메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 23, Issue 2, 2009, Pages 241-256

Reckless states and Realism

(1)  Mearsheimer, John J a  

a NONE

Author keywords

Balancing; International outcomes; Normative theory; Rational actor assumption; Realism; State behavior; Status quo bias; Suboptimal behavior; Theory of foreign policy; Theory of international relations

Indexed keywords


EID: 69249178095     PISSN: 00471178     EISSN: 17412862     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/0047117809104637     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (91)

References (72)
  • 2
    • 0005904588 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For examples of scholars arguing that realists assume states to be rational actors, see, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,)
    • For examples of scholars arguing that realists assume states to be rational actors, see Jack Donnelly, Realism and International Relations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), pp. 64-5
    • (2000) Realism and International Relations , pp. 64-5
    • Donnelly, J.1
  • 3
    • 0004143348 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Robert O. Keohane (ed.), (New York: Columbia University Press,)
    • Robert O. Keohane (ed.), Neorealism and its Critics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1986), pp. 7, 167;
    • (1986) Neorealism and its Critics
  • 4
    • 0033442950 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Is Anybody Still a Realist?
    • Jeffrey W. Legro and Andrew Moravscik, Is Anybody Still a Realist? International Security, 24(2), 1999, pp. 6-7, 12-13, 18.
    • (1999) International Security , vol.24 , Issue.2
    • Legro, J.W.1    Moravscik, A.2
  • 5
    • 0001873679 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Horses for Courses: Why Not Neorealist Theories of Foreign Policy?
    • For examples of scholars arguing that Waltz assumes that states are rational agents, see
    • For examples of scholars arguing that Waltz assumes that states are rational agents, see Colin Elman, Horses for Courses: Why Not Neorealist Theories of Foreign Policy? Security Studies, 6(1), 1996, p. 43
    • (1996) Security Studies , vol.6 , Issue.1 , pp. 43
    • Elman, C.1
  • 6
    • 79952787250 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • unpublished book manuscript, University of Chicago, 3 April, ch. 5
    • Charles L. Glaser, Theory of Rational International Politics, unpublished book manuscript, University of Chicago, 3 April 2008, ch. 5, p. 4;
    • (2008) Theory of Rational International Politics
    • Glaser, C.L.1
  • 8
    • 84937267392 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rationality in International Relations
    • On realism's complicated relationship with the rational actor assumption, see
    • On realism's complicated relationship with the rational actor assumption, see Miles Kahler, Rationality in International Relations, International Organization, 52(4), 1998, pp. 919-25
    • (1998) International Organization , vol.52 , Issue.4 , pp. 919-25
    • Kahler, M.1
  • 9
    • 84937326543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Power Test: Evaluating Realism in Response to the End of the Cold War
    • Randall L. Schweller and William C. Wohlforth, Power Test: Evaluating Realism in Response to the End of the Cold War, Security Studies, 9(3), 2000, p. 70.
    • (2000) Security Studies , vol.9 , Issue.3 , pp. 70
    • Schweller, R.L.1    Wohlforth, W.C.2
  • 10
    • 0002767132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reflections on Theory of International Politics: A Response to My Critics
    • in Keohane
    • Kenneth N. Waltz, Reflections on Theory of International Politics: A Response to My Critics, in Keohane, Neorealism and its Critics, p. 330
    • Neorealism and its Critics , pp. 330
    • Waltz, K.N.1
  • 12
    • 69249191248 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • comment made by Kenneth Waltz at 'The King of Thought' conference, Aberystwyth, 17 September 2008. It is worth noting that Waltz maintains that, 'deterrence does not depend on rationality. It depends on fear.', (New York: Norton,)
    • comment made by Kenneth Waltz at 'The King of Thought' conference, Aberystwyth, 17 September 2008. It is worth noting that Waltz maintains that, 'deterrence does not depend on rationality. It depends on fear.' Scott D. Sagan and Kenneth N. Waltz, The Spread of Nuclear Weapons: A Debate Renewed (New York: Norton, 2003), p. 154.
    • (2003) The Spread of Nuclear Weapons: A Debate Renewed , pp. 154
    • Sagan, S.D.1    Waltz, K.N.2
  • 16
    • 85050416431 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For Waltz's theory to work, he also needs to assume that states can never be certain about the intentions of other states. See Conversations in International Relations - Interview with, (Part II)
    • For Waltz's theory to work, he also needs to assume that states can never be certain about the intentions of other states. See Conversations in International Relations - Interview with John J. Mearsheimer (Part II), International Relations, 20(2), 2006, pp. 231, 240-1.
    • (2006) International Relations , vol.20 , Issue.2
    • Mearsheimer, J.J.1
  • 17
    • 0003333081 scopus 로고
    • The Origins of War in Neorealist Theory
