Carr's classic realist statement contains similarly self-conscious dichotomies. Carr, The Twenty-Years' Crisis, 1919-1939 (New York: Harper and Row, 1964), pp. 93-94.
    • (1964) The Twenty-Years' Crisis, 1919-1939 , pp. 93-94
    • Carr1
  • 172
    • 84873840682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See especially Morgenthau, Politics among Nations, pp. 50-51. About this there is no exegetical ambiguity in the relevant chapters. Still, we agree with Robert Keohane that there is considerable contradiction and paradigmatic ambiguity in these theorists.
    • Politics among Nations , pp. 50-51
    • Morgenthau1
  • 174
    • 0003953233 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, citations are from a manuscript copy
    • Stephen Van Evera, Causes of War: Power and the Roots of Conflict (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1999); citations are from a manuscript copy.
    • (1999) Causes of War: Power and the Roots of Conflict
    • Van Evera, S.1
  • 176
    • 85034146028 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., pp. 9-10. Van Evera is quite explicit that he considers this move realist: "The theories discussed here address the effects of the structure of power, or of perceptions of the structure of power. As such they fall into the Realist camp. Their explanatory power therefore adds to the overall explanatory power of Realism, and bolsters Realist arguments that power factors strongly shape international politics."
    • Causes of War: Power and the Roots of Conflict , pp. 9-10
  • 179
    • 70450188797 scopus 로고
    • The Spoils of Conquest
    • Fall
    • For a study demonstrating why it is necessary to treat Van Evera as something other than a realist in order to engage in any sort of orderly empirical testing, see Peter Liberman, "The Spoils of Conquest," International Security, Vol. 18, No. 2 (Fall 1993), pp. 125-153.
    • (1993) International Security , vol.18 , Issue.2 , pp. 125-153
    • Liberman, P.1
  • 181
    • 84971922880 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Realism, Game Theory, and Cooperation
    • April
    • Robert Jervis, "Realism, Game Theory, and Cooperation," World Politics, Vol. 40, No. 3 (April 1988), pp. 317-349. It is, of course, consistent with realism to trace the nature of perception and calculation back to the distribution of material power, as does Waltz in Theory of International Politics, pp. 168-172.
    • (1988) World Politics , vol.40 , Issue.3 , pp. 317-349
    • Jervis, R.1
  • 182
    • 84971922880 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Robert Jervis, "Realism, Game Theory, and Cooperation," World Politics, Vol. 40, No. 3 (April 1988), pp. 317-349. It is, of course, consistent with realism to trace the nature of perception and calculation back to the distribution of material power, as does Waltz in Theory of International Politics, pp. 168-172.
    • Theory of International Politics , pp. 168-172
    • Waltz1
  • 183
    • 0004267628 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Snyder, Myths of Empire, pp. 41-42, 49. Van Evera recognizes the problem and resolves it by assertion: " The Realist family includes causes lying in the structure of international power and in the misperceptions of that structure, although rather limited room is allowed for misperceptions." Van Evera, Causes of War, p. 9 n. 12.
    • Myths of Empire , pp. 41-42
    • Snyder1
  • 184
    • 85034151331 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Realist family includes causes lying in the structure of international power and in the misperceptions of that structure, although rather limited room is allowed for misperceptions
    • Snyder, Myths of Empire, pp. 41-42, 49. Van Evera recognizes the problem and resolves it by assertion: " The Realist family includes causes lying in the structure of international power and in the misperceptions of that structure, although rather limited room is allowed for misperceptions." Van Evera, Causes of War, p. 9 n. 12.
    • Causes of War , Issue.12 , pp. 9
    • Van Evera1
  • 185
    • 0004171805 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 6.
