메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 79, Issue 2, 2011, Pages 506-541

Group consensus, individual consent

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 79956074966     PISSN: 00168076     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (23)

References (257)
  • 3
    • 84869735767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 28 U.S.C. § 1407 (2006).
    • (2006) U.S.C. , vol.28 , pp. 1407
  • 5
    • 84875510302 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In re Zyprexa Prods. Liab. Litig., 491 E.D.N.Y
    • In re Zyprexa Prods. Liab. Litig., 424 F. Supp. 2d 488, 491 (E.D.N.Y. 2006)
    • (2006) F. Supp. 2D , vol.424 , pp. 488
  • 6
    • 34249090271 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lilly settles with 18,000 over zyprexa
    • Jan. 5
    • Alex Berenson, Lilly Settles with 18,000 over Zyprexa, N.Y. TIMES, Jan. 5, 2007, at C1
    • (2007) N.Y. Times
    • Berenson, A.1
  • 7
    • 79956070806 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • last visited Nov. 14, (sponsored by the Vioxx MDL Plaintiffs' Steering Committee)
    • OFFICIAL VIOXX SETTLEMENT, http://www.officialvioxxsettlement.com/ (last visited Nov. 14, 2010) (sponsored by the Vioxx MDL Plaintiffs' Steering Committee).
    • (2010) Official Vioxx Settlement
  • 8
    • 79952828006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • From class actions to multidistrict consolidations: Aggregate mass tort litigation after ortiz
    • For the most recent empirical study of multidistrict litigation in comparison with class actions, see 806 ("Though the number of [personal injury products liability] class action lawsuits has shifted very little, the percentage in which a party files a motion to certify a class that a court grants for litigation purposes appears to have shrunk markedly. and, while the shift in class certification was taking place, the [Judicial Panel on Multidistrict Litigation] began transferring products-liability litigations to single courts for consolidated management at a higher rate, and the number of products-liability consolidated cases expanded.")
    • For the most recent empirical study of multidistrict litigation in comparison with class actions, see Thomas E. Willging & Emery G. Lee III, From Class Actions to Multidistrict Consolidations: Aggregate Mass Tort Litigation After Ortiz, 58 U. KAN. L. REV. 775, 806 (2010) ("Though the number of [personal injury products liability] class action lawsuits has shifted very little, the percentage in which a party files a motion to certify a class that a court grants for litigation purposes appears to have shrunk markedly. and, while the shift in class certification was taking place, the [Judicial Panel on Multidistrict Litigation] began transferring products-liability litigations to single courts for consolidated management at a higher rate, and the number of products-liability consolidated cases expanded.").
    • (2010) U. Kan. L. Rev. , vol.58 , pp. 775
    • Willging, T.E.1    Lee III, E.G.2
  • 9
    • 77950403790 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (g) ("A lawyer who represents two or more clients shall not participate in making an aggregate settlement of the claims of or against the clients . . . unless each client gives informed consent, in a writing signed by the client."). Every state has enacted some version of this aggregate settlement rule
    • MODEL RULES OF PROF'L CONDUCT R. 1.8(g) (2008) ("A lawyer who represents two or more clients shall not participate in making an aggregate settlement of the claims of or against the clients . . . unless each client gives informed consent, in a writing signed by the client."). Every state has enacted some version of this aggregate settlement rule.
    • (2008) Model Rules of Prof'l Conduct R. , pp. 18
  • 11
    • 77958549189 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The trouble with all-or-nothing settlements
    • For an overview of how these provisions exert ethical pressure on plaintiffs' counsel, see 980
    • For an overview of how these provisions exert ethical pressure on plaintiffs' counsel, see Howard M. Erichson, the Trouble with All-or-Nothing Settlements, 58 U. KAN. L. REV. 979, 980 (2010).
    • (2010) U. Kan. L. Rev. , vol.58 , pp. 979
    • Erichson, H.M.1
  • 12
    • 79956126599 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Litigating groups
    • See 8-9 [hereinafter Burch, Litigating Groups]
    • See Elizabeth Chamblee Burch, Litigating Groups, 61 ALA. L. REV. 1, 8-9 (2009) [hereinafter Burch, Litigating Groups]
    • (2009) Ala. L. Rev. , vol.61 , pp. 1
    • Burch, E.C.1
  • 13
    • 75649144455 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The public value of settlement
    • 1185
    • Samuel Issacharoff & Robert H. Klonoff, the Public Value of Settlement, 78 FORDHAM L. REV. 1177, 1185 (2010)
    • (2010) Fordham L. Rev. , vol.78 , pp. 1177
    • Issacharoff, S.1    Klonoff, R.H.2
  • 14
    • 79952164710 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mass lawsuits and the aggregate settlement rule
    • 767
    • Charles Silver & Lynn A. Baker, Mass Lawsuits and the Aggregate Settlement Rule, 32 WAKE FOREST L. REV. 733, 767 (1997).
    • (1997) Wake Forest L. Rev. , vol.32 , pp. 733
    • Silver, C.1    Baker, L.A.2
  • 15
    • 79956106030 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Empirical studies have shown that allowing people to participate in designing process ex ante (in this case, before a settlement offer) enhances their judgment about procedural fairness and the substantive outcome
    • Empirical studies have shown that allowing people to participate in designing process ex ante (in this case, before a settlement offer) enhances their judgment about procedural fairness and the substantive outcome.
  • 17
    • 77951268693 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Procedural justice in nonclass aggregation
    • 38 [hereinafter Burch, Procedural Justice]
    • Elizabeth Chamblee Burch, Procedural Justice in Nonclass Aggregation, 44 WAKE FOREST L. REV. 1, 38 (2009) [hereinafter Burch, Procedural Justice]
    • (2009) Wake Forest L. Rev. , vol.44 , pp. 1
    • Burch, E.C.1
  • 18
    • 0009915317 scopus 로고
    • The effects of control on perceived fairness of procedures and outcomes
    • 237-38
    • Linda Musante et al., the Effects of Control on Perceived Fairness of Procedures and Outcomes, 19 J. EXPERIMENTAL SOC. PSYCHOL. 223, 237-38 (1983)
    • (1983) J. Experimental Soc. Psychol , vol.19 , pp. 223
    • Musante, L.1
  • 19
    • 4544386410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Procedural preferences in alternative dispute resolution: A closer, modern look at an old idea
    • 233, 243
    • Donna Shestowsky, Procedural Preferences in Alternative Dispute Resolution: A Closer, Modern Look at an Old Idea, 10 PSYCHOL. PUB. POL'Y & L. 211, 233, 243 (2004).
    • (2004) Psychol. Pub. Pol'y & L. , vol.10 , pp. 211
    • Shestowsky, D.1
  • 22
    • 0043011224 scopus 로고
    • See ("Many people, particularly those caught up in mass cases, feel alienated and dehumanized when dealing with our institutions. their participation in the system is too often, from their view, ineffective. they are items, things, rather than persons. . . . [T]hey are anonymous recipients of a form of justice they do not understand-players in a kind of lottery of awards and rejections from our system of law.")
    • See JACK B. WEINSTEIN, INDIVIDUAL JUSTICE IN MASS TORT LITIGATION 9 (1995) ("Many people, particularly those caught up in mass cases, feel alienated and dehumanized when dealing with our institutions. their participation in the system is too often, from their view, ineffective. they are items, things, rather than persons. . . . [T]hey are anonymous recipients of a form of justice they do not understand-players in a kind of lottery of awards and rejections from our system of law.").
    • (1995) Individual Justice in Mass Tort Litigation , pp. 9
    • Weinstein, J.B.1
  • 23
    • 79956128172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aggregation, community, and the line between
    • Although I have introduced and explored these ideas in considerable detail elsewhere, my aim here is to assess how they fit within section 3.17(b)'s framework and alleviate the potential for attorney manipulation. I have written a series of articles addressing both the problems in nonclass aggregation and the solution of "litigating together. [hereinafter Burch, Aggregation, Community, and the Line Between] (considering the political theory underlying moral obligations, including how these obligations fit within the liberal and communitarian traditions)
    • Although I have introduced and explored these ideas in considerable detail elsewhere, my aim here is to assess how they fit within section 3.17(b)'s framework and alleviate the potential for attorney manipulation. I have written a series of articles addressing both the problems in nonclass aggregation and the solution of "litigating together." Elizabeth Chamblee Burch, Aggregation, Community, and the Line Between, 58 U. KAN. L. REV. 889 (2010) [hereinafter Burch, Aggregation, Community, and the Line Between] (considering the political theory underlying moral obligations, including how these obligations fit within the liberal and communitarian traditions)
    • (2010) U. Kan. L. Rev. , vol.58 , pp. 889
    • Burch, E.C.1
  • 24
    • 79251609418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 8 (developing the theory of moral obligations between plaintiffs who litigate together)
    • Burch, Litigating Groups, supra note 8 (developing the theory of moral obligations between plaintiffs who litigate together)
    • Litigating Groups
    • Burch1
  • 25
    • 79952835328 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Litigating together: Social, moral, and legal obligations
    • forthcoming [hereinafter Burch, Litigating Together], available at (translating the theory developed in "Litigating Groups" into practice)
    • Elizabeth Chamblee Burch, Litigating Together: Social, Moral, and Legal Obligations, 91 B.U. L. REV. (forthcoming 2011) [hereinafter Burch, Litigating Together], available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract-id= 1577073 (translating the theory developed in "Litigating Groups" into practice)
    • (2011) B.U. L. Rev. , vol.91
    • Burch, E.C.1
  • 26
    • 79956129755 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 9 (explaining the problems and risks presented by nonclass aggregation in procedural fairness terms)
    • Burch, Procedural Justice, supra note 9 (explaining the problems and risks presented by nonclass aggregation in procedural fairness terms).
