메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 38, Issue 1, 2010, Pages 76-110

Can There Be a Global Demos? An Agency-Based Approach

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 79956236099     PISSN: 00483915     EISSN: 10884963     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1088-4963.2009.01174.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (67)

References (96)
  • 1
    • 84926182926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Global Collective Action
    • (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 2004)
    • Todd Sandler, Global Collective Action (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 2004)
    • Sandler, T.1
  • 2
    • 84920364150 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Oxford andNew York: Oxford University Press). We use the term "public goods" broadly to include common pool resources.
    • Scott Barrett, Why Cooperate? The Incentive to Supply Global Public Goods (Oxford andNew York: Oxford University Press, 2007). We use the term "public goods" broadly to include common pool resources.
    • (2007) Why Cooperate? The Incentive to Supply Global Public Goods
    • Barrett, S.1
  • 4
    • 33646126581 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Democratic Accountability and Political Effectiveness from a Cosmopolitan Perspective
    • ed. David Held and Mathias Koenig-Archibugi (Oxford: Blackwell,
    • David Held, "Democratic Accountability and Political Effectiveness from a Cosmopolitan Perspective," in Global Governance and Public Accountability, ed. David Held and Mathias Koenig-Archibugi (Oxford: Blackwell, 2005), pp. 240-67.
    • (2005) Global Governance and Public Accountability , pp. 240-67
    • Held, D.1
  • 6
    • 84982518812 scopus 로고
    • Does Europe Need a Constitution? Demos, Telos and the German Maastricht Decision
    • J.H.H. Weiler, "Does Europe Need a Constitution? Demos, Telos and the German Maastricht Decision," European Law Journal 1 (1995): 219-58.
    • (1995) European Law Journal , vol.1 , pp. 219-58
    • Weiler, J.H.H.1
  • 7
    • 69149086231 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Democracy's Domain
    • See, however, David Miller's recent article, which came to our attention afterwe completed the present article. We briefly compare Miller's interesting analysis with ours in a later note.
    • See, however, David Miller's recent article, "Democracy's Domain," Philosophy and Public Affairs 37 (2009): 201-28, which came to our attention afterwe completed the present article. We briefly compare Miller's interesting analysis with ours in a later note.
    • (2009) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.37 , pp. 201-28
  • 8
    • 85055300006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Boundaries Beyond Borders: Delineating Democratic 'Peoples' in a Globalizing World
    • E.g., Terry Macdonald, "Boundaries Beyond Borders: Delineating Democratic 'Peoples' in a Globalizing World," Democratization 10 (2003): 173-94
    • (2003) Democratization , vol.10 , pp. 173-94
    • Macdonald, T.1
  • 9
    • 42949095831 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Democratic Theory of Territory and Some Puzzles about Global Democracy
    • Thomas Christiano, "A Democratic Theory of Territory and Some Puzzles about Global Democracy," Journal of Social Philosophy 37 (2006): 81-107
    • (2006) Journal of Social Philosophy , vol.37 , pp. 81-107
    • Christiano, T.1
  • 10
    • 33846650147 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Enfranchising All Affected Interests, and Its Alternatives
    • Robert E. Goodin, "Enfranchising All Affected Interests, and Its Alternatives," Philosophy and Public Affairs 35 (2007): 40-68.
    • (2007) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.35 , pp. 40-68
    • Goodin, R.E.1
  • 11
    • 84874787729 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Christian List and Philip Pettit, Group Agency: The Possibility, Design and Status of Corporate Agents (Oxford: Oxford University Press) as well as other references therein.
    • See Christian List and Philip Pettit, Group Agency: The Possibility, Design and Status of Corporate Agents (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010) as well as other references therein.
    • (2010)
  • 12
    • 0002959322 scopus 로고
    • Deliberative Democracy and Social Choice
    • E.g., David Miller, "Deliberative Democracy and Social Choice," Political Studies 40 [special issue] (1992): 54-67
    • (1992) Political Studies , vol.40 , Issue.SPECIAL ISSUE , pp. 54-67
    • Miller, D.1
  • 13
    • 84970772283 scopus 로고
    • Aggregation and Deliberation: On the Possibility of Democratic Legitimacy
    • Jack Knight and James Johnson, "Aggregation and Deliberation: On the Possibility of Democratic Legitimacy," Political Theory 22
    • (1994) Political Theory , vol.22 , pp. 277-96
    • Knight, J.1    Johnson, J.2
  • 14
    • 0037277275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Social Choice Theory and Deliberative Democracy: A Reconciliation
    • John Dryzek and Christian List, "Social Choice Theory and Deliberative Democracy: A Reconciliation," British Journal of Political Science 33 (2003): 1-28
    • (2003) British Journal of Political Science , vol.33 , pp. 1-28
    • Dryzek, J.1    List, C.2
  • 15
    • 84874787874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deliberation, Single-Peakedness, and the Possibility of Meaningful Democracy: Evidence from Deliberative Polls," working paper, London School of Economics and Stanford Center for Deliberative Democracy (2000/2007).
