-
2
-
-
62749132996
-
Illusory losses
-
Cass R. Sunstein, Illusory Losses, 37 J. LEGAL STUD. S157, S176, S178 (2008) (arguing that the legal system can award damages to one that loses a capability on the basis of something aside from hedonic loss);
-
(2008)
J. Legal Stud.
, vol.37
-
-
Sunstein, C.R.1
-
3
-
-
62749100125
-
Pain and suffering awards: They shouldn't be (just) about pain and suffering
-
Peter A. Ubel & George Loewenstein, Pain and Suffering Awards: They Shouldn't Be (Just) About Pain and Suffering, 37 J. LEGAL STUD. S195, S206 (2008) (noting that because "there are dimensions of richness of experience and complexity and sophistication of thought that have value over and above simple happiness," it cannot be the only measure of harm);
-
(2008)
J. Legal Stud.
, vol.37
-
-
Ubel, P.A.1
Loewenstein, G.2
-
4
-
-
79955442048
-
-
Mar. 2, unpublished manuscript
-
Rick Swedloff & Peter H. Huang, Tort Damages and the New Science of Happiness 37 (Mar. 2, 2009) (unpublished manuscript), available at http:/ /works.bepress.com/peter-huang/l (noting that "[i]n addition to, or quite possibly even completely besides, the presence of positive affect and the absence of negative affect, people want additional desiderata");
-
(2009)
Tort Damages and the New Science of Happiness
, pp. 37
-
-
Swedloff, R.1
Huang, P.H.2
-
5
-
-
36248991788
-
Hedonic damages, hedonic adaptation, and disability
-
see Samuel R. Bagenstos & Margo Schlanger, Hedonic Damages, Hedonic Adaptation, and Disability, 60 VAND. L. REV. 745, 760 (2007) (arguing that the view that disability limits the ability to enjoy life does not reflect how most people with disabilities actually feel).
-
(2007)
Vand. L. Rev.
, vol.60
-
-
Bagenstos, S.R.1
Schlanger, M.2
-
6
-
-
79955378593
-
-
Sunstein, supra note 2, at S178
-
Sunstein, supra note 2, at S178.
-
-
-
-
7
-
-
0038979676
-
An integrated model of psychosocial adjustment following acquired disability
-
Elizabeth Kendall & Nicholas Buys, An Integrated Model of Psychosocial Adjustment Following Acquired Disability, 64 J. REHABILITATION 16, 17 (1998) (discussing the psychological tension of navigating a change in self-identity that occurs post disability).
-
(1998)
J. Rehabilitation
, vol.64
-
-
Kendall, E.1
Buys, N.2
-
8
-
-
79955376008
-
-
Übel & Loewenstein, supra note 2, at S198
-
Übel & Loewenstein, supra note 2, at S198.
-
-
-
-
9
-
-
79955380579
-
-
See infra Part I.A
-
See infra Part I.A.
-
-
-
-
10
-
-
71849090367
-
Happiness and punishment
-
See, e.g., John Bronsteen, Christopher Buccafusco & Jonathan Masur, Happiness and Punishment, 76 U. CHI. L. REV. 1037, 1038 (2009)
-
(2009)
U. Chi. L. Rev.
, vol.76
-
-
Bronsteen, J.1
Buccafusco, C.2
Masur, J.3
-
11
-
-
78651330343
-
-
[hereinafter Happiness and Punishment] (studying how adaptation to prison makes it difficult to fashion appropriate sentences);
-
Happiness and Punishment
-
-
-
12
-
-
56849084593
-
Hedonic adaptation and the seulement of civil lawsuits
-
John Bronsteen, Christopher Buccafusco & Jonathan S. Masur, Hedonic Adaptation and the Seulement of Civil Lawsuits, 108 COLUM. L. REV. 1516, 1516 (2008)
-
(2008)
Colum. L. Rev.