    • Procedural Justice
    • Burch1
  • 27
    • 79956124080 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, debates within the annual ALI meetings have led to several iterations of section 3.17(b)
    • For example, debates within the annual ALI meetings have led to several iterations of section 3.17(b).
  • 28
    • 79956096220 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • for example, believes that we could be bound by both natural duties and voluntarily incurred obligations, but that those obligations must be construed against a backdrop of preexisting morality
    • John Rawls, for example, believes that we could be bound by both natural duties and voluntarily incurred obligations, but that those obligations must be construed against a backdrop of preexisting morality.
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 29
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • ("Acquiescence in, or even consent to, clearly unjust institutions does not give rise to obligations. It is generally agreed that extorted promises are void ab initio.")
    • JOHN RAWLS, A THEORY OF JUSTICE 343 (1971) ("Acquiescence in, or even consent to, clearly unjust institutions does not give rise to obligations. It is generally agreed that extorted promises are void ab initio.")
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice , pp. 343
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 31
    • 0041405888 scopus 로고
    • Contract law and distributive justice
    • See 478-79 (discussing the difficulty of determining when circumstances might render a promise involuntary)
    • See Anthony T. Kronman, Contract Law and Distributive Justice, 89 YALE L.J. 472, 478-79 (1980) (discussing the difficulty of determining when circumstances might render a promise involuntary).
    • (1980) Yale L.J. , vol.89 , pp. 472
    • Kronman, A.T.1
  • 32
    • 0036379660 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Autonomy, peace, and put options in the mass tort class action
    • See 750
    • See Richard A. Nagareda, Autonomy, Peace, and Put Options in the Mass Tort Class Action, 115 HARV. L. REV. 747, 750 (2002)
    • (2002) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.115 , pp. 747
    • Nagareda, R.A.1
  • 33
    • 38849196868 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Class actions, litigant autonomy, and the foundations of procedural due process
    • 1574
    • Martin H. Redish & Nathan D. Larsen, Class Actions, Litigant Autonomy, and the Foundations of Procedural Due Process, 95 CALIF. L. REV. 1573, 1574 (2007).
    • (2007) Calif. L. Rev. , vol.95 , pp. 1573
    • Redish, M.H.1    Larsen, N.D.2
  • 34
    • 84868048548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For information on the Vioxx settlement, including the estimated $4.85 billion payout, see supra note 5
    • For information on the Vioxx settlement, including the estimated $4.85 billion payout, see OFFICIAL VIOXX SETTLEMENT, supra note 5.
    • Official Vioxx Settlement
  • 35
    • 79956092933 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Settlement Agreement at 5-6, No. 05-01657 E.D. La. Nov. 9, available at After some plaintiffs' attorneys contended the settlement conflicted with ethical rules, it was reinterpreted to mean that the attorneys should recommend the deal only if it was in the client's best interest
    • Settlement Agreement at 5-6, Vioxx Prod. Liab. Litig., No. 05-01657 (E.D. La. Nov. 9, 2007), available at http://www.merck.com/newsroom/vioxx/pdf/ Settlement-Agreement.pdf. After some plaintiffs' attorneys contended the settlement conflicted with ethical rules, it was reinterpreted to mean that the attorneys should recommend the deal only if it was in the client's best interest.
    • (2007) Vioxx Prod. Liab. Litig.
  • 36
    • 79952155814 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lawyers seek to alter settlement over vioxx
    • See Dec. 21
    • See Alex Berenson, Lawyers Seek to Alter Settlement over Vioxx, N.Y. TIMES, Dec. 21, 2007, at C4.
    • (2007) N.Y. Times
    • Berenson, A.1
  • 37
    • 79956114261 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Settlement Agreement, supra note 19, at
    • Settlement Agreement, supra note 19, at 41.
  • 38
    • 79956084337 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Merck vioxx judge threatens to end suit consolidation
    • See Jan. 5
    • See Jef Feeley & Leslie Snadowsky, Merck Vioxx Judge Threatens to End Suit Consolidation, BLOOMBERG, Jan. 5, 2006
    • (2006) Bloomberg
    • Feeley, J.1    Snadowsky, L.2
  • 39
    • 84928442417 scopus 로고
    • Mass justice: The limited and unlimited power of the courts
    • cf. 230 ("Faced with mass tort litigation, judges are not simply neutral arbiters; rather, they have strong personal incentives to speed the judicial process, save costs and labor, and reduce redundancy.")
    • Cf. Mark A. Peterson & Molly Selvin, Mass Justice: The Limited and Unlimited Power of the Courts, 54 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 227, 230 (1991) ("Faced with mass tort litigation, judges are not simply neutral arbiters; rather, they have strong personal incentives to speed the judicial process, save costs and labor, and reduce redundancy.")
    • (1991) Law & Contemp. Probs. , vol.54 , pp. 227
    • Peterson, M.A.1    Selvin, M.2
  • 40
    • 84892170148 scopus 로고
    • The role of judges in settling complex cases: The agent orange example
    • 361-62 ("Judges, like other people, do not like to invest a great deal in a project without receiving the anticipated return.")
    • Peter H. Schuck, the Role of Judges in Settling Complex Cases: The Agent Orange Example, 53 U. CHI. L. REV. 337, 361-62 (1986) ("Judges, like other people, do not like to invest a great deal in a project without receiving the anticipated return.").
    • (1986) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.53 , pp. 337
    • Schuck, P.H.1
  • 41
    • 79251609418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., supra note 8, at
    • See, e.g., Burch, Litigating Groups, supra note 8, at 36-37
    • Litigating Groups , pp. 36-37
    • Burch1
  • 43
    • 77951279537 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Embedded aggregation in civil litigation
    • 1155-56
    • Richard A. Nagareda, Embedded Aggregation in Civil Litigation, 95 CORNELL L. REV. 1105, 1155-56 (2010).
    • (2010) Cornell L. Rev. , vol.95 , pp. 1105
    • Nagareda, R.A.1
  • 44
    • 0037921905 scopus 로고
    • Paramount Pictures
    • THE GODFATHER (Paramount Pictures 1972).
    • (1972) The Godfather
  • 46
    • 79956142763 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 15, at
    • See RAWLS, supra note 15, at 343-45
    • Rawls1
  • 47
    • 79956098085 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 22, at
    • Erichson & Zipursky, supra note 22, at 301-11
    • Erichson1    Zipursky2
  • 49
    • 79956155204 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • About us
    • last visited Nov. 14
    • About Us, PLAINTIFFS VIEW, http://plaintiffsview.org/aboutus.html (last visited Nov. 14, 2010)
    • (2010) Plaintiffs View
  • 50
    • 79956063019 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also My Story last visited Nov. 14
    • see also Al Pennington, My Story, http://plaintiffsview.org/MystoryAl. html (last visited Nov. 14, 2010).
    • (2010)
    • Pennington, A.1
  • 51
    • 79956063576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 15, at
    • RAWLS, supra note 15, at 345.
    • Rawls1
  • 53
    • 79956074855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 22, at (pinpointing the timing of consent-when money was on the table for attorneys and their clients-as the principal problem with the Vioxx deal)
    • See Nagareda, supra note 22, at 1161 (pinpointing the timing of consent-when money was on the table for attorneys and their clients-as the principal problem with the Vioxx deal).
    • Nagareda1
  • 55
    • 0042745654 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • § 122 cmts. c(i), d (discussing the role of client sophistication in informed consent)
    • RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF THE LAW GOVERNING LAWYERS § 122 cmts. c(i), d (2000) (discussing the role of client sophistication in informed consent)
    • (2000) Restatement (Third) of the Law Governing Lawyers
  • 57
    • 79956088838 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (c) Discussion Draft No. 2, ("[E]ach claimant may consent, in a writing signed by each claimant, to such collective decisionmaking either as part of the lawyer or law firm's retainer agreement or at any other point during the course of the litigation.")