    • I cannot find any place in Waltz's work where he explicitly argues that states should seek to gain power at the expense of other states. I do think, however, that it is implicit in his work that states should seek to improve their position in the balance of power, although he makes clear that they should not attempt to gain too much power. The best discussion of his thinking about war is, in Robert I. Rotberg and Theodore K. Rabb (eds), (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,)
    • I cannot find any place in Waltz's work where he explicitly argues that states should seek to gain power at the expense of other states. I do think, however, that it is implicit in his work that states should seek to improve their position in the balance of power, although he makes clear that they should not attempt to gain too much power. The best discussion of his thinking about war is Kenneth N. Waltz, The Origins of War in Neorealist Theory, in Robert I. Rotberg and Theodore K. Rabb (eds), The Origins and Prevention of Major Wars (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), pp. 39-52.
    • (1988) The Origins and Prevention of Major Wars , pp. 39-52
    • Waltz, K.N.1
  • 18
    • 84979705350 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Waltz sometimes argues that wars are the result of uncertainty and miscalculation, which seems to imply that starting wars is a mistake
    • Waltz sometimes argues that wars are the result of uncertainty and miscalculation, which seems to imply that starting wars is a mistake. Origins of War, p. 47
    • Origins of War , pp. 47
  • 20
    • 84873864330 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Waltz, Theory, pp. 190-1.
    • Theory , pp. 190-1
    • Waltz1
  • 30
    • 69249169734 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On balancing and bandwagoning more generally, see
    • On balancing and bandwagoning more generally, see Theory, pp. 124-8.
    • Theory , pp. 124-8
  • 31
    • 0003134512 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Neorealism's Status-Quo Bias: What Security Dilemma?
    • Randall L. Schweller, Neorealism's Status-Quo Bias: What Security Dilemma? Security Studies, 5(3), 1996, pp. 90-121.
    • (1996) Security Studies , vol.5 , Issue.3 , pp. 90-121
    • Schweller, R.L.1
  • 32
    • 36749012937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The International Wanderings of a Liberal Idea, or Why Liberals Can Learn to Stop Worrying and Love the Balance of Power
    • Although Schweller was the first person to describe Waltz's theory as having a 'status-quo bias', he does not argue it is due to balancing behavior, as I do. Instead, he argues that it is because Waltz focuses exclusively on security-seeking states and ignores revisionist or greedy states. Also see
    • Although Schweller was the first person to describe Waltz's theory as having a 'status-quo bias', he does not argue it is due to balancing behavior, as I do. Instead, he argues that it is because Waltz focuses exclusively on security-seeking states and ignores revisionist or greedy states. Also see Deborah Boucoyannis, The International Wanderings of a Liberal Idea, or Why Liberals Can Learn to Stop Worrying and Love the Balance of Power, Perspectives on Politics, 5(4), 2007, pp. 710-11, 719;
    • (2007) Perspectives on Politics , vol.5 , Issue.4
    • Boucoyannis, D.1
  • 34
    • 84974173124 scopus 로고
    • Realism, Neorealism, and American Liberalism
    • Keith L. Shimko, Realism, Neorealism, and American Liberalism, Review of Politics, 54(2), 1992, pp. 281-301
    • (1992) Review of Politics , vol.54 , Issue.2 , pp. 281-301
    • Shimko, K.L.1
  • 35
    • 0003461380 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I disagree with Waltz on this important point. I argue that the international system would be competitive and dangerous even if all the states were rational agents, (New York: Norton), As discussed below, Waltz's world becomes competitive and dangerous once he takes away the rational actor assumption and allows that great powers often act recklessly. Indeed, I maintain that states become even more aggressive than he appears to recognize. I do not explore our difference, however, because the focus here is on examining Waltz's theory on its own terms
    • I disagree with Waltz on this important point. I argue that the international system would be competitive and dangerous even if all the states were rational agents. John J. Mearsheimer, The Tragedy of Great Power Politics (New York: Norton, 2001). As discussed below, Waltz's world becomes competitive and dangerous once he takes away the rational actor assumption and allows that great powers often act recklessly. Indeed, I maintain that states become even more aggressive than he appears to recognize. I do not explore our difference, however, because the focus here is on examining Waltz's theory on its own terms.
    • (2001) The Tragedy of Great Power Politics
    • Mearsheimer, J.J.1
  • 36
    • 69249181061 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Recklessness is not simply misguided aggressiveness. A reckless state can also fail to take the necessary steps to defend itself against a dangerous adversary
    • Recklessness is not simply misguided aggressiveness. A reckless state can also fail to take the necessary steps to defend itself against a dangerous adversary.
  • 38
    • 69249167719 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Comment made by, at, conference
