메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 99, Issue 4, 2014, Pages 685-734

Three symmetries between textualist and purposivist theories of statutory interpretation-and the irreducible roles of values and judgment within both

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84902456534     PISSN: 00108847     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (27)

References (162)
  • 2
    • 84861415118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The new purposivism
    • See John F. Manning, The New Purposivism, 2011 SUP. CT. REV. 113, 120.
    • (2011) Sup. Ct. Rev. , vol.113 , pp. 120
    • Manning, J.F.1
  • 3
    • 84902514565 scopus 로고
    • But cf. RONALD DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE 313 (1986) (characterizing the judicial "role as fundamentally the creative one of a partner continuing to develop, in what [the judge] believes is the best way, the statutory scheme Congress began")
    • (1986) Law's Empire , vol.313
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 4
    • 84934454328 scopus 로고
    • Dynamic statutory interpretation
    • William N. Eskridge, Jr., Dynamic Statutory Interpretation, 135 U. PA. L. REV. 1479, 1482 (1987) (depicting judges as agents "who must often update their orders to meet changing circumstances").
    • (1987) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.135 , Issue.1479 , pp. 1482
    • Eskridge Jr., W.N.1
  • 5
    • 0036328270 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Our democratic constitution
    • See, e.g., Stephen Breyer, Our Democratic Constitution, 77 N.Y.U. L. REV. 245, 266 (2002) (arguing that "purposive" interpretation "reminds the judge . . . that it is in Congress, not the courts, where the Constitution places the authority to enact a statute")
    • (2002) N.Y.U. L. Rev. , vol.77 , Issue.245 , pp. 266
    • Breyer, S.1
  • 6
    • 0346615803 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Essay the courts and the congress: Should judges disdain political history?
    • Peter L. Strauss, Essay, The Courts and the Congress: Should Judges Disdain Political History?, 98 COLUM. L. REV. 242, 252-53 (1998) (arguing that purposivism makes courts the most effective agents of the legislature). In using the term "purposivism" as I do, I link two approaches that sometimes have been separated by subsuming what might be called "intentionalism" under the rubric of purposivism. As a conceptual matter, there is undoubtedly a clear difference between two varieties of statutory purpose: the specific intentions of the statute's enacting legislature and the more "general aim or policy which pervades a statute."
    • (1998) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.98 , Issue.242 , pp. 252-253
    • Strauss, P.L.1
  • 7
    • 0042962330 scopus 로고
    • Judge learned hand and the interpretation of statutes
    • Archibald Cox, Judge Learned Hand and the Interpretation of Statutes, 60 HARV. L. REV. 370, 370-71 (1947)
    • (1947) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.60 , Issue.370 , pp. 370-371
    • Cox, A.1
  • 8
    • 0347771587 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Textualism as a nondelegation doctrine
    • n.11
    • see John F. Manning, Textualism as a Nondelegation Doctrine, 97 COLUM. L. REV. 673, 677 & n.11 (1997) (discussing this distinction).
    • (1997) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.97 , Issue.673 , pp. 677
    • Manning, J.F.1
  • 9
    • 39649100836 scopus 로고
    • Statutory interpretation-in the classroom and in the courtroom
    • For an approach centered on the former kind of purpose, or what might be labeled legislative "intent," see Richard A. Posner, Statutory Interpretation - in the Classroom and in the Courtroom, 50 U. CHI. L. REV. 800, 817 (1983) ("The judge should try to think his way as best he can into the minds of the enacting legislators and imagine how they would have wanted the statute applied to the case at bar.").
    • (1983) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.50 , Issue.800 , pp. 817
    • Posner, R.A.1
  • 10
    • 0002055435 scopus 로고
    • William N. Eskridge Jr. & Philip P. Frickey Eds.
    • For the classic statement of the latter, more general approach, see HENRY M. HART, Jr. & ALBERT M. SACKS, THE LEGAL PROCESS: BASIC PROBLEMS IN THE MAKING AND APPLICATION OF LAW 1374, 1378 (William N. Eskridge, Jr. & Philip P. Frickey eds., 1994) (urging interpreters to "[d]ecide what purpose ought to be attributed to the statute and to any subordinate provision of it which may be involved" on the assumption that the legislature consisted of "reasonable persons pursuing reasonable purposes reasonably," and to "[i]nterpret the words of the statute immediately in question so as to carry out the purpose" as well as possible).
    • (1994) The Legal Process: Basic Problems in the Making and Application of Law , vol.1374 , pp. 1378
    • Hart Jr., H.M.1    Sacks, A.M.2
  • 11
    • 84860131640 scopus 로고
    • Text, history, and structure in statutory interpretation
    • See, e.g., Frank H. Easterbrook, Text, History, and Structure in Statutory Interpretation, 17 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 61, 63 (1994) (arguing that judges "are supposed to be faithful agents, not independent principals")
    • (1994) Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol'y , vol.17 , Issue.61 , pp. 63
    • Easterbrook, F.H.1
  • 12
    • 0348050646 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Textualism and the equity of the statute
    • John F. Manning, Textualism and the Equity of the Statute, 101 COLUM. L. REV. 1, 18 (2001) ("The root of the textualist position is . . . in straightforward faithful agent theory.").
    • (2001) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.101 , Issue.1 , pp. 18
    • Manning, J.F.1
  • 13
    • 0039884712 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Common-law courts in a civil-law system: The role of united states federal courts in interpreting the constitution and laws
    • Amy Gutmann ed.
    • See, e.g., ANTONIN SCALIA, Common-Law Courts in a Civil-Law System: The Role of United States Federal Courts in Interpreting the Constitution and Laws, in A MATTER OF INTERPRETATION 3, 17-18 (Amy Gutmann ed., 1997) ("The practical threat is that, under the guise or even the self-delusion of pursuing unexpressed legislative intents, common-law judges will in fact pursue their own objectives and desires . . . .").
    • (1997) A Matter of Interpretation , vol.3 , pp. 17-18
    • Scalia, A.1
  • 14
    • 18444397773 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Textualism and legislative intent
    • See John F. Manning, Textualism and Legislative Intent, 91 VA. L. REV. 419, 419-20 (2005).
    • (2005) Va. L. Rev. , vol.91 , Issue.419 , pp. 419-420
    • Manning, J.F.1
  • 15
    • 32044457967 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What divides textualists from purposivists?
    • See John F. Manning, What Divides Textualists From Purposivists?, 106 COLUM. L. REV. 70, 73, 79-80 (2006) (discussing the importance of context for textualism and purposivism)
    • (2006) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.106 , Issue.70-73 , pp. 79-80
    • Manning, J.F.1
  • 17
    • 0037791008 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The absurdity doctrine
    • See John F. Manning, The Absurdity Doctrine, 116 HARV. L. REV. 2387, 2456 (2003) [hereinafter Manning, Absurdity Doctrine] ("In contrast with their literalist predecessors in the 'plain meaning' school, modern textualists reject the idea that interpretation can occur 'within the four corners' of a statute."
