메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 123, Issue 1, 2009, Pages 4-72

Foreword: System effects and the constitution

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 76449121052     PISSN: 0017811X     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (71)

References (287)
  • 1
    • 0004163153 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This definition is adapted, with major modifications, from ROBERT JERVIS, SYSTEM EFFECTS 6 (1997).
    • (1997) System Effects , pp. 6
    • Jervis, R.1
  • 2
    • 0003347562 scopus 로고
    • Essay on the application of mathematics to the theory of decision-making
    • Keith Michael Baker ed.
    • See MARQUIS DE CONDORCET, Essay on the Application of Mathematics to the Theory of Decision-Making, in CONDORCET SELECTED WRITINGS 33, 52-55 (Keith Michael Baker ed., 1976).
    • (1976) Condorcet Selected Writings , vol.33 , pp. 52-55
    • De Condorcet, M.1
  • 3
    • 60949086046 scopus 로고
    • The one and the many: Adjudication in collegial courts
    • 10-12
    • See Lewis A. Kornhauser & Lawrence G. Sager, The One and the Many: Adjudication in Collegial Courts, 81 CAL. L. REV. 1, 10-12 (1993).
    • (1993) Cal. L. Rev. , vol.81 , pp. 1
    • Kornhauser, L.A.1    Sager, L.G.2
  • 4
    • 24944513437 scopus 로고
    • The supreme court, 1958 term-foreword: The time-chart of the justices
    • 84
    • As in some other Forewords, the past Term's cases will not be the focus. See, e. g., Henry M. Hart, Jr., The Supreme Court, 1958 Term-Foreword: The Time-Chart of the Justices, 73 HARV. L. REV. 84, 84 (1959) ("This Foreword departs from the pattern of most of its predecessors by addressing itself not to any especially noteworthy decisions or events of the past term but rather to problems of the Court's administration which are common to every term . . . .").
    • (1959) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.73 , pp. 84
    • Hart Jr., H.M.1
  • 5
    • 0000351211 scopus 로고
    • The origin and scope of the American doctrine of constitutional law
    • 144
    • See James B. Thayer, The Origin and Scope of the American Doctrine of Constitutional Law, 7 HARV. L. REV. 129, 144 (1893).
    • (1893) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.7 , pp. 129
    • Thayer, J.B.1
  • 6
    • 0003741603 scopus 로고
    • For formal renditions of these fallacies, with social science applications, see JON ELSTER, LOGIC AND SOCIETY 97-106 (1978). Philosophers of logic have identified several subcases, in which the fallacies can rest on either semantic, conceptual, or causal mistakes.
    • (1978) Logic and Society , pp. 97-106
    • Elster, J.O.N.1
  • 7
    • 76449115118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., id. at 98-103
    • See, e.g., id. at 98-103;
  • 8
    • 76449114283 scopus 로고
    • The fallacy of composition
    • 89-91
    • William L. Rowe, The Fallacy of Composition, 71 MIND 87, 89-91 (1962). For the most part, my examples fall into the latter two categories; in any event, the philosophical refinements are not material for my purposes.
    • (1962) Mind , vol.71 , pp. 87
    • Rowe, W.L.1
  • 9
    • 0041920709 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The irrelevance of constitutional amendments
    • Alternatively, although I will not pursue the issue, the primitives of the system might themselves be propositions of fact, morality, or law. In the best case, a system effect arises when a set of legal provisions has properties that differ from the properties of some or all of its individual members. It has been argued, for example, that the possibility of constitutional amendment is systematically irrelevant. The failure of the Equal Rights Amendment (ERA) made no difference, on this view, because the Supreme Court read the ERA's content into the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment; the latter subsumed the former. See David A. Strauss, The Irrelevance of Constitutional Amendments, 114 HARV. L. REV. 1457 (2001). However, putting aside the possibility that would-be amendments are subsumed by provisions of the original Constitution, it is a fallacy of composition to argue that because any given amendment might in this fashion be shown to be irrelevant, all amendments can be shown to be irrelevant simultaneously. At least one amendment must be in place and be efficacious in order to subsume the others; in the example above, the Fourteenth Amendment plays that role.
    • (2001) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.114 , pp. 1457
    • Strauss, D.A.1
  • 10
    • 84926971589 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constitutional amendments and the constitutional common law
    • Richard W. Bauman & Tsvi Kahana eds.
    • For a more extended treatment, see Adrian Vermeule, Constitutional Amendments and the Constitutional Common Law, in THE LEAST EXAMINED BRANCH: THE ROLE OF LEGISLATURES IN THE CONSTITUTIONAL STATE 229, 231-242 (Richard W. Bauman & Tsvi Kahana eds., 2006).
    • (2006) The Least Examined Branch: The Role of Legislatures in the Constitutional State , vol.229 , pp. 231-242
    • Vermeule, A.1
  • 13
    • 76449086626 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Andrew Skinner ed., Penguin Books 1776
    • ADAM SMITH, THE WEALTH OF NATIONS: BOOKS IV-V 32 (Andrew Skinner ed., Penguin Books 1999) (1776).
    • (1999) The Wealth of Nations: Books , vol.4-5 , pp. 32
    • Smith, A.1
  • 15
    • 47349096245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The free rider problem
    • Russell Hardin, The Free Rider Problem, in STANFORD ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY (2003), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2009/entries/free- rider.
    • (2003) Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
    • Hardin, R.1
  • 16
    • 76449118810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See CONDORCET, supra note 2, at 52-56.
    • See CONDORCET, supra note 2, at 52-56.
  • 17
    • 57349104663 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Public choice defended
    • 784
    • See Saul Levmore, Public Choice Defended, 72 U. CHI. L. REV. 777, 784 (2005)
    • (2005) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.72 , pp. 777
    • Levmore, S.1
  • 20
    • 0002139585 scopus 로고
    • Popular representation and the distribution of information
    • John A. Ferejohn & James H. Kuklinski eds.
    • See Philip E. Converse, Popular Representation and the Distribution of Information, in INFORMATION AND DEMOCRATIC PROCESSES 369, 381-382 (John A. Ferejohn & James H. Kuklinski eds., 1990).
    • (1990) Information and Democratic Processes , vol.369 , pp. 381-382
    • Converse, P.E.1
  • 22
    • 76449105167 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See CONDORCET, supra note 2, at 48-49
    • See CONDORCET, supra note 2, at 48-49.
  • 23
    • 0000721263 scopus 로고
    • Thirteen theorems in search of the truth
    • 271
    • In fact, so long as the distribution of competence is symmetric around the mean in a group with three voters, the Theorem can hold so long as the average chance of getting the right answer is greater than 0.471. See Bernard Grofman et al., Thirteen Theorems in Search of the Truth, 15 THEORY & DECISION 261, 271 (1983).
    • (1983) Theory & Decision , vol.15 , pp. 261
    • Grofman, B.1
  • 24
    • 76449100030 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See CONDORCET, supra note 2, at 49
    • See CONDORCET, supra note 2, at 49.
  • 26
    • 84935546166 scopus 로고
    • The condorcet jury theorem, free speech, and correlated votes
    • 625-30
    • Krishna K. Ladha, The Condorcet Jury Theorem, Free Speech, and Correlated Votes, 36 AM. J. POL. SCI. 617, 625-30 (1992).
    • (1992) Am. J. Pol. Sci. , vol.36 , pp. 617
    • Ladha, K.K.1
  • 27
    • 76449103886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Ladha, supra note 21, at 625-630
    • See Ladha, supra note 21, at 625-630
  • 28
    • 49749096004 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The new legal realism
    • For a survey of the literature, see generally Thomas J. Miles & Cass R. Sunstein, The New Legal Realism, 75 U. CHI. L. REV. 831 (2008).
    • (2008) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.75 , pp. 831
    • Miles, T.J.1    Sunstein, C.R.2
  • 29
    • 84922242112 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Collective wisdom: Lessons from the theory of judgment aggregation
    • Hélène Landemore & Jon Elster eds., forthcoming (manuscript at 6 tbl.2)
    • Christian List, Collective Wisdom: Lessons from the Theory of Judgment Aggregation, in COLLECTIVE WISDOM (Hélène Landemore & Jon Elster eds., forthcoming) (manuscript at 6 tbl.2), available at http://personal.lse.ac.uk/LIST/pdf-files/CollectiveWisdom19Oct.pdf.
    • Collective Wisdom
    • List, C.1
  • 30
    • 84928450283 scopus 로고
    • Unpacking the court
    • 102-105
    • See Lewis A. Kornhauser & Lawrence G. Sager, Unpacking the Court, 96 YALE L.J. 82, 102-105 (1986).
    • (1986) Yale L.J. , vol.96 , pp. 82
    • Kornhauser, L.A.1    Sager, L.G.2
  • 31
    • 0012547007 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aggregating sets of judgments: An impossibility result
    • 96-100 considering procedures that meet the following criteria: universal domain, anonymity and systematicity
    • See Christian List & Philip Pettit, Aggregating Sets of Judgments: An Impossibility Result, 18 ECON. & PHIL. 89, 96-100 (2002) (considering procedures that meet the following criteria: universal domain, anonymity and systematicity).