    • PRINCIPLES OF THE LAW OF AGGREGATE LITIG. § 3.17(c) (Discussion Draft No. 2, 2007) ("[E]ach claimant may consent, in a writing signed by each claimant, to such collective decisionmaking either as part of the lawyer or law firm's retainer agreement or at any other point during the course of the litigation.")
    • (2007) Principles of the Law of Aggregate Litig , pp. 317
  • 58
  • 61
    • 79251609418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also supra note 8, at
    • see also Burch, Litigating Groups, supra note 8, at 39-40.
    • Litigating Groups , pp. 39-40
    • Burch1
  • 62
    • 79960883549 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • § (g)
    • 11 U.S.C. § 524(g) (2006)
    • (2006) U.S.C. , vol.11 , pp. 524
  • 66
    • 79956063994 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ethical issues in asbestos litigation
    • 866
    • Lester Brickman, Ethical Issues in Asbestos Litigation, 33 HOFSTRA L. REV. 833, 866 (2005).
    • (2005) Hofstra L. Rev. , vol.33 , pp. 833
    • Brickman, L.1
  • 67
    • 79956120626 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 36, at
    • NAGAREDA, supra note 36, at 172-73.
    • Nagareda1
  • 68
    • 79956122238 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 12, at
    • WEINSTEIN, supra note 12, at 49-50.
    • Weinstein1
  • 69
    • 51149102036 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Framing the choice between cash and the courthouse: Experiences with the 9/11 victim compensation fund
    • See 649, 661-62
    • See Gillian K. Hadfield, Framing the Choice Between Cash and the Courthouse: Experiences with the 9/11 Victim Compensation Fund, 42 LAW & SOC'Y REV. 645, 649, 661-62 (2008)
    • (2008) Law & Soc'y Rev. , vol.42 , pp. 645
    • Hadfield, G.K.1
  • 70
    • 36849037289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It's not about the money!: A theory on misconceptions of the plaintiffs' litigation aims
    • 363 ("Plaintiffs' articulated litigation aims were largely composed of extra-legal objectives of principle, with 41% not mentioning monetary compensation at all, 35% saying it was of secondary importance, 18% describing money as their primary objective in suing, and only one person (6%) saying it was money alone.")
    • Tamara Relis, "It's Not About the Money!": A theory on Misconceptions of the Plaintiffs' Litigation Aims, 68 U. PITT L. REV. 341, 363 (2006) ("Plaintiffs' articulated litigation aims were largely composed of extra-legal objectives of principle, with 41% not mentioning monetary compensation at all, 35% saying it was of secondary importance, 18% describing money as their primary objective in suing, and only one person (6%) saying it was money alone.").
    • (2006) U. Pitt L. Rev. , vol.68 , pp. 341
    • Relis, T.1
  • 71
    • 79956078562 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 41, at
    • Hadfield, supra note 41, at 649.
    • Hadfield1
  • 72
    • 79956130816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 41, at
    • Relis, supra note 41, at 341.
    • Relis1
  • 73
    • 79956090911 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 41, at
    • Hadfield, supra note 41, at 662-63
    • Hadfield1
  • 74
    • 79956072366 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also supra note 12, at
    • see also WEINSTEIN, supra note 12, at 8-9.
    • Weinstein1
  • 75
    • 79956095725 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 41, at
    • Hadfield, supra note 41, at 672.
    • Hadfield1
  • 76
    • 72749094184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Age discrimination in employment act of 1967
    • As I have discussed elsewhere, this suggests that when plaintiffs want extralegal relief, we should consider a fee-shifting statute akin to those in civil rights legislation. I thank Richard Nagareda for suggesting this to me. For examples of civil rights statutes that require losing defendants to pay "reasonable" plaintiffs' attorneys fees, see the § (b)
    • As I have discussed elsewhere, this suggests that when plaintiffs want extralegal relief, we should consider a fee-shifting statute akin to those in civil rights legislation. I thank Richard Nagareda for suggesting this to me. For examples of civil rights statutes that require losing defendants to pay "reasonable" plaintiffs' attorneys fees, see the Age Discrimination in Employment Act of 1967, 29 U.S.C. § 626(b) (2006)
    • (2006) U.S.C. , vol.29 , pp. 626
  • 77
    • 79956063575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Civil rights attorney's fees awards act of 1976
    • § (b)
    • Civil Rights Attorney's Fees Awards Act of 1976, 42 U.S.C. § 1988(b) (2006)
    • (2006) U.S.C. , vol.42 , pp. 1988
  • 78
    • 78751663503 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Title VII of the civil rights act of 1964
    • § (k)
    • Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, 42 U.S.C. § 2000e-5(k) (2006)
    • (2006) U.S.C. , vol.42
  • 79
    • 15744373438 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Americans with disabilities act of 1990
    • §
    • Americans with Disabilities Act of 1990, 42 U.S.C. § 12205 (2006).
    • (2006) U.S.C. , vol.42 , pp. 12205
  • 80
    • 30144439568 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Privacy act of 1974
    • For examples of other statutes promoting the public interest that also permit fee shifting, see the § (g)(2)(B), (g)(3)(B)
    • For examples of other statutes promoting the public interest that also permit fee shifting, see the Privacy Act of 1974, 5 U.S.C. § 552a(g)(2)(B), (g)(3)(B) (2006)
    • (2006) U.S.C. , vol.5
  • 81
    • 30144439568 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Government in the sunshine act
    • § (i)
    • Government in the Sunshine Act, 5 U.S.C. § 552b(i) (2006)
    • (2006) U.S.C. , vol.5
  • 82
    • 79956079994 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Equal access to justice act
    • § (b), (d)(1)(A)
    • Equal Access to Justice Act, 28 U.S.C. § 2412(b), (d)(1)(A) (2006)
    • (2006) U.S.C. , vol.28 , pp. 2412
  • 83
    • 33847017974 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Clean air act
    • § (f)
    • Clean Air Act, 42 U.S.C. § 7607(f) (2006).
    • (2006) U.S.C. , vol.42 , pp. 7607
  • 84
    • 0005497708 scopus 로고
    • Class conflicts in class actions
    • See 1183 ("A fundamental premise of American adjudicative structures is that clients, not their counsel, define litigation objectives."). the right to sue in tort is a property interest protected by the Due Process Clause. As defined by Karl Llewellyn, "rights" are "statements of likelihood that in a given situation a certain type of court action loomed in the offing
    • See Deborah L. Rhode, Class Conflicts in Class Actions, 34 STAN. L. REV. 1183, 1183 (1982) ("A fundamental premise of American adjudicative structures is that clients, not their counsel, define litigation objectives."). the right to sue in tort is a property interest protected by the Due Process Clause. As defined by Karl Llewellyn, "rights" are "statements of likelihood that in a given situation a certain type of court action loomed in the offing.
    • (1982) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.34 , pp. 1183
    • Rhode, D.L.1
  • 85
    • 0011322694 scopus 로고
    • A realistic jurisprudence-the next step
    • 448
    • Karl N. Llewellyn, A Realistic Jurisprudence-the Next Step, 30 COLUM. L. REV. 431, 448 (1930).
    • (1930) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.30 , pp. 431
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 86
    • 79956146604 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For more information on the economic disjunction, see supra note 13
    • For more information on the economic disjunction, see Burch, Litigating Together, supra note 13.
    • Litigating Together
    • Burch1
  • 87
    • 79956135485 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 47, at I realize this statement is controversial in many circles. My point is to underscore the necessity of process in enforcing legislatively defined substantive rights
    • Llewellyn, supra note 47, at 448. I realize this statement is controversial in many circles. My point is to underscore the necessity of process in enforcing legislatively defined substantive rights.
    • Llewellyn1
  • 89
    • 59549083449 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some realism about mass torts
    • see also 1979 ("Guided by Llewellyn's insight, I maintain that a rigid boundary between substance and procedure for the purpose of identifying the components of a right to sue does not exist if a right to sue is that which entitles its holder to attempt to require her adversary to conform to a peparticular duty. Defined accordingly, a right to sue is abstract and meaningless in any real-world sense if no procedural avenue exists for its attempted vindication.")
    • see also David Marcus, Some Realism About Mass Torts, 75 U. CHI. L. REV. 1949, 1979 (2008) ("Guided by Llewellyn's insight, I maintain that a rigid boundary between substance and procedure for the purpose of identifying the components of a right to sue does not exist if a right to sue is that which entitles its holder to attempt to require her adversary to conform to a peparticular duty. Defined accordingly, a right to sue is abstract and meaningless in any real-world sense if no procedural avenue exists for its attempted vindication.").
    • (2008) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.75 , pp. 1949
    • Marcus, D.1
  • 90
    • 79956146604 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 13 manuscript at
    • See Burch, Litigating Together, supra note 13 (manuscript at 8).
    • Litigating Together , pp. 8
    • Burch1
  • 92
    • 79956082133 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 8, at
    • Silver & Baker, supra note 8, at 755-67.