    • Comment made by Waltz at The King of Thought conference.
    • The King of Thought
    • Waltz1
  • 39
    • 84865717399 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Interview with Ken Waltz
    • Waltz told Fred Halliday and Justin Rosenberg in May 1993, 'I've been a fierce critic of American military policy and spending and strategy, at least since the 1970s.' See
    • Waltz told Fred Halliday and Justin Rosenberg in May 1993, 'I've been a fierce critic of American military policy and spending and strategy, at least since the 1970s.' See Interview with Ken Waltz, Review of International Studies, 24(3), 1998, p. 373.
    • (1998) Review of International Studies , vol.24 , Issue.3 , pp. 373
  • 40
    • 80051765045 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • He elaborates his criticisms throughout this interview. Also see, ch. 23
    • He elaborates his criticisms throughout this interview. Also see Waltz, Realism and International Politics, ch. 23.
    • Realism and International Politics
    • Waltz1
  • 42
    • 69249195503 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Theory, Waltz emphasizes that socialization and competition are important processes that tend to produce 'sameness' among states. 'Competition', he argues, 'spurs the actors to accommodate their ways to the socially most acceptable and successful practices. Socialization and competition are two aspects of a process by which the variety of behaviors and of outcomes is reduced.' Theory, pp. 74-7, 127-8. One might think that socialization and competition lead states to become increasingly rational over time in Waltz's world. But he does not make that argument; there is no evidence from his writings that he believes that states have learned to act more strategically over time. As he remarked at the 'King of Thought' conference, 'state learning is not impressive'. Of course, in a world where reckless states are commonplace, socialization might very well perpetuate the presence of reckless states, and undermine smart learning
    • In Theory, Waltz emphasizes that socialization and competition are important processes that tend to produce 'sameness' among states. 'Competition', he argues, 'spurs the actors to accommodate their ways to the socially most acceptable and successful practices. Socialization and competition are two aspects of a process by which the variety of behaviors and of outcomes is reduced.' Theory, pp. 74-7, 127-8. One might think that socialization and competition lead states to become increasingly rational over time in Waltz's world. But he does not make that argument; there is no evidence from his writings that he believes that states have learned to act more strategically over time. As he remarked at the 'King of Thought' conference, 'state learning is not impressive'. Of course, in a world where reckless states are commonplace, socialization might very well perpetuate the presence of reckless states, and undermine smart learning.
  • 43
    • 84873864330 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Also see
    • Waltz, Theory, p. 72. Also see pp. 67-73, 121-3.
    • Theory
    • Waltz1
  • 46
  • 48
    • 0002487538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • International Politics Is Not Foreign Policy
    • Also see, and Colin Elman, 'A Response to Kenneth Waltz', in
    • Also see Kenneth N. Waltz, International Politics Is Not Foreign Policy, and Colin Elman, 'A Response to Kenneth Waltz', in Security Studies, 6(1), 1996, pp. 54-61.
    • (1996) Security Studies , vol.6 , Issue.1 , pp. 54-61
    • Waltz, K.N.1
  • 50
    • 80051765045 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This subheading is based on Waltz's comment that, 'A theory is not a statement about everything that is important in international-political life, but rather a necessarily slender explanatory construct.'
    • This subheading is based on Waltz's comment that, 'A theory is not a statement about everything that is important in international-political life, but rather a necessarily slender explanatory construct.' Waltz, Realism and International Politics, p. 76.
    • Realism and International Politics , pp. 76
    • Waltz1
  • 54
    • 46949101769 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Rose by Any Other Name: Neoclassical Realism as the Logical and Necessary Extension of Structural Realism
    • Neoclassical realists also combine realist and unit-level variables in ways that are consistent with Waltz's thinking. See
    • Neoclassical realists also combine realist and unit-level variables in ways that are consistent with Waltz's thinking. See Brian Rathbun, A Rose by Any Other Name: Neoclassical Realism as the Logical and Necessary Extension of Structural Realism, Security Studies, 17(2), 2008, pp. 294-321.
    • (2008) Security Studies , vol.17 , Issue.2 , pp. 294-321
    • Rathbun, B.1
  • 55
    • 69249173909 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The fact that realists like Posen, Snyder, and Van Evera incorporate domestic political factors into their theories leads Jeffrey Legro and Andrew Moravscik to question whether they should be categorized as realists. 'Is Anybody Still a Realist?' There is no question that these scholars have developed compound theories, not straightforward realist theories, and thus one can legitimately raise questions about whether they should be categorized as realists. But this is simply a labeling issue, which is of little consequence