    • (2002) Econ. & Phil. , vol.18 , pp. 89
    • List, C.1    Pettit, P.2
  • 32
    • 70450162442 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legal doctrine on collégial courts
    • 957-958
    • See Dimitri Landa & Jeffrey R. Lax, Legal Doctrine on Collégial Courts, 71 J. POL. 946, 957-958 (2009).
    • (2009) J. Pol. , vol.71 , pp. 946
    • Landa, D.1    Lax, J.R.2
  • 33
    • 76449103142 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 34
    • 0003350907 scopus 로고
    • Ways of criticizing the court
    • 815-817
    • See Frank H. Easterbrook, Ways of Criticizing the Court, 95 HARV. L. REV. 802, 815-817 (1982).
    • (1982) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.95 , pp. 802
    • Easterbrook, F.H.1
  • 35
    • 76449106279 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 817-821
    • See id. at 817-821
  • 36
    • 84868188774 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ("Majority voting plus stare decisis is thus a formula under which the Court may produce any outcome favored by any number of Justices, however small, even though a majority of Justices would reject that rule ... on the basis of first principles." Id. at 819.)
    • ("Majority voting plus stare decisis is thus a formula under which the Court may produce any outcome favored by any number of Justices, however small, even though a majority of Justices would reject that rule ... on the basis of first principles." Id. at 819.).
  • 38
    • 0011674694 scopus 로고
    • stating that the libertarian thesis "tells us to be equally suspicious of all sources of law
    • See DANIEL A. FARBER & PHILIP P. FRICKEY, LAW AND PUBLIC CHOICE 55 (1991) (stating that the libertarian thesis "tells us to be equally suspicious of all sources of law").
    • (1991) Law and Public Choice , pp. 55
    • Farber, D.A.1    Frickey, P.P.2
  • 40
    • 76449096841 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 53
    • See id. at 53.
  • 41
    • 84868176512 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stearns's definition of the fallacy -as "the assumption that if phenomenon X produces result Y, more of phenomenon X will necessarily produce more of result Y," id. -is nonstandard and would be more apt as a definition of an increasing function. However, the substance of Stearns's point holds straightforwardly, given the definition used here.
    • Stearns's definition of the fallacy -as "the assumption that if phenomenon X produces result Y, more of phenomenon X will necessarily produce more of result Y," id. -is nonstandard and would be more apt as a definition of an increasing function. However, the substance of Stearns's point holds straightforwardly, given the definition used here.
  • 42
    • 0000388293 scopus 로고
    • Bicameralism: When are two decisions better than one?
    • 147
    • Saul Levmore, Bicameralism: When Are Two Decisions Better than One?, 12 INT'L REV. L. & ECON. 145, 147 (1992).
    • (1992) Int'l Rev. L. & Econ. , vol.12 , pp. 145
    • Levmore, S.1
  • 43
    • 84963082747 scopus 로고
    • The general theory of second best
    • See generally R. G. Lipsey & R. K. Lancaster, The General Theory of Second Best, 24 REV. ECON. STUD, 11 (1956).
    • (1956) Rev. Econ. Stud , vol.24 , pp. 11
    • Lipsey, R.G.1    Lancaster, R.K.2
  • 44
    • 76449118809 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 11-12
    • Id. at 11-12.
  • 45
    • 76449095592 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 46
    • 0041878195 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Courts, legislatures, and the general theory of second best in law and economics
    • 204-207
    • For a similar example, see Thomas S. Ulen, Courts, Legislatures, and the General Theory of Second Best in Law and Economics, 73 CHI-KENT L. REV. 189, 204-207 (1998).
    • (1998) Chi-Kent L. Rev. , vol.73 , pp. 189
    • Ulen, T.S.1
  • 47
    • 0040828272 scopus 로고
    • Ideals and second bests
    • Seymour Fox ed.
    • The general theory of second best also shows that it is not necessarily best for the relevant variables to approach their optimal values as closely as possible, assuming that at least one such variable does not reach the optimum. This mistake has been called the "approximation assump-tion." Avishai Margalit, Ideals and Second Bests, in PHILOSOPHY FOR EDUCATION 77, 77 (Seymour Fox ed., 1983).
    • (1983) Philosophy for Education , vol.77 , pp. 77
    • Margalit, A.1
  • 48
    • 44449166753 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constitutional possibilities
    • 311-12, 327-328
    • For illuminating discussions of the second best in legal theory, see Lawrence B. Solum, Constitutional Possibilities, 83 IND. L. J. 307, 311-12, 327-328 (2008);
    • (2008) Ind. L. J. , vol.83 , pp. 307
    • Solum, L.B.1
  • 49
    • 76449087650 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Ulen, supra note 39, at 208-219
    • and Ulen, supra note 39, at 208-219
  • 51
    • 76449119720 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Second best theories and the implications for institutional design
    • Robert E. Goodin ed.
    • Bruce Talbot Coram, Second Best Theories and the Implications for Institutional Design, in THE THEORY OF INSTITUTIONAL DESIGN 90, 90-95 (Robert E. Goodin ed., 1996);
    • (1996) The Theory of Institutional Design , vol.90 , pp. 90-95
    • Coram, B.T.1
  • 52
    • 84975992288 scopus 로고
    • Political ideals and political practice
    • 52-55
    • and Robert E. Goodin, Political Ideals and Political Practice, 25 BRIT. J. POL. SCI. 37, 52-55 (1995).
    • (1995) Brit. J. Pol. Sci. , vol.25 , pp. 37
    • Goodin, R.E.1
  • 53
    • 63849214457 scopus 로고
    • Ian Scott-Kilvert trans., Penguin Books
    • POLYBIUS, THE RISE OF THE ROMAN EMPIRE 312-318 (Ian Scott-Kilvert trans., Penguin Books 1979).
    • (1979) Polybius, The Rise of the Roman Empire , pp. 312-318
  • 54
    • 76449088881 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ELSTER, supra note 41, at 440
    • ELSTER, supra note 41, at 440.
  • 57
    • 84868176514 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also ELSTER, supra note 41, at 440 (describing the rule of the Ottomans, the tsars in Russia, Mussolini in Italy, and Franco in Spain as "despotism tempered by incompetence" (internal quotation marks omitted))
    • see also ELSTER, supra note 41, at 440 (describing the rule of the Ottomans, the tsars in Russia, Mussolini in Italy, and Franco in Spain as "despotism tempered by incompetence" (internal quotation marks omitted)).
  • 58
    • 79954162162 scopus 로고
    • Of the independency of parliament
    • Eugene F. Miller ed., Liberty Fund 1777
    • See DAVID HUME, Of the Independency of Parliament, in ESSAYS: MORAL, POLITICAL, AND LITERARY 42, 44-45 (Eugene F. Miller ed., Liberty Fund 1985) (1777).
    • (1985) Essays: Moral, Political, and Literary , vol.42 , pp. 44-45
    • Hume, D.1
  • 59
    • 22044442624 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That politics may be reduced to a science
    • supra note 45, 18
    • DAVID HUME, That Politics May Be Reduced to a Science, in ESSAYS: MORAL, POLITICAL, AND LITERARY, supra note 45, at 14, 18. The substance of Hume's reasoning is flawed, because in a hereditary monarchy the prospect of a crown may induce attempts to overthrow the reigning family through intrigue or violence.
    • Essays: Moral, Political, and Literary , pp. 14
    • Hume, D.1
  • 60
    • 76449104733 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • "Their Laws and Clothes were equally Objects of Mutability; For, what was well done for a time, In half a Year became a Crime; Yet while they alter'd thus their Laws, Still finding and correcting Flaws, They mended by Inconstancy Faults, which no Prudence could foresee." MANDEVILLE, supra note 9, at 28.
  • 62
    • 0042578750 scopus 로고
    • The rise and rise of the administrative state
    • 1252-53
    • Gary Lawson, The Rise and Rise of the Administrative State, 107 HARV. L. REV. 1231, 1252-53 (1994)
    • (1994) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.107 , pp. 1231
    • Lawson, G.1
  • 63
    • 21844493006 scopus 로고
    • Mistakes, precedent and the rise of the administrative state: Toward a constitutional theory of the second best
    • 30-39
    • (citing Peter B. McCutchen, Mistakes, Precedent and the Rise of the Administrative State: Toward a Constitutional Theory of the Second Best, 80 CORNELL L. REV. 1, 30-39 (1994)).
    • (1994) Cornell L. Rev. , vol.80 , pp. 1
    • McCutchen, P.B.1
  • 64
    • 0041557883 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The most dangerous branch
    • 1828-1839
    • See Martin S. Flaherty, The Most Dangerous Branch, 105 YALE L. J. 1725, 1828-1839 (1996);
    • (1996) Yale L. J. , vol.105 , pp. 1725
    • Flaherty, M.S.1
  • 65
    • 84937308408 scopus 로고
    • Checks and balances in an era of presidential lawmaking
    • 155
    • Abner S. Greene, Checks and Balances in an Era of Presidential Lawmaking, 61 U. CHI. L. REV. 123, 155 (1994).
    • (1994) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.61 , pp. 123
    • Greene, A.S.1
  • 66
    • 0042028060 scopus 로고
    • Some normative arguments for the unitary executive
    • 78-81
    • See Steven G. Calabresi, Some Normative Arguments for the Unitary Executive, 48 ARK. L. REV. 23, 78-81 (1995);
    • (1995) Ark. L. Rev. , vol.48 , pp. 23
    • Calabresi, S.G.1
  • 67
    • 26444577629 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The new majoritarianism
    • 121-122
    • Robert Justin Lipkin, The New Majoritarianism, 69 U. CIN. L. REV. 107, 121-122 (2000).