    • Christian List, Robert Luskin, James Fishkin, and Iain McLean, "Deliberation, Single-Peakedness, and the Possibility of Meaningful Democracy: Evidence from Deliberative Polls," working paper, London School of Economics and Stanford Center for Deliberative Democracy (2000/2007).
    • List, C.1    Luskin, R.2    Fishkin, J.3    McLean, I.4
  • 16
    • 84874789377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • List and Pettit, Group Agency.
    • List and Pettit, Group Agency.
  • 17
    • 84874787515 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As discussed below, on some accounts it only evermakes sense to define the demos in relation to the all-encompassing set of all issues, while on other accounts there can be issue-specific demoi.
    • As discussed below, on some accounts it only evermakes sense to define the demos in relation to the all-encompassing set of all issues, while on other accounts there can be issue-specific demoi.
  • 19
    • 0007265115 scopus 로고
    • Prologue: Democratic Theory and the Boundary Problem
    • New York: New York University Press
    • Frederick G. Whelan, "Prologue: Democratic Theory and the Boundary Problem," in Nomos XXV: Liberal Democracy (New York: New York University Press, 1983, pp. 13-47)
    • (1983) Nomos XXV: Liberal Democracy , pp. 13-47
    • Whelan, F.G.1
  • 20
    • 84874762686 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Boundaries Beyond Borders Goodin, Enfranchising All Affected Interests Miller, Democracy's Domain
    • Macdonald
    • Macdonald, "Boundaries Beyond Borders"; Goodin, "Enfranchising All Affected Interests"; Miller, "Democracy's Domain."
  • 21
    • 84874762287 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • fact, both criteria have a number of different variants, but we set the details aside here. A third approach-whereby the demos is defined as the set of those individuals who happen to be nationals of a state that is governed democratically-is not relevant here.
    • In fact, both criteria have a number of different variants, but we set the details aside here. A third approach-whereby the demos is defined as the set of those individuals who happen to be nationals of a state that is governed democratically-is not relevant here.
  • 22
    • 84874776639 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The sentence "Quod omnes tangit ab omnibus approbetur" was first used in a constitutional rather than private law sense in the thirteenth century, most famously in thewrit by King Edward I of England that summoned the bishops and abbots to the so-called Model Parliament of 1295
    • The sentence "Quod omnes tangit ab omnibus approbetur" was first used in a constitutional rather than private law sense in the thirteenth century, most famously in thewrit by King Edward I of England that summoned the bishops and abbots to the so-called Model Parliament of 1295.
  • 23
    • 79953333136 scopus 로고
    • Freedom and the Medieval Church
    • ed. R. W. Davies (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press
    • Brian Tierney, "Freedom and the Medieval Church," in The Origins of Modern Freedom in the West, ed. R. W. Davies (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 1995), pp. 86-88.
    • (1995) The Origins of Modern Freedom in the West , pp. 86-88
    • Tierney, B.1
  • 25
    • 84874766410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • his recent article, "Democracy's Domain," David Miller has made the interesting suggestion that the difference between two approaches to delimiting the demos-one that stresses the inclusion of all affected interests and another that stresses the role of sympathetic identification, underlying agreement on ethical principles, interpersonal trust, and stable relationships-derives at least in part from a deeper difference between a "liberal" and a "radical" conception of democracy. Miller argues that liberal democrats, for whom democracy is mainly instrumentally valuable, tend to look favorably on the principle of affected interest. By contrast, radical democrats, for whom democracy is principally intrinsically valuable, tend to emphasize sympathetic identification, underlying agreement on ethical principles, interpersonal trust, and the existence of stable relationships as delimitation criteria for the demos.