, vol.108
-
-
Bronsteen, J.1
Buccafusco, C.2
Masur, J.S.3
-
14
-
-
79955422396
-
-
Sunstein, supra note 2, at S160
-
Sunstein, supra note 2, at S160 (noting the "emerging literature attempting to measure hedonic effects");
-
-
-
-
15
-
-
79955427493
-
-
Ubel & Loewenstein, supra note 2
-
Ubel & Loewenstein, supra note 2;
-
-
-
-
16
-
-
79955397682
-
-
Bagenstos &: Schlanger, supra note 2, at 746
-
see also Bagenstos &: Schlanger, supra note 2, at 746 (noting that the concept of adaptive preferences has played an important role in several fields over the past twenty-five years);
-
-
-
-
17
-
-
29744449014
-
Progressive taxation and happiness
-
Thomas D. Griffith, Progressive Taxation and Happiness, 45 B.C. L. REV. 1363, 1365 (2004) (analyzing how research on happiness can inform income redistribution);
-
(2004)
B.C. L. Rev.
, vol.45
-
-
Griffith, T.D.1
-
18
-
-
79955419372
-
-
Swedloff & Huang, supra note 2, at 2
-
Swedloff & Huang, supra note 2, at 2 (noting the emergence of "legal hedonists" who argue new data on happiness requires changes to existing legal institutions).
-
-
-
-
21
-
-
0035125390
-
Quality of life after spinal cord injury: A qualitative study
-
These events will almost certainly have immediate, if fleeting, emotional effects. Colette Hillebrand Duggan & Marcel Dijkers, Quality of Life After Spinal Cord Injury: A Qualitative Study, 46 REHABILITATION PSYCHOL. 3, 23 (2001) (reporting that the suicide rate for those with spinal cord injuries is three to five times higher than the general population, with most suicides occurring within a few years of the initial injury);
-
(2001)
Rehabilitation Psychol.
, vol.46
-
-
Duggan, C.H.1
Dijkers, M.2
-
22
-
-
7544245263
-
Men, sport, and spinal cord injury: An analysis of metaphors and narrative types
-
Brett Smith & Andrew C. Sparkes, Men, Sport, and Spinal Cord Injury: An Analysis of Metaphors and Narrative Types, 19 DISABILITY & SOC'Y 613, 619-20 (2004) ("Before the accident I was happy and life was good. The injury and everything that has happened since has choked any life and happiness out of me. I have nothing now. . . . Am nothing. . . . My life is in darkness. . . . I'm shattered.")(emphasis removed).
-
(2004)
Disability & Soc'y
, vol.19
-
-
Smith, B.1
Sparkes, A.C.2
-
23
-
-
0032159427
-
Immune neglect: A source of durability bias in affective forecasting
-
See generally Daniel T. Gilbert et al., Immune Neglect: A Source of Durability Bias in Affective Forecasting, 75 J. PERSONALITY & Soc. PSYCHOL. 617 (1998) (noting that individuals neglect their psychological immune systems when making predictions about the duration of their affective reactions to negative events).
-
(1998)
J. Personality & Soc. Psychol.
, vol.75
, pp. 617
-
-
Gilbert, D.T.1
-
24
-
-
0000234279
-
Coping with irrevocable loss
-
Gary R. VandenBos & Brenda K. Bryant eds
-
See Camille B. Wortman & Roxanne Cohen Silver, Coping with Irrevocable Loss, in CATACLYSMS, CRISES, AND CATASTROPHES: PSYCHOLOGY IN ACTION, 185, 197-99 (Gary R. VandenBos & Brenda K. Bryant eds., 1987) (analyzing the effect of time on the happiness of individuals who recently suffered spinal cord injuries).
-
(1987)
Cataclysms, Crises, and Catastrophes: Psychology in Action
-
-
Wortman, C.B.1
Silver, R.C.2
-
25
-
-
0026018685
-
Spinal cord injuries: Clinical, functional, and emotional status
-
See generally C. Lundqvist et al., Spinal Cord Injuries: Clinical, Functional, and Emotional Status, 16 SPINE 78 (1991) (analyzing the effect of time on the moods of persons with tetraplegia and paraplegia).