    • (2000) U. Cin. L. Rev. , vol.69 , pp. 107
    • Lipkin, R.J.1
  • 68
    • 69249136821 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The new separation of powers
    • 656-57
    • See Bruce Ackerman, The New Separation of Powers, 113 HARV. L. REV. 633, 656-57 (2000). There are significant scholarly controversies about whether presidentialism makes democracy unstable and whether proportional representation or fragmentation of parties also plays a role.
    • (2000) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.113 , pp. 633
    • Ackerman, B.1
  • 69
    • 33750210202 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., JOSE ANTONIO CHEIBUB, PRESIDENTIALISM, PARLIAMENTARIANISM, AND DEMOCRACY (2007). For present purposes, the substance of these controversies is irrelevant; what matters is the structure of the second-best argument described above.
    • (2007) Presidentialism, Parliamentarianism, and Democracy
    • Cheibub, J.A.1
  • 70
    • 0003958303 scopus 로고
    • This is Duverger's Law. See Barbara North & Robert North trans., John Wiley & Sons 3d Eng. ed., rev. 1951
    • This is Duverger's Law. See MAURICE DUVERGER, POLITICAL PARTIES: THEIR ORGANIZATION AND ACTIVITY IN THE MODERN STATE 217 (Barbara North & Robert North trans., John Wiley & Sons 3d Eng. ed., rev. 1963) (1951).
    • (1963) Political Parties: Their Organization and Activity in the Modern State , pp. 217
    • Duverger, M.1
  • 72
    • 0011527688 scopus 로고
    • The president and the administration
    • 2-3
    • See Lawrence Lessig & Cass R. Sunstein, The President and the Administration, 94 COLUM. L. REV. 1, 2-3 (1994).
    • (1994) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.94 , pp. 1
    • Lessig, L.1    Sunstein, C.R.2
  • 73
    • 76449098162 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 81-87, 97-101
    • Id. at 81-87, 97-101.
  • 74
    • 76449083823 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ELSTER, supra note 41, at 439
    • ELSTER, supra note 41, at 439.
  • 76
    • 67650529572 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Media incentives and national security secrets
    • For an illuminating critique, see Note, Media Incentives and National Security Secrets, 122 HARV. L. REV. 2228 (2009).
    • (2009) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.122 , pp. 2228
  • 77
    • 76449103508 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This seems to be Bickel's implicit argument. See BICKEL, supra note 58, at 81-87
    • This seems to be Bickel's implicit argument. See BICKEL, supra note 58, at 81-87.
  • 78
    • 0039154936 scopus 로고
    • London, MacMillan & Co.
    • See JAMES FITZJAMES STEPHEN, A GENERAL VIEW OF THE CRIMINAL LAW OF ENGLAND 166 (London, MacMillan & Co. 1863) (arguing that although "the inquisitorial theory of criminal procedure is beyond all question the true one," nonetheless "it may be and probably is, the case, that in our own time and country, the best manner of conducting such an inquiry is to consider the trial mainly as a litigation and to allow each party to say all that can be said in support of their own view").
    • (1863) A General View of the Criminal Law of England , pp. 166
    • Stephen, J.F.1
  • 79
    • 0000098233 scopus 로고
    • Originalism: The lesser evil
    • 864
    • See Antonin Scalia, Originalism: The Lesser Evil, 57 U. CIN. L. REV. 849, 864 (1989).
    • (1989) U. Cin. L. Rev. , vol.57 , pp. 849
    • Scalia, A.1
  • 80
    • 76449087837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 81
    • 77954490901 scopus 로고
    • Fidelity in translation
    • 1171-73, 1189-1192
    • See Lawrence Lessig, Fidelity in Translation, 71 TEX. L. REV. 1165, 1171-73, 1189-1192 (1993).
    • (1993) Tex. L. Rev. , vol.71 , pp. 1165
    • Lessig, L.1
  • 82
    • 0040373276 scopus 로고
    • Translating federalism: United States v. Lopez
    • Lawrence Lessig, Translating Federalism: United States v. Lopez, 1995 SUP. CT. REV. 125, 193.
    • (1995) Sup. Ct. Rev. , vol.125 , pp. 193
    • Lessig, L.1
  • 83
    • 85081729421 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Feb. 9, unpublished manuscript, on file with the Harvard Law School Library
    • At least if we bracket the possibility that the analyst is engaged in what David Estlund calls "hopeless aspirational theory." Such analysts, Estlund argues, can ignore problems of the second best. See David Estlund, Utopophobia (Feb. 9, 2009) (unpublished manuscript, on file with the Harvard Law School Library). I will put aside the possibility of hopeless theorizing in what follows.
    • (2009) Utopophobia
    • Estlund, D.1
  • 84
    • 84893327878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Clinton Rossiter ed.
    • THE FEDERALIST NO. 51, at 318-319 (James Madison) (Clinton Rossiter ed., 1999).
    • (1999) The Federalist No. 51 , pp. 318-319
    • Madison, J.1
  • 85
    • 20744460634 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Adam Smith's reception among the American founders, 1776-1790
    • For analyses of Adam Smith's influence on Madison, see Samuel Fleischacker, Adam Smith's Reception Among the American Founders, 1776-1790, 59 WM. & MARY Q. 897 (2002);
    • (2002) Wm. & Mary Q. , vol.59 , pp. 897
    • Fleischacker, S.1
  • 86
    • 4544258591 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The invisible hand of James Madison
    • and David Prindle, The Invisible Hand of James Madison, 15 CONST. POL. ECON. 223 (2004).
    • (2004) Const. Pol. Econ. , vol.15 , pp. 223
    • Prindle, D.1
  • 87
    • 0040090642 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The invisible hand and the cunning of reason
    • 182
    • Edna Ullmann-Margalit, The Invisible Hand and the Cunning of Reason, 64 SOC. RES. 181, 182 (1997).
    • (1997) Soc. Res. , vol.64 , pp. 181
    • Ullmann-Margalit, E.1
  • 88
    • 76449090102 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Prindle, supra note 67, at 231-234
    • Prindle, supra note 67, at 231-234
  • 90
    • 76449084447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • However, it is not necessary that all institutions act to promote their institutional ambitions. If (say) the President and the Congress are relentlessly self-promoting as institutions, while the Court decides on the merits of particular cases, then the ambitions of the first two institutions may cancel each other out, allowing the public interest to emerge. The general theory of second best does not entail that lack of universal public-spiritedness must necessarily yield bad results, only that it can do so. (This example is structurally analogous to the miracle of aggregation, discussed supra section I.A.4(a), pp. 12-13)
  • 91
    • 76449119312 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Structurally similar puzzles arise in many other legal contexts in which invisible-hand reasoning is invoked. To mention only one example, an adversarial system of litigation is often justified on the ground that biased presentation by competing parties is the best mechanism for producing truth overall. See STEPHEN, supra note 60, at 166. In criminal litigation, however, it is also a legal shibboleth that the prosecutor's obligation is to "seek[| truth and not victims."
  • 92
    • 76449093689 scopus 로고
    • The federal prosecutor, address at the second annual conference of United States attorneys (Apr. 1, 1940)
    • John Jay Douglass ed.
    • Robert H. Jackson, The Federal Prosecutor, Address at the Second Annual Conference of United States Attorneys (Apr. 1, 1940), in NAT'L COLL. OF DIST. ATT'YS, ETHICAL CONSIDERATIONS IN PROSECUTION 2, 4 (John Jay Douglass ed., 1977). Yet if the prosecutor seeks truth while the defendant pursues adversarial advantage, the defendant's interests may in effect be doublecounted. This asymmetric role morality can be justified, if at all, only on extrinsic grounds.
    • (1977) Nat'l Coll. of Dist. Att'ys, Ethical Considerations in Prosecution , vol.2 , pp. 4
    • Jackson, R.H.1
  • 93
    • 76449115117 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • unpublished manuscript, on file with the Harvard Law School Library
    • For a discussion of such problems, see Adrian Vermeule, The Invisible Hand in Legal Theory (2009) (unpublished manuscript, on file with the Harvard Law School Library).
    • (2009) The Invisible Hand in Legal Theory
    • Vermeule, A.1
  • 94
    • 13244256992 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Empire-building government in constitutional law
    • 923-937
    • See Daryl J. Levinson, Empire-Building Government in Constitutional Law, 118 HARV. L. REV. 915, 923-937 (2005).
    • (2005) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.118 , pp. 915
    • Levinson, D.J.1
  • 96
    • 76449104107 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Levinson, supra note 73, at 920
    • See Levinson, supra note 73, at 920.
  • 97
    • 0347389797 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The role of institutional interest in East European constitution-making
    • For some conjectures on how such alignment occurred in Eastern Europe, see Jon Elster, The Role of Institutional Interest in East European Constitution-Making, 5 E. EUR. CONST. REV. 63 (1996).
    • (1996) E. Eur. Const. Rev. , vol.5 , pp. 63
    • Elster, J.1
  • 98
    • 76449094546 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See SMITH, supra note 10, at 32
    • See SMITH, supra note 10, at 32.