    • (2003) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.116 , Issue.2387 , pp. 2456
    • Manning, J.F.1
  • 19
    • 84863587651 scopus 로고
    • Statutory construction and the coordinating function of plain meaning
    • Frederick Schauer, Statutory Construction and the Coordinating Function of Plain Meaning, 1990 SUP. CT. REV. 231, 252 ("Plain meaning . . . is a blunt, frequently crude, and certainly narrowing device, cutting off access to many features of some particular conversational or communicative or interpretive context that would otherwise be available to the interpreter or conversational participant.").
    • (1990) Sup. CT. Rev. , vol.231 , pp. 252
    • Schauer, F.1
  • 20
    • 32044431698 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The rise and fall of textualism
    • For an important previous exploration of convergences between textualist and purposivist theories, see Jonathan T. Molot, The Rise and Fall of Textualism, 106 COLUM. L. REV. 1, 34-43 (2006).
    • (2006) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.106 , Issue.1 , pp. 34-43
    • Molot, J.T.1
  • 21
    • 84902514557 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We have, built into the workings of our mind[s], a mechanism that creates an uncomfortable feeling of dissonance, or lack of harmony, when we become aware of some inconsistency among the various attitudes, beliefs, and items of knowledge that constitute our mental store
    • 4th ed.
    • There may be some similarities to the psychological theory of cognitive dissonance, according to which "we have, built into the workings of our mind[s], a mechanism that creates an uncomfortable feeling of dissonance, or lack of harmony, when we become aware of some inconsistency among the various attitudes, beliefs, and items of knowledge that constitute our mental store." PETER GRAY, PSYCHOLOGY 520 (4th ed. 2002).
    • (2002) Peter Gray, Psychology , vol.520
  • 22
    • 84902514558 scopus 로고
    • The theory traces to LEON FESTINGER, A THEORY OF COGNITIVE DISSONANCE 3 (1957) ("The existence of dissonance, being psychologically uncomfortable, will motivate the person [experiencing it] to try to reduce the dissonance and achieve consonance.").
    • (1957) Leon Festinger A Theory of Cognitive Dissonance , vol.3
  • 25
    • 0011307639 scopus 로고
    • Context
    • Acontextuality could never be more than relative. Cf. Martha Minow & Elizabeth V. Spelman, In Context, 63 S. CAL. L. REV. 1597, 1651 (1990) ("[T]he call to make judgments in context . . . seems misleading if it implies that we could ever make judgments outside of a context; the question is always what context matters or what context should we make matter for this moment.").
    • (1990) S. Cal. L. Rev. , vol.63 , Issue.1597 , pp. 1651
    • Minow, M.1    Spelman, E.V.2
  • 26
    • 34250747190 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Defaults in semantics and pragmatics
    • Edward N. Zalta ed.
    • An analogy involves what philosophers of language sometimes refer to as "default meaning." "[D]efault interpretation of the speaker's utterance is normally understood to mean salient meaning intended by the speaker, or presumed by the addressee to have been intended, and recovered (a) without the help of inference from the speaker's intentions or (b) without conscious inferential process altogether." Katarzyna M. Jaszczolt, Defaults in Semantics and Pragmatics, in THE STANFORD ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY (Edward N. Zalta ed., 2010), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2010/entries/ defaultssemantics- pragmatics. But the literature contains "no one, unique 'default model' of utterance interpretation."
    • (2010) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
    • Jaszczolt, K.M.1
  • 27
    • 34250095606 scopus 로고
    • Transparency and doubt: Understanding and interpretation in pragmatics and in law
    • See Marcelo Dascal & Jerzy Wroblewski, Transparency and Doubt: Understanding and Interpretation in Pragmatics and in Law, 7 LAW & PHIL. 203, 220 (1988) ("A legal text which formulates legal rules is always understood in the context of the legal system to which these rules belong. It is usually assumed that such system has - or should have - the properties of consistency, coherence and eventually completeness and lack of redundancy. Whenever the direct reading of a legal text does not conform to such assumed properties, one can say that the systemic context generates a doubt that prompts a search for a more appropriate interpretation.")
    • (1988) Law & Phil. , vol.7 , Issue.203 , pp. 220
    • Dascal, M.1    Wroblewski, J.2
  • 28
    • 84902461039 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Zuni Pub. Sch. Dist. No. v. Dep't of Educ., 550 U.S. 81, 116 (2007) (Scalia, J., dissenting) (derisively describing the majority opinion as adopting the approach of "that miraculous redeemer of lost causes, Church of the Holy Trinity")
    • (2007) Zuni Pub. Sch. Dist. No. V. Dep't of Educ., 550 U.S. , vol.81 , pp. 116
  • 30
    • 0039276206 scopus 로고
    • Section 1983 and federal protection of individual rights-will the statute remain alive or fade away?
    • For discussions of interpretive methodology focused specifically on § 1983, see generally Harry A. Blackmun, Section 1983 and Federal Protection of Individual Rights - Will the Statute Remain Alive or Fade Away?, 60 N.Y.U. L. REV. 1 (1985) (discussing the proper scope of federal protection of individual rights under § 1983)
    • (1985) N.Y.U. L. Rev. , vol.60 , Issue.1
    • Blackmun, H.A.1
  • 31
    • 0346975862 scopus 로고
    • Section 1983: Doctrinal foundations and an empirical study
    • Theodore Eisenberg, Section 1983: Doctrinal Foundations and an Empirical Study, 67 CORNELL L. REV. 482 (1982) (discussing the Court's contributions to current confusion in interpreting § 1983)
    • (1982) Cornell L. Rev. , vol.67 , Issue.482
    • Eisenberg, T.1
  • 32
    • 84928223681 scopus 로고
    • The source of law in civil rights actions: Some old light on section 1983
    • Seth F. Kreimer, The Source of Law in Civil Rights Actions: Some Old Light on Section 1983, 133 U. PA. L. REV. 601, 604-11 (1985) (discussing how federal courts have sketched out the details of § 1983).
    • (1985) U. PA. L. Rev. , vol.133 , Issue.601 , pp. 604-611
    • Kreimer, S.F.1
  • 34
    • 33646408410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Competing presumptions about statutory coherence
    • See, e.g., John F. Manning, Competing Presumptions About Statutory Coherence, 74 FORDHAM L. REV. 2009, 2029 (2006)
    • (2006) Fordham L. Rev. , vol.74 , Issue.2009 , pp. 2029
    • Manning, J.F.1
  • 36
    • 84893124436 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U.S.C. Gould Sch. of Law Legal Studies Research Paper Series, Paper No 12-13
    • The vocabulary may have some tendency to confuse. Although textualists say that they are concerned with semantic context, what they seek to ascertain is not limited to a legal text's "semantic meaning" insofar as the semantic content of an expression "is fully determined by the lexical meaning of the words used and the syntactical structure of the sentence." Andrei Marmor, Textualism in Context 6 (U.S.C. Gould Sch. of Law Legal Studies Research Paper Series, Paper No. 12-13, 2012), available at http://papers.ssrn. com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract-id=2112384. Rather, textualists seek to identify a legal text's pragmatic or contextual, rather than its purely semantic, meaning.