    • The fact that realists like Posen, Snyder, and Van Evera incorporate domestic political factors into their theories leads Jeffrey Legro and Andrew Moravscik to question whether they should be categorized as realists. 'Is Anybody Still a Realist?' There is no question that these scholars have developed compound theories, not straightforward realist theories, and thus one can legitimately raise questions about whether they should be categorized as realists. But this is simply a labeling issue, which is of little consequence.
  • 57
    • 0039907927 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nevertheless, Waltz does appear to make some policy predictions, as Colin Elman points out in
    • Nevertheless, Waltz does appear to make some policy predictions, as Colin Elman points out in Horses for Courses, pp. 10-11.
    • Horses for Courses , pp. 10-11
  • 58
    • 69249161513 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, Waltz's theory allows for rational as well as misguided states. He is not saying that all great powers behave foolishly all of the time. Indeed, there have to be some savvy states if balancing coalitions are to form against especially aggressive great powers. His theory should be able to predict how those rational states will act, and he says as much when he writes: 'The theory leads us to expect states to behave in ways that result in balances forming.', Also see
    • Of course, Waltz's theory allows for rational as well as misguided states. He is not saying that all great powers behave foolishly all of the time. Indeed, there have to be some savvy states if balancing coalitions are to form against especially aggressive great powers. His theory should be able to predict how those rational states will act, and he says as much when he writes: 'The theory leads us to expect states to behave in ways that result in balances forming.' Theory, p. 125. Also see pp. 71-2, 128
    • Theory
  • 60
    • 69249172808 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is the behavior of reckless states that his theory cannot explain. And given how commonplace they are in his world, he has little choice but to concentrate on explaining outcomes, while maintaining that 'the behavior of states and of statesmen ... is indeterminate'
    • It is the behavior of reckless states that his theory cannot explain. And given how commonplace they are in his world, he has little choice but to concentrate on explaining outcomes, while maintaining that 'the behavior of states and of statesmen ... is indeterminate'. Theory, p. 68.
    • Theory , pp. 68
  • 63
    • 84873864330 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Also see
    • Also see Waltz, Theory, p. 70.
    • Theory , pp. 70
    • Waltz1
  • 64
    • 0032339799 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Domestic Politics, Foreign Policy, and Theories of International Relations
    • Two other studies which emphasize the connection between behavior and outcomes in Waltz's work are Elman, 'Horses for Courses', and
    • Two other studies which emphasize the connection between behavior and outcomes in Waltz's work are Elman, 'Horses for Courses', and James D. Fearon, Domestic Politics, Foreign Policy, and Theories of International Relations, Annual Review of Political Science, 1, 1998, pp. 289-313.
    • (1998) Annual Review of Political Science , vol.1 , pp. 289-313
    • Fearon, J.D.1
  • 69
    • 84876840844 scopus 로고
    • Primed for Peace: Europe After the Cold War
    • Stephen Van Evera, Primed for Peace: Europe After the Cold War, International Security, 15(3), 1990/1, p. 36.
    • (1990) International Security , vol.15 , Issue.3 , pp. 36
    • van Evera, S.1
  • 70
    • 79952787250 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ch. 1, p. 24; ch. 2, p. 1; ch. 6, p. 1. Another option is to view Waltz's theory as a Weberian 'ideal type' that helps to make the workings of the international system intelligible, but does not explain how it works in practice
    • Glaser, Theory of Rational International Politics, ch. 1, p. 24; ch. 2, p. 1; ch. 6, p. 1. Another option is to view Waltz's theory as a Weberian 'ideal type' that helps to make the workings of the international system intelligible, but does not explain how it works in practice.
    • Theory of Rational International Politics
    • Glaser1
  • 71
    • 67749133356 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Importance of Social Philosophy to Morgenthau and Waltz
    • in G. O. Mazur (ed.), (New York: Semenenko Foundation,)
    • Stephen Turner, The Importance of Social Philosophy to Morgenthau and Waltz, in G. O. Mazur (ed.), Twenty-Five Year Memorial Commemoration to the Life of Hans Morgenthau (1904-2005) (New York: Semenenko Foundation, 2006), pp. 174-93.
    • (2006) Twenty-Five Year Memorial Commemoration to the Life of Hans Morgenthau (1904-2005) , pp. 174-93
    • Turner, S.1
  • 72
    • 84921559498 scopus 로고
    • Also see, ed. and trans. Michael Howard and Peter Paret (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press,)
    • Also see Carl Von Clausewitz, On War, ed. and trans. Michael Howard and Peter Paret (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1976), p. 141.
    • (1976) On War , pp. 141
    • von Clausewitz, C.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.