-
(1991)
Spine
, vol.16
, pp. 78
-
-
Lundqvist, C.1
-
26
-
-
0026694508
-
Psychosocial adaptation of children and adolescents with limb deficiencies: A review
-
See Vida L. Tyc, Psychosocial Adaptation of Children and Adolescents with Limb Deficiencies: A Review, 12 CLINICAL PSYCHOL. REV. 275, 275 (1992) (noting that "the available literature suggests that pediatric amputees report minimal psychosocial distress, achieve good functional outcomes, and adapt well to their disability").
-
(1992)
Clinical Psychol. Rev.
, vol.12
-
-
Tyc, V.L.1
-
27
-
-
0027562997
-
Psychological effects of severe burn injuries
-
See David R. Patterson et al., Psychological Effects of Severe Burn Injuries, 113 PSYCHOL. BULL. 362, 364 (1993) (arguing that "most people seem to undergo emotional adjustment to burn injuries relatively well").
-
(1993)
Psychol. Bull.
, vol.113
-
-
Patterson, D.R.1
-
28
-
-
13844272552
-
Ignorance of hedonic adaptation to hemodialysis: A study using ecological momentary assessment
-
See Jason Riis et al., Ignorance of Hedonic Adaptation to Hemodialysis: A Study Using Ecological Momentary Assessment, 134 J. EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOL. 3, 7 (2005) (finding that hemodialysis patients adapt to their condition).
-
(2005)
J. Experimental Psychol.
, vol.134
-
-
Riis, J.1
-
29
-
-
79955381660
-
-
Gilbert et al., supra note 10, at 623-24
-
Additionally, failing to obtain tenure appears to have no long-term hedonic impact Gilbert et al., supra note 10, at 623-24.
-
-
-
-
30
-
-
85047683481
-
Lollery winners and accident victims: Is happiness relative?
-
Philip Brickman et al., Lollery Winners and Accident Victims: Is Happiness Relative?, 36 J. PERSONALITY & Soc. PSYCHOL. 917, 926 (1978) (suggesting that individuals overestimate the duration of feeling generated by an event).
-
(1978)
J. Personality & Soc. Psychol.
, vol.36
-
-
Brickman, P.1
-
31
-
-
79955440413
-
-
Id. at 920-22
-
Id. at 920-22.
-
-
-
-
32
-
-
34547577613
-
Psychological or physiological: Why are tetraplegic patients content?
-
See, e.g., Fátima de N. Abrantes-Pais et al., Psychological or Physiological: Why Are Tetraplegic Patients Content?, 69 NEUROLOGY 261, 261 (2007) (finding that persons with spinal cord injuries report being overall content);
-
(2007)
Neurology
, vol.69
-
-
De Abrantes-Pais, F.N.1
-
33
-
-
4143129892
-
Psychosocial adjustment to lower-limb amputation: A review
-
Olga Horgan & Malcolm MacLachlan, Psychosocial Adjustment to Lower-Limb Amputation: A Review, 26 DISABILITY & REHABILITATION 837, 839 (2004) (finding that while rates of depression in people with an amputation are high between the first and second years following amputation, rates decrease after this period to what is found in the general population);
-
(2004)
Disability & Rehabilitation
, vol.26
-
-
Horgan, O.1
MacLachlan, M.2
-
34
-
-
79955459209
-
-
Riis et al., supra note 15, at 7
-
Riis et al., supra note 15, at 7 (finding no difference in moods between dialysis patients and control patients).
-
-
-
-
35
-
-
40849130124
-
Does happiness adapt? A longitudinal study of disability with implications for economists and judges
-
Andrew J. Oswald & Nattavudh Powdthavee, Does Happiness Adapt? A Longitudinal Study of Disability with Implications for Economists and Judges, 92 J. PUB. ECON. 1061, 1066 (2008) (noting that level of happiness falls abruptly in the year of injury).
-
(2008)
J. Pub. Econ.
, vol.92
-
-
Oswald, A.J.1
Powdthavee, N.2
-
36
-
-
0003495123
-
-
This Article adopts the social model of disability. Under this model, the bare physical alteration of the body that accompanies an injury is called an impairment When the victim's surrounding environment does not accommodate the impairment, the interaction of the impairment and the environment creates a disability. For further discussions on these concepts, see MICHAEL OLIVER, THE POLITICS OF DISABLEMENT: A SOCIOLOGICAL APPROACH 11 (1990).