    • (2012) Textualism in Context , vol.6
    • Marmor, A.1
  • 37
    • 84877717812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why abstention is not illegitimate: An essay on the distinction between "legitimate" and "illegitimate" statutory interpretation and judicial lawmaking
    • See Richard H. Fallon, Jr., Why Abstention Is Not Illegitimate: An Essay on the Distinction Between "Legitimate" and "Illegitimate" Statutory Interpretation and Judicial Lawmaking, 107 NW. U. L. REV. 847, 878-79 (2013)
    • (2013) Nw. U. L. Rev. , vol.107 , Issue.847 , pp. 878-879
    • Fallon Jr., R.H.1
  • 38
    • 0039186388 scopus 로고
    • Hypothetical bargains: The normative structure of contract interpretation
    • cf. David Charny, Hypothetical Bargains: The Normative Structure of Contract Interpretation, 89 MICH. L. REV. 1815, 1830 (1991) ("Nothing about the necessary contexts that provide the basis for interpretation can tell one how far one should go in getting information about that context."). Issues arising from the need to frame the context within which statutory interpretation properly occurs may exemplify the more profound claim that in continuous relationships played out over time, such as those involving the government and its citizens or Congress and the courts, "constitutional law has no criteria for isolating transactions from . . . background relationship[s]" and that the "framing" of transactions or contexts for analysis is therefore frequently outcome determinative in legal controversies.
    • (1991) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.89 , Issue.1815 , pp. 1830
    • Charny, D.1
  • 39
    • 0348190012 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Framing transactions in constitutional law
    • Daryl J. Levinson, Framing Transactions in Constitutional Law, 111 YALE L.J. 1311, 1313 (2002).
    • (2002) Yale L.J. , vol.111 , Issue.1311 , pp. 1313
    • Levinson, D.J.1
  • 40
    • 33646399736 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The missing step of textualism
    • See Abner S. Greene, The Missing Step of Textualism, 74 FORDHAM L. REV. 1913, 1923 (2006) (characterizing the absence of a principled method for distinguishing relevant from irrelevant aspects of background knowledge as "the missing step of textualism")
    • (2006) Fordham L. Rev. , vol.74 , Issue.1913 , pp. 1923
    • Greene, A.S.1
  • 41
    • 0032283281 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Textualism and contextualism in administrative law
    • Jonathan R. Siegel, Textualism and Contextualism in Administrative Law, 78 B.U. L. REV. 1023, 1029-32 (1998) (emphasizing the importance of the question of what constitutes relevant context for administrative law adjudication and calling attention to background principles).
    • (1998) B.U. L. Rev. , vol.78 , Issue.1023 , pp. 1029-1032
    • Siegel, J.R.1
  • 43
    • 0041453152 scopus 로고
    • The role of original intent in statutory construction
    • See, e.g., Frank H. Easterbrook, The Role of Original Intent in Statutory Construction, 11 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 59, 65 (1988) ("We should look at the statutory structure and hear the words as they would sound in the mind of a skilled, objectively reasonable user of words.")
    • (1988) Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol'y , vol.11 , Issue.59 , pp. 65
    • Easterbrook, F.H.1
  • 44
    • 84902439669 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Representation and interpretation
    • DONALD DAVIDSON, Representation and Interpretation, in PROBLEMS OF RATIONALITY 87, 97 (2004).
    • (2004) Problems of Rationality , vol.87 , pp. 97
    • Donald, D.1
  • 45
    • 77954519040 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The states as laboratories of statutory interpretation: Methodological consensus and the new modified textualism
    • Cf. Abbe R. Gluck, The States As Laboratories of Statutory Interpretation: Methodological Consensus and the New Modified Textualism, 119 YALE L.J. 1750, 1768 (2010) (conceding that "one cannot prove that methodology dictates outcomes in cases" but emphasizing that "it surely affects opinion writing").
    • (2010) Yale L.J. , vol.119 , Issue.1750 , pp. 1768
    • Gluck, A.R.1
  • 46
    • 23844499443 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Canons of construction and the elusive quest for neutral reasoning
    • But cf. James J. Brudney & Corey Ditslear, Canons of Construction and the Elusive Quest for Neutral Reasoning, 58 VAND. L. REV. 1, 58-60 (2005) (concluding that Justices' reliance on either substantive or language canons of construction is driven by ideology, not methodology)
    • (2005) Vand. L. Rev. , vol.58 , Issue.1 , pp. 58-60
    • Brudney, J.J.1    Ditslear, C.2
  • 47
    • 34547457992 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The significance of statutory interpretive methodologies
    • Frank B. Cross, The Significance of Statutory Interpretive Methodologies, 82 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 1971, 1991-95 (2007) (finding that convergence upon textualist and purposivist methodologies does not produce consensus among the Justices with respect to results).
    • (2007) Notre Dame L. Rev. , vol.82 , Issue.1971 , pp. 1991-1995
    • Cross, F.B.1
  • 48
    • 84884122041 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I also make no effort to compare the relative merits of either textualism or purposivism with theories that call for statutory interpreters to play roles other than that of a faithful agent of the enacting legislature. In the domain of constitutional interpretation, I have elsewhere defended an approach in which precedent, among other factors, sometimes calls for interpretive conclusions other than those that a faithful agent of the framers and ratifiers of relevant constitutional provisions might have reached. See RICHARD H. FALLON, JR., IMPLEMENTING THE CONSTITUTION 111-26 (2001)
    • (2001) Implementing the Constitution , pp. 111-126
    • Fallon Jr., R.H.1
  • 49
    • 77950512613 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constitutional precedent viewed through the lens of hartian positivist jurisprudence
    • Richard H. Fallon, Jr., Constitutional Precedent Viewed Through the Lens of Hartian Positivist Jurisprudence, 86 N.C. L. REV. 1107, 1116 (2008) (arguing that overturning some settled but mistaken precedents "would exceed [the Court's] lawful authority").
    • (2008) N.C. L. Rev. , vol.86 , Issue.1107 , pp. 1116
    • Fallon Jr., R.H.1
  • 51
    • 0040871052 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Radical interpretation
    • 2d ed.
    • See, e.g., DONALD DAVIDSON, Radical Interpretation, in INQUIRIES INTO TRUTH AND INTERPRETATION 125, 125 (2d ed. 2001) [hereinafter DAVIDSON, Radical Interpretation] ("All understanding of the speech of another involves radical interpretation.")
    • (2001) Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation , vol.125 , pp. 125
    • Davidson, D.1
  • 52
    • 0040276801 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Belief and the basis of meaning
    • supra, at 141
    • DONALD DAVIDSON, Belief and the Basis of Meaning, in INQUIRIES INTO TRUTH AND INTERPRETATION, supra, at 141, 141 ("We interpret a bit of linguistic behaviour when we say what a speaker's words mean on an occasion of use.").
    • Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation , pp. 141
    • Davidson, D.1
  • 53
    • 0041914783 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See DENNIS PATTERSON, LAW AND TRUTH 86-88 (1996) (criticizing Dworkin as making "far too much of the work of interpretation").