    • In his recent article, "Democracy's Domain," David Miller has made the interesting suggestion that the difference between two approaches to delimiting the demos-one that stresses the inclusion of all affected interests and another that stresses the role of sympathetic identification, underlying agreement on ethical principles, interpersonal trust, and stable relationships-derives at least in part from a deeper difference between a "liberal" and a "radical" conception of democracy. Miller argues that liberal democrats, for whom democracy is mainly instrumentally valuable, tend to look favorably on the principle of affected interest. By contrast, radical democrats, for whom democracy is principally intrinsically valuable, tend to emphasize sympathetic identification, underlying agreement on ethical principles, interpersonal trust, and the existence of stable relationships as delimitation criteria for the demos. Miller suggests that the latter factors are privileged by radical democrats because they are "qualities that a group of people must possess in order to function as a demos" (pp. 207-8)
  • 26
    • 84874779993 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • At first sight, this may seem to suggest that radical democrats are more interested in the "proper functioning" of the demos than liberal democrats are, and thus that the former lean more towards what we call the "performative" approach to conceptualizing the demos, while the latter lean more towards the "compositional" one. However, we would resist this suggestion. Precisely because liberal democrats focus on the ability of democracy to produce desirable outcomes such as a larger aggregate social welfare, they have no less interest in its proper functioning than radical democrats. For this reason, we think that it is more appropriate to maintain that every democrat takes (or should take) an interest in securing the existence of a well-functioning demos, but also that such functioning can be conceptualized in a number of different and potentially contrasting ways. The bulk of our article deals with the task of providing a more precise and operationalizable
    • At first sight, this may seem to suggest that radical democrats are more interested in the "proper functioning" of the demos than liberal democrats are, and thus that the former lean more towards what we call the "performative" approach to conceptualizing the demos, while the latter lean more towards the "compositional" one. However, we would resist this suggestion. Precisely because liberal democrats focus on the ability of democracy to produce desirable outcomes such as a larger aggregate social welfare, they have no less interest in its proper functioning than radical democrats. For this reason, we think that it is more appropriate to maintain that every democrat takes (or should take) an interest in securing the existence of a well-functioning demos, but also that such functioning can be conceptualized in a number of different and potentially contrasting ways. The bulk of our article deals with the task of providing a more precise and operationalizable interpretation of the idea of functioning, in the context of what we call an agency-based approach to conceptualizing the demos.
  • 27
    • 84874776499 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed, many proponents of the affectivity criterion hold that, in reality, a demos requires one level of identity to take priority over others (that is, there cannot be multiple issue-specific demoi).
    • Indeed, many proponents of the affectivity criterion hold that, in reality, a demos requires one level of identity to take priority over others (that is, there cannot be multiple issue-specific demoi).
  • 28
    • 84874767210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "A Democratic Theory of Territory," Thomas Christiano argues that democratic boundaries should be drawn around "common worlds." For a group of individuals, a common world is "a world in which all or nearly all the individuals' fundamental interests are intertwined with each other"
    • In "A Democratic Theory of Territory," Thomas Christiano argues that democratic boundaries should be drawn around "common worlds." For a group of individuals, a common world is "a world in which all or nearly all the individuals' fundamental interests are intertwined with each other" (p. 97).
  • 29
    • 38049021452 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Democratic Theory and Border Coercion: No Right to Unilaterally Control Your Own Borders
    • See, for example, Arash Abizadeh, "Democratic Theory and Border Coercion: No Right to Unilaterally Control Your Own Borders," Political Theory 36 (2008): 37-65.
    • (2008) Political Theory , vol.36 , pp. 37-65
    • Abizadeh, A.1
  • 30
    • 0005193752 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The End of theOld Order? Globalization and the Prospects for World Order
    • 219-45
    • David Held and Anthony McGrew, "The End of theOld Order? Globalization and the Prospects for World Order," Review of International Studies 24 (1998): 219-45, at p. 237.
    • (1998) Review of International Studies , vol.24 , pp. 237
    • Held, D.1    McGrew, A.2
  • 31
    • 84874786356 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Goodin, "Enfranchising All Affected Interests." On the all-inclusiveness criterion, see, further, Raffaele Marchetti, Global Democracy: For and Against (London and New York: Routledge,
    • Goodin, "Enfranchising All Affected Interests." On the all-inclusiveness criterion, see, further, Raffaele Marchetti, Global Democracy: For and Against (London and New York: Routledge, 2008).
    • (2008)
  • 34
    • 84874762761 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Goodin, in "Enfranchising All Affected Interests," retorts: "It is arbitrary, from a moral point of view, to whom we happen to feel sentimentally attached or with whom we happen to share a common history or ancestry. What makes those factors matter, in ways that justify constituting our demoi around them, is the way that those factors lead to people's interests being intertwined. The reason we think that territorial or historical or national groups ought make decisions together is that, typically if not invariably, the interests of individuals within those groups are affected by the actions and choices of others in that group"
    • Goodin, in "Enfranchising All Affected Interests," retorts: "It is arbitrary, from a moral point of view, to whom we happen to feel sentimentally attached or with whom we happen to share a common history or ancestry. What makes those factors matter, in ways that justify constituting our demoi around them, is the way that those factors lead to people's interests being intertwined. The reason we think that territorial or historical or national groups ought make decisions together is that, typically if not invariably, the interests of individuals within those groups are affected by the actions and choices of others in that group" (p. 48).