-
(1990)
The Politics of Disablement: A Sociological Approach
, pp. 11
-
-
Oliver, M.1
-
37
-
-
79955453185
-
-
Oswald & Powddiavee, supra note 20, at 1072
-
Oswald & Powddiavee, supra note 20, at 1072.
-
-
-
-
38
-
-
34249706821
-
Long-term disability is associated with lasting changes in subjective well-being: Evidence from two nationally representative longitudinal studies
-
But see Richard E. Lucas, Long-Term Disability Is Associated with Lasting Changes in Subjective Well-Being: Evidence from Two Nationally Representative Longitudinal Studies, 92 J. PERSONALITY & Soc. PSYCHOL. 717, 722 (2007) (finding no evidence of hedonic adaption based on the same underlying data).
-
(2007)
J. Personality & Soc. Psychol.
, vol.92
-
-
Lucas, R.E.1
-
39
-
-
79955400700
-
-
Ubel & Loewenstein, supra note 2, at S200
-
See Ubel & Loewenstein, supra note 2, at S200.
-
-
-
-
40
-
-
0025380528
-
The Duchenne smile: Emotional expression and brain physiology II
-
See, e.g., Paul Ekman et al., The Duchenne Smile: Emotional Expression and Brain Physiology II, 58 J. PERSONALITY & Soc. PSYCHOL. 342, 342 (1990).
-
(1990)
J. Personality & Soc. Psychol.
, vol.58
-
-
Ekman, P.1
-
41
-
-
79955460171
-
-
Ubel & Loewenstein, supra note 2, at S199-S202
-
For a concise defense of happiness research, see Ubel & Loewenstein, supra note 2, at S199-S202.
-
-
-
-
42
-
-
62749097388
-
Who is the happy warrior? Philosophy poses questions to psychology
-
For several concerns about the importance of happiness research, see generally Martha C. Nussbaum, Who Is the Happy Warrior? Philosophy Poses Questions to Psychology, 37 J. LEGAL STUD. S81 (2008).
-
(2008)
J. Legal Stud.
, vol.37
-
-
Nussbaum, M.C.1
-
43
-
-
0028899901
-
Psychosocial adaption to disability and its investigation among persons with multiple sclerosis
-
See Richard F. Antonak & Hanoch Livneh, Psychosocial Adaption to Disability and Its Investigation Among Persons with Multiple Sclerosis, 40 Soc. Sci. MED. 1099, 1105 (1995) (noting that reactions of anxiety, depression, and irritability are common during the period when symptoms of multiple sclerosis become apparent, followed by a period of acceptance, followed by a period of "pronounced and prolonged disintegration");
-
(1995)
Soc. Sci. Med.
, vol.40
-
-
Antonak, R.F.1
Livneh, H.2
-
44
-
-
0026438171
-
Adaptation in patients with chronic rheumatoid arthritis: Application of a general model
-
Craig A Smith & Kenneth A Wallston, Adaptation in Patients with Chronic Rheumatoid Arthritis: Application of a General Model, 11 HEALTH PSYCHOL. 151, 151 (1992) (noting that rheumatoid arthritis has been "linked to poor adjustment").
-
(1992)
Health Psychol.
, vol.11
-
-
Smith, C.A.1
Wallston, K.A.2
-
45
-
-
25144451764
-
Heath, weatlh, and happiness: Financial resources buffer subjective well-being after the onset of a disability
-
See Dylan M. Smith et al., Heath, Weatlh, and Happiness: Financial Resources Buffer Subjective Well-Being After the Onset of a Disability, 16 PSYCHOL. SCI. 663, 665 (2005) (finding that wealth buffers against the detrimental effects of disability, but that the gap narrows over time).
-
(2005)
Psychol. Sci.