    • (1996) Law and Truth , pp. 86-88
    • Patterson, D.1
  • 55
    • 0000293049 scopus 로고
    • Freedom and constraint in adjudication: A critical phenomenology
    • As Duncan Kennedy emphasizes, there may be occasions on which a sense of uncertainty or puzzlement emerges from a prior, instrumentally or ideologically motivated effort to discover vagueness or ambiguity that a first-blush meaning would not otherwise have displayed. See Duncan Kennedy, Freedom and Constraint in Adjudication: A Critical Phenomenology, 36 J. LEGAL EDUC. 518, 547-48 (1986). It is, for example, a familiar role of lawyers to attempt to generate doubts where judges would not otherwise have felt them. Professor Kennedy points out that judges, spurred by ideological commitment, might assume a similar role.
    • (1986) J. Legal Educ. , vol.36 , Issue.518 , pp. 547-548
    • Kennedy, D.1
  • 56
    • 84876983531 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ambiguity and vagueness in legal interpretation
    • As so defined, ambiguity is different from, and does not subsume all cases of, vagueness. See Ralf Poscher, Ambiguity and Vagueness in Legal Interpretation, in THE OXFORD HANDBOOK OF LANGUAGE AND LAW 128, 129 (Peter M. Tiersma & Lawrence M. Solan eds., 2012) ("Ambiguous expressions have multiple meanings, as in the case of the homonym 'bank' which can mean both 'river bank' and 'commercial bank.' . . . In contrast, an expression is vague if it has borderline cases.")
    • The Oxford Handbook of Language and Law , vol.128 , pp. 129
    • Poscher, R.1
  • 57
    • 84860461714 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The interpretation-construction distinction
    • Lawrence B. Solum, The Interpretation-Construction Distinction, 27 CONST. COMMENT. 95, 97-98 (2010) ("In the technical sense, ambiguity refers to the multiplicity of sense: a term is ambiguous if it has more than one sense. . . . The technical sense of vagueness refers to the existence of borderline cases: a term is vague if there are cases where the term might or might not apply.").
    • (2010) Const. Comment. , vol.27 , Issue.95 , pp. 97-98
    • Solum, L.B.1
  • 58
    • 84902514550 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See TIMOTHY A.O. ENDICOTT, VAGUENESS IN LAW 9 (2000) (describing a law as "vague if the boundaries of the area affected by [it] are unclear")
    • (2000) Endicott, Vagueness in Law , vol.9
    • Timothy, A.O.1
  • 59
    • 84902514551 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3d Ed.
    • see also H.L.A. HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW 126 (3d ed. 2012) ("There will indeed be plain cases . . . to which general expressions are clearly applicable . . . but there will also be cases where it is not clear whether they apply or not.").
    • (2012) The Concept of Law , vol.126
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 60
    • 0000580092 scopus 로고
    • Positivism and the separation of law and morals
    • This much-discussed example apparently originated with H.L.A. Hart, Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals, 71 HARV. L. REV. 593, 607 (1958).
    • (1958) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.71 , pp. 607
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 65
    • 34250124588 scopus 로고
    • The principle of charity
    • Christopher Gauker, The Principle of Charity, 69 SYNTHESE 1, 1 (1986).
    • (1986) Synthese , vol.69 , Issue.1 , pp. 1
    • Gauker, C.1
  • 67
    • 0003725028 scopus 로고
    • In a particularly well-known example, H.P. Grice identifies a number of normative "maxims" that are conventionally at work in human conversation and that function to facilitate cooperation in the communication of thought and information, including "[m]ake your contribution as informative as is required," "[t]ry to make your contribution one that is true," "[b]e relevant," and "[a]void obscurity of expression." PAUL GRICE, STUDIES IN THE WAY OF WORDS 26-28 (1989). According to Grice, we normally trust others to observe these maxims and feel entitled to draw inferences about the meaning of their utterances in reliance on them.
    • (1989) Studies in the Way of Words , pp. 26-28
    • Grice, P.1
  • 68
    • 84930559625 scopus 로고
    • Sovereignty in silence
    • n.52
    • For the argument that Grice's theory functions better as a theory of communication than as a theory of meaning, see Heidi M. Hurd, Sovereignty in Silence, 99 YALE L.J. 945, 965 & n.52 (1990) ("Contrary to what Grice contended, we must look to the conventions which govern the meaning of sentences to determine what a speaker means rather than look to what the speaker means to determine what his or her sentences mean.").
    • (1990) Yale L.J. , vol.99 , Issue.945 , pp. 965
    • Hurd, H.M.1
  • 69
    • 18444417148 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What is textualism?
    • Caleb Nelson, What is Textualism?, 91 VA. L. REV. 347, 353-57 (2005) (discussing textualists' search for statutes' "objectified intent").
    • (2005) VA. L. Rev. , vol.91 , Issue.347 , pp. 353-357
    • Nelson, C.1
  • 70
    • 52549131287 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Charity, interpretation fallacy
    • Jonathan E. Adler, Charity, Interpretation, Fallacy, 29 PHIL. & RHETORIC 329, 330 (1996). Adler not only ascribes this view to Davidson but also ultimately defends it.
    • (1996) Phil. & Rhetoric , vol.29 , Issue.329 , pp. 330
    • Adler, J.E.1
  • 72
    • 84902514547 scopus 로고
    • citing United States v. Palmer, 16 U.S. (3 Wheat.) 610, 631 (1818) (invoking interpretive presumption that statutes do not apply extraterritorially)
    • (1818) United States v Palmer 16 US (3 Wheat) , vol.610 , pp. 631
  • 74
    • 84902514539 scopus 로고
    • quoting Blatchford v. Native Vill. of Noatak, 501 U.S. 775, 786 (1991) (stating that, as a result of "the important role played by the Eleventh Amendment and the broader principles that it reflects," a congressional intent to abrogate state sovereign immunity "must be obvious from 'a clear legislative statement'")
    • (1991) Blatchford V. Native Vill. of Noatak, 501 U.S. , vol.775 , pp. 786
  • 76
    • 84902478608 scopus 로고
    • quoting Atascadero State Hosp. v. Scanlon, 473 U. S. 234, 242 (1985) (relying on a presumption that "if Congress intends to alter the usual constitutional balance between the States and the Federal Government, it must make its intention to do so unmistakably clear in the language of the statute" in concluding that a federal statute barring age discrimination by employers, including States, did not apply to state judges (internal quotation marks omitted)).
    • (1985) Atascadero State Hosp. V. Scanlon, 473 U. S. , vol.234 , pp. 242
  • 77
    • 84902460602 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Webster v. Doe, 486 U.S. 592, 603 (1988) (demanding a "heightened showing" of congressional intent to preclude judicial review of constitutional claims in light of the "serious constitutional question" that a denial of review would raise).
    • (1988) Webster V. Doe, 486 U.S. , vol.592 , pp. 603
  • 78
    • 84902514540 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., United Steelworkers of Am. v. Weber, 443 U.S. 193, 200-08 (1979) (holding that a provision of Title VII making racial discrimination unlawful did not forbid private affirmative action plans because the "background of the legislative history of Title VII and the historical context from which the Act arose" revealed an intent to benefit historically disadvantaged groups). 85 131 S. Ct. 1910 (2011).