  • 35
    • 84874777379 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Macdonald, in "Boundaries Beyond Borders," develops a similar argument about how different approaches mandate either the "alignment" of boundaries of power to the boundaries of legitimate solidaristic peoples or vice versa, although we would not describe the contrast as one between "idealist" and "realist" approaches On the tension between "inclusionary push" and "exclusionary pull," see also Miller, "Democracy's Domain."
    • Macdonald, in "Boundaries Beyond Borders," develops a similar argument about how different approaches mandate either the "alignment" of boundaries of power to the boundaries of legitimate solidaristic peoples or vice versa, although we would not describe the contrast as one between "idealist" and "realist" approaches (pp. 178-79). On the tension between "inclusionary push" and "exclusionary pull," see also Miller, "Democracy's Domain."
  • 36
    • 84874772570 scopus 로고
    • The use of the term "populist" here is inspired byWilliam Riker, Liberalism Against Populism (San Francisco: W. H. Freeman
    • The use of the term "populist" here is inspired byWilliam Riker, Liberalism Against Populism (San Francisco: W. H. Freeman, 1982).
    • (1982)
  • 37
    • 84874785067 scopus 로고
    • Inspired by Jürgen Habermas, Faktizität und Geltung: Beiträge zur Diskurstheorie des Rechts und des demokratischen Rechtsstaats (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp
    • Inspired by Jürgen Habermas, Faktizität und Geltung: Beiträge zur Diskurstheorie des Rechts und des demokratischen Rechtsstaats (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1992), pp. 364-66
    • (1992) , pp. 364-66
  • 38
    • 38549137435 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Transnationalizing the Public Sphere: On the Legitimacy and Efficacy of Public Opinion in a Post-Westphalian World
    • Nancy Fraser, "Transnationalizing the Public Sphere: On the Legitimacy and Efficacy of Public Opinion in a Post-Westphalian World," Theory, Culture and Society 24 (2007): 7-30
    • (2007) Theory, Culture and Society , vol.24 , pp. 7-30
    • Fraser, N.1
  • 40
  • 42
    • 84874771288 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is entirely conceivable, of course, that there are correlations between certain compositional criteria and certain performative ones, in that groups satisfying the one set of criteria may also be likely to satisfy the other. However, such correlations are a contingent matter and do not undermine the fact that, conceptually, the compositional and performative questions about the demos are distinct.
    • It is entirely conceivable, of course, that there are correlations between certain compositional criteria and certain performative ones, in that groups satisfying the one set of criteria may also be likely to satisfy the other. However, such correlations are a contingent matter and do not undermine the fact that, conceptually, the compositional and performative questions about the demos are distinct.
  • 43
    • 84874769713 scopus 로고
    • This way of defining an agent follows List and Pettit, Group Agency, and Daniel Dennett, The Intentional Stance (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press,
    • This way of defining an agent follows List and Pettit, Group Agency, and Daniel Dennett, The Intentional Stance (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1987).
    • (1987)
  • 44
    • 84874772215 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • List and Pettit, Group Agency.
    • List and Pettit, Group Agency.
  • 45
    • 84874764893 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • List and Pettit, Group Agency.
    • List and Pettit, Group Agency.
  • 46
    • 0007129872 scopus 로고
    • Procedural Democracy
    • 5th series, ed. Peter Laslett and James S. Fishkin (Oxford: Blackwell,
    • Robert A. Dahl, "Procedural Democracy," in Philosophy, Politics and Society, 5th series, ed. Peter Laslett and James S. Fishkin (Oxford: Blackwell, 1979), pp. 97-133.
    • (1979) Philosophy, Politics and Society , pp. 97-133
    • Dahl, R.A.1
  • 47
    • 84874771824 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • List and Pettit, Group Agency. Axiomatic social choice theory goes back to Kenneth Arrow, Social Choice and Individual Values (New York: Wiley, 1951/1963).
    • E.g., List and Pettit, Group Agency. Axiomatic social choice theory goes back to Kenneth Arrow, Social Choice and Individual Values (New York: Wiley, 1951/1963).
  • 48
    • 84874782962 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the question of whether a democratic institutional structure could emerge at the global level, see Mathias Koenig-Archibugi, "Is Global Democracy Possible?" European Journal of International Relations (forthcoming). Moreover, the question of whether a given collection under a particular actual or possible organizational structure counts as a state-like agent permits a continuum of answers, since state-like agency is not a simple on-off phenomenon. There exists a continuum of possible cases ranging from a fully developed, well-ordered state at one end (which, in turn, can take a number of different forms) to an extreme Hobbesian state of nature at the other end. The kinds of institutions we currently find at the level of the European Union, for instance, presumably fall somewhere in the middle.