    • Van Evera, Causes of War, chap. 6. Building on Van Evera's earlier work, Christensen and Snyder emphasize perception and misperception of the offense-defense balance to explain alliance patterns in nineteenth- and twentieth-century Europe. In contrast to Waltz and traditional realists, however, Christensen and Snyder do not view perceptions as endogenous to power (or as a random product of uncertainty), but as the result of the lessons of past wars and the relative domestic power of civilians and the military. Their aspiration to synthesize different theories and levels of analysis is a progressive step more generally - a point to which we return in the final section. Yet there remains considerable ambiguity whether Christensen and Snyder believe this is a "progressive problem shift" within the realist paradigm or a form of theory synthesis. Certainly they are often cited as realists (e.g., Grieco, "Realist International Theory," p. 181). Either way, Christensen and Snyder clearly demonstrate the fundamental limits not just of neorealist theory but of the realism paradigm more broadly. Thomas J. Christensen and Jack Snyder, "Chain Gangs and Passed Bucks: Predicting Alliance Patterns in Multipolarity" International Organization, Vol. 44, No. 2 (Spring 1990), pp. 144, 166; Christensen, "Perceptions and Alliances in Europe," International Organization, Vol. 51, No. 1 (Winter 1997), p. 65; and
    • Causes of War
    • Van Evera1
  • 186
    • 85034144305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Van Evera, Causes of War, chap. 6. Building on Van Evera's earlier work, Christensen and Snyder emphasize perception and misperception of the offense-defense balance to explain alliance patterns in nineteenth- and twentieth-century Europe. In contrast to Waltz and traditional realists, however, Christensen and Snyder do not view perceptions as endogenous to power (or as a random product of uncertainty), but as the result of the lessons of past wars and the relative domestic power of civilians and the military. Their aspiration to synthesize different theories and levels of analysis is a progressive step more generally - a point to which we return in the final section. Yet there remains considerable ambiguity whether Christensen and Snyder believe this is a "progressive problem shift" within the realist paradigm or a form of theory synthesis. Certainly they are often cited as realists (e.g., Grieco, "Realist International Theory," p. 181). Either way, Christensen and Snyder clearly demonstrate the fundamental limits not just of neorealist theory but of the realism paradigm more broadly. Thomas J. Christensen and Jack Snyder, "Chain Gangs and Passed Bucks: Predicting Alliance Patterns in Multipolarity" International Organization, Vol. 44, No. 2 (Spring 1990), pp. 144, 166; Christensen, "Perceptions and Alliances in Europe," International Organization, Vol. 51, No. 1 (Winter 1997), p. 65; and
    • Realist International Theory , pp. 181
    • Grieco1
  • 187
    • 84976151554 scopus 로고
    • Chain Gangs and Passed Bucks: Predicting Alliance Patterns in Multipolarity
    • Spring
    • Van Evera, Causes of War, chap. 6. Building on Van Evera's earlier work, Christensen and Snyder emphasize perception and misperception of the offense-defense balance to explain alliance patterns in nineteenth- and twentieth-century Europe. In contrast to Waltz and traditional realists, however, Christensen and Snyder do not view perceptions as endogenous to power (or as a random product of uncertainty), but as the result of the lessons of past wars and the relative domestic power of civilians and the military. Their aspiration to synthesize different theories and levels of analysis is a progressive step more generally - a point to which we return in the final section. Yet there remains considerable ambiguity whether Christensen and Snyder believe this is a "progressive problem shift" within the realist paradigm or a form of theory synthesis. Certainly they are often cited as realists (e.g., Grieco, "Realist International Theory," p. 181). Either way, Christensen and Snyder clearly demonstrate the fundamental limits not just of neorealist theory but of the realism paradigm more broadly. Thomas J. Christensen and Jack Snyder, "Chain Gangs and Passed Bucks: Predicting Alliance Patterns in Multipolarity" International Organization, Vol. 44, No. 2 (Spring 1990), pp. 144, 166; Christensen, "Perceptions and Alliances in Europe," International Organization, Vol. 51, No. 1 (Winter 1997), p. 65; and
    • (1990) International Organization , vol.44 , Issue.2 , pp. 144
    • Christensen, T.J.1    Snyder, J.2
  • 188
    • 0031476202 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Perceptions and Alliances in Europe
    • Winter
    • Van Evera, Causes of War, chap. 6. Building on Van Evera's earlier work, Christensen and Snyder emphasize perception and misperception of the offense-defense balance to explain alliance patterns in nineteenth- and twentieth-century Europe. In contrast to Waltz and traditional realists, however, Christensen and Snyder do not view perceptions as endogenous to power (or as a random product of uncertainty), but as the result of the lessons of past wars and the relative domestic power of civilians and the military. Their aspiration to synthesize different theories and levels of analysis is a progressive step more generally - a point to which we return in the final section. Yet there remains considerable ambiguity whether Christensen and Snyder believe this is a "progressive problem shift" within the realist paradigm or a form of theory synthesis. Certainly they are often cited as realists (e.g., Grieco, "Realist International Theory," p. 181). Either way, Christensen and Snyder clearly demonstrate the fundamental limits not just of neorealist theory but of the realism paradigm more broadly. Thomas J. Christensen and Jack Snyder, "Chain Gangs and Passed Bucks: Predicting Alliance Patterns in Multipolarity" International Organization, Vol. 44, No. 2 (Spring 1990), pp. 144, 166; Christensen, "Perceptions and Alliances in Europe," International Organization, Vol. 51, No. 1 (Winter 1997), p. 65; and
    • (1997) International Organization , vol.51 , Issue.1 , pp. 65
    • Christensen1
  • 191
    • 0043236389 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • American Empire: Review of Fareed Zakaria, from Wealth to Power: The Unusual Origins of America's World Role,"
    • May 3
    • In an otherwise highly complimentary review, historian Walter McDougall calls our attention to precisely this empirical indeterminacy. McDougall, "American Empire: Review of Fareed Zakaria, From Wealth to Power: The Unusual Origins of America's World Role," New York Times Book Review, May 3, 1998, p. 25.