    • (1979) United Steelworkers of Am. V. Weber, 443 U.S. , vol.193 , pp. 200-208
  • 79
    • 0040283174 scopus 로고
    • From the big sleep to the big heat: The revival of theory in statutory interpretation
    • On the awakening of interest in theories of statutory interpretation, see Philip P. Frickey, From the Big Sleep to the Big Heat: The Revival of Theory in Statutory Interpretation, 77 MINN. L. REV. 241, 248-49 (1992).
    • (1992) Minn. L. Rev. , vol.77 , Issue.241 , pp. 248-249
    • Frickey, P.P.1
  • 80
    • 0039292674 scopus 로고
    • Some reflections on the reading of statutes
    • Felix Frankfurter, Some Reflections on the Reading of Statutes, 47 COLUM. L. REV. 527, 539 (1947) (arguing that "the judge must seek and effectuate" a statute's "aim" or "policy").
    • (1947) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.47 , Issue.527 , pp. 539
    • Frankfurter, F.1
  • 81
    • 74049089308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The inexorable radicalization of textualism
    • See Jonathan R. Siegel, The Inexorable Radicalization of Textualism, 158 U. PA. L. REV. 117, 121 (2009) (arguing that a "pure" version of textualism would allow "absurd" results).
    • (2009) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.158 , Issue.117 , pp. 121
    • Siegel, J.R.1
  • 82
    • 84902476729 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Zuni Pub. Sch. Dist. No. 89 v. Dep't of Educ., 550 U.S. 81, 106 (2007) (Stevens, J., concurring) ("Analysis of legislative history is . . . a traditional tool of statutory construction. There is no reason why we must confine ourselves to, or begin our analysis with, the statutory text if other tools of statutory construction provide better evidence of congressional intent with respect to the precise point at issue." (footnote omitted))
    • (2007) Zuni Pub. Sch. Dist. No 89 V. Dep't of Educ., 550 U.S. 81 , pp. 106
    • Stevens, J.1
  • 83
    • 84902514541 scopus 로고
    • Wis. Pub. Intervenor v. Mortier, 501 U.S. 597, 611 n.4 (1991) ("As for the propriety of using legislative history[,] . . . common sense suggests that inquiry benefits from reviewing additional information rather than ignoring it. As Chief Justice Marshall put it, '[w]here the mind labours to discover the design of the legislature, it seizes every thing from which aid can be derived.'" (alteration in original)
    • (1991) Wis. Pub. Intervenor V. Mortier, 501 U.S. , vol.597 , Issue.4 , pp. 611
  • 85
    • 0040876203 scopus 로고
    • On the uses of legislative history in interpreting statutes
    • Stephen Breyer, On the Uses of Legislative History in Interpreting Statutes, 65 S. CAL. L. REV. 845, 848 (1992) (arguing that "[l]egislative history helps a court understand the context and purpose of a statute").
    • (1992) S. Cal. L. Rev. , vol.65 , Issue.845 , pp. 848
    • Breyer, S.1
  • 86
    • 84902514543 scopus 로고
    • N.Y.
    • See 22 N.E. 188, 189-90 (N.Y. 1889).
    • (1889) N.E. , vol.22 , Issue.188 , pp. 189-190
  • 87
    • 84872234182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The reasonable person
    • See, e.g., Alan D. Miller & Ronen Perry, The Reasonable Person, 87 N.Y.U. L. REV. 323, 391 (2012) (maintaining that "a positive definition of reasonableness is a logical impossibility" because "no positive definition can satisfy" all of the axioms that a positive definition would need to embrace).
    • (2012) N.Y.U. L. Rev. , vol.87 , Issue.323 , pp. 391
    • Miller, A.D.1    Perry, R.2
  • 88
    • 84902514544 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., JOHN RAWLS, POLITICAL LIBERALISM 49 n.1 (1993) ("[K]nowing that people are rational we do not know the ends they will pursue, only that they will pursue them intelligently. Knowing that people are reasonable where others are concerned, we know that they are willing to govern their conduct by a principle from which they and others can reason in common; and reasonable people take into account the consequences of their actions on others' well-being."
    • (1993) Political Liberalism , vol.49 , Issue.1
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 89
    • 0002289978 scopus 로고
    • The rational versus the reasonable
    • citing W.M. Sibley, The Rational Versus the Reasonable, 62 PHIL. REV. 554, 560 (1953))
    • (1953) Phil. Rev. , vol.62 , Issue.554 , pp. 560
    • Sibley, W.M.1
  • 90
    • 0003867020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • T.M. SCANLON, WHAT WE OWE TO EACH OTHER 191-92 (1998) (suggesting that rationality entails a simple capacity for means-ends analysis while reasonableness involves "tak[ing] others' interests into account".
    • (1998) What We Owe to Each Other , pp. 191-192
    • Scanlon, T.M.1
  • 91
    • 0004015503 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Issues arising from reasonable disagreement are endemic both to law, see, e.g., JEREMY WALDRON, LAW AND DISAGREEMENT 4-6 (1999) ("Law . . . represents the aspiration to justice of a community . . . not of those who think similarly, but of those who think differently, about matters of common concern."
    • (1999) Law and Disagreement , pp. 4-6
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 92
    • 84902514545 scopus 로고
    • 467 U.S. 837, 843-44
    • 467 U.S. 837, 843-44 (1984).
    • (1984)
  • 93
    • 0036856476 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A judge on judging: The role of a supreme court in a democracy
    • Aharon Barak, A Judge on Judging: The Role of a Supreme Court in a Democracy, 116 HARV. L. REV. 19, 75 (2002).
    • (2002) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.116 , Issue.19 , pp. 75
    • Barak, A.1
  • 94
    • 62749138931 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intention is all there is: A critical analysis of aharon barak's purposive interpretation in law
    • See Stanley Fish, Intention Is All There Is: A Critical Analysis of Aharon Barak's Purposive Interpretation in Law, 29 CARDOZO L. REV. 1109, 1135-36 (2008).
    • (2008) Cardozo L. Rev. , vol.29 , Issue.1109 , pp. 1135-1136
    • Fish, S.1
  • 95
    • 0346975726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The case of the speluncean explorers: Revisited
    • Frank H. Easterbrook, The Case of the Speluncean Explorers: Revisited, 112 HARV. L. REV. 1876, 1913-14 (1997).
    • (1997) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.112 , Issue.1876 , pp. 1913-1914
    • Easterbrook, F.H.1
  • 96
    • 84902514533 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But cf. United States v. Oakland Cannabis Buyers' Coop., 532 U.S. 483, 490 (2001) (describing as "an open question whether federal courts ever have authority to recognize a necessity defense not provided by statute").