, vol.16
-
-
Smith, D.M.1
-
46
-
-
0029883651
-
Psychosocial adjustment following closed head injury: A model for understanding individual differences and predicting outcome
-
See Elizabeth Kendall & Deborah J. Terry, Psychosocial Adjustment Following Closed Head Injury: A Model for Understanding Individual Differences and Predicting Outcome, 6 NEUROPSYCHOL. REHABILITATION 101, 115-16 (1996) (noting that "self-esteem and control expectancies may play a role in the facilitation of adjustment after CHI").
-
(1996)
Neuropsychol. Rehabilitation
, vol.6
-
-
Kendall, E.1
Terry, D.J.2
-
47
-
-
0021305962
-
Physically disabled people assess the quality of their lives
-
See Nancy Weinberg, Physically Disabled People Assess the Quality of Their Lives, 45 REHABILITATION LITERATURE 12, 14 (1984) (finding that, out of thiirty patients who were interviewed, two would refuse a free riskless cure, and three were "hesitant").
-
(1984)
Rehabilitation Literature
, vol.45
-
-
Weinberg, N.1
-
48
-
-
33750967918
-
Misremembering colostomies? Former patients give lower utility ratings than do current patients
-
See Dylan M. Smith et al., Misremembering Colostomies? Former Patients Give Lower Utility Ratings Than Do Current Patients, 25 HEALTH PSYCHOL. 688, 691 (2006) (finding that current colostomy patients were willing to give up, on average, 15% of their remaining life years to reverse the colostomy).
-
(2006)
Health Psychol.
, vol.25
-
-
Smith, D.M.1
-
49
-
-
34548676552
-
Prospection: Experiencing the future
-
Daniel T. Gilbert & Timothy D. Wilson, Prospection: Experiencing the Future, 317 SCIENCE 1351, 1353 (2007) ("The tendency to underestimate how quickly we will adapt to a wide range of pleasurable and painful events is probably the most commonly observed error in research on hedonic prediction." (citation omitted)).
-
(2007)
Science
, vol.317
-
-
Gilbert, D.T.1
Wilson, T.D.2
-
50
-
-
79955366732
-
-
Gilbert et al., supra note 10, at 623-24
-
Gilbert et al., supra note 10, at 623-24.
-
-
-
-
51
-
-
0039915193
-
Does living in california make people happy? A focusing illusion in judgments of life satisfaction
-
See David A Schkade & Daniel Kahneman, Does Living in California Make People Happy? A Focusing Illusion in Judgments of Life Satisfaction, 9 PSYCHOL. SCI. 340, 345 (1998).
-
(1998)
Psychol. Sci.
, vol.9
-
-
Schkade, D.A.1
Kahneman, D.2
-
52
-
-
36348949003
-
Relationship between quality of life and self-efficacy in persons with spinal cord injuries
-
Although victims of spinal cord injuries have persistently lower quality of life ratings than the general population, James Middleton et al., Relationship Between Quality of Life and Self-Efficacy in Persons with Spinal Cord Injuries, 88 ARCHIVES PHYSICAL MED. & REHABILITATION 1643, 1643 (2007), people appear to exaggerate the negative effect of spinal cord injuries on quality of life.
-
(2007)
Archives Physical Med. & Rehabilitation
, vol.88
-
-
Middleton, J.1
-
53
-
-
22944442223
-
Disability and sunshine: Can hedonic predictions be improved by drawing attention to focusing illusions or emotional adaptation?
-
See Peter A. Ubel et al., Disability and Sunshine: Can Hedonic Predictions Be Improved by Drawing Attention to Focusing Illusions or Emotional Adaptation?, 11 J. EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOL.: APPLIED 111, 117-18 (2005) (finding that subjects predicted low quality of life after paraplegia, but that these rating increased when subjects were explicitly asked to consider how they might adapt to the disability).
-
(2005)
J. Experimental Psychol.: Applied
, vol.11
-
-
Ubel, P.A.1
-
54
-
-
0018155086
-
The utility of different health states as perceived by the general public
-
See David L. Sackett & George W. Torrance, The Utility of Different Health States as Perceived by the General Public, 31 J. CHRONIC DISEASES 697, 702 (1978) (finding that individuals already on a home dialysis program rated their daily health state utility higher than individuals predicted their daily health state utility would be if on dialysis).