    • On the question of whether a democratic institutional structure could emerge at the global level, see Mathias Koenig-Archibugi, "Is Global Democracy Possible?" European Journal of International Relations (forthcoming). Moreover, the question of whether a given collection under a particular actual or possible organizational structure counts as a state-like agent permits a continuum of answers, since state-like agency is not a simple on-off phenomenon. There exists a continuum of possible cases ranging from a fully developed, well-ordered state at one end (which, in turn, can take a number of different forms) to an extreme Hobbesian state of nature at the other end. The kinds of institutions we currently find at the level of the European Union, for instance, presumably fall somewhere in the middle.
  • 49
    • 0003691257 scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 2.8.96.
    • John Locke, Two Treatises of Government (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1960), 2.8.96.
    • (1960) Two Treatises of Government
    • Locke, J.1
  • 50
    • 84874767968 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. Victor Gourevitch (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,), bk. 4, chap. 2. For further discussion, see List and Pettit, Group Agency, chap. 2.
    • Jean-Jacques Rousseau, The Social Contract and Later Political Writings, ed. Victor Gourevitch (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), bk. 4, chap. 2. For further discussion, see List and Pettit, Group Agency, chap. 2.
    • (1997) The Social Contract and Later Political Writings
    • Rousseau, J.-J.1
  • 51
    • 84874781265 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • First, it is open to all possible combinations of individual attitudes on the issue in question ("universal domain"). Second, all individuals have equal weight in determining the collective attitude ("anonymity"). Third, the criterion itself is unbiased between a positive and a negative attitude ("neutrality"). And fourth, the collective attitude is a positively responsive function of the individual attitudes ("positive responsiveness").
    • First, it is open to all possible combinations of individual attitudes on the issue in question ("universal domain"). Second, all individuals have equal weight in determining the collective attitude ("anonymity"). Third, the criterion itself is unbiased between a positive and a negative attitude ("neutrality"). And fourth, the collective attitude is a positively responsive function of the individual attitudes ("positive responsiveness")
  • 52
    • 0000661802 scopus 로고
    • A Set of Independent Necessary and Sufficient Conditions for Simple Majority Decision
    • Kenneth O. May, "A Set of Independent Necessary and Sufficient Conditions for Simple Majority Decision," Econometrica 20 (1952): 680-84
    • (1952) Econometrica , vol.20 , pp. 680-84
    • May, K.O.1
  • 53
    • 33748784091 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Conditional Defense of Plurality Rule: Generalizing May's Theorem in a Restricted Informational Environment
    • Robert E. Goodin and Christian List, "A Conditional Defense of Plurality Rule: Generalizing May's Theorem in a Restricted Informational Environment," American Journal of Political Science 50 (2006): 940-49.
    • (2006) American Journal of Political Science , vol.50 , pp. 940-49
    • Goodin, R.E.1    List, C.2
  • 54
    • 84874775221 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A full defense of any given criterion for ascribing collective attitudes is beyond the scope of this article.
    • A full defense of any given criterion for ascribing collective attitudes is beyond the scope of this article.
  • 55
    • 3342997150 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2003)
    • E.g., Cass Sunstein, Why Societies Need Dissent (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2003)
    • Why Societies Need Dissent
    • Sunstein, C.1
  • 57
    • 1642424522 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Two Concepts of Agreement
    • Christian List, "Two Concepts of Agreement," The Good Society 11 (2002): 72-79
    • (2002) The Good Society , vol.11 , pp. 72-79
    • List, C.1
  • 58
    • 84874777893 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deliberation and Agreement
    • ed. Shawn W. Rosenberg (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan
    • revised as "Deliberation and Agreement," in Deliberation, Participation and Democracy: Can the People Govern? ed. Shawn W. Rosenberg (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2008), pp. 64-8.
    • (2008) Deliberation, Participation and Democracy: Can the People Govern? , pp. 64-8
  • 59
    • 33744726255 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These definitions are based on List, "Two Concepts of Agreement." Some subsequent notions of meta-consensus were discussed in John S. Dryzek and Simon J. Niemeyer, "Reconciling Pluralism and Consensus as Political Ideals," American Journal of Political Science
    • These definitions are based on List, "Two Concepts of Agreement." Some subsequent notions of meta-consensus were discussed in John S. Dryzek and Simon J. Niemeyer, "Reconciling Pluralism and Consensus as Political Ideals," American Journal of Political Science 50 (2006): 634-49.