  • 99
    • 44649087896 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constitutional showdowns
    • 1032-1033
    • See Eric A. Posner & Adrian Vermeule, Constitutional Showdowns, 156 U. PA. L. REV. 991, 1032-1033 (2008).
    • (2008) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.156 , pp. 991
    • Posner, E.A.1    Vermeule, A.2
  • 100
    • 85050413007 scopus 로고
    • Constitutional review by the executive in foreign affairs and war powers: A consequence of rational choice in the separation of powers
    • Autumn 303
    • E.g., John O. McGinnis, Constitutional Review by the Executive in Foreign Affairs and War Powers: A Consequence of Rational Choice in the Separation of Powers, LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS., Autumn 1993, at 293, 303;
    • (1993) Law & Contemp. Probs. , pp. 293
    • McGinnis, J.O.1
  • 101
    • 39449086970 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The spontaneous order of war powers
    • 1326
    • John O. McGinnis, The Spontaneous Order of War Powers, 47 CASE W. RES. L. REV. 1317, 1326 (1997).
    • (1997) Case W. Res. L. Rev. , vol.47 , pp. 1317
    • McGinnis, J.O.1
  • 102
    • 76449097429 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra pp. 18-19
    • See supra pp. 18-19.
  • 103
    • 84868180265 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Divide and conquer
    • A version of the following discussion is included in that paper
    • For an analysis of divide-and-conquer tactics, see Eric A. Posner, Kathryn E. Spier & Adrian Vermeule, Divide and Conquer (Univ. of Chi., John M. Olin Law & Econ. Working Paper No. 467, 2009), available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract-id=1414319. A version of the following discussion is included in that paper.
    • (2009) Univ. of Chi., John M. Olin Law & Econ. Working Paper No. 467
    • Posner, E.A.1    Spier, K.E.2    Vermeule, A.3
  • 104
    • 76449104955 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HUME, supra note 45, at 44.
    • HUME, supra note 45, at 44.
  • 105
    • 76449118224 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 45
    • Id. at 45.
  • 106
    • 21344482597 scopus 로고
    • Cheap bribes and the corruption ban: A coordination game among rational legislators
    • 309-313
    • This interpretation applies Eric Rasmusen & J. Mark Ramseyer, Cheap Bribes and the Corruption Ban: A Coordination Game Among Rational Legislators, 78 PUB. CHOICE 305, 309-313 (1994).
    • (1994) Pub. Choice , vol.78 , pp. 305
    • Rasmusen, E.1    Ramseyer, J.M.2
  • 107
    • 76449105166 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 313
    • Id. at 313.
  • 108
    • 0040003931 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Contracting with externalities
    • 343
    • For similar models of divide-and-conquer tactics in other settings, see Ilya Segal, Contracting with Externalities, 114 Q.J. ECON. 337, 343 (1999);
    • (1999) Q.J. Econ. , vol.114 , pp. 337
    • Segal, I.1
  • 109
    • 0347578233 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Coordination and discrimination in contracting with externalities: Divide and conquer?
    • 153-155
    • Ilya Segal, Coordination and Discrimination in Contracting with Externalities: Divide and Conquer?, 113 J. ECON. THEORY 147, 153-155 (2003);
    • (2003) J. Econ. Theory , vol.113 , pp. 147
    • Segal, I.1
  • 111
    • 76449100238 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This feature of discriminatory vote-buying offers tracks the logic of divide-and-conquer models in other areas, in which discriminatory offers allow the single party on one side of the transaction to exclude equilibria in which the multiple parties on the other side of the transaction coordinate for mutual gain.
  • 112
    • 34948825295 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bribing voters
    • 791-795
    • This interpretation applies the ingenious model in Ernesto Dal Bó, Bribing Voters, 51 AM. J. POL. SCI. 789, 791-795 (2007).
    • (2007) Am. J. Pol. Sci. , vol.51 , pp. 789
    • Bó, E.D.1
  • 113
    • 76449114710 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 793
    • See id. at 793.
  • 114
    • 76449090551 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • More specifically, a sum equal to the individual costs to the pivotal voter if the Crown's proposal is enacted plus a token amount, in order to make the pivotal voter prefer that it be enacted
    • More specifically, a sum equal to the individual costs to the pivotal voter if the Crown's proposal is enacted plus a token amount, in order to make the pivotal voter prefer that it be enacted.
  • 115
    • 76449120284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 794
    • See id. at 794.
  • 116
    • 76449100425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 793-794
    • See id. at 793-794
  • 117
    • 76449110558 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 792
    • See id. at 792.
  • 118
    • 76449120675 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id.
    • See id.
  • 119
    • 76449106278 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Whether the British Government inclines more to absolute monarchy, or to a republic
    • supra note 45, 48.
    • DAVID HUME, Whether the British Government Inclines More to Absolute Monarchy, or to a Republic, in ESSAYS: MORAL, POLITICAL, AND LITERARY, supra note 45, at 47, 48.
    • Essays: Moral, Political, and Literary , pp. 47
    • Hume, D.1
  • 121
    • 33747076145 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The fable of the nationalist president and the parochial congress
    • 1221, 1231-1242
    • See Jide Nzelibe, The Fable of the Nationalist President and the Parochial Congress, 53 UCLAL. REV. 1217, 1221, 1231-1242 (2006).
    • (2006) Uclal. Rev. , vol.53 , pp. 1217
    • Nzelibe, J.1
  • 122
    • 76449085437 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 1235-1242
    • See id. at 1235-1242
  • 123
    • 0006037416 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Separation of powers and political accountability
    • 1179-1183
    • See Torsten Persson, Gérard Roland & Guido Tabellini, Separation of Powers and Political Accountability, 112 Q.J. ECON. 1163, 1179-1183 (1997).
    • (1997) Q.J. Econ. , vol.112 , pp. 1163
    • Persson, T.1    Roland, G.2    Tabellini, G.3
  • 124
    • 76449084252 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 1182-1183
    • See id. at 1182-1183
  • 125
    • 76449114709 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Levmore, supra note 35, at 147-148
    • Levmore, supra note 35, at 147-148
  • 128
    • 76449105943 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 233-34, 239-240
    • See id. at 233-34, 239-240
  • 129
    • 84868184942 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 517 U.S. 748, describing bicameralism as a feature of Congress that makes for "responsive" lawmaking
    • Cf. Loving v. United States, 517 U.S. 748, 757-758 (1996) (describing bicameralism as a feature of Congress that makes for "responsive" lawmaking).
    • (1996) Cf. Loving V. United States , pp. 757-758
  • 130
    • 76449101856 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BUCHANAN & TULLOCK, supra note 100, at 233-234
    • See BUCHANAN & TULLOCK, supra note 100, at 233-234
  • 131
    • 84868181823 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Second-best democracy
    • Parts of this section are adapted, with modifications, from Adrian Vermeule, Second-Best Democracy, I HARV. L. & POL'Y REV. ONLINE (2006), http://www.hlpronline.com/2006/11/vermeule-01.html.
    • (2006) I Harv. L. & Pol'y Rev. Online
    • Vermeule, A.1
  • 134
    • 76449120477 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 50-51
    • Id. at 50-51.
  • 135
    • 76449099582 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 87-88
    • Id. at 87-88.
  • 136
    • 76449102240 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 125, 136-137
    • Id. at 125, 136-137
  • 137
    • 76449111916 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 8-9, 27-29, 49
    • See id. at 8-9, 27-29, 49.
  • 138
    • 84868184941 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I use "emergent" strictly in the philosophical sense of an emergent property. I do not mean to connote the very different idea that legal and political institutions evolve toward democracy
    • I use "emergent" strictly in the philosophical sense of an emergent property. I do not mean to connote the very different idea that legal and political institutions evolve toward democracy.
  • 139
    • 76449086415 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LEVINSON, supra note 106, at 49
    • LEVINSON, supra note 106, at 49.
  • 140
    • 76449120888 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 50-52
    • See id. at 50-52.
  • 141
    • 76449096212 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 88-89
    • See id. at 88-89.
  • 142
    • 0042919001 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The mathematics and statistics of voting power
    • 426-428
    • See Andrew Gelman et al., The Mathematics and Statistics of Voting Power, 17 STAT. SCI. 420, 426-428 (2002).
    • (2002) Stat. Sci. , vol.17 , pp. 420
    • Gelman, A.1
  • 143
    • 84868176507 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Unless the relevant interests are defined in excessively general terms, such as "the powerful" or "the wealthy"
    • Unless the relevant interests are defined in excessively general terms, such as "the powerful" or "the wealthy."
  • 144
    • 76449106880 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Persson, Roland & Tabellini, supra note 97, at 1179-1183
    • Persson, Roland & Tabellini, supra note 97, at 1179-1183
  • 145
    • 76449122244 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., LEVINSON, supra note 106, at 52
    • See, e.g., LEVINSON, supra note 106, at 52.
  • 146
    • 76449109899 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., id. at 109-16
    • See, e.g., id. at 109-16;
  • 147
    • 84868188767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 167 (listing "[e]xcessive presidential power" as a "grievous defect[]" of the Constitution)
    • id. at 167 (listing "[e]xcessive presidential power" as a "grievous defect[]" of the Constitution).