    • (1998) New York Times Book Review , pp. 25
    • McDougall1
  • 193
    • 84935995217 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press
    • For specific claims of a progressive shift, see Stephen M. Walt, The Origins of Alliances (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1987), pp. viii, 5, 21, 263-265. The underlying problem is that a prediction of balancing is not unique to realism. Nearly all international relations paradigms and theories predict that states align and balance against threats to the realization of one's interests, whether the latter are status quo or revisionist. Why else would a rational government form a military alliance? Theories differ in their predictions about conditions under which states balance. Liberal theories predict balancing against "aggressor" states, institutionalist theories predict balancing within institutions, epistemic and some constructivist theories predict balancing where it is perceived as efficacious, and realist theories predict balancing against power.
    • (1987) The Origins of Alliances , pp. 8
    • Walt, S.M.1
  • 194
    • 84959600098 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a striking statement, see ibid., p. 149: "In the Arab world, the most important source of power has been the ability to manipulate one's own image and the images of one's rivals in the minds of other Arab elites. . . . We are therefore dealing with two broad types of balancing: balancing conducted by military means [and] balancing conducted by political means directed at an opponent's image and legitimacy." There remains ambiguity about whether perceptions of intentions involve basic variations in preferences or beliefs about such intentions - the heart of which lies in the lack of theoretical constraint Walt is able to impose on "state intentions."
    • The Origins of Alliances , pp. 149
  • 195
    • 68949098362 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 22. Our criticism is not simply this indeterminacy, but that his concept of "threat" subsumes all but the most implausible of prevailing rationalist explanations. Ibid., p. 26. Waltz takes a similar view, arguing that Walt (like Schweller and others) should not be seen as "increasing the explanatory power of defective theory and making it more precise," but bringing in extra-theoretical variables. "Walt," he writes, "[has] unfortunately taken the imaginative application of the theory to be a new one." Waltz, "Evaluating Theories," p. 916. See also Gunther Hellmann and Reinhard Wolf, "Neorealism, Neoliberal Institutionalism, and the Future of NATO," Security Studies, Vol. 3, No. 1 (Autumn 1993), pp. 3-43.
    • The Origins of Alliances , pp. 22
  • 196
    • 68949098362 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 22. Our criticism is not simply this indeterminacy, but that his concept of "threat" subsumes all but the most implausible of prevailing rationalist explanations. Ibid., p. 26. Waltz takes a similar view, arguing that Walt (like Schweller and others) should not be seen as "increasing the explanatory power of defective theory and making it more precise," but bringing in extra-theoretical variables. "Walt," he writes, "[has] unfortunately taken the imaginative application of the theory to be a new one." Waltz, "Evaluating Theories," p. 916. See also Gunther Hellmann and Reinhard Wolf, "Neorealism, Neoliberal Institutionalism, and the Future of NATO," Security Studies, Vol. 3, No. 1 (Autumn 1993), pp. 3-43.
    • The Origins of Alliances , pp. 26
  • 197
    • 68949098362 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 22. Our criticism is not simply this indeterminacy, but that his concept of "threat" subsumes all but the most implausible of prevailing rationalist explanations. Ibid., p. 26. Waltz takes a similar view, arguing that Walt (like Schweller and others) should not be seen as "increasing the explanatory power of defective theory and making it more precise," but bringing in extra-theoretical variables. "Walt," he writes, "[has] unfortunately taken the imaginative application of the theory to be a new one." Waltz, "Evaluating Theories," p. 916. See also Gunther Hellmann and Reinhard Wolf, "Neorealism, Neoliberal Institutionalism, and the Future of NATO," Security Studies, Vol. 3, No. 1 (Autumn 1993), pp. 3-43.
    • Evaluating Theories , pp. 916
    • Waltz1
  • 198
    • 68949098362 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Neorealism, Neoliberal Institutionalism, and the Future of NATO
    • Autumn
    • Ibid., p. 22. Our criticism is not simply this indeterminacy, but that his concept of "threat" subsumes all but the most implausible of prevailing rationalist explanations. Ibid., p. 26. Waltz takes a similar view, arguing that Walt (like Schweller and others) should not be seen as "increasing the explanatory power of defective theory and making it more precise," but bringing in extra-theoretical variables. "Walt," he writes, "[has] unfortunately taken the imaginative application of the theory to be a new one." Waltz, "Evaluating Theories," p. 916. See also Gunther Hellmann and Reinhard Wolf, "Neorealism, Neoliberal Institutionalism, and the Future of NATO," Security Studies, Vol. 3, No. 1 (Autumn 1993), pp. 3-43.