    • Silver1    Baker2
  • 95
    • 79956074311 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., § (b), (d) Discussion Draft
    • See, e.g., PRINCIPLES OF THE LAW OF AGGREGATE LITIG. § 3.17(b), (d) (Discussion Draft 2006).
    • (2006) Principles of the Law of Aggregate Litig , pp. 317
  • 97
    • 79956071819 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 24, at
    • SANDEL, supra note 24, at 144-45.
    • Sandel1
  • 98
    • 79956100272 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 15, at 333-50 (noting the need for altruism and reciprocity, but observing that "affection and ties of sentiment" are "not demanded as a matter of justice")
    • See RAWLS, supra note 15, at 178, 333-50 (noting the need for altruism and reciprocity, but observing that "affection and ties of sentiment" are "not demanded as a matter of justice").
    • Rawls1
  • 101
    • 79956074854 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 24, at
    • SANDEL, supra note 24, at 223-25
    • Sandel1
  • 103
    • 0004238625 scopus 로고
    • Although these scholars have become known as communitarians, most dislike that label. Sandel, in particular, sees himself as reviving civic republicanism
    • MICHAEL WALZER, SPHERES OF JUSTICE 64 (1983). Although these scholars have become known as communitarians, most dislike that label. Sandel, in particular, sees himself as reviving civic republicanism.
    • (1983) Spheres of Justice , pp. 64
    • Walzer, M.1
  • 105
    • 79956153571 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 59, at (internal quotation marks omitted)
    • MACINTYRE, supra note 59, at 216 (internal quotation marks omitted).
    • Macintyre1
  • 106
    • 79956135484 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 24, at
    • SANDEL, supra note 24, at 241
    • Sandel1
  • 107
    • 84936068266 scopus 로고
    • see also Dworkin's larger project aims to join liberalism and community by arguing that liberalism is the best way to understand our political community
    • see also RONALD DWORKIN, LAW'S EMPIRE 195-202 (1986). Dworkin's larger project aims to join liberalism and community by arguing that liberalism is the best way to understand our political community.
    • (1986) Law's Empire , pp. 195-202
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 108
    • 84929062912 scopus 로고
    • Liberal community
    • See generally
    • See generally Ronald Dworkin, Liberal Community, 77 CALIF. L. REV. 479 (1989).
    • (1989) Calif. L. Rev. , vol.77 , pp. 479
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 109
    • 0004176314 scopus 로고
    • Communitarian ethics and legal justification
    • See 737-38
    • See Geoffrey C. Hazard, Jr., Communitarian Ethics and Legal Justification, 59 U. COLO. L. REV. 721, 737-38 (1988)
    • (1988) U. Colo. L. Rev. , vol.59 , pp. 721
    • Hazard Jr., G.C.1
  • 110
    • 84928459309 scopus 로고
    • The idea of communitarian morality
    • 449 ("[A community] is a comprehensive framework for social life. . . . [A]lthough in a genuine community there must be a minimum of integration, including shared symbolic experience, we also expect to find relatively self-regulating activities, groups, and institutions. . . the individual is bound into a community by way of participation in more limited, more person-centered groups." (emphasis omitted))
    • Philip Selznick, the Idea of Communitarian Morality, 75 CALIF. L. REV. 445, 449 (1987) ("[A community] is a comprehensive framework for social life. . . . [A]lthough in a genuine community there must be a minimum of integration, including shared symbolic experience, we also expect to find relatively self-regulating activities, groups, and institutions. . . the individual is bound into a community by way of participation in more limited, more person-centered groups." (emphasis omitted)).
    • (1987) Calif. L. Rev. , vol.75 , pp. 445
    • Selznick, P.1
  • 111
    • 79956066087 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 12, at
    • See WEINSTEIN, supra note 12, at 47.
    • Weinstein1
  • 112
    • 0019480612 scopus 로고
    • The evolution of cooperation
    • See, e.g
    • See, e.g., Robert Axelrod & William D. Hamilton, the Evolution of Cooperation, 211 SCIENCE 1390 (1981)
    • (1981) Science , vol.211 , pp. 1390
    • Axelrod, R.1    Hamilton, W.D.2
  • 113
  • 114
    • 0020470415 scopus 로고
    • Cultural transmission and the evolution of cooperative behavior
    • Robert Boyd & Peter J. Richerson, Cultural Transmission and the Evolution of Cooperative Behavior, 10 HUM. ECOLOGY 325 (1982)
    • (1982) Hum. Ecology , vol.10 , pp. 325
    • Boyd, R.1    Richerson, P.J.2
  • 115
    • 0000058232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reciprocity as a contract enforcement device: Experimental evidence
    • Ernst Fehr et al., Reciprocity as a Contract Enforcement Device: Experimental Evidence, 65 ECONOMETRICA 833 (1997)
    • (1997) Econometrica , vol.65 , pp. 833
    • Fehr, E.1
  • 116
    • 0036328914 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Strong reciprocity, human cooperation and the enforcement of social norms
    • 20
    • Ernst Fehr et al., Strong Reciprocity, Human Cooperation and the Enforcement of Social Norms, 13 HUM. NATURE 1, 20 (2002)
    • (2002) Hum. Nature , vol.13 , pp. 1
    • Fehr, E.1
  • 117
    • 0000773694 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A theory of fairness, competition, and cooperation
    • 818
    • Ernst Fehr & Klaus M. Schmidt, A theory of Fairness, Competition, and Cooperation, 114 Q.J. ECON. 817, 818 (1999)
    • (1999) Q.J. Econ. , vol.114 , pp. 817
    • Fehr, E.1    Schmidt, K.M.2
  • 118
    • 84970118747 scopus 로고
    • Reciprocity and cooperation in social dilemmas
    • 495
    • S. S. Komorita et al., Reciprocity and Cooperation in Social Dilemmas, 35 J. CONFLICT RESOL. 494, 495 (1991)
    • (1991) J. Conflict Resol. , vol.35 , pp. 494
    • Komorita, S.S.1
  • 119
    • 1842484264 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Social identity as social glue: The origins of group loyalty
    • 586
    • Mark Van Vugt & Claire M. Hart, Social Identity as Social Glue: The Origins of Group Loyalty, 86 J. PERSONALITY & SOC. PSYCHOL. 585, 586 (2004).
    • (2004) J. Personality & Soc. Psychol , vol.86 , pp. 585
    • Van Vugt, M.1    Hart, C.M.2
  • 120
    • 79956069663 scopus 로고
    • State farm to pay women $157 million for job bias
    • Apr. 29
    • Philip Hager, State Farm to Pay Women $157 Million for Job Bias, L.A. TIMES, Apr. 29, 1992, at A1
    • (1992) L.A. Times
    • Hager, P.1
  • 121
    • 79956141008 scopus 로고
    • Largest sex bias suit ever is settled: State farm to pay $157 million to California women for refusing to hire them as agents
    • Apr. 28, I thank Judith Resnik for pointing this out to me
    • Carol Ness, Largest Sex Bias Suit Ever Is Settled: State Farm to Pay $157 Million to California Women for Refusing to Hire them as Agents, S.F. EXAM'R, Apr. 28, 1992, at A1. I thank Judith Resnik for pointing this out to me.
    • (1992) S.F. Exam'r
    • Ness, C.1
  • 122
    • 79956107653 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 65
    • Hager, supra note 65.
    • Hager1
  • 123
    • 79956150000 scopus 로고
    • Toxic dreams: A California town finds meaning in an acid pit
    • July 61-62. the hazardous waste cleanup is ongoing
    • Jack Hitt, Toxic Dreams: A California Town Finds Meaning in an Acid Pit, HARPER'S MAG., July 1995, at 57, 61-62. the hazardous waste cleanup is ongoing.
    • (1995) Harper's Mag , pp. 57
    • Hitt, J.1
  • 125
    • 79956131350 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 67, at
    • Hitt, supra note 67, at 58.
    • Hitt1
  • 126
    • 79956089894 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 57-58.
    • Hitt1
  • 127
    • 79956113202 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 61.
    • Hitt1
  • 129
    • 79956068124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Most people tend to follow norms of distributive fairness
    • See id. Most people tend to follow norms of distributive fairness.
    • Hitt1
  • 130
    • 0030210472 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Information in ultimatum games: An experimental study
    • See 197-98
    • See Rachel T.A. Croson, Information in Ultimatum Games: An Experimental Study, 30 J. ECON. BEHAV. & ORG. 197, 197-98 (1996)
    • (1996) J. Econ. Behav. & Org. , vol.30 , pp. 197
    • Croson, R.T.A.1
  • 131
    • 84920483597 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tacit coordination and social dilemmas: On the importance of self-interest and fairness
    • 148-50 David De Cremer et al. eds
    • Erick van Dijk & David De Cremer, Tacit Coordination and Social Dilemmas: On the Importance of Self-Interest and Fairness, in SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY AND ECONOMICS 141, 148-50 (David De Cremer et al. eds., 2006)
    • (2006) Social Psychology and Economics , pp. 141
    • Van Dijk, E.1    De Cremer, D.2
  • 133
    • 79956063017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 61, at
    • See DWORKIN, supra note 61, at 195-202.