-
(1978)
J. Chronic Diseases
, vol.31
-
-
Sackett, D.L.1
Torrance, G.W.2
-
55
-
-
0025217036
-
Whose utilities for decision analysis?
-
See Norman F. Boyd et al., Whose Utilities for Decision Analysis?, 10 MED. DECISION MAKING 58, 65 (1990).
-
(1990)
Med. Decision Making
, vol.10
-
-
Boyd, N.F.1
-
56
-
-
0034455460
-
Perception of quality of life by patients, partners and treating physicians
-
See Kerry A. Wilson et al., Perception of Quality of Life by Patients, Partners and Treating Physicians, 9 QUALITY LIFE RES. 1041, 1045 (2000) (noting that physicians underestimate patient quality of life for patients with metastatic breast cancer).
-
(2000)
Quality Life Res.
, vol.9
-
-
Wilson, K.A.1
-
57
-
-
79955426035
-
-
Sackett & Torrance, supra note 34, at 702
-
See generally Sackett & Torrance, supra note 34, at 702;
-
-
-
-
58
-
-
79955404374
-
-
Ubel et al., supra note 33, at 120
-
Ubel et al., supra note 33, at 120 (noting that "people predict that their quality of life with various disabilities would be lower than the quality of life actually reported by people who have those disabilities");
-
-
-
-
59
-
-
23244432843
-
Misimagining the unimaginable: The disability paradox and health care decision making
-
Peter A. Ubel et al., Misimagining the Unimaginable: The Disability Paradox and Health Care Decision Making, 24 HEALTH PSYCHOL. S57, S57 (2005) (noting that people "mispredict the impact that circumstances will have on their well-being and quality of life").
-
(2005)
Health Psychol.
, vol.24
-
-
Ubel, P.A.1
-
60
-
-
79955409011
-
-
Ubel & Loewenstein, supra note 2, at S203
-
Ubel & Loewenstein, supra note 2, at S203 (citation omitted).
-
-
-
-
61
-
-
79955398631
-
-
Wilson et al., supra note 36, at 1045
-
Wilson et al., supra note 36, at 1045.
-
-
-
-
62
-
-
79955418375
-
-
Bagenstos & Schlanger, supra note 2, at 752-53
-
Bagenstos & Schlanger, supra note 2, at 752-53.
-
-
-
-
63
-
-
79955402386
-
-
78 S.W.3d 392, 412 Tex. App
-
Schindler Elevator Corp. v. Anderson, 78 S.W.3d 392, 412 (Tex. App. 2001), review granted, judgment vacated, (May 22, 2003);
-
(2001)
Schindler Elevator Corp. V. Anderson
-
-
-
64
-
-
79955446922
-
-
Bagenstos & Schlanger, supra note 2, at 755
-
Bagenstos & Schlanger, supra note 2, at 755 ("In many cases upholding hedonic damages awards, judges seem to have concluded explicitly that the mere fact of disability, without more, necessarily limits life's enjoyment").
-
-
-
-
65
-
-
79955377042
-
-
648 N.E.2d 617, 623 Ill. App. Ct
-
See, e.g. Knight v. Lord, 648 N.E.2d 617, 623 (Ill. App. Ct 1995);
-
(1995)
Knight V. Lord
-
-
-
66
-
-
79955384761
-
-
563 N.E.2d 1279, 1281-83 Ind
-
Canfield v. Sandock, 563 N.E.2d 1279, 1281-83 (Ind. 1990);
-
(1990)
Canfield V. Sandock
-
-
-
68
-
-
79955421854
-
-
791 P.2d 1329, 1336 Kan
-
Gregory v. Carey, 791 P.2d 1329, 1336 (Kan. 1990);
-
(1990)
Gregory V. Carey
-
-
-
69
-
-
79955401315
-
-
951 S.W.2d 318, 320 Ky
-
Giuliani v. Guiler, 951 S.W.2d 318, 320 (Ky. 1997) (noting that it "is the purpose of all tort law to compensate one for the harm caused by another and to deter future wrongdoing");
-
(1997)
Giuliani v. Guiler
-
-
-
71
-
-
79955455214
-
-
277 N.W.2d 697, 700 Neb
-
Swiler v. Baker's Super Mkt., Inc., 277 N.W.2d 697, 700 (Neb. 1979) (noting that a majority of the courts have approved inclusion of "loss of enjoyment of life as a consideration" that may be instructed upon in the proper tort case);
-
(1979)
Swiler V. Baker's Super Mkt., Inc.