    • (1993) Security Studies , vol.3 , Issue.1 , pp. 3-43
    • Hellmann, G.1    Wolf, R.2
  • 199
    • 0042735161 scopus 로고
    • August
    • Douglas J. MacDonald's review in Journal of Politics, Vol. 51, No. 2 (August 1989), p. 796, accuses Walt of employing a "rigid" definition. Walt acknowledges, for example, that the Soviet Union allied with leftist regimes in the Middle East and the United States did not, but he does not treat such actions as ideologically motivated because neither superpower demanded that its allies alter their domestic policies.
    • (1989) Journal of Politics , vol.51 , Issue.2 , pp. 796
    • MacDonald's, D.J.1
  • 200
    • 84935995217 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Walt, The Origins of Alliances, pp. 149, 168, 266; and Stephen M. Walt, "Alliance Formation and the Balance of World Politics," in Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller, The Perils of Anarchy, pp. 214, 243 (emphasis in original).
    • The Origins of Alliances , pp. 149
    • Walt1
  • 201
    • 11544310428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alliance Formation and the Balance of World Politics
    • Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller, emphasis in original
    • Walt, The Origins of Alliances, pp. 149, 168, 266; and Stephen M. Walt, "Alliance Formation and the Balance of World Politics," in Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller, The Perils of Anarchy, pp. 214, 243 (emphasis in original).
    • The Perils of Anarchy , pp. 214
    • Walt, S.M.1
  • 202
    • 0039907923 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Realism and the End of the Cold War
    • Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller
    • We set aside another problem, namely Wohlforth's evident reliance on a distinction between status quo and revisionist states as a "contextual" factor explaining Soviet preferences and, in particular, the absence of a "World War III." As we have already discussed degeneration into liberal theory, we focus here on Wohlforth's overt perceptual challenge to objective power analysis in William C. Wohlforth, "Realism and the End of the Cold War," in Brown, Lynn-Jones, and Miller, The Perils of Anarchy, pp. 32, 36-37.
    • The Perils of Anarchy , pp. 32
    • Wohlforth, W.C.1
  • 205
    • 0040627008 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wohlforth, The Elusive Balance, pp. 233-234, 242-243, 251; and Wohlforth, "Realism and the End of the Cold War," pp. 19-22, 37.
    • The Elusive Balance , pp. 233-234
    • Wohlforth1
  • 211
    • 85034128321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 23. It remains unclear whether Wohlforth means to argue that regime type actually shifted East European policies, or shifted Soviet perception of its relative power. Either way, the connection to relative power capabilities - even understood in a more fine-grained sense - remains unclear. Wohlforth also stresses the unintended consequences of Soviet policy shifts, particularly in Eastern Europe.
    • Realism and the End of the Cold War , pp. 23
  • 212
    • 0009338143 scopus 로고
    • New York: Simon and Schuster
    • On Bismarck, see Henry Kissinger, Diplomacy (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1994), pp. 120-131. On the realist view of international law and institutions, see Mearsheimer, "The False Promise of International Institutions." Recall that institutionalists adhere to nearly all the same assumptions as realists - an underlying state of anarchy, states as rational egotistical actors, substantial conflict of interest - but argue that governments faced with collective action problems can contract among themselves to mitigate the major disadvantages of anarchy.
    • (1994) Diplomacy , pp. 120-131
    • Kissinger, H.1
  • 213
    • 85034144305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Grieco, "Realist International Theory," pp. 184-186. Liberals and institutionalists have relatively little trouble explaining this outcome. See Andrew Moravcsik, The Choice for Europe: Social Purpose and State Power from Messina to Maastricht (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1998).
    • Realist International Theory , pp. 184-186
    • Grieco1
  • 215
    • 85034133054 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • State Interests and Institutional Rule Trajectories: A Neorealist Interpretation of the Maastricht Treaty and European Economic and Monetary Union
    • Joseph M. Grieco, "State Interests and Institutional Rule Trajectories: A Neorealist Interpretation of the Maastricht Treaty and European Economic and Monetary Union," in Frankel, Realism, pp. 287-290.