    • (2006) , vol.50 , pp. 634-49
  • 60
    • 84874785241 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As acknowledged in the following discussion, substantive agreement on certain particularly fundamental issues may be a necessary condition for the capacity for democratic agency.
    • As acknowledged in the following discussion, substantive agreement on certain particularly fundamental issues may be a necessary condition for the capacity for democratic agency.
  • 61
    • 0012203902 scopus 로고
    • See List, "Two Concepts of Agreement"; List et al., "Deliberation, Single- Peakedness, and the Possibility of Meaningful Democracy"; Richard G. Niemi, "Majority Decision-Making with Partial Unidimensionality," American Political Science Review
    • See List, "Two Concepts of Agreement"; List et al., "Deliberation, Single- Peakedness, and the Possibility of Meaningful Democracy"; Richard G. Niemi, "Majority Decision-Making with Partial Unidimensionality," American Political Science Review 63 (1969): 488-97.
    • (1969) , vol.63 , pp. 488-97
  • 62
    • 0001008280 scopus 로고
    • Condorcet's Paradox
    • William V. Gehrlein, "Condorcet's Paradox," Theory and Decision 15 (1983): 161-97.
    • (1983) Theory and Decision , vol.15 , pp. 161-97
    • Gehrlein, W.V.1
  • 63
    • 84874760208 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Riker, Liberalism Against Populism.
    • Riker, Liberalism Against Populism.
  • 64
    • 0034375282 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Unlikelihood of Condorcet's Paradox in a Large Society
    • Andranik S. Tangian, "Unlikelihood of Condorcet's Paradox in a Large Society," Social Choice and Welfare 17 (2000): 337-65
    • (2000) Social Choice and Welfare , vol.17 , pp. 337-65
    • Tangian, A.S.1
  • 65
    • 0035603046 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Epistemic Democracy: Generalizing the Condorcet Jury Theorem
    • appendix 3
    • Christian List and Robert E. Goodin, "Epistemic Democracy: Generalizing the Condorcet Jury Theorem," Journal of Political Philosophy 9 (2001): 277-306, appendix 3
    • (2001) Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.9 , pp. 277-306
    • List, C.1    Goodin, R.E.2
  • 66
    • 0242627507 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Impartial Culture Maximizes the Probability of Majority Cycles
    • Ilia Tsetlin, Michel Regenwetter, and Bernard Grofman, "The Impartial Culture Maximizes the Probability of Majority Cycles," Social Choice and Welfare 21 (2003): 387-98.
    • (2003) Social Choice and Welfare , vol.21 , pp. 387-98
    • Tsetlin, I.1    Regenwetter, M.2    Grofman, B.3
  • 67
    • 84928854618 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
    • Gerry Mackie, Democracy Defended (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004)
    • (2004) Democracy Defended
    • Mackie, G.1
  • 69
    • 84874760278 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One such measure is the "Laakso-Taagepera index of fragmentation." Suppose n1 (among n) individuals most prefer the first alternative (among k alternatives), n2 most prefer the second, , nk most prefer the k-th. Then the "Laakso-Taagepera index" can be defined as In particular, LT = 1 means perfect consensus; LT ? ∞ means extreme fragmentation. See List et al., "Deliberation, Single-Peakedness, and the Possibility of Meaningful Democracy."
    • One such measure is the "Laakso-Taagepera index of fragmentation." Suppose n1 (among n) individuals most prefer the first alternative (among k alternatives), n2 most prefer the second, , nk most prefer the k-th. Then the "Laakso-Taagepera index" can be defined as In particular, LT = 1 means perfect consensus; LT ? ∞ means extreme fragmentation. See List et al., "Deliberation, Single-Peakedness, and the Possibility of Meaningful Democracy."
  • 70
    • 0001786352 scopus 로고
    • On the Rationale of Group Decision-Making
    • Duncan Black, "On the Rationale of Group Decision-Making," Journal of Political Economy 56 (1948): 23-34
    • (1948) Journal of Political Economy , vol.56 , pp. 23-34
    • Black, D.1
  • 71
    • 0000411128 scopus 로고
    • A Note on the Simple Majority Decision Rule
    • Arrow, Social Choice and Individual Values. Other contributions to the literature on such structure conditions include K.-I. Inada,
    • Arrow, Social Choice and Individual Values. Other contributions to the literature on such structure conditions include K.-I. Inada, "A Note on the Simple Majority Decision Rule," Econometrica 32 (1964): 525-31
    • (1964) Econometrica , vol.32 , pp. 525-31
  • 72
    • 0001653838 scopus 로고
    • A Possibility Theorem on Majority Decisions
    • Amartya K. Sen, "A Possibility Theorem on Majority Decisions," Econometrica 34 (1966): 491-99
    • (1966) Econometrica , vol.34 , pp. 491-99
    • Sen, A.K.1
  • 73
    • 84874783034 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and more recently Wulf Gaertner, Domain Conditions in Social Choice Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
    • and more recently Wulf Gaertner, Domain Conditions in Social Choice Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001)
    • (2001)
  • 75
    • 84874788066 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • the stylized example of the world population subdivided into three groups, the condition is violated: No matter how we align the three options from left to right, one of the three groups will fail to have preferences that fit the pattern of single-peakedness. If, on the other hand, one of the groups were to change their views, transforming their preferences into those of one of the other groups, or into the reverse of their previous preferences, the violation of single-peakedness would disappear.