-
-
-
72
-
-
79955411999
-
-
102 P.3d 52, 64 Nev
-
Banks v. Sunrise Hosp., 102 P.3d 52, 64 (Nev. 2004);
-
(2004)
Banks V. Sunrise Hosp.
-
-
-
73
-
-
79955391975
-
-
536 N.E.2d 372, 375-77 N.Y
-
McDougald v. Garber, 536 N.E.2d 372, 375-77 (N.Y. 1989);
-
(1989)
McDougald V. Garber
-
-
-
75
-
-
77951865445
-
-
541 S.E.2d 242, 245 S.C
-
Boan v. Blackwell, 541 S.E.2d 242, 245 (S.C. 2001).
-
(2001)
Boan V. Blackwell
-
-
-
76
-
-
62749177989
-
Hedonic damages: The rapidly bubbling cauldron
-
A growing minority separate lost enjoyment of life from other categories of damages. Victor E. Schwartz & Cary Silverman, Hedonic Damages: The Rapidly Bubbling Cauldron, 69 BROOK. L. REV. 1037, 1046 (2004).
-
(2004)
Brook. L. Rev.
, vol.69
-
-
Schwartz, V.E.1
Silverman, C.2
-
77
-
-
79955365646
-
-
Boan, 541 S.E.2d at 244
-
Boan, 541 S.E.2d at 244.
-
-
-
-
78
-
-
79955439886
-
-
775 N.E.2d 865, 877-78 Ohio Ct App
-
Other descriptions of these damages include: "disabilities that include the basic mechanical body functions of walking, climbing, feeding oneself and so on," McGarry v. Horlacher, 775 N.E.2d 865, 877-78 (Ohio Ct App. 2002), "the ability to enjoy the occupation of your choice, activities of daily living, social leisure activities and internal well-being,"
-
(2002)
McGarry V. Horlacher
-
-
-
79
-
-
77951821889
-
-
214 F.3d 1235,1245-46 10th Cir
-
Smith v. Ingersoll-Rand Co., 214 F.3d 1235,1245-46 (10th Cir. 2000) (quotations omitted), and the joy from "going on a first date, reading, debating politics, the sense of taste, recreational activities, and family activities."
-
(2000)
Smith V. Ingersoll-Rand Co.
-
-
-
81
-
-
79955417847
-
-
Bagenstos & Schlanger, supra note 2, at 748-50
-
Bagenstos & Schlanger, supra note 2, at 748-50.
-
-
-
-
82
-
-
79955421856
-
-
127 A. 602, 604 N.J
-
In an early New Jersey case, the court stated that "[a] shriveled hand and wrist.... [D]eprives one of much of the enjoyment of life." Haeussler v. Consol. Stone & Sand Co., 127 A. 602, 604 (N.J. 1925).
-
(1925)
Haeussler V. Consol. Stone & Sand Co.
-
-
-
83
-
-
79955379126
-
-
Bagenstos & Schlanger, supra note 2, at 748
-
See, e.g., Bagenstos & Schlanger, supra note 2, at 748;
-
-
-
-
84
-
-
79955391972
-
-
Schwartz & Silverman, supra note 42, at 1039
-
Schwartz & Silverman, supra note 42, at 1039.
-
-
-
-
85
-
-
79955420334
-
-
Bagenstos & Schlanger, supra note 2, at 797
-
See Bagenstos & Schlanger, supra note 2, at 797.
-
-
-
-
86
-
-
79955424959
-
-
Id
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
87
-
-
79955452705
-
-
Id. at 751
-
Id. at 751.