    • (2001) United States v Oakland Cannabis Buyers' Coop 532 US , vol.483 , pp. 490
  • 102
    • 84902514526 scopus 로고
    • See Nat'l Private Truck Council, Inc. v. Okla. Tax Comm'n, 515 U.S. 582, 589 (1995) ("[W]e must interpret § 1983 in light of the strong background principle against federal interference with state taxation."). Justice Scalia joined Justice Thomas's opinion for the Court.
    • (1995) Nat'l Private Truck Council, Inc. V. Okla. Tax comm'N, 515 U.S. , vol.582 , pp. 589
  • 103
    • 84902514527 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Burns v. Reed, 500 U.S. 478, 497 (1991) (Scalia, J., concurring in the judgment in part and dissenting in part). 122 501 U.S. 452, 473 (1991).
    • (1991) Burns V. Reed, 500 U.S. , vol.478 , Issue.497
  • 106
    • 0040477593 scopus 로고
    • The new textualism
    • William N. Eskridge, Jr., The New Textualism, 37 UCLA L. REV. 621, 623 (1990) ("The new textualism posits that once the Court has ascertained a statute's plain meaning, consideration of legislative history becomes irrelevant. Legislative history should not even be consulted to confirm the apparent meaning of a statutory text.")
    • (1990) Ucla L. Rev. , vol.37 , Issue.621 , pp. 623
    • Eskridge Jr., W.N.1
  • 107
    • 84902514532 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Green v. Bock Laundry Mach. Co., 490 U.S. 504, 527 (1989) (Scalia, J., concurring in the judgment) (relying on legislative history "to verify that what seems to us an unthinkable disposition . . . was indeed unthought of")
    • (1989) Green V. Bock Laundry Mach. Co., 490 U.S. , vol.504 , pp. 527
  • 108
    • 84879766337 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The new textualism and normative canons
    • But see William N. Eskridge, Jr., The New Textualism and Normative Canons, 113 COLUM. L. REV. 531, 561 (2013)
    • (2013) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.113 , Issue.531 , pp. 561
    • Eskridge Jr., W.N.1
  • 110
    • 84923037815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. JOSEPH RAZ, BETWEEN AUTHORITY AND INTERPRETATION 118-20 (2009) (asserting the dependence of theories of legal interpretation on moral theory and denying the possibility of "a general theory of legal interpretation" or an "operational" moral theory that would prescribe correct conclusions to someone who did not already have good moral judgment).
    • (2009) Between Authority and Interpretation , pp. 118-120
    • Raz, J.1
  • 111
    • 84902514531 scopus 로고
    • In order to determine how precepts and theories apply to particular cases, we ordinarily count not on proliferating layers of interpretive rules but, instead, on the availability of a foundational human capacity such as that of "understanding" with respect to utterances that require no clarification, see ANDREI MARMOR, INTERPRETATION AND LEGAL THEORY 22 (1992)
    • (1992) Interpretation and Legal Theory , vol.22
    • Marmor, A.1
  • 112
    • 81355135218 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Neutral principles, motivated cognition and some problems for constitutional law
    • See Dan M. Kahan, Neutral Principles, Motivated Cognition, and Some Problems for Constitutional Law, 125 HARV. L. REV. 1, 19 (2011) (defining "motivated reasoning" as "the unconscious tendency of individuals to process information in a manner that suits some end or goal extrinsic to the formation of accurate beliefs"). Modern psychological research has confirmed what common sense has always suggested: human beings have a powerful psychological propensity to determine facts and appraise arguments in ways that accord with their preexisting, ideologically inflected beliefs and preferences.
    • (2011) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.125 , Issue.1 , pp. 19
    • Kahan, D.M.1
  • 114
    • 84902514530 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Kiobel v. Royal Dutch Petroleum Co., 133 S. Ct. 1659, 1664 (2013) (noting that the canon presuming that statutes do not apply extraterritorially "serves to protect against unintended clashes between our laws and those of other nations which could result in international discord"
    • (2013) Kiobel V. Royal Dutch Petroleum Co., 133 S. Ct. , vol.1659 , Issue.1664
  • 117
    • 84876232707 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Statutory interpretation from the inside-an empirical study of congressional drafting, delegation, and the canons: Part i
    • See Abbe R. Gluck & Lisa Shultz Bressman, Statutory Interpretation from the Inside - An Empirical Study of Congressional Drafting, Delegation, and the Canons: Part I, 65 STAN. L. REV. 901, 926-64 (2013).
    • (2013) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.65 , Issue.901 , pp. 926-964
    • Gluck, A.R.1    Bressman, L.S.2
  • 118
    • 0346170897 scopus 로고
    • The principle of charity and the problem of irrationality (translation and the problem of irrationality)
    • Cf. David K. Henderson, The Principle of Charity and the Problem of Irrationality (Translation and the Problem of Irrationality), 73 SYNTHESE 225, 226-27 (1987) (arguing that the principle of charity disfavors but should not preclude some ascriptions of irrationality). 164 515 U.S. 687, 690 (1995).
    • (1987) Synthese , vol.73 , Issue.225 , pp. 226-227
    • Henderson, D.K.1
  • 122
    • 84902513775 scopus 로고
    • Cf. Michael H. v. Gerald D., 491 U.S. 110, 127 n.6 (1989) (plurality opinion of Scalia, J.) (maintaining that the appropriate "level of generality" at which to identify a constitutionally pertinent tradition is "the most specific level at which a relevant tradition protecting, or denying protection to, the asserted right can be identified").
    • (1989) Michael H. V. Gerald D., 491 U.S. , vol.110 , Issue.6 , pp. 127
  • 123
    • 46649085906 scopus 로고
    • Levels of generality in the definition of rights
    • For discussion of the pertinence of levels of generality and the difficulties in establishing them without making value judgments, see generally Laurence H. Tribe & Michael C. Dorf, Levels of Generality in the Definition of Rights, 57 U. CHI. L. REV. 1057 (1990).
    • (1990) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.57 , pp. 1057
    • Tribe, L.H.1    Dorf, M.C.2
  • 124
    • 84878347297 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Defense of big waiver
    • 174 535 US, 137, 2002
    • Such issues arise nearly ubiquitously in the modern administrative state, in which new legislation routinely threatens to conflict with existing statutory regulation touching the same domain. See David J. Barron & Todd D. Rakoff, In Defense of Big Waiver, 113 COLUM. L. REV. 265, 302-03 (2013). 174 535 U.S. 137 (2002).
    • (2013) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.113 , Issue.265 , pp. 302-303
    • Barron, D.J.1    Rakoff, T.D.2
  • 127
    • 84902514518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., City of Rancho Palos Verdes v. Abrams, 544 U.S. 113, 121 (2005) ("The provision of an express, private means of redress in the statute itself is ordinarily an indication that Congress did not intend to leave open a more expansive remedy under § 1983.")
    • (2005) City of Rancho Palos Verdes V. Abrams 544 U.S. , vol.113 , Issue.121
  • 128
    • 84902514519 scopus 로고
    • Middlesex Cnty. Sewerage Auth. v. Nat'l Sea Clammers Ass'n, 453 U.S. 1, 20 (1981) ("When the remedial devices provided in a particular Act are sufficiently comprehensive, they may suffice to demonstrate congressional intent to preclude the remedy of suits under § 1983.").