  • 148
    • 76449109279 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., id. at 89-91
    • See, e.g., id. at 89-91.
  • 149
    • 76449087649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., DAHL, supra note 105, at 68-72
    • See, e.g., DAHL, supra note 105, at 68-72.
  • 150
    • 76449089087 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. LANDIS, supra note 54.
    • Cf. LANDIS, supra note 54.
  • 151
    • 84868184937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 1 ("[T]he administrative process springs from the inadequacy of a simple tripartite form of government to deal with modern problems.")
    • See id. at 1 ("[T]he administrative process springs from the inadequacy of a simple tripartite form of government to deal with modern problems.").
  • 152
    • 0036927160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gerrymandering and political cartels
    • 617-630
    • See, e.g., Samuel Issacharoff, Gerrymandering and Political Cartels, 116 HARV. L. REV. 593, 617-630 (2002).
    • (2002) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.116 , pp. 593
    • Issacharoff, S.1
  • 153
    • 0346346077 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reply: In defense of foxes guarding henhouses: the case for judicial acquiescence to incumbent-protecting gerrymanders
    • 668
    • See Nathaniel Persily, Reply: In Defense of Foxes Guarding Henhouses: The Case for Judicial Acquiescence to Incumbent-Protecting Gerrymanders, 116 HARV. L. REV. 649, 668 (2002).
    • (2002) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.116 , pp. 649
    • Persily, N.1
  • 154
    • 76449121858 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 155
    • 14544290920 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Second-order diversity
    • 1117-1118
    • Heather K. Gerken, Second-Order Diversity, 118 HARV. L. REV. 1099, 1117-1118 (2005).
    • (2005) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.118 , pp. 1099
    • Gerken, H.K.1
  • 157
    • 0041157751 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Narratives of federalism: Of continuities and comparative constitutional experience
    • 226, 272-279
    • See Vicki C. Jackson, Narratives of Federalism: Of Continuities and Comparative Constitutional Experience, 51 DUKE LJ. 223, 226, 272-279 (2001);
    • (2001) Duke LJ. , vol.51 , pp. 223
    • Jackson, V.C.1
  • 158
    • 4344564858 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • emphasizing that, because institutions are interdependent, the constitutional designer cannot evaluate them piecemeal. Thanks to Mark Tushnet for these references
    • see also MIKHAIL FILIPPOV, PETER C. ORDESHOOK & OLGA SHVETSOVA, DESIGNING FEDERALISM. 300-301 (2004) (emphasizing that, because institutions are interdependent, the constitutional designer cannot evaluate them piecemeal). Thanks to Mark Tushnet for these references.
    • (2004) Designing Federalism , pp. 300-301
    • Filippov, M.1    Ordeshook, P.C.2    Shvetsova, O.3
  • 160
    • 76449108108 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The hydraulics of constitutional reform: A skeptical response to our undemocratic constitution
    • 927
    • Heather K. Gerken, The Hydraulics of Constitutional Reform: A Skeptical Response to Our Undemocratic Constitution, 55 DRAKE L. REV. 925, 927 n.14 (2007).
    • (2007) Drake L. Rev. , vol.55 , Issue.14 , pp. 925
    • Gerken, H.K.1
  • 163
    • 33645815488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The core of the case against judicial review
    • Jeremy Waldron, The Core of the Case Against Judicial Review, 115 YALE L.J. 1346 (2006).
    • (2006) Yale L.J. , vol.115 , pp. 1346
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 164
    • 0347177012 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Institutions and enforcement of the bill of rights
    • 1550-1576
    • For an important line of critique, see Frank B. Cross, Institutions and Enforcement of the Bill of Rights, 85 CORNELL L. REV. 1529, 1550-1576 (2000);
    • (2000) Cornell L. Rev. , vol.85 , pp. 1529
    • Cross, F.B.1
  • 165
    • 44849128099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The core of an uneasy case for judicial review
    • and Richard H. Fallon, Jr., The Core of an Uneasy Case for Judicial Review, 121 HARV. L. REV. 1693 (2008).
    • (2008) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.121 , pp. 1693
    • Fallon Jr., R.H.1
  • 167
    • 76449098966 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally VERMEULE, supra note 130
    • See generally VERMEULE, supra note 130.
  • 169
    • 76449101854 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Cross, supra note 132, at 1550-76
    • See Cross, supra note 132, at 1550-76;
  • 170
    • 76449112701 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fallon, supra note 132, at 1718-1728
    • Fallon, supra note 132, at 1718-1728
  • 171
    • 76449117841 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I believe that robust judicial review cannot, in fact, be justified in such terms, see VERMEULE, supra note 133, but that is a separate question
    • I believe that robust judicial review cannot, in fact, be justified in such terms, see VERMEULE, supra note 133, but that is a separate question.
  • 172
    • 33947096855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The supreme court, 2005 term-foreword: The court's agenda and the nation's
    • See Frederick Schauer, The Supreme Court, 2005 Term-Foreword: The Court's Agenda And the Nation's, 120 HARV. L. REV. 4 (2006).
    • (2006) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.120 , pp. 4
    • Schauer, F.1
  • 173
    • 76449117238 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schauer also briefly discusses the Court's statutory agenda, but the main implications he elicits are addressed to constitutional theory, see id., so I shall focus on his discussion of the Court's constitutional agenda
    • Schauer also briefly discusses the Court's statutory agenda, but the main implications he elicits are addressed to constitutional theory, see id., so I shall focus on his discussion of the Court's constitutional agenda.
  • 174
    • 76449083629 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 50
    • Id. at 50.
  • 175
    • 76449116136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 53
    • Id. at 53.
  • 177
    • 84868184929 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schauer, supra note 137, at 53. Schauer limits his argument by saying that the Court should intervene primarily on "low-salience" questions
    • Schauer, supra note 137, at 53. Schauer limits his argument by saying that the Court should intervene primarily on "low-salience" questions.
  • 178
    • 76449099378 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 36-62. This limitation partially but not wholly avoids the problem noted in the text, because it will be uncertain ex ante when the limitation applies
    • See id. at 36-62. This limitation partially but not wholly avoids the problem noted in the text, because it will be uncertain ex ante when the limitation applies.
  • 179
    • 76449105942 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 128 S. Ct. 2229 (2008)
    • -128 S. Ct. 2229 (2008).
  • 180
    • 84868176503 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I will ignore "personal" bias, which arises when rulings are based on bribery or family connections
    • I will ignore "personal" bias, which arises when rulings are based on bribery or family connections.
  • 181
    • 76449092681 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Miles & Sunstein, supra note 23, at 831
    • Miles & Sunstein, supra note 23, at 831.
  • 182
    • 76449092966 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ((8 x .5) + 1)/9 ≈ .56
    • ((8 x .5) + 1)/9 ≈ .56.
  • 183
    • 76449116611 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • 8) = (70 + 56 + 28 + 8 + 1)/256 ≈ .64. Thanks to Joanna Huey and John Polley for this calculation.
  • 184
    • 76449116135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • People are sometimes confused by the idea that someone can vote worse than randomly; doesn't that mean the swing Justice could improve her competence by flipping a coin? But this confuses the standpoint of the analyst with the standpoint of the actor. The swing Justice might not perceive the cognitive limitations that reduce her competence below that of a coin flip.
  • 185
    • 76449113320 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This assumes that all the Justices vote sincerely, not strategically, although one votes based on political attitudes while the others vote based on their best understanding of the relevant law
    • This assumes that all the Justices vote sincerely, not strategically, although one votes based on political attitudes while the others vote based on their best understanding of the relevant law.
  • 186
    • 33749459207 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Do judges make regulatory policy? An empirical investigation of chevron
    • 834 This study does not include Chief Justice Roberts or Justices Alito and Sotomayor
    • Thomas J. Miles & Cass R. Sunstein, Do Judges Make Regulatory Policy? An Empirical Investigation of Chevron, 73 U. CHI. L. REV. 823, 834 (2006). This study does not include Chief Justice Roberts or Justices Alito and Sotomayor.
    • (2006) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.73 , pp. 823
    • Miles, T.J.1    Sunstein, C.R.2
  • 187
    • 76449099376 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Appeals courts pushed to right by bush choices
    • Oct. 29
    • See Charlie Savage, Appeals Courts Pushed to Right by Bush Choices, N.Y. TIMES, Oct. 29, 2008, at A1.
    • (2008) N.Y. Times
    • Savage, C.1
  • 188
    • 49749123816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Does political bias in the judiciary matter?: Implications of judicial bias studies for legal and constitutional reform
    • 858-868
    • See Eric A. Posner, Does Political Bias in the Judiciary Matter?: Implications of Judicial Bias Studies for Legal and Constitutional Reform, 75 U. CHI. L. REV. 853, 858-868 (2008).
    • (2008) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.75 , pp. 853
    • Posner, E.A.1
  • 189
    • 35648951816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Resurrecting lochner: A defense of unprincipled judicial activism
    • See generally James R. Rogers & Georg Vanberg, Resurrecting Lochner: A Defense of Unprincipled Judicial Activism, 23 J.L. ECON. & ORG. 442 (2007).