    • Frankel, Realism , pp. 287-290
    • Grieco, J.M.1
  • 216
    • 85034127978 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Grieco, with admirable honesty, concedes the indeterminacy: "It will be of intense interest to students of international politics," he concludes, "to observe whether institutions [i.e., Grieco's binding hypothesis] or underlying differentials of power [i.e., the conventional realist argument] will have a greater impact on the future course of European monetary affairs." Ibid., p. 304. Yet in a realist theory of European integration in the 1990s, shouldn't the outcome of EMU be a decisive theoretical prediction, not a matter of empirical happenstance?
  • 217
    • 85034144305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Grieco, "Realist International Theory," pp. 185-186; and Grieco, "State Interests and Institutional Rule Trajectories," p. 286. Grieco rightly observes that the historical record does not confirm that initial and ongoing support for the agreement by the most powerful government, that of Germany (rather than imposing an institutional solution on weaker countries) can be explained as an effort to balance against U.S. monetary power. Grieco invokes at various points the claim that EMU generates absolute gains (as liberals maintain) and that Germany or others may have misperceived the likely economic outcome (as epistemic theory might suggest), or because international institutions enhance the credibility of national commitments (as institutionalists maintain). He also argues that Germany was forced to grant a quid pro quo in exchange for German unification, but this flies in the face of a growing consensus that the German commitment to move to EMU began months, even years, before reunification, and did not weaken when reunification was complete. For a review of the evidence, see Moravcsik, The Choice for Europe, chap. 6.
    • Realist International Theory , pp. 185-186
    • Grieco1
  • 218
    • 84890631213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Grieco rightly observes that the historical record does not confirm that initial and ongoing support for the agreement by the most powerful government, that of Germany (rather than imposing an institutional solution on weaker countries) can be explained as an effort to balance against U.S. monetary power. Grieco invokes at various points the claim that EMU generates absolute gains (as liberals maintain) and that Germany or others may have misperceived the likely economic outcome (as epistemic theory might suggest), or because international institutions enhance the credibility of national commitments (as institutionalists maintain). He also argues that Germany was forced to grant a quid pro quo in exchange for German unification, but this flies in the face of a growing consensus that the German commitment to move to EMU began months, even years, before reunification, and did not weaken when reunification was complete. For a review of the evidence
    • Grieco, "Realist International Theory," pp. 185-186; and Grieco, "State Interests and Institutional Rule Trajectories," p. 286. Grieco rightly observes that the historical record does not confirm that initial and ongoing support for the agreement by the most powerful government, that of Germany (rather than imposing an institutional solution on weaker countries) can be explained as an effort to balance against U.S. monetary power. Grieco invokes at various points the claim that EMU generates absolute gains (as liberals maintain) and that Germany or others may have misperceived the likely economic outcome (as epistemic theory might suggest), or because international institutions enhance the credibility of national commitments (as institutionalists maintain). He also argues that Germany was forced to grant a quid pro quo in exchange for German unification, but this flies in the face of a growing consensus that the German commitment to move to EMU began months, even years, before reunification, and did not weaken when reunification was complete. For a review of the evidence, see Moravcsik, The Choice for Europe, chap. 6.
    • State Interests and Institutional Rule Trajectories , pp. 286
    • Grieco1
  • 219
    • 0004223905 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 6
    • Grieco, "Realist International Theory," pp. 185-186; and Grieco, "State Interests and Institutional Rule Trajectories," p. 286. Grieco rightly observes that the historical record does not confirm that initial and ongoing support for the agreement by the most powerful government, that of Germany (rather than imposing an institutional solution on weaker countries) can be explained as an effort to balance against U.S. monetary power. Grieco invokes at various points the claim that EMU generates absolute gains (as liberals maintain) and that Germany or others may have misperceived the likely economic outcome (as epistemic theory might suggest), or because international institutions enhance the credibility of national commitments (as institutionalists maintain). He also argues that Germany was forced to grant a quid pro quo in exchange for German unification, but this flies in the face of a growing consensus that the German commitment to move to EMU began months, even years, before reunification, and did not weaken when reunification was complete. For a review of the evidence, see Moravcsik, The Choice for Europe, chap. 6.
    • The Choice for Europe
    • Moravcsik1
  • 220
    • 0001226653 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • he argues that "contingent realism suggests the importance of motives" and renders standard power variables "less important."
    • Glaser is ambiguous on the role of motives. In "Realists as Optimists," pp. 394-397, he argues that "contingent realism suggests the importance of motives" and renders standard power variables "less important." In Charles L. Glaser, "The Security Dilemma Revisited," World Politics, Vol. 50, No. 1 (October 1997) p. 191, he argues, "contrary to the standard [realist] argument, countries should not focus solely on capabilities, but also on motives. " Kydd, "Sheep in Sheep's Clothing," p. 17, brings the distinction between democracy and nondemocracy, as well as variation in ideology, to explain such behavior.