    • (1981) Middlesex Cnty. Sewerage Auth. V. Nat'l Sea Clammers ass'N, 453 U.S. , vol.1 , Issue.20
  • 129
    • 41649114050 scopus 로고
    • Sunstein interpreting statutes in the regulatory state
    • Although Cass R. Sunstein, Interpreting Statutes in the Regulatory State, 103 HARV. L. REV. 405, 421-22 (1989)
    • (1989) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.103 , Issue.405 , pp. 421-422
    • Although, C.R.1
  • 132
    • 84902514521 scopus 로고
    • ("Congress did not authorize injunctive or declaratory relief under § 1983 in state tax cases . . . ."), and Patsy v. Bd. of Regents, 457 U.S. 496, 507 (1982) ("[T]he 1871 Congress did not intend that an individual be compelled in every case to exhaust state administrative remedies before filing an action under § 1 of the Civil Rights Act."). In any event, a textualist who believed that § 1983 could be appropriately characterized as a "common law statute," subject to special interpretive principles, would need to explain that conclusion by reference to a very broad, and contestable, specification of the statute's interpretive context. 181 515 U.S. 582, 588 (1995).
    • (1982) Patsy V. Bd. of Regents, 457 U.S. , vol.496 , pp. 507
  • 133
    • 84902457625 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Heck v. Humphrey, 512 U.S. 477, 483-84 (1994) (Scalia, J.) ("[T]o determine whether there is any bar to [a § 1983] suit, we look first to the common law of torts.").
    • (1994) Heck V. Humphrey, 512 U.S. , vol.477 , pp. 483-484
  • 134
    • 84902514522 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Buckley v. Fitzsimmons, 509 U.S. 259, 279-80 (1993) (Scalia, J., concurring) (citing "a well-established common-law privilege [that existed] in 1871, when § 1983 was enacted")
    • (1993) Buckley V. Fitzsimmons, 509 U.S. , vol.259 , pp. 279-280
    • Scalia, J.1
  • 135
    • 84902514523 scopus 로고
    • Burns v. Reed, 500 U.S. 478, 497-98 (1991) (Scalia, J., concurring in the judgment in part and dissenting in part) (arguing that "the common-law practice, which governs whether absolute immunity exists under § 1983, is that this prosecutorial action would have enjoyed only qualified immunity").
    • (1991) Burns V. Reed, 500 U.S. , vol.478 , pp. 497-498
    • Scalia, J.1
  • 136
    • 84902514516 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Heck, 512 U.S. at 483-84 (holding that § 1983 was unavailable for bringing a plaintiff's wrongful imprisonment claim because common law malicious prosecution actions required "termination of the prior criminal proceeding in favor of the accused").
    • (1983) Heck, 512 U.S. , pp. 483-484
  • 137
    • 84902478903 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Pierson v. Ray, 386 U.S. 547, 554-55 (1967) ("The legislative record [of § 1983] gives no clear indication that Congress meant to abolish wholesale all common-law immunities."). In Rehberg v. Paulk, the Court noted that while its "approach is tied to the common law's identification of the functions that merit the protection of absolute immunity, the Court's precedents have not mechanically duplicated the precise scope of the absolute immunity that the common law provided to protect those functions," but instead have innovated where necessary to accommodate modern policy concerns.
    • (1967) Pierson V. Ray 386 U.S. 547 554-55
  • 138
    • 84902514517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • S. Ct. 1497, 1503-04 (2012).
    • (2012) S. Ct. , vol.1497 , pp. 1503-1504
  • 139
    • 84902492418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Due in part to stare decisis, Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas have acquiesced in an approach that strays from the common law in certain instances. See, e.g., Kalina v. Fletcher, 522 U.S. 118, 132-35 (1997) (Scalia, J., concurring)
    • (1997) Kalina V. Fletcher, 522 U.S. , vol.118 , pp. 132-135
    • Scalia, J.1
  • 141
    • 84902514513 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Younger v. Harris, 401 U.S. 37, 54 (1971) (holding that "the possible unconstitutionality of a statute 'on its face' does not in itself justify an injunction against good-faith attempts to enforce it" and declining to consider whether any Act of Congress authorizes such an injunction).
    • (1971) Younger V. Harris, 401 U.S. , vol.37 , pp. 54
  • 142
    • 46849086031 scopus 로고
    • Abstention, separation of powers, and the limits of the judicial function
    • But see Martin H. Redish, Abstention, Separation of Powers, and the Limits of the Judicial Function, 94 YALE L.J. 71, 84 (1984) ("The language of the relevant statutes leaves no room for judicial limitation or modification . . . . Moreover, the very purpose of [the Reconstruction] legislation [often involved in abstention cases] was to interpose the federal judiciary between the state and individual, largely because of concern about the functioning of state judiciaries."). 187 517 U.S. 706, 717 (1996).
    • (1984) Yale L.J. , vol.94 , Issue.71 , pp. 84
    • Redish, M.H.1
  • 143
    • 84902514514 scopus 로고
    • Either the ultimate example of interpretive purposivism or its limiting case came in Harlow v. Fitzgerald, 457 U.S. 800 (1982), in which the Court self-consciously reformulated the standard for defining the qualified immunity that most officials enjoy.
    • (1982) Harlow V. Fitzgerald, 457 U.S. , vol.800
  • 144
    • 0041141473 scopus 로고
    • Jurisdiction and discretion
    • 194 143 US 457 1892
    • As David Shapiro has put it, the Court reads jurisdiction-conferring statutes against the background of "experience and tradition" - which might be redescribed as either a semantic or a policy context - in light of which it has felt free to identify circumstances in which statutes should be "read as an authorization to the court to entertain an action but not as an inexorable command" to do so. David L. Shapiro, Jurisdiction and Discretion, 60 N.Y.U. L. REV. 543, 574-75 (1985). 194 143 U.S. 457 (1892).
    • (1985) N.Y.U. L. Rev. , vol.60 , Issue.543 , pp. 574-575
    • Shapiro, D.L.1
  • 145
    • 0042956235 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Textualism, the unknown ideal?
    • See William N. Eskridge, Jr., Textualism, The Unknown Ideal?, 96 MICH. L. REV. 1509, 1518 (1998)
    • (1998) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.96 , Issue.1509 , pp. 1518
    • Eskridge Jr., W.N.1
  • 146
    • 0003790681 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • reviewing ANTONIN SCALIA, A MATTER OF INTERPRETATION: FEDERAL COURTS AND THE LAW (1997) (asserting that in its historical context the Alien Contract Labor Act's reference to "labor or service" would have been understood to mean "physical and helper work").
    • (1997) A Matter of Interpretation: Federal Courts and the Law
    • Scalia, A.1
  • 147
    • 84902514515 scopus 로고
    • 5th Cir.
    • See 132 S. Ct. 694, 705 & n.2, 706 (2012). In the first of the modern cases finding a ministerial exception to Title VII of the 1964 Civil Rights Act, the Fifth Circuit relied on the canon counseling construction of statutes to avoid "a serious doubt of constitutionality" in holding that "Congress did not intend, through the nonspecific wording of the applicable provisions of Title VII, to regulate the employment relationship between church and minister." McClure v. Salvation Army, 460 F.2d 553, 560-61 (5th Cir. 1972).