    • Dworkin1
  • 134
    • 79251609418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a detailed treatment of what makes a "group" in aggregate litigation and when obligations attach, see supra note 8, at
    • For a detailed treatment of what makes a "group" in aggregate litigation and when obligations attach, see Burch, Litigating Groups, supra note 8, at 38-47.
    • Litigating Groups , pp. 38-47
    • Burch1
  • 135
    • 79956079081 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I have explored these basic ideas in more detail elsewhere
    • I have explored these basic ideas in more detail elsewhere.
  • 137
    • 79956146604 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 13 manuscript at
    • Burch, Litigating Together, supra note 13 (manuscript at 28-29).
    • Litigating Together , pp. 28-29
    • Burch1
  • 138
    • 79956099725 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 61, at ("the connection we recognize between communal obligation and choice is much more complex and more a matter of degree that varies from one form of communal association to another.")
    • See DWORKIN, supra note 61, at 197 ("the connection we recognize between communal obligation and choice is much more complex and more a matter of degree that varies from one form of communal association to another.").
    • Dworkin1
  • 139
    • 79956070805 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To be clear, my claim is that these communal obligations morally, not legally, bind plaintiffs. Thus, communal obligations would not be subject to judicial enforcement
    • To be clear, my claim is that these communal obligations morally, not legally, bind plaintiffs. Thus, communal obligations would not be subject to judicial enforcement.
  • 140
    • 79956113727 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This differs from an individualistic account in that cooperation is not governed solely by self-interest. One might, however, reconcile it with Rawls's sentimental conception of community. In this sense, community is partially contained within the feelings, emotions, and sentiments of those who are pursuing some end together
    • This differs from an individualistic account in that cooperation is not governed solely by self-interest. One might, however, reconcile it with Rawls's sentimental conception of community. In this sense, community is partially contained within the feelings, emotions, and sentiments of those who are pursuing some end together.
  • 141
    • 79956088871 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 15, at
    • See RAWLS, supra note 15, at 177-78
    • Rawls1
  • 142
    • 79956065578 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 15, at 173 ("For a society to be a community in this strong sense, community must be constitutive of the shared self-understandings of the participants and embodied in their institutional arrangements, not simply an attribute of certain of the participants' plans of life.")
    • SANDEL, supra note 15, at 148-49, 173 ("For a society to be a community in this strong sense, community must be constitutive of the shared self-understandings of the participants and embodied in their institutional arrangements, not simply an attribute of certain of the participants' plans of life.").
    • Sandel1
  • 143
    • 79956126598 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 64
    • See supra note 64.
  • 144
    • 79956091431 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Even if plaintiffs do not develop other-regarding preferences, they may still frame their reasoning as an appeal to the good of the group. As James Fearon elaborates, [E]ven majorities commonly justify their actions in terms of the general public good rather than the narrow interest of the voting majority. . . . I would conjecture that often what is most important is the desire not to appear selfish or self-interested. there is something embarrassing or even shameful about statements like "We don't care what anyone else gets we just want more for ourselves
    • Even if plaintiffs do not develop other-regarding preferences, they may still frame their reasoning as an appeal to the good of the group. As James Fearon elaborates, [E]ven majorities commonly justify their actions in terms of the general public good rather than the narrow interest of the voting majority. . . . I would conjecture that often what is most important is the desire not to appear selfish or self-interested. there is something embarrassing or even shameful about statements like "We don't care what anyone else gets; we just want more for ourselves.
  • 145
    • 0002138257 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deliberation as discussion
    • 54 Jon Elster ed., (emphasis omitted)
    • James D. Fearon, Deliberation as Discussion, in DELIBERATIVE DEMOCRACY 44, 54 (Jon Elster ed., 1998) (emphasis omitted).
    • (1998) Deliberative Democracy , pp. 44
    • Fearon, J.D.1
  • 146
    • 79251609418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 8, at
    • See Burch, Litigating Groups, supra note 8, at 43-44.
    • Litigating Groups , pp. 43-44
    • Burch1
  • 147
    • 79956129755 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 9, at
    • See Burch, Procedural Justice, supra note 9, at 48-49.
    • Procedural Justice , pp. 48-49
    • Burch1
  • 148
    • 79956149461 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Voice and participation opportunities are critical components of procedural justice
    • Voice and participation opportunities are critical components of procedural justice.
  • 150
    • 58149205641 scopus 로고
    • Voice, control & procedural justice: Instrumental and noninstrumental concerns in fairness judgments
    • E. Allen Lind et al., Voice, Control & Procedural Justice: Instrumental and Noninstrumental Concerns in Fairness Judgments, 59 J. PER SONALITY & SOC. PSYCHOL. 952 (1990)
    • (1990) J. Per Sonality & Soc. Psychol. , vol.59 , pp. 952
    • Lind, E.A.1
  • 151
    • 21344438090 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Individuals within the aggregate: Relationships, representation, and fees
    • 306 ("[T]ort litigants share judicial and legal theorists' beliefs that process matters.")
    • Judith Resnik et al., Individuals Within the Aggregate: Relationships, Representation, and Fees, 71 N.Y.U. L. REV. 296, 306 (1996) ("[T]ort litigants share judicial and legal theorists' beliefs that process matters.").
    • (1996) N.Y.U. L. Rev. , vol.71 , pp. 296
    • Resnik, J.1
  • 152
    • 79956086715 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 12, at
    • WEINSTEIN, supra note 12, at 13.
    • Weinstein1
  • 154
    • 79952130004 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The American law institute's draft proposal to bypass the aggregate settlement rule: Do mass tort clients need (or want) group decision making?
    • This lessens the potential that an agreement would not express true client preferences as Professor Moore suggests might occur if the agreement is signed early in the litigation or solely at the behest of the attorney. 415
    • This lessens the potential that an agreement would not express true client preferences as Professor Moore suggests might occur if the agreement is signed early in the litigation or solely at the behest of the attorney. Nancy J. Moore, the American Law Institute's Draft Proposal to Bypass the Aggregate Settlement Rule: Do Mass Tort Clients Need (or Want) Group Decision Making?, 57 DEPAUL L. REV. 395, 415 (2008).
    • (2008) Depaul L. Rev. , vol.57 , pp. 395
    • Moore, N.J.1
  • 155
    • 0346353782 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Regulation of Groups: The Influence of Legal and Nonlegal Sanctions on Collective Action
    • See Eric A. Posner, the Regulation of Groups: The Influence of Legal and Nonlegal Sanctions on Collective Action, 63 U. CHI. L. REV. 133, 137 (1996). (Pubitemid 126408713)
    • (1996) University of Chicago Law Review , vol.63 , Issue.1 , pp. 133
    • Posner, E.A.1
  • 157
    • 79956121712 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 80, at
    • Fearon, supra note 80, at 45-46.
    • Fearon1
  • 158
    • 79956120077 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It also makes it possible for the defendant to define the category of claimants in a way that guarantees that a settlement offer will obtain the requisite supermajority. This means that a majority of claimants with weaker legal claims, when lumped together with stronger claims, could cram the settlement down on those with serious injuries and fewer causation problems
    • It also makes it possible for the defendant to define the category of claimants in a way that guarantees that a settlement offer will obtain the requisite supermajority. This means that a majority of claimants with weaker legal claims, when lumped together with stronger claims, could cram the settlement down on those with serious injuries and fewer causation problems.
  • 159
    • 79956139009 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 86, at But if plaintiffs categorize themselves and engineer their own agreement, they might decide on weighted voting, where those with stronger claims have a vote that counts as more than a single vote
    • See Moore, supra note 86, at 410-11. But if plaintiffs categorize themselves and engineer their own agreement, they might decide on weighted voting, where those with stronger claims have a vote that counts as more than a single vote.
    • Moore1
  • 160
    • 79956085679 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 13 manuscript at (discussing the role of a "special officer" as a third-party neutral)
    • See Burch, Litigating Together, supra note 13 (manuscript at 25-28) (discussing the role of a "special officer" as a third-party neutral).