    • Realists as Optimists , pp. 394-397
  • 221
    • 0001226653 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Security Dilemma Revisited
    • October he argues, "contrary to the standard [realist] argument, countries should not focus solely on capabilities, but also on motives
    • Glaser is ambiguous on the role of motives. In "Realists as Optimists," pp. 394-397, he argues that "contingent realism suggests the importance of motives" and renders standard power variables "less important." In Charles L. Glaser, "The Security Dilemma Revisited," World Politics, Vol. 50, No. 1 (October 1997) p. 191, he argues, "contrary to the standard [realist] argument, countries should not focus solely on capabilities, but also on motives. " Kydd, "Sheep in Sheep's Clothing," p. 17, brings the distinction between democracy and nondemocracy, as well as variation in ideology, to explain such behavior.
    • (1997) World Politics , vol.50 , Issue.1 , pp. 191
    • Glaser, C.L.1
  • 222
    • 0001226653 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • brings the distinction between democracy and nondemocracy, as well as variation in ideology, to explain such behavior
    • Glaser is ambiguous on the role of motives. In "Realists as Optimists," pp. 394-397, he argues that "contingent realism suggests the importance of motives" and renders standard power variables "less important." In Charles L. Glaser, "The Security Dilemma Revisited," World Politics, Vol. 50, No. 1 (October 1997) p. 191, he argues, "contrary to the standard [realist] argument, countries should not focus solely on capabilities, but also on motives. " Kydd, "Sheep in Sheep's Clothing," p. 17, brings the distinction between democracy and nondemocracy, as well as variation in ideology, to explain such behavior.
    • Sheep in Sheep's Clothing , pp. 17
    • Kydd1
  • 224
    • 85033297919 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Another example is Mearsheimer's detailed refutation of collective security theory, yet Mearsheimer cites very few, if any, clear advocates of collective security (as opposed to concerts or regimes) after the 1950s. Robert Keohane explicitly rejects such an "idealist" account
    • Ibid., p. 411. Another example is Mearsheimer's detailed refutation of collective security theory, yet Mearsheimer cites very few, if any, clear advocates of collective security (as opposed to concerts or regimes) after the 1950s. Robert Keohane explicitly rejects such an "idealist" account. Keohane, After Hegemony, pp. 59-60 n. 2.
    • Realists as Optimists , pp. 411
  • 225
    • 85034150448 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 411. Another example is Mearsheimer's detailed refutation of collective security theory, yet Mearsheimer cites very few, if any, clear advocates of collective security (as opposed to concerts or regimes) after the 1950s. Robert Keohane explicitly rejects such an "idealist" account. Keohane, After Hegemony, pp. 59-60 n. 2.
    • After Hegemony , Issue.2 , pp. 59-60
    • Keohane1
  • 227
    • 85034127838 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See n. 60.
  • 228
    • 85034136306 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • employ nearly identical categories, but different labels
    • For example, Lake and Powell, in Strategic Choice, employ nearly identical categories, but different labels.
    • Strategic Choice
    • Lake1    Powell2
  • 234
    • 0004264732 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Waltz, Theory of International Politics; Mearsheimer, "False Promise of International Institutions," p. 351; and Charles Lipson, "International Cooperation in Economic and Security Affairs," in Baldwin, Neorealism and Neoliberalism, pp. 60-84.
    • Neorealism and Neoliberalism , pp. 60-84
    • Baldwin1
  • 235
    • 85034141744 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We should expect war and realist security dynamics, for example, only involving at least one state sufficiently "aggressive" to raise "vital" interests for all involved. Here we find support from Schweller, "New Realist Research on Alliances," pp. 928-929. For a classic statement of this position, see also Stanley Hoffmann, Duties beyond Borders: On the Limits and Possibilities of an Ethical International Politics (Syracuse, N.Y: Syracuse University Press, 1981), pp. 14-16.
    • New Realist Research on Alliances , pp. 928-929
    • Schweller1
  • 236
    • 0003723057 scopus 로고
    • Syracuse, N.Y: Syracuse University Press
    • We should expect war and realist security dynamics, for example, only involving at least one state sufficiently "aggressive" to raise "vital" interests for all involved. Here we find support from Schweller, "New Realist Research on Alliances," pp. 928-929. For a classic statement of this position, see also Stanley Hoffmann, Duties beyond Borders: On the Limits and Possibilities of an Ethical International Politics (Syracuse, N.Y: Syracuse University Press, 1981), pp. 14-16.