    • (1972) McClure V. Salvation Army, 460 F.2d , vol.553 , pp. 560-561
  • 148
    • 44649102899 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note, the ministerial exception to title vii: The case for a deferential primary duties test
    • Following McClure, eight other circuit courts explicitly adopted a ministerial exception, see Note, The Ministerial Exception to Title VII: The Case for a Deferential Primary Duties Test, 121 HARV. L. REV. 1776, 1778 & n.19 (2008), which they also extended to statutes such as the Age Discrimination in Employment Act (ADEA), the Americans with Disabilities Act, and state common law claims against religious employers
    • (2008) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.121 , Issue.19 , pp. 1776-1778
  • 149
    • 84902458199 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6th Cir.
    • see Hollins v. Methodist Healthcare, Inc., 474 F.3d 223, 225 (6th Cir. 2007) (collecting cases). But the Fourth Circuit broke with McClure by concluding that the statutory language would not support a construction that exempted suits by ministers from its coverage and by putting its decision squarely on constitutional grounds.
    • (2007) Hollins V. Methodist Healthcare, Inc., 474 F.3d , vol.223 , pp. 225
  • 151
    • 84877935158 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Comment protecting preachers from prejudice: Methods for improving analysis of the ministerial exception to title VII
    • Thereafter, other circuits seem generally to have followed Rayburn in characterizing their conclusions as constitutionally dictated, see Benton C. Martin, Comment, Protecting Preachers from Prejudice: Methods for Improving Analysis of the Ministerial Exception to Title VII, 59 EMORY L.J. 1297, 1304-06 (2010)
    • (2010) Emory L.J. , vol.59 , Issue.1297 , pp. 1304-1306
    • Martin, B.C.1
  • 153
    • 84902467202 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3d Cir.
    • See also Petruska v. Gannon Univ., 462 F.3d 294, 303 n.4 (3d Cir. 2006) ("Whereas some courts have derived the ministerial exception from the doctrine of constitutional avoidance, others have determined that, under its plain language, Title VII applies to ministerial employment decisions, but they have nevertheless concluded that such an application is unconstitutional." (citations omitted)).
    • (2006) Petruska V. Gannon Univ. 462 F.3d 294 303 N.4
  • 154
    • 84902514508 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In establishing that "the Courts of Appeals have uniformly recognized the existence of a 'ministerial exception' . . . that precludes application of [antidiscrimination] legislation to claims concerning the employment relationship between a religious institution and its ministers," Hosanna-Tabor, 132 S. Ct. at 705, the Supreme Court did not distinguish among lower court cases that had based the exception on grounds of statutory interpretation pursuant to the "avoidance canon" and those that had held statutes unconstitutional insofar as they failed to provide a ministerial exemption. Nor did the Court wholly resolve the ambiguity in its own analysis. It began by stating "[w]e agree there is . . . a ministerial exception."
    • Hosanna-Tabor, 132 S. Ct. , pp. 705
  • 156
    • 44349102361 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The continuum of difference: Supreme court treatment of agency statutory interpretations from chevron to hamdan
    • William N. Eskridge, Jr. & Lauren E. Baer, The Continuum of Difference: Supreme Court Treatment of Agency Statutory Interpretations from Chevron to Hamdan, 96 GEO. L.J. 1083 (2008).
    • (2008) Geo. L.J. , vol.96 , pp. 1083
    • Eskridge Jr., W.N.1    Baer, L.E.2
  • 157
    • 84902514509 scopus 로고
    • Cf. Rose v. Rose, 481 U.S. 619, 644 (1987) (Scalia, J., concurring in part and concurring in the judgment) (criticizing the Court for assuming "a broad power to limit clear text on the basis of apparent congressional purpose")
    • (1987) Rose V. Rose, 481 U.S. , vol.619 , pp. 644
    • Scalia, J.1
  • 158
    • 0036000776 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The "conservative" paths of the rehnquist court's federalism decisions
    • Cf. Richard H. Fallon, Jr., The "Conservative" Paths of the Rehnquist Court's Federalism Decisions, 69 U. CHI. L. REV. 429, 462 (2002) (maintaining that the conservatism of the majority Justices of the Rehnquist Court sometimes trumped their commitment to judicial federalism in statutory preemption cases).
    • (2002) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.69 , Issue.429 , pp. 462
    • Fallon Jr., R.H.1
  • 159
    • 84885828212 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Preemption and textualism
    • For example, some commentators have maintained that these two Justices have frequently joined their colleagues in failing to abide by textualist commitments in many statutory preemption cases, see, e.g., Daniel J. Meltzer, Preemption and Textualism, 112 MICH. L. REV. 1, 22 (2013), at least prior to Justice Thomas's apparently nearly total renunciation of implied preemption analysis in Wyeth v. Levine, 555 U.S. 555, 604 (2009) (Thomas, J., concurring in the judgment) ("I can no longer assent to a doctrine that pre-empts state laws merely because they stand as an obstacle to . . . the full purposes and objectives of federal law . . . ." (internal quotation marks and citations omitted)).
    • (2013) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.112 , Issue.1 , pp. 22
    • Meltzer, D.J.1
  • 160
    • 84922432681 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Textualism and obstacle preemption
    • 442
    • Cf. John David Ohlendorf, Textualism and Obstacle Preemption, 47 GA. L. REV. 369, 427-38, 442 (2013) (identifying implicit textualist assumptions about meaning in context that permit "a rapprochement between textualism and obstacle preemption").
    • (2013) Ga. L. Rev. , vol.47 , Issue.369 , pp. 427-438
    • Ohlendorf, J.D.1
  • 161
    • 84885760156 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Against freewheeling, extratextual obstacle preemption: Is justice clarence thomas the lone principled federalist?
    • For the argument that Justice Thomas's stance in implied preemption cases fits uneasily with his readiness to employ broadly purposive analysis in interpreting preemption and savings clauses, see Catherine M. Sharkey, Against Freewheeling, Extratextual Obstacle Preemption: Is Justice Clarence Thomas the Lone Principled Federalist?, 5 N.Y.U. J.L. & LIBERTY 63, 95-98 (2010).
    • (2010) N.Y.U. J.L. & Liberty , vol.5 , Issue.63 , pp. 95-98
    • Sharkey, C.M.1
  • 162
    • 79952465823 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Statutory interpretation as a multifarious enterprise
    • Cf. Todd D. Rakoff, Statutory Interpretation as a Multifarious Enterprise, 104 NW. U. L. REV. 1559, 1585 (2010) (maintaining that "[t]o assert that a statute has a clear meaning . . . is to claim that one particular interpretive frame . . . should be used" and that "ambiguity very often results precisely from the fact that there is more than one frame of reference with a decent claim to being relevant").
    • (2010) Nw. U. L. Rev. , vol.104 , Issue.1559 , pp. 1585
    • Rakoff, T.D.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.