    • (2007) J.L. Econ. & Org. , vol.23 , pp. 442
    • Rogers, J.R.1    Vanberg, G.2
  • 190
    • 84868184931 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Posner, supra note 152, at 855 ("[J]udicial bias (within limits) does not matter at all and could even be beneficial in a system . . . where judges are expected to block or restrict government actions . . . that are themselves likely to reflect 'bias.'" (emphasis omitted))
    • Cf. Posner, supra note 152, at 855 ("[J]udicial bias (within limits) does not matter at all and could even be beneficial in a system . . . where judges are expected to block or restrict government actions . . . that are themselves likely to reflect 'bias.'" (emphasis omitted)).
  • 191
    • 76449112106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 879
    • See id. at 879.
  • 192
    • 84868188759 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. id. at 880 ("If legislative bias yields inefficient and unfair statutes because the legislative process is insufficiently supermajoritarian and if legislative bargaining costs are low, then review of statutes by biased judges may be socially desirable . . . .").
    • Cf. id. at 880 ("If legislative bias yields inefficient and unfair statutes because the legislative process is insufficiently supermajoritarian and if legislative bargaining costs are low, then review of statutes by biased judges may be socially desirable . . . .").
  • 193
  • 194
    • 0346983715 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Environmental regulation, ideology, and the D.C. circuit
    • 1719
    • Richard L. Revesz, Environmental Regulation, Ideology, and the D.C. Circuit, 83 VA. L. REV. 1717, 1719 (1997).
    • (1997) Va. L. Rev. , vol.83 , pp. 1717
    • Revesz, R.L.1
  • 195
    • 67149089425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deliberation and strategy on the United States courts of appeals: An empirical exploration of panel effects
    • 1320-1327
    • For a recent overview of the literature on panel effects, see Pauline T. Kim, Deliberation and Strategy on the United States Courts of Appeals: An Empirical Exploration of Panel Effects, 157 U. PA. L. REV. 1319, 1320-1327 (2009).
    • (2009) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.157 , pp. 1319
    • Kim, P.T.1
  • 197
    • 0002048138 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In praise of theory
    • 364
    • See Ronald Dworkin, In Praise of Theory, 29 ARIZ. ST. L.J. 353, 364 (1997).
    • (1997) Ariz. St. L.J. , vol.29 , pp. 353
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 198
    • 42949091748 scopus 로고
    • Rights and agency
    • 3
    • See Amartya Sen, Rights and Agency, 11 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 3, 3 (1982).
    • (1982) Phil. & Pub. Aff. , vol.11 , pp. 3
    • Sen, A.1
  • 199
    • 76449084445 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • "All" is not necessarily to be taken literally; I use it as shorthand for whatever critical mass of judges is necessary to produce the beneficial consequences promised by the relevant theory.
  • 200
    • 84868184932 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Diachronie system effects can obtain so long as it is costly to reverse the action of past judges. Here too, I use "irreversible" merely as a shorthand.
    • Diachronie system effects can obtain so long as it is costly to reverse the action of past judges. Here too, I use "irreversible" merely as a shorthand.
  • 201
    • 38049075773 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The judiciary Is a they, not an it: Interpretive theory and the fallacy of division
    • This section and the next are adapted, with heavy modifications, from Adrian Vermeule, The Judiciary Is a They, Not an It: Interpretive Theory and the Fallacy of Division, 14 J. CON-TEMP. LEGAL ISSUES 549 (2005).
    • (2005) J. Con-temp. Legal Issues , vol.14 , pp. 549
    • Vermeule, A.1
  • 202
    • 40749084517 scopus 로고
    • 487 U.S. 326, 346 (Scalia, J., concurring in part) ("[W]e have an obligation to conduct our exegesis in a fashion which fosters th[e] democratic process [specified in the bicameralism and presentment requirements of Article I].")
    • See, e.g., United States v. Taylor, 487 U.S. 326, 346 (1988) (Scalia, J., concurring in part) ("[W]e have an obligation to conduct our exegesis in a fashion which fosters th[e] democratic process [specified in the bicameralism and presentment requirements of Article I].");
    • (1988) United States V. Taylor
  • 203
    • 76449110975 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legal scholarship in the age of legislation
    • 685 ("MJethods like textualism and rules of clear statement are best understood as efforts to improve the quality of the decisionmaking in the politically accountable branches.")
    • Elizabeth Garrett, Legal Scholarship in the Age of Legislation, 34 TULSA L.J. 679, 685 (1999) ("[MJethods like textualism and rules of clear statement are best understood as efforts to improve the quality of the decisionmaking in the politically accountable branches.");
    • (1999) Tulsa L.J. , vol.34 , pp. 679
    • Garrett, E.1
  • 204
    • 84933489847 scopus 로고
    • Legislative history and the need to bring statutory interpretation under the rule of law
    • 407-410 (arguing that judicial recourse to legislative history results in irresponsible and incoherent congressional lawmaking).
    • cf. W. David Slawson, Legislative History and the Need To Bring Statutory Interpretation Under the Rule of Law, 44 STAN. L. REV. 383, 407-410 (1992) (arguing that judicial recourse to legislative history results in irresponsible and incoherent congressional lawmaking).
    • (1992) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.44 , pp. 383
    • David Slawson, W.1
  • 205
    • 76449106492 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Vermeule, supra note 162, at 564-565
    • Supra Note , vol.162 , pp. 564-565
    • Vermeule1
  • 206
    • 76449114069 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For discussion of this issue, see id. at 569-71
    • For discussion of this issue, see id. at 569-71;
  • 208
  • 209
    • 22744441097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Common law, common ground and Jefferson's principle
    • 1730-1731
    • See David A. Strauss, Common Law, Common Ground and Jefferson's Principle, 112 YALE L.J. 1717, 1730-1731 (2003).
    • (2003) Yale L.J. , vol.112 , pp. 1717
    • Strauss, D.A.1
  • 210
    • 0040045872 scopus 로고
    • Social constraint or implicit collusion?: Toward a game theoretic analysis of stare decisis
    • 748-753
    • See Erin O'Hara, Social Constraint or Implicit Collusion?: Toward a Game Theoretic Analysis of Stare Decisis, 24 SETON HALL L. REV. 736, 748-753 (1993).
    • (1993) Seton Hall L. Rev. , vol.24 , pp. 736
    • O'Hara, E.1
  • 212
    • 76449088035 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The difference is that games such as Assurance have coordination built into their very structure.
    • This distinction is slightly inaccurate. Although a one-shot Prisoners' Dilemma has no coordination element -each player has a dominant strategy -a repeated version of the game makes coordination important. See O'Hara, supra note 168, at 751-53. The difference is that games such as Assurance have coordination built into their very structure.
    • Supra Note , vol.168 , pp. 751-753
  • 213
    • 62549087027 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beyond the Prisoners' Dilemma: Coordination, game theory, and law
    • 220-222
    • See Richard H. McAdams, Beyond the Prisoners' Dilemma: Coordination, Game Theory, and Law, 82 S. CAL. L. REV. 209, 220-222 (2009).
    • (2009) S. Cal. L. Rev. , vol.82 , pp. 209
    • McAdams, R.H.1
  • 214
    • 76449085693 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See McAdams, supra note 170, at 222-23;
    • Supra Note , vol.170 , pp. 222-223
    • McAdams1
  • 215
    • 76449119921 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For hybrid games in which the Battle of the Sexes is embedded within an iterated Prisoners' Dilemma
    • Strauss, supra note 167, at 1733-1735 For hybrid games in which the Battle of the Sexes is embedded within an iterated Prisoners' Dilemma,
    • Supra Note , vol.167 , pp. 1733-1735
    • Strauss1
  • 216
    • 76449087047 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Such refinements, while important, are not necessary for the points I attempt to make here.
    • see McAdams, supra note 170, at 226-230 Such refinements, while important, are not necessary for the points I attempt to make here.
    • Supra Note , vol.170 , pp. 226-230
    • McAdams1
  • 218
    • 76449103883 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Within this broad rubric, there are different ways of specifying Thayerism. Some Thayerian judges may hold that a reasonable reading of constitutional text is required; some may hold that a reasonable account of original understandings, or of precedent, is required. Some especially capacious Thayerians may hold that the legislation should be upheld so long as it can reasonably be justified in terms of any of the standard sources of constitutional law. These distinctions, however, are not material to the second-best problems facing Thayerians, which are the same however the approach is specified.
  • 219
    • 76449088238 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In previous work, I failed to take adequate account of this problem for Thayerians. See, for example, the brief and unsatisfactory remarks in VERMEULE, supra note 133, at 263-264
    • Supra Note , vol.133 , pp. 263-264
    • Vermeule1
  • 220
    • 76449096428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For suggestions that the Court should eliminate judicial review only prospectively and that unilateral disarmament is a bad idea, see TUSHNET, supra note 141, at 175.
    • Supra Note , vol.141 , pp. 175
    • Tushnet1
  • 221
  • 222
    • 76449119111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 248-249
    • For more on the problem of local maxima, see generally ELSTER, supra note 41, at 111 248-249
    • Supra Note , vol.41 , pp. 111
    • Elster1
  • 223
    • 42949148252 scopus 로고
    • Incompletely theorized agreements
    • Cass R. Sunstein, Incompletely Theorized Agreements, 108 HARV. L. REV. 1733 (1995).