    • (1981) Duties Beyond Borders: on the Limits and Possibilities of an Ethical International Politics , pp. 14-16
    • Hoffmann, S.1
  • 237
    • 85034142418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • We have noted these examples above. Such scholars voice criticisms of what they take to be liberal views, but they tend to take the form of either skepticism that democracies are stable or concerns about the transition to democracy, neither of which supports realist claims against liberal ones.
  • 238
    • 0043236447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously," pp. 523-524. See also Posen, The Sources of Military Doctrine, pp. 60-61; Morrow, "Social Choice and System Structure," pp. 83-84; and Andrew Mack, "Why Big Nations Lose Small Wars: The Politics of Asymmetrical Conflict," World Politics, Vol. 27, No. 2 (January 1975), pp. 175-200.
    • Taking Preferences Seriously , pp. 523-524
    • Moravcsik1
  • 239
    • 0003957432 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously," pp. 523-524. See also Posen, The Sources of Military Doctrine, pp. 60-61; Morrow, "Social Choice and System Structure," pp. 83-84; and Andrew Mack, "Why Big Nations Lose Small Wars: The Politics of Asymmetrical Conflict," World Politics, Vol. 27, No. 2 (January 1975), pp. 175-200.
    • The Sources of Military Doctrine , pp. 60-61
    • Posen1
  • 240
    • 0043236301 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously," pp. 523-524. See also Posen, The Sources of Military Doctrine, pp. 60-61; Morrow, "Social Choice and System Structure," pp. 83-84; and Andrew Mack, "Why Big Nations Lose Small Wars: The Politics of Asymmetrical Conflict," World Politics, Vol. 27, No. 2 (January 1975), pp. 175-200.
    • Social Choice and System Structure , pp. 83-84
    • Morrow1
  • 241
    • 84974201272 scopus 로고
    • Why Big Nations Lose Small Wars: The Politics of Asymmetrical Conflict
    • January
    • Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously," pp. 523-524. See also Posen, The Sources of Military Doctrine, pp. 60-61; Morrow, "Social Choice and System Structure," pp. 83-84; and Andrew Mack, "Why Big Nations Lose Small Wars: The Politics of Asymmetrical Conflict," World Politics, Vol. 27, No. 2 (January 1975), pp. 175-200.
    • (1975) World Politics , vol.27 , Issue.2 , pp. 175-200
    • Mack, A.1
  • 242
    • 84972167842 scopus 로고
    • Is Realism Dead? The Domestic Sources of International Politics
    • Autumn
    • John Ruggie, personal communication. For a view that one theory must dominate, see Ethan B. Kapstein, "Is Realism Dead? The Domestic Sources of International Politics," International Organization, Vol. 49, No. 4 (Autumn 1995), pp. 751-774.
    • (1995) International Organization , vol.49 , Issue.4 , pp. 751-774
    • Kapstein, E.B.1
  • 246
    • 85034147377 scopus 로고
    • Theory of International Politics: Structural Realism and Beyond
    • Keohane, ed., New York: Columbia University Press
    • Robert O. Keohane, "Theory of International Politics: Structural Realism and Beyond," in Keohane, ed., Neorealism and Its Critics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1990), p. 192. See also Stephen Brooks, "Dueling Realisms," International Organization, Vol. 51, No. 3 (Summer 1997), pp. 471-472.
    • (1990) Neorealism and Its Critics , pp. 192
    • Keohane, R.O.1
  • 247
    • 0031524620 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dueling Realisms
    • Summer
    • Robert O. Keohane, "Theory of International Politics: Structural Realism and Beyond," in Keohane, ed., Neorealism and Its Critics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1990), p. 192. See also Stephen Brooks, "Dueling Realisms," International Organization, Vol. 51, No. 3 (Summer 1997), pp. 471-472.
    • (1997) International Organization , vol.51 , Issue.3 , pp. 471-472
    • Brooks, S.1
  • 248
    • 0032398923 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Culture Clash: Assessing the Importance of Ideas in Security Studies
    • Summer
    • Michael C. Desch, "Culture Clash: Assessing the Importance of Ideas in Security Studies," International Security, Vol. 23, No. 1 (Summer 1998), p. 170.
    • (1998) International Security , vol.23 , Issue.1 , pp. 170
    • Desch, M.C.1
  • 249
    • 85034146976 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The "two-step" model to explain static bargaining outcomes follows, in our view, directly from the rationality assumption shared by realism and most of its basic competitors. As classic studies of power by Robert Dahl and others taught us a generation ago, it is impossible to model strategic interaction without first determining preferences or beliefs (or both) independently of the strategic circumstances. Only where the pattern of preferences is consistent with the realist assumptions above - preferences are intense, symmetrical, and zero-sum - is it proper even to consider realist theory. In any other case - say a situation where preferences are compatible or where the collective action problem is informational - realism is not simply incorrect; it is completely inappropriate. Thus in classical bargaining theory, the locations of ideal points and outside options (preferences) are almost always relevant, whereas linkage to threats and inducements are only relevant under specific conditions. This mechanism for theory synthesis is the most powerful basic tool that rationalist social science theory has developed for this sort theory synthesis.