    • Litigating Together , pp. 25-28
    • Burch1
  • 162
    • 0036818401 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On apology and consilience
    • As Erin O'Hara and Douglas Yarn explain: [P]eople often value apology more than monetary compensation. Ford and Firestone had to broadcast a videotaped apology on national television to reach a settlement with a [woman] paralyzed by an accident caused by a roll-over of a Ford Explorer with defective Firestone tires. In the face of several attractive monetary offers, Paula Jones demanded-but never received-an apology from President Clinton as a condition of settlement 1125 (citation omitted)
    • As Erin O'Hara and Douglas Yarn explain: [P]eople often value apology more than monetary compensation. Ford and Firestone had to broadcast a videotaped apology on national television to reach a settlement with a [woman] paralyzed by an accident caused by a roll-over of a Ford Explorer with defective Firestone tires. In the face of several attractive monetary offers, Paula Jones demanded-but never received-an apology from President Clinton as a condition of settlement. Erin Ann O'Hara & Douglas Yarn, On Apology and Consilience, 77 WASH. L. REV. 1121, 1125 (2002) (citation omitted).
    • (2002) Wash. L. Rev. , vol.77 , pp. 1121
    • O'Hara, E.A.1    Yarn, D.2
  • 163
    • 79956098653 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra notes 18-26 and accompanying text
    • See supra notes 18-26 and accompanying text.
  • 164
    • 79956066595 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra notes 49-50 and accompanying text
    • See supra notes 49-50 and accompanying text.
  • 165
    • 54549108484 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • When does deliberating improve decisionmaking?
    • But see 12 (arguing that expertise systems provide a better result than using deliberation "as a palliative to decisionmaking")
    • But see Mathew D. McCubbins & Daniel B. Rodriguez, When Does Deliberating Improve Decisionmaking?, 15 J. CONTEMP. LEGAL ISSUES 9, 12 (2006) (arguing that expertise systems provide a better result than using deliberation "as a palliative to decisionmaking").
    • (2006) J. Contemp. Legal Issues , vol.15 , pp. 9
    • McCubbins, M.D.1    Rodriguez, D.B.2
  • 166
    • 0035537731 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legitimacy and economy in deliberative democracy
    • See 651-52 ("[O]utcomes are legitimate to the extent they receive reflective assent through participation in authentic deliberation by all those subject to the decision in question.")
    • See John S. Dryzek, Legitimacy and Economy in Deliberative Democracy, 29 POL. THEORY 651, 651-52 (2001) ("[O]utcomes are legitimate to the extent they receive reflective assent through participation in authentic deliberation by all those subject to the decision in question.")
    • (2001) Pol. theory , vol.29 , pp. 651
    • Dryzek, J.S.1
  • 167
    • 11844286307 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Procedural justice
    • 277-82
    • Lawrence B. Solum, Procedural Justice, 78 S. CAL. L. REV. 181, 277-82 (2002)
    • (2002) S. Cal. L. Rev. , vol.78 , pp. 181
    • Solum, L.B.1
  • 168
    • 79956117823 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deliberation as a discursive feature of contemporary theories of democracy: Comment on John S. Dryzek
    • 72-73 Anne Van Aaken et al. eds
    • Axel Tschentscher, Deliberation as a Discursive Feature of Contemporary theories of Democracy: Comment on John S. Dryzek, in DELIBERATION AND DECISION: ECONOMICS, CONSTITUTIONAL THEORY AND DELIBERATIVE DEMOCRACY 72, 72-73 (Anne Van Aaken et al. eds., 2004)
    • (2004) Deliberation and Decision: Economics, Constitutional theory and Deliberative Democracy , pp. 72
    • Tschentscher, A.1
  • 169
    • 0004015503 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. (arguing that deliberations are the task of modern legislatures and play a role in the legitimacy of legislation as a source of law)
    • Cf. JEREMY WALDRON, LAW AND DISAGREEMENT 70 (1999) (arguing that deliberations are the task of modern legislatures and play a role in the legitimacy of legislation as a source of law).
    • (1999) Law and Disagreement , pp. 70
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 170
    • 38949143560 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ("Demands for coherence and consistency on the intentions of each of the individuals then require each to seek consistency and coherence in the overall package of subplans of both. . . . these pressures toward meshing subplans will help shape the reasoning and bargaining of each in the pursuit of the shared activity.")
    • See MICHAEL E. BRATMAN, STRUCTURES OF AGENCY 291-95 (2007) ("Demands for coherence and consistency on the intentions of each of the individuals then require each to seek consistency and coherence in the overall package of subplans of both. . . . these pressures toward meshing subplans will help shape the reasoning and bargaining of each in the pursuit of the shared activity.").
    • (2007) Structures of Agency , pp. 291-295
    • Bratman, M.E.1
  • 171
    • 79956082132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 12, at
    • See WEINSTEIN, supra note 12, at 47
    • Weinstein1
  • 172
    • 42049114254 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Democracy and collective decision making
    • 256-57
    • Samuel Issacharoff, Democracy and Collective Decision Making, 6 INT'L J. CONST. L. 231, 256-57 (2008).
    • (2008) Int'l J. Const. L. , vol.6 , pp. 231
    • Issacharoff, S.1
  • 173
    • 79956109758 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 12, at
    • WEINSTEIN, supra note 12, at 47.
    • Weinstein1
  • 174
    • 79956146066 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally supra note 83, at ("If judges and lawyers are rational actors, however, they have strong incentives to conceive of litigation as multipurposed, to believe that some fundamental form of governance is enacted by adjudicatory modes of dispute inresolution, and therefore to be wary of principal-agent analogies that are not enriched with relationship, voice, expression, and human dignity.")
    • See generally Resnik et al., supra note 83, at 381 ("If judges and lawyers are rational actors, however, they have strong incentives to conceive of litigation as multipurposed, to believe that some fundamental form of governance is enacted by adjudicatory modes of dispute inresolution, and therefore to be wary of principal-agent analogies that are not enriched with relationship, voice, expression, and human dignity.").
    • Resnik1
  • 175
    • 13744258776 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Doing good, doing well
    • See 2097-98 (quoting interviews with Minnesota tobacco lawyers and activists on the importance of publically disclosing the tobacco discovery documents)
    • See Howard M. Erichson, Doing Good, Doing Well, 57 VAND. L. REV. 2087, 2097-98 (2004) (quoting interviews with Minnesota tobacco lawyers and activists on the importance of publically disclosing the tobacco discovery documents).
    • (2004) Vand. L. Rev. , vol.57 , pp. 2087
    • Erichson, H.M.1
  • 176
    • 0032393741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cohesion and respect: An examination of group decision making in social and escalation dilemmas
    • See 291-92
    • See Leigh Thompson et al., Cohesion and Respect: An Examination of Group Decision Making in Social and Escalation Dilemmas, 34 J. EXPERIMENTAL SOC. PSYCHOL. 289, 291-92 (1998).
    • (1998) J. Experimental Soc. Psychol. , vol.34 , pp. 289
    • Thompson, L.1
  • 177
    • 79956073806 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally supra note 80, at 60-63
    • See generally Fearon, supra note 80, at 53-54, 60-63
    • Fearon1
  • 178
    • 79956147410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 64. Groups who discuss a dilemma with each other are substantially more likely to cooperate to reach an acceptable outcome
    • supra note 64. Groups who discuss a dilemma with each other are substantially more likely to cooperate to reach an acceptable outcome.
  • 179
    • 1542710569 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Social dilemmas: The anatomy of cooperation
    • See 194
    • See Peter Kollock, Social Dilemmas: The Anatomy of Cooperation, 24 ANN. REV. SOC. 183, 194 (1998)
    • (1998) Ann. Rev. Soc. , vol.24 , pp. 183
    • Kollock, P.1
  • 180
    • 84985822141 scopus 로고
    • The effect of social motives, communication and group size on behaviour in an N-person multi-stage mixed-motive game
    • 251-52 Plus, discussion increases cooperation by eliciting social norms
    • Wim B. G. Liebrand, the Effect of Social Motives, Communication and Group Size on Behaviour in an N-Person Multi-Stage Mixed-Motive Game, 14 EUR. J. SOC. PSYCHOL. 239, 251-52 (1984). Plus, discussion increases cooperation by eliciting social norms.
    • (1984) Eur. J. Soc. Psychol. , vol.14 , pp. 239
    • Liebrand, W.B.G.1
  • 181
    • 38249026751 scopus 로고
    • Not me or thee but we: The importance of group identity in eliciting cooperation in dilemma situations
    • See
    • See Robyn M. Dawes et al., Not Me or thee but We: The Importance of Group Identity in Eliciting Cooperation in Dilemma Situations, 68 ACTA PSYCHOLOGICA 83 (1988).
    • (1988) Acta Psychologica , vol.68 , pp. 83
    • Dawes, R.M.1
  • 182
    • 79956128171 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally supra note 97, at
    • See generally BRATMAN, supra note 97, at 303.
    • Bratman1
  • 183
    • 79956114795 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 24, at
    • See SANDEL, supra note 24, at 260-63.
    • Sandel1
  • 184
    • 79956083821 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See at
    • See id. at 261.