    • In the stylized example of the world population subdivided into three groups, the condition is violated: No matter how we align the three options from left to right, one of the three groups will fail to have preferences that fit the pattern of single-peakedness. If, on the other hand, one of the groups were to change their views, transforming their preferences into those of one of the other groups, or into the reverse of their previous preferences, the violation of single-peakedness would disappear.
  • 76
    • 84874765500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deliberation, Single-Peakedness, and the Possibility of Meaningful Democracy"; Niemi, "Majority Decision-Making with Partial Unidimensionality."
    • List et al.
    • List et al., "Deliberation, Single-Peakedness, and the Possibility of Meaningful Democracy"; Niemi, "Majority Decision-Making with Partial Unidimensionality."
  • 77
    • 84874781983 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Riker, Liberalism Against Populism
    • Riker, Liberalism Against Populism, p. 128.
  • 78
    • 84874783515 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Miller, "Deliberative Democracy and Social Choice"; Knight and Johnson, "Aggregation and Deliberation"; Dryzek and List, "Social Choice Theory and Deliberative Democracy"; List, "Deliberation and Agreement."
    • Miller, "Deliberative Democracy and Social Choice"; Knight and Johnson, "Aggregation and Deliberation"; Dryzek and List, "Social Choice Theory and Deliberative Democracy"; List, "Deliberation and Agreement."
  • 79
    • 34547284241 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Citizen Participation in a Deliberative Poll: Factors Predicting Attitude Change and Political Engagement
    • Specifically, the deliberation appears to move individual preferences away from combinations leading to cycles, by increasing proximity to single-peakedness, as empirically investigated in List et al., "Deliberation, Single-Peakedness, and the Possibility of Meaningful Democracy." Deliberative Polls have also shown that deliberative exercises may have a negative, neutral, or positive effect on substantive agreement. E.g., R. A. Eggins, K. J. Reynolds, P. J. Oakes, and K. I. Mavor,
    • Specifically, the deliberation appears to move individual preferences away from combinations leading to cycles, by increasing proximity to single-peakedness, as empirically investigated in List et al., "Deliberation, Single-Peakedness, and the Possibility of Meaningful Democracy." Deliberative Polls have also shown that deliberative exercises may have a negative, neutral, or positive effect on substantive agreement. E.g., R. A. Eggins, K. J. Reynolds, P. J. Oakes, and K. I. Mavor, "Citizen Participation in a Deliberative Poll: Factors Predicting Attitude Change and Political Engagement," Australian Journal of Psychology 59 (2007): 94-100
    • (2007) Australian Journal of Psychology , vol.59 , pp. 94-100
  • 80
    • 34247374779 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • How Deliberation Makes Better Citizens: The Danish Deliberative Poll on the Euro
    • V. N. Andersen and K. M. Hansen, "How Deliberation Makes Better Citizens: The Danish Deliberative Poll on the Euro," European Journal of Political Research 46 (2007): 531-56
    • (2007) European Journal of Political Research , vol.46 , pp. 531-56
    • Andersen, V.N.1    Hansen, K.M.2
  • 82
    • 84874762828 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Immanuel Kant, "Toward Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch," in Toward Perpetual Peace and Other Writings on Politics, Peace and History, ed. Pauline Kleingeld (New Haven, CT, and London: Yale University Press, 1795/2006), pp. 67-109, at p. 84.
    • Immanuel Kant, "Toward Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch," in Toward Perpetual Peace and Other Writings on Politics, Peace and History, ed. Pauline Kleingeld (New Haven, CT, and London: Yale University Press, 1795/2006), pp. 67-109, at p. 84.