  • 250
    • 0003950725 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Otto Hintze, The Historical Essays of Otto Hintze (New York: Oxford University Press, 1975); Charles Tilly, ed., The Formation of National States in Western Europe (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1975); Grieco, "Realist International Theory"; and Layne "Kant or Cant," pp. 326- 327.
    • (1975) The Historical Essays of Otto Hintze
    • Hintze, O.1
  • 251
    • 0003816455 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press
    • Otto Hintze, The Historical Essays of Otto Hintze (New York: Oxford University Press, 1975); Charles Tilly, ed., The Formation of National States in Western Europe (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1975); Grieco, "Realist International Theory"; and Layne "Kant or Cant," pp. 326- 327.
    • (1975) The Formation of National States in Western Europe
    • Tilly, C.1
  • 252
    • 85034144305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Otto Hintze, The Historical Essays of Otto Hintze (New York: Oxford University Press, 1975); Charles Tilly, ed., The Formation of National States in Western Europe (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1975); Grieco, "Realist International Theory"; and Layne "Kant or Cant," pp. 326- 327.
    • Realist International Theory
    • Grieco1
  • 253
    • 61449162892 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Otto Hintze, The Historical Essays of Otto Hintze (New York: Oxford University Press, 1975); Charles Tilly, ed., The Formation of National States in Western Europe (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1975); Grieco, "Realist International Theory"; and Layne "Kant or Cant," pp. 326-327.
    • Kant or Cant , pp. 326-327
    • Layne1
  • 254
    • 85055296575 scopus 로고
    • Nationalism, the Mass Army, and Military Power
    • Fall
    • Barry R. Posen, "Nationalism, the Mass Army, and Military Power," International Security, Vol. 18, No. 2 (Fall 1993), pp. 80-124; and Mearsheimer, "Back to the Future."
    • (1993) International Security , vol.18 , Issue.2 , pp. 80-124
    • Posen, B.R.1
  • 255
    • 0040948397 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Barry R. Posen, "Nationalism, the Mass Army, and Military Power," International Security, Vol. 18, No. 2 (Fall 1993), pp. 80-124; and Mearsheimer, "Back to the Future."
    • Back to the Future
    • Mearsheimer1
  • 256
    • 84972442822 scopus 로고
    • Anarchy Is What You Make of It: The Social Construction of Power Politics
    • Spring
    • Alexander Wendt, "Anarchy Is What You Make of It: The Social Construction of Power Politics," International Organization, Vol. 46, No. 2 (Spring 1992), pp. 391-425.
    • (1992) International Organization , vol.46 , Issue.2 , pp. 391
    • Wendt, A.1
  • 259
    • 0004061150 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some constructivists seem also to encourage the use of this dichotomy. We have not, however, considered a constructivist "theory" here because we take seriously those who warn that "constructivism" - like "materialism," "rationalism," and other such broad categories of social theory-does not define a discrete international relations paradigm or theory. It should not, therefore, be employed as a counterpart to realism, liberalism, institutionalism, or epistemic theory. Constructivist arguments might be found in any of these categories. A realist versus idealist/constructionist dichotomy would thus be unhelpful. See Wendt, "Social Theory and International Politics"; and Martha Finnemore and Kathryn Sikkink, "International Norm Dynamics and Political Change," International Organization, Vol. 52, No. 2 (Spring 1998), pp. 890, 909-912.
    • Social Theory and International Politics
    • Wendt1
  • 260
    • 85017051786 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • International Norm Dynamics and Political Change
    • Spring
    • Some constructivists seem also to encourage the use of this dichotomy. We have not, however, considered a constructivist "theory" here because we take seriously those who warn that "constructivism" - like "materialism," "rationalism," and other such broad categories of social theory- does not define a discrete international relations paradigm or theory. It should not, therefore, be employed as a counterpart to realism, liberalism, institutionalism, or epistemic theory. Constructivist arguments might be found in any of these categories. A realist versus idealist/constructionist dichotomy would thus be unhelpful. See Wendt, "Social Theory and International Politics"; and Martha Finnemore and Kathryn Sikkink, "International Norm Dynamics and Political Change," International Organization, Vol. 52, No. 2 (Spring 1998), pp. 890, 909-912.
    • (1998) International Organization , vol.52 , Issue.2 , pp. 890
    • Finnemore, M.1    Sikkink, K.2


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.