    • Sandel1
  • 186
    • 84883932767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the benefits for diversity in decisionmaking, and hence the need for discussion not only among categories but also across them, see generally
    • On the benefits for diversity in decisionmaking, and hence the need for discussion not only among categories but also across them, see generally SCOTT E. PAGE, THE DIFFERENCE: HOW THE POWER OF DIVERSITY CREATES BETTER GROUPS, FIRMS, SCHOOLS, AND SOCIETIES (2007)
    • (2007) The Difference: How the Power of Diversity Creates Better Groups, Firms, Schools, and Societies
    • Page, S.E.1
  • 190
    • 33744726255 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reconciling pluralism and consensus as political ideals
    • My interpretation of section 3.17 has strands of both pluralism and consensus and relies sometimes on communitarianism and other times on the need for diversity (particularly as an antidote to group polarization). For one perspective on reconciling the two general perspectives on some points, see
    • My interpretation of section 3.17 has strands of both pluralism and consensus and relies sometimes on communitarianism and other times on the need for diversity (particularly as an antidote to group polarization). For one perspective on reconciling the two general perspectives on some points, see John S. Dryzek & Simon Niemeyer, Reconciling Pluralism and Consensus as Political Ideals, 50 AM. J. POL. SCI. 634 (2006).
    • (2006) Am. J. Pol. Sci. , vol.50 , pp. 634
    • Dryzek, J.S.1    Niemeyer, S.2
  • 191
    • 79956149999 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Even so, how we tolerate and encourage pluralism within the coherent whole raises a related question about when and whether plaintiffs who fundamentally disagree with the litigation's eventual course should be permitted to exit. Although I find the question worth considering further, exit's wide-ranging impact on preclusion doctrines, the All-Writs Act, and abstention doctrines require me to leave the topic for another day
    • Even so, how we tolerate and encourage pluralism within the coherent whole raises a related question about when and whether plaintiffs who fundamentally disagree with the litigation's eventual course should be permitted to exit. Although I find the question worth considering further, exit's wide-ranging impact on preclusion doctrines, the All-Writs Act, and abstention doctrines require me to leave the topic for another day.
  • 192
    • 79956159389 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 80, at
    • See Fearon, supra note 80, at 55-58.
    • Fearon1
  • 193
  • 194
    • 79956160926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some political theorists who advocate deliberative democracy disfavor this emphasis on voting and would promote collective choice through reasoned agreement instead
    • Some political theorists who advocate deliberative democracy disfavor this emphasis on voting and would promote collective choice through reasoned agreement instead.
  • 195
    • 79956076921 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., supra note 88, at To others, like Joshua Cohen, voting is a second-best solution but an important failsafe when consensus proves impossible
    • See, e.g., DRYZEK, supra note 88, at 47. To others, like Joshua Cohen, voting is a second-best solution but an important failsafe when consensus proves impossible.
    • Dryzek1
  • 196
    • 0042125935 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deliberation and democratic legitimacy
    • 163 Robert E. Goodin & Philip Pettit eds., 2d ed. ("Even under ideal conditions there is no promise that consensual reasons will be forthcoming. If they are not, then deliberation concludes with voting, subject to some form of majority rule.")
    • Joshua Cohen, Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy, in CONTEMPORARY POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY: AN ANTHOLOGY 159, 163 (Robert E. Goodin & Philip Pettit eds., 2d ed. 2006) ("Even under ideal conditions there is no promise that consensual reasons will be forthcoming. If they are not, then deliberation concludes with voting, subject to some form of majority rule.").
    • (2006) Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Anthology , pp. 159
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 197
    • 79956075925 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 9, at 210-11
    • LIND & TYLER, supra note 9, at 81-83, 210-11.
    • Lind1    Tyler2
  • 198
    • 79956135483 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 67
    • See supra note 67.
  • 200
    • 79955572905 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also § (b)(1) ("Claimants may exercise their collective decisionmaking power to approve a settlement through the selection of an independent agent other than counsel.")
    • see also id. § 3.17(b)(1) ("Claimants may exercise their collective decisionmaking power to approve a settlement through the selection of an independent agent other than counsel.").
    • (2010) Principles of the Law of Aggregate Litig. , pp. 317
  • 201
    • 79956134640 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 96, at
    • See Solum, supra note 96, at 279-80.
    • Solum1
  • 202
    • 72749126022 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Even though plaintiffs will have already filed their complaints, Rule 15 permits liberal amendments "when justice so requires." (a). For the interested reader, I have elaborated on these ideas of using representatives, special officers, regional meetings, and modern media elsewhere
    • Even though plaintiffs will have already filed their complaints, Rule 15 permits liberal amendments "when justice so requires." FED. R. CIV. P. 15(a). For the interested reader, I have elaborated on these ideas of using representatives, special officers, regional meetings, and modern media elsewhere.
    • Fed. R. Civ. P. , pp. 15
  • 204
    • 79956146604 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 13. I have also noted that if the categories of claimants truly want to pursue disparate and fundamentally incompatible ends, then we may need to consider either certifying a Rule 23(b)(2) class if injunctive or declaratory judgments would subject the defendant to incompatible judgments or disaggregating into smaller litigation groups
    • Burch, Litigating Together, supra note 13. I have also noted that if the categories of claimants truly want to pursue disparate and fundamentally incompatible ends, then we may need to consider either certifying a Rule 23(b)(2) class if injunctive or declaratory judgments would subject the defendant to incompatible judgments or disaggregating into smaller litigation groups.
    • Litigating Together
    • Burch1
  • 207
    • 61349108040 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Making class actions work: The untapped potential of the internet
    • 763-64
    • Robert H. Klonoff et al., Making Class Actions Work: The Untapped Potential of the Internet, 69 U. PITT. L. REV. 727, 763-64 (2008).
    • (2008) U. Pitt. L. Rev. , vol.69 , pp. 727
    • Klonoff, R.H.1
  • 208
    • 79956109254 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., supra note 61
    • See, e.g., DWORKIN, supra note 61
    • Dworkin1
  • 210
    • 79956100806 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 107
    • PAGE, supra note 107
    • Page1
  • 211
    • 79956081077 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 15, at
    • RAWLS, supra note 15, at 358-59
    • Rawls1
  • 212
    • 79956134639 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 107
    • RHEINGOLD, supra note 107
    • Rheingold1
  • 213
    • 79956089893 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 107
    • SUROWIECKI, supra note 107
    • Surowiecki1
  • 214
    • 0000673282 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Democracy and liberty
    • Jon Elster ed
    • Joshua Cohen, Democracy and Liberty, in DELIBERATIVE DEMOCRACY (Jon Elster ed., 1998)
    • (1998) Deliberative Democracy
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 215
    • 79956077454 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 96, at
    • Dryzek, supra note 96, at 652
    • Dryzek1
  • 216
    • 85050417329 scopus 로고
    • Who's afraid of deliberative democracy? on the strategic/deliberative dichotomy in recent constitutional jurisprudence
    • David M. Estlund, Who's Afraid of Deliberative Democracy? On the Strategic/Deliberative Dichotomy in Recent Constitutional Jurisprudence, 71 TEX. L. REV. 1437 (1993)
    • (1993) Tex. L. Rev. , vol.71 , pp. 1437
    • Estlund, D.M.1
  • 217
    • 79956074853 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 96, at
    • Solum, supra note 96, at 277-82
    • Solum1
  • 218
    • 84970763608 scopus 로고
    • The wisdom of the multitude: Some reflections on book 3, chapter 11 of aristotle's politics
    • Jeremy Waldron, the Wisdom of the Multitude: Some Reflections on Book 3, Chapter 11 of Aristotle's Politics, 23 POL. THEORY 563 (1995).
    • (1995) Pol. theory , vol.23 , pp. 563
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 219
    • 0013315511 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deliberative trouble? Why groups go to extremes
    • See 73 (describing the ideal of "deliberative democracy" but arguing that such an ideal is not empirically confirmed)
    • See Cass R. Sunstein, Deliberative Trouble? Why Groups Go to Extremes, 110 YALE L.J. 71, 73 (2000) (describing the ideal of "deliberative democracy" but arguing that such an ideal is not empirically confirmed).
    • (2000) Yale L.J. , vol.110 , pp. 71
    • Sunstein, C.R.1
  • 220
    • 79956092423 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 98, at (describing the challenges of collective decisionmaking as well as Kenneth Arrow's work on cycling)
    • See Issacharoff, supra note 98, at 257-58 (describing the challenges of collective decisionmaking as well as Kenneth Arrow's work on cycling)
    • Issacharoff1
  • 223
    • 79956139501 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 120, at As Sunstein explains, the Internet may serve "as a breeding ground for extremism" if the discussion group allows participants to post anonymously
    • See Sunstein, supra note 120, at 74-75. As Sunstein explains, the Internet may serve "as a breeding ground for extremism" if the discussion group allows participants to post anonymously.
    • Sunstein1
  • 224
    • 79956115303 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 101.