    • (1995) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.108 , pp. 1733
    • Sunstein, C.R.1
  • 225
    • 21744433271 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Response, on reading recipes... and constitutions
    • 1823-24 Other originalists do not seem to draw such a distinction, saying generally that originalism has pragmatic benefits.
    • The issue is slightly complicated by the distinction between interpretation and adjudication. Some originalists believe that this distinction is coherent and that originalism is the only valid form of interpretation, whereas originalism as a method of adjudication must be justified by reference to its consequences. See, e.g., Gary Lawson, Response, On Reading Recipes . . . and Constitutions, 85 GEO. L.J. 1823, 1823-24 (1997). Other originalists do not seem to draw such a distinction, saying generally that originalism has pragmatic benefits.
    • (1997) Geo. L.J. , vol.85 , pp. 1823
    • Lawson, G.1
  • 226
    • 50949111158 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A pragmatic defense of originalism
    • I will confine my remarks to originalist adjudication and so will ignore the issue here.
    • See, e.g., John O. McGinnis & Michael B. Rappaport, A Pragmatic Defense of Originalism, 31 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 917 (2008). I will confine my remarks to originalist adjudication and so will ignore the issue here.
    • (2008) Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol'y , vol.31 , pp. 917
    • McGinnis, J.O.1    Rappaport, M.B.2
  • 228
    • 76449099377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of snakes and butterflies: A reply
    • 2236 &
    • quoted in Cass R. Sunstein, Of Snakes and Butterflies: A Reply, 106 COLUM. L. REV. 2234, 2236 & n.8 (2006).
    • (2006) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.106 , Issue.8 , pp. 2234
    • Sunstein, C.R.1
  • 229
    • 0346675678 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Originalism as an "Ism,"
    • 303-304
    • See Jonathan R. Macey, Originalism as an "Ism," 19 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 301, 303-304 (1996).
    • (1996) Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol'y , vol.19 , pp. 301
    • Macey, J.R.1
  • 230
    • 84868181788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The desirable constitution and the case for originalism
    • Research Paper No. 08-05
    • See John O. McGinnis & Michael B. Rappaport, The Desirable Constitution and the Case for Originalism 7-18 (Nw. Univ. Sch. of Law Pub. Law & Legal Theory Working Paper Series, Research Paper No. 08-05, 2009), available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfmPabstract-id=1109247.
    • (2009) Nw. Univ. Sch. of Law Pub. Law & Legal Theory Working Paper Series , vol.7-18
    • McGinnis, J.O.1    Rappaport, M.B.2
  • 233
    • 76449120115 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 235
    • 50949095189 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Two (More) problems with originalism
    • 915
    • Larry Kramer, Two (More) Problems with Originalism, 31 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 907, 915 (2008);
    • (2008) Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol'y , vol.31 , pp. 907
    • Kramer, L.1
  • 236
    • 77954490901 scopus 로고
    • Fidelity in translation
    • 1182-1188
    • see also Lawrence Lessig, Fidelity in Translation, 71 TEX. L. REV. 1165, 1182-1188 (1993).
    • (1993) Tex. L. Rev. , vol.71 , pp. 1165
    • Lessig, L.1
  • 237
    • 76449118601 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lessig, supra note 187, at 1189-1192
    • Supra Note , vol.187 , pp. 1189-1192
    • Lessig1
  • 239
    • 68149165182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reconciling originalism and precedent
    • This point is overlooked by John O. McGinnis & Michael B. Rappaport, Reconciling Originalism and Precedent, 103 Nw. U. L. REV. 803 (2009).
    • (2009) Nw. U. L. Rev. , vol.103 , pp. 803
    • McGinnis, J.O.1    Rappaport, M.B.2
  • 240
    • 76449101447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Trumping precedent with original meaning: Not as radical as it sounds
    • 263-269 I have compressed two of Barnett's categories -"construction" and "liquidation" -into one, because they largely overlap.
    • See Randy E. Barnett, Trumping Precedent with Original Meaning: Not as Radical as It Sounds, 22 CONST. COMMENT. 257, 263-269 (2005). I have compressed two of Barnett's categories -"construction" and " liquidation" -into one, because they largely overlap.
    • (2005) Const. Ccomment. , vol.22 , pp. 257
    • Barnett, R.E.1
  • 241
    • 76449102061 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 269-270 (arguing that this version of originalism leaves much room for the doctrine of precedent).
    • See id. at 269-270 (arguing that this version of originalism leaves much room for the doctrine of precedent).
  • 242
    • 76449119718 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 272 U.S. 52 (1926).
    • -272 U.S. 52 (1926).
  • 243
    • 76449121115 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 176.
    • See id. at 176.
  • 244
    • 76449096632 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 295 U.S. 602 (1935).
    • -295 U.S. 602 (1935).
  • 245
    • 76449108754 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 626 (limiting Myers to very narrow factual circumstances despite the Myers Court's extensive historical and legislative analysis).
    • Id. at 626 (limiting Myers to very narrow factual circumstances despite the Myers Court's extensive historical and legislative analysis).
  • 246
    • 84924212940 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • According to a recent review of the evidence, "it is a mistake to characterize the |J|ustices on the Court as strategic actors, who take advantage of their strategic positions to achieve their legal or policy goals. Strategic behavior occurs on the Court, but it takes place much less often than the strategic scholars claim." SAUL BRENNER & JOSEPH M. WHITMEYER, STRATEGY ON THE UNITED STATES SUPREME COURT 165 (2009).
    • (2009) Strategy On The United States Supreme Court , vol.165
    • Brenner, S.1    Whitmeyer, J.M.2
  • 247
    • 84868179040 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "[I]n most strategic models that are applied to federal courts, judges act solely on the goal of achieving good policy,"
    • For a clear recognition that these two axes are distinct, see LAWRENCE BAUM, JUDGES AND THEIR AUDIENCES 6-8 (2006). "[I]n most strategic models that are applied to federal courts, judges act solely on the goal of achieving good policy,"
    • (2006) Judges and Their Audiences , vol.6-8
    • Baum, L.1
  • 248
    • 76449105941 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 6, but as Baum points out, there is no logical connection between assuming that judges are strategic and assuming that they are attitudinal, in the sense of policy-oriented, rather than legalist
    • id. at 6, but as Baum points out, there is no logical connection between assuming that judges are strategic and assuming that they are attitudinal, in the sense of policy-oriented, rather than legalist,
  • 249
    • 84868188753 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see id. at 7-8. Another standard formulation in the literature is that judges are "single-minded seekers of legal policy."
    • see id. at 7-8. Another standard formulation in the literature is that judges are "single-minded seekers of legal policy."
  • 250
    • 84971768398 scopus 로고
    • On the nature of supreme court decision making
    • 325 (emphasis added). However, this formulation is intrinsically ambiguous.
    • Tracey E. George & Lee Epstein, On the Nature of Supreme Court Decision Making, 86 AM. POL. SCI. REV. 323, 325 (1992) (emphasis added). However, this formulation is intrinsically ambiguous.
    • (1992) Am. Pol. Sci. Rev. , vol.86 , pp. 323
    • George, T.E.1    Epstein, L.2
  • 253
    • 0000426076 scopus 로고
    • A positive theory of statutory interpretation
    • 268 (using the phrase "politically sophisticated honest agent" to describe strategic legalism as one of three models of judicial interpretation). For a hybrid argument that strategic judges advance their views of both good law and good policy
    • There is only a small body of work that models judges as strategic maximizers of their legal views. See, e.g., John A. Ferejohn & Barry R. Weingast, A Positive Theory of Statutory Interpretation, 12 INT'L REV. L. & ECON. 263, 268 (1992) (using the phrase "politically sophisticated honest agent" to describe strategic legalism as one of three models of judicial interpretation). For a hybrid argument that strategic judges advance their views of both good law and good policy,
    • (1992) Int'l Rev. L. & Econ. , vol.12 , pp. 263
    • Ferejohn, J.A.1    Weingast, B.R.2
  • 254
    • 0030529058 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Invitations to override: Congressional reversals of supreme court decisions
    • 504 Both articles, however, focus on the interaction between the Court and Congress, whereas I am focusing on the interactions among judges.
    • see Pablo T. Spiller & Emerson H. Tiller, Invitations to Override: Congressional Reversals of Supreme Court Decisions, 16 INT'L REV. L. &. ECON. 503, 504 (1996). Both articles, however, focus on the interaction between the Court and Congress, whereas I am focusing on the interactions among judges.
    • (1996) Int'l Rev. L. &. Econ. , vol.16 , pp. 503
    • Spiller, P.T.1    Tiller, E.H.2
  • 255
    • 76449105378 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thanks to Daryl Levinson for suggesting this term.
    • Thanks to Daryl Levinson for suggesting this term.
  • 256
    • 33646881859 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 545 U.S. 1, 58 (Thomas, J., dissenting) (rejecting the Court's understanding of the Commerce Clause in favor of an understanding based on the "text, structure, and history" of the clause)
    • See, e.g., Gonzales v. Raich, 545 U.S. 1, 58 (2005) (Thomas, J., dissenting) (rejecting the Court's understanding of the Commerce Clause in favor of an understanding based on the "text, structure, and history" of the clause);
    • (2005) Gonzales V. Raich
  • 257
    • 76449092145 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 531 U.S. 457, 487 (Thomas, J., concurring) (questioning the Court's reliance on the intelligible principle doctrine in delegation jurisprudence).