  • 83
    • 84874759923 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chicago Council on Global Affairs and WorldPublicOpinion.org, "Publics Around the World Say UN Has Responsibility to Protect Against Genocide," Accessed April 4
    • Chicago Council on Global Affairs and WorldPublicOpinion.org, "Publics Around the World Say UN Has Responsibility to Protect Against Genocide," http://www .worldpublicopinion.org/pipa/pdf/apr07/CCGA+_Genocide_article.pdf Accessed April 4, 2007.
    • (2007)
  • 84
    • 84874763375 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But it should be noted that, even in national opinion polls, questions are rarely asked in such a way as to capture possible cyclical majority preferences.
    • But it should be noted that, even in national opinion polls, questions are rarely asked in such a way as to capture possible cyclical majority preferences.
  • 85
    • 46649120468 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Coalition Diversity and Normative Legitimacy in Human Security Negotiations
    • Fen Osler Hampson and Holly Reid, "Coalition Diversity and Normative Legitimacy in Human Security Negotiations," International Negotiation 8 (2003): 7-42.
    • (2003) International Negotiation , vol.8 , pp. 7-42
    • Hampson, F.O.1    Reid, H.2
  • 86
    • 0033247996 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Drafting the International Criminal Court Treaty: Two Years to Rome and an Afterword on the Rome Diplomatic Conference
    • Fanny Benedetti and John L. Washburn, "Drafting the International Criminal Court Treaty: Two Years to Rome and an Afterword on the Rome Diplomatic Conference," Global Governance 5 (1999): 1-38
    • (1999) Global Governance , vol.5 , pp. 1-38
    • Benedetti, F.1    Washburn, J.L.2
  • 87
    • 84933480235 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The First Two Sessions of the UN Preparatory Committee on the Establishment of an International Criminal Court
    • Christopher Keith Hall, "The First Two Sessions of the UN Preparatory Committee on the Establishment of an International Criminal Court," American Journal of International Law 91 (1997): 177-87
    • (1997) American Journal of International Law , vol.91 , pp. 177-87
    • Hall, C.K.1
  • 88
    • 84937263239 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Third and Fourth Sessions of theUN Preparatory Committee on the Establishment of an International Criminal Court
    • "The Third and Fourth Sessions of theUN Preparatory Committee on the Establishment of an International Criminal Court," American Journal of International Law 92 (1998):124-33
    • (1998) American Journal of International Law , vol.92 , pp. 124-33
  • 89
    • 84937262044 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Fifth Session of the UN Preparatory Committee on the Establishment of an International Criminal Court
    • "The Fifth Session of the UN Preparatory Committee on the Establishment of an International Criminal Court," American Journal of International Law 92 (1998): 331-39
    • (1998) American Journal of International Law , vol.92 , pp. 331-39
  • 90
    • 84937258473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Sixth Session of the UN Preparatory Committee on the Establishment of an International Criminal Court
    • "The Sixth Session of the UN Preparatory Committee on the Establishment of an International Criminal Court," American Journal of International Law 92 (1998): 548-56
    • (1998) American Journal of International Law , vol.92 , pp. 548-56
  • 92
    • 84874763588 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For instance, if we consider the positions voiced at the beginning of the negotiation process, a hypothetical vote by simple majority rule on pairs of alternatives and on the basis of the "one state, one vote" principle might have produced a majority cycle, as the sum of LM and CS votes could have ensured a majority for Strong against Subordinate, the sum of LM and RS votes could have ensured a majority for Subordinate against Weak, and the sum of CS and RS votes could have ensured a majority for Weak against Strong.
    • For instance, if we consider the positions voiced at the beginning of the negotiation process, a hypothetical vote by simple majority rule on pairs of alternatives and on the basis of the "one state, one vote" principle might have produced a majority cycle, as the sum of LM and CS votes could have ensured a majority for Strong against Subordinate, the sum of LM and RS votes could have ensured a majority for Subordinate against Weak, and the sum of CS and RS votes could have ensured a majority for Weak against Strong.
  • 93
    • 84874767581 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Überzeugung in der Politik. Grundzüge einer Diskurstheorie internationalen Regierens (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp
    • Nicole Deitelhoff, Überzeugung in der Politik. Grundzüge einer Diskurstheorie internationalen Regierens (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 2006)
    • (2006)
    • Deitelhoff, N.1
  • 94
    • 68349139175 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Discursive Process of Legalization: Charting Islands of Persuasion in the ICC Case
    • "The Discursive Process of Legalization: Charting Islands of Persuasion in the ICC Case," International Organization 63 (2009): 33-65
    • (2009) International Organization , vol.63 , pp. 33-65
  • 96
    • 84874760313 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deitelhoff, Überzeugung in der Politik, 228-37.
    • Deitelhoff, Überzeugung in der Politik, pp. 212, 228-37.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.