  • 225
    • 79956132608 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 107, at (observing that depolarization occurs where equally opposed subgroups are put together and that "the group judgment will move toward the middle")
    • See SUNSTEIN, supra note 107, at 134 (observing that depolarization occurs where equally opposed subgroups are put together and that "the group judgment will move toward the middle").
    • Sunstein1
  • 227
    • 79956079080 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 7, at
    • See Erichson, supra note 7, at 982-83.
    • Erichson1
  • 228
    • 79956147920 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This inquiry is analogous to procedural unconscionability in contract law
    • This inquiry is analogous to procedural unconscionability in contract law.
  • 229
    • 79956063574 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See §
    • See U.C.C. § 2-302 (2005)
    • (2005) U.C.C. , pp. 2302
  • 231
    • 84877715220 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ingle v. Circuit City Stores, Inc., 1170-73 9th Cir. (distinguishing between procedural and substantive unconscionability and suggesting a sliding-scale approach)
    • Ingle v. Circuit City Stores, Inc., 328 F.3D 1165, 1170-73 (9th Cir. 2003) (distinguishing between procedural and substantive unconscionability and suggesting a sliding-scale approach)
    • (2003) F.3D , vol.328 , pp. 1165
  • 232
    • 79956095218 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Harris v. Green Tree Fin. Corp. 181 3D Cir. ("Procedural unconscionability pertains to the process by which an agreement is reached and the form of an agreement, including the use therein of fine print and convoluted or unclear language.")
    • Harris v. Green Tree Fin. Corp., 183 F.3D 173, 181 (3D Cir. 1999) ("Procedural unconscionability pertains to the process by which an agreement is reached and the form of an agreement, including the use therein of fine print and convoluted or unclear language.").
    • (1999) F.3D , vol.183 , pp. 173
  • 233
    • 84882257995 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See In re Combustion Eng'g, 239 3D Cir. (referring to the Bankruptcy Code's policy of "equality of distribution among creditors" and requiring "similar treatment to similarly situated claims"). This inquiry is somewhat akin to substantive unconscionability in contract doctrine, that is, the notion that certain contractual terms are so one-sided under the circumstances that they "shock the conscience
    • See In re Combustion Eng'g, 391 F.3D 190, 239 (3D Cir. 2004) (referring to the Bankruptcy Code's policy of "equality of distribution among creditors" and requiring "similar treatment to similarly situated claims"). This inquiry is somewhat akin to substantive unconscionability in contract doctrine, that is, the notion that certain contractual terms are so one-sided under the circumstances that they "shock the conscience.
    • (2004) F.3D , vol.391 , pp. 190
  • 234
    • 79956076412 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ingle
    • Ingle, 328 F.3D at 1172
    • F.3D , vol.328 , pp. 1172
  • 235
    • 79956114257 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also (explaining that "[s]ubstantive unconscionability refers to contractual terms that are unreasonably or grossly favorable to one side")
    • see also Harris, 183 F.3D at 181 (explaining that "[s]ubstantive unconscionability refers to contractual terms that are unreasonably or grossly favorable to one side").
    • F.3D , vol.183 , pp. 181
    • Harris1
  • 236
    • 79956060920 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 15, at
    • See SANDEL, supra note 15, at 106.
    • Sandel1
  • 239
    • 79956085678 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 15, at
    • RAWLS, supra note 15, at 345-47.
    • Rawls1
  • 240
    • 79956158315 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 15, at
    • See SANDEL, supra note 15, at 106-07.
    • Sandel1
  • 241
    • 79955572905 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • § (e) (incorporated by reference in § 3.18(a))
    • PRINCIPLES OF THE LAW OF AGGREGATE LITIG. § 3.17(e) (2010) (incorporated by reference in § 3.18(a))
    • (2010) Principles of the Law of Aggregate Litig. , pp. 317
  • 242
    • 79956081076 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see infra note 138
    • see infra note 138.
  • 244
    • 79955572905 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • the ALI suggests that judges consider: [T]he timing of the agreement, the sophistication of the claimants, the information disclosed to the claimants, whether the terms of the settlement were reviewed by a neutral or special master as defined in § 3.09 (a)(2), whether the claimants have some prior common relationship, and whether the claims of the claimants are similar. § (d) (incorporated by reference in § 3.18(a))
    • the ALI suggests that judges consider: [T]he timing of the agreement, the sophistication of the claimants, the information disclosed to the claimants, whether the terms of the settlement were reviewed by a neutral or special master as defined in § 3.09(a)(2), whether the claimants have some prior common relationship, and whether the claims of the claimants are similar. PRINCIPLES OF THE LAW OF AGGREGATE LITIG. § 3.17(d) (2010) (incorporated by reference in § 3.18(a)).
    • (2010) Principles of the Law of Aggregate Litig. , pp. 317
  • 245
    • 79956064547 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 15, at
    • RAWLS, supra note 15, at 85-86.
    • Rawls1
  • 246
  • 249
    • 79956118404 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Section 3.18 refers back to section 3.17(e), which makes "whether the claimants are treated equitably (relative to each other) based on their facts and circumstances" a substantive consideration. § (e). I am not sure that this interpersonal concern is necessarily a substantive one. For example, if one of the Drug-D claimants feels that she has a good claim (strong causation evidence and suffered a heart attack) and that this claim is worth far more than what the defendant offers, that is a matter of alleged substantive unfairness. If, on the other hand, she has to take the offer because her attorney forces her to sign the settlement at gunpoint, then that is a matter of procedural unfairness. But if she acknowledges that she receives the going market rate for a heart attack (assuming it could be established), but objects that others are receiving more for similar injuries, it is not obvious to me whether this is a complaint about substantive or procedural unfairness
    • Section 3.18 refers back to section 3.17(e), which makes "whether the claimants are treated equitably (relative to each other) based on their facts and circumstances" a substantive consideration. Id. § 3.17(e). I am not sure that this interpersonal concern is necessarily a substantive one. For example, if one of the Drug-D claimants feels that she has a good claim (strong causation evidence and suffered a heart attack) and that this claim is worth far more than what the defendant offers, that is a matter of alleged substantive unfairness. If, on the other hand, she has to take the offer because her attorney forces her to sign the settlement at gunpoint, then that is a matter of procedural unfairness. But if she acknowledges that she receives the going market rate for a heart attack (assuming it could be established), but objects that others are receiving more for similar injuries, it is not obvious to me whether this is a complaint about substantive or procedural unfairness.
  • 250
    • 33646064394 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The concept of equality in civil procedure
    • See 1893-97 (explaining the problems created when "like cases" are not "treated alike")
    • See William B. Rubenstein, the Concept of Equality in Civil Procedure, 23 CARDOZO L. REV. 1865, 1893-97 (2002) (explaining the problems created when "like cases" are not "treated alike").
    • (2002) Cardozo L. Rev. , vol.23 , pp. 1865
    • Rubenstein, W.B.1
  • 251
    • 79956121711 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For one view of how equality and community might intertwine, see supra note 61, at ("[Communities] may be structured, even hierarchical, in the way a family is, but the structure and hierarchy must reflect the group's assumption that its roles and rules are equally in the interests of all, that no one's life is more important than anyone else's.")
    • For one view of how equality and community might intertwine, see DWORKIN, supra note 61, at 200-01 ("[Communities] may be structured, even hierarchical, in the way a family is, but the structure and hierarchy must reflect the group's assumption that its roles and rules are equally in the interests of all, that no one's life is more important than anyone else's.").
    • Dworkin1
  • 252
    • 79956131348 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 15, at (emphasis omitted)
    • SANDEL, supra note 15, at 106 (emphasis omitted).
    • Sandel1
  • 253
    • 79956127652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., supra note 25, at
    • See, e.g., FRIED, supra note 25, at 104-06
    • Fried1
  • 254
    • 0347736395 scopus 로고
    • A reexamination of nonsubstantive unconscionability
    • 1071-76
    • Alan Schwartz, A Reexamination of Nonsubstantive Unconscionability, 63 VA. L. REV. 1053, 1071-76 (1977).
    • (1977) Va. L. Rev. , vol.63 , pp. 1053
    • Schwartz, A.1
  • 255
    • 10844289838 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paternalism, unconscionability doctrine, and accommodation
    • 224
    • Seana Valentine Shiffrin, Paternalism, Unconscionability Doctrine, and Accommodation, 29 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 205, 224 (2000).
    • (2000) Phil. & Pub. Aff. , vol.29 , pp. 205
    • Shiffrin, S.V.1
  • 257
    • 0002563028 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Endogenous preferences: The cultural consequences of markets and other economic institutions
    • See
    • See Samuel Bowles, Endogenous Preferences: The Cultural Consequences of Markets and Other Economic Institutions, 36 J. ECON. LITERATURE 75 (1998).
    • (1998) J. Econ. Literature , vol.36 , pp. 75
    • Bowles, S.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.