    • Whitman v. Am. Trucking Ass'n, 531 U.S. 457, 487 (2001) (Thomas, J., concurring) (questioning the Court's reliance on the intelligible principle doctrine in delegation jurisprudence).
    • (2001) Whitman V. Am. Trucking Ass'n
  • 258
    • 76449104313 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See McAdams, supra note 170, at 212-213
    • Supra Note , vol.170 , pp. 212-213
    • McAdams1
  • 259
    • 84868180996 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jon Elster quotes a dictum of Montaigne's: "In the state of indecision and perplexity brought upon us by our inability to see what is most advantageous and to choose it... , since we doubt which is the shorter road, we should keep going straight ahead."
    • Jon Elster quotes a dictum of Montaigne's: "In the state of indecision and perplexity brought upon us by our inability to see what is most advantageous and to choose it... , since we doubt which is the shorter road, we should keep going straight ahead."
  • 260
    • 79955575359 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mimicking impartiality
    • Keith Dowding, Robert E. Goodin & Carole Pateman eds.
    • Jon Elster, Mimicking Impartiality, in JUSTICE AND DEMOCRACY 112, 113 (Keith Dowding, Robert E. Goodin & Carole Pateman eds., 2004)
    • (2004) Justice and Democracy , vol.112 , pp. 113
    • Elster, J.1
  • 261
    • 76449119311 scopus 로고
    • M.A. Screech trans., Penguin Books
    • (quoting MICHEL DE MONTAIGNE, THE COMPLETE ESSAYS 144 (M.A. Screech trans., Penguin Books 1991) (1580)).
    • (1991) The Complete Essays , vol.144 , pp. 1580
    • De Montaigne, M.1
  • 262
    • 76449085019 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I mean this in a different sense than the form of second-best originalism attributed to Justice Scalia in section I.C.2, p. 22. Justice Scalia's view of originalism as "the librarian who talks too softly" works, if it works at all, only if followed by all judges ab initio, whereas the version of second-best originalism considered in the text attempts to address the problems created by nonoriginalist decisions in the past.
  • 263
    • 76449084251 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • However, because it is addressed to a different institutional setting, I believe that Ulen's argument is much stronger than the constitutional version of the argument I mention in the text.
    • For a somewhat similar argument that common law adjudication should ignore problems of the second best, see Ulen, supra note 39, at 217. However, because it is addressed to a different institutional setting, I believe that Ulen's argument is much stronger than the constitutional version of the argument I mention in the text.
    • Supra Note , vol.39 , pp. 217
    • Ulen1
  • 264
    • 0037412586 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hume's second-best constitutionalism
    • 435-437
    • For discussion of that question, and an earlier analysis of the issues in this paragraph, see Adrian Vermeule, Hume's Second-Best Constitutionalism, 70 U. CHI. L. REV. 421, 435-437 (2003).
    • (2003) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.70 , pp. 421
    • Vermeule, A.1
  • 265
    • 0346053743 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Judicial auditing
    • 659-665
    • I will confine the discussion to the benefits of methodological diversity within the highest court in a judicial hierarchy, such as the Supreme Court. It has been shown that in some circumstances ideological diversity at lower levels of the hierarchy can conserve on the costs of judicial administration, by allowing high-court judges to use the known ideology of lower-court judges as a screening device to reduce the number of decisions that must be reviewed on appeal. See Matt Spitzer & Eric Talley, Judicial Auditing, 29 J. LEGAL STUD. 649, 659-665 (2000).
    • (2000) J. Legal Stud. , vol.29 , pp. 649
    • Spitzer, M.1    Talley, E.2
  • 266
    • 76449088880 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Ladha, supra note 21, at 629.
    • Supra Note , vol.21 , pp. 629
    • Ladha1
  • 267
    • 76449111159 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an extensive treatment, see generally PAGE, supra note 21.
    • Supra Note , vol.21
  • 270
    • 76449085626 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why societies need dissent
    • See SUNSTEIN, WHY SOCIETIES NEED DISSENT, supra note 211, at 112-114
    • Supra Note , vol.211 , pp. 112-114
    • Sunstein1
  • 271
    • 76449115544 scopus 로고
    • 487 U.S. 654, 697-734 (Scalia, J., dissenting).
    • See, e.g., Morrison v. Olson, 487 U.S. 654, 697-734 (1988) (Scalia, J., dissenting).
    • (1988) Morrison V. Olson
  • 272
    • 0011629734 scopus 로고
    • 462 U.S. 919, 967-1003 (White, J., dissenting).
    • See, e.g., INS v. Chadha, 462 U.S. 919, 967-1003 (1983) (White, J., dissenting).
    • (1983) INS V. Chadha
  • 274
    • 76449112699 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 487 U.S. 654.
    • -487 U.S. 654.
  • 275
    • 76449108877 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 524 U.S. 417 (1998).
    • -524 U.S. 417 (1998).
  • 276
    • 76449095158 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 466-469 (Scalia, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part).
    • See id. at 466-469 (Scalia, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part).
  • 277
    • 76449093901 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 476 (Breyer, J., dissenting).
    • See id. at 476 (Breyer, J., dissenting).
  • 278
    • 27844598991 scopus 로고
    • The contemporary debate about legislative-executive separation of powers
    • 486
    • See Thomas O. Sargentich, The Contemporary Debate About Legislative-Executive Separation of Powers, 72 CORNELL L. REV. 430, 486 (1987).
    • (1987) Cornell L. Rev. , vol.72 , pp. 430
    • Sargentich, T.O.1
  • 279
    • 56149085719 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A critical guide to vehicles in the park
    • 1127-1129
    • See Frederick Schauer, A Critical Guide to Vehicles in the Park, 83 N.Y.U. L. REV. 1109, 1127-1129 (2008);
    • (2008) N.Y.U. L. Rev. , vol.83 , pp. 1109
    • Schauer, F.1
  • 280
    • 0346975665 scopus 로고
    • The practice and problems of plain meaning: A response to Aleinikoff and Shaw
    • 729
    • Frederick Schauer, The Practice and Problems of Plain Meaning: A Response to Aleinikoff and Shaw, 45 VAND. L. REV. 715, 729 (1992).
    • (1992) Vand. L. Rev. , vol.45 , pp. 715
    • Schauer, F.1
  • 281
    • 76449102730 scopus 로고
    • 201 S.W.2d 999, 1000 Ark.
    • See Cernauskas v. Fletcher, 201 S.W.2d 999, 1000 (Ark. 1947).
    • (1947) Cernauskas V. Fletcher
  • 283
    • 76449100029 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 458-62. For an argument that Holy Trinity got the legislative intentions and purposes wrong, thus creating rather than avoiding a mistake
    • Id. at 458-62. For an argument that Holy Trinity got the legislative intentions and purposes wrong, thus creating rather than avoiding a mistake,
  • 284
    • 0347417190 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legislative history and the limits of judicial competence: The untold story of Holy Trinity church
    • For a contrasting view
    • see Adrian Vermeule, Legislative History and the Limits of Judicial Competence: The Untold Story of Holy Trinity Church, 50 STAN. L. REV. 1833 (1998). For a contrasting view,
    • (1998) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.50 , pp. 1833
    • Vermeule, A.1
  • 285
    • 0043262800 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Unlocking the mysteries of Holy Trinity: Spirit, letter and history in statutory interpretation
    • see Carol Chomsky, Unlocking the Mysteries of Holy Trinity: Spirit, Letter and History in Statutory Interpretation, 100 COLUM. L. REV. 901 (2000).
    • (2000) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.100 , pp. 901
    • Chomsky, C.1
  • 286
    • 76449112902 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The first is that Hercules has superhuman epistemic capacities, whereas real appellate judges have epistemic limits. The second is that Hercules sits alone, whereas real appellate judges sit collegially. The second objection implies that what it is best for the judge to do is not a question that can be answered in isolation. Even a superhuman Hercules must operate in an environment where the behavior of other judges, not to mention other institutions, may affect what would otherwise be his best course of action.
    • There are thus two distinct objections to Ronald Dworkin's mythical judge, Hercules. See generally DWORKIN, supra note 157. The first is that Hercules has superhuman epistemic capacities, whereas real appellate judges have epistemic limits. The second is that Hercules sits alone, whereas real appellate judges sit collegially. The second objection implies that what it is best for the judge to do is not a question that can be answered in isolation. Even a superhuman Hercules must operate in an environment where the behavior of other judges, not to mention other institutions, may affect what would otherwise be his best course of action.
    • Supra Note , pp. 157
    • Dworkin1
  • 287
    • 76449103135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • As I have tried to show, the multimember character of the appellate court may, under certain conditions, magnify the epistemic competence of its members, by virtue of the Jury Theorem. In that case, the second objection would itself provide a partial cure for the first. Furthermore, the judges may calculate that the cognitive costs of strategic legalism are too high, resulting in a sophisticated second-best naïveté that causes them to mimic the behavior of a judge, like Hercules, who ignores what other judges do. In that case, the first objection would itself provide a partial cure for the second. Needless to say, however, these possibilities require an entirely different type of analysis than Dworkin provides; his framework makes the questions themselves invisible.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.