-
-
-
-
88
-
-
79955458167
-
-
Id
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
89
-
-
79955373921
-
-
Id. at 757 n.49 (collecting cases)
-
Id. at 757 n.49 (collecting cases).
-
-
-
-
90
-
-
79955379124
-
-
Sunstein, supra note 2, at S180
-
Sunstein, supra note 2, at S180 ("A key question, which a reading of the cases cannot answer, is whether the decisions are animated by some kind of hedonic judgment error or instead an intuitive but sensible judgment about capabilities.").
-
-
-
-
91
-
-
79955422392
-
-
Ubel & Loewenstein, supra note 2, at S205
-
See Ubel & Loewenstein, supra note 2, at S205.
-
-
-
-
92
-
-
79955386756
-
-
id. at S205-07
-
See id. at S205-07.
-
-
-
-
93
-
-
0038171291
-
Adler, risk, death and harm: The normative foundations of risk regulation
-
Matthew D. Adler, Risk, Death And Harm: The Normative Foundations of Risk Regulation, 87 MINN. L. REV. 1293, 1322-40 (2003).
-
(2003)
Minn. L. Rev.
, vol.87
-
-
Matthew, D.1
-
94
-
-
79955451203
-
-
id. at 1295
-
See id. at 1295;
-
-
-
-
96
-
-
0001830030
-
An introduction to the principles of morals and legislation
-
Mary Warnock ed
-
Jeremy Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, in JOHN STUART MILL, UTILITARIANISM, ON LIBERTY, ESSAY ON BENTHAM 33, 34 (Mary Warnock ed. 1962) ("By utility is meant that property in any object, whereby it tends to produce benefit, advantage, pleasure, good, or happiness . . . [or] to prevent the happening of mischief, pain, evil, or unhappiness . . . .").
-
(1962)
John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism, on Liberty, Essay on Bentham
-
-
Bentham, J.1
-
98
-
-
79955372351
-
-
Nussbaum, supra note 24, at S82
-
Nussbaum, supra note 24, at S82;
-
-
-
-
99
-
-
4043048735
-
Toward national well-being accounts
-
see also Daniel Kahneman et al., Toward National Well-Being Accounts, 94 AM. ECON. REV. 429, 429-31 (2004) (measuring happiness through time budgets and affective ratings of experiences in order to gauge well-being).
-
(2004)
Am. Econ. Rev.
, vol.94
-
-
Kahneman, D.1
-
100
-
-
60949222141
-
The simpple desire-fulfillment theory
-
See Mark C. Murphy, The Simpple Desire-Fulfillment Theory, 33 NOûS 247, 247 (1999) (noting that "[a]ccording to the desire-fulfillment, or DF, theory, an agent's well-being is constituted by the obtaining of states of affairs that are desired by that agent").
-
(1999)
NoûS
, vol.33
-
-
Murphy, M.C.1
-
101
-
-
79955372350
-
-
See Ubel & Loewenstein, supra note 2, at S205
-
See Ubel & Loewenstein, supra note 2, at S205.
-
-
-
-
102
-
-
79955397681
-
-
Smith et al., supra note 29, at 690, 691
-
See Smith et al., supra note 29, at 690, 691.
-
-
-
-
103
-
-
79955420844
-
-
Ubel & Loewenstein, supra note 2, at S202-04
-
For a broader discussion of these studies, see Ubel & Loewenstein, supra note 2, at S202-04.
-
-
-
-
104
-
-
79955422395
-
-
Smith et al., supra note 29, at 692
-
Smith et al., supra note 29, at 692 (finding that: current patients, community members, and former patients who had their colostomies reversed, all exhibited similar levels of life satisfaction; that patients and former patients reported similar moods and quality of life; and that patients only exhibited slightly lower quality of life scores than community members);
-
-
-
-
105
-
-
79955381106
-
-
Riis et al., supra note 15, at 7
-
see also Riis et al., supra note 15, at 7 (finding that hemodialysis patients "do not appear to be much, if at all, less happy than people who do not have kidney disease").
-
-
-
-
106
-
-
79955377552
-
-
Adler, supra note 54, at 1305
-
See Adler, supra note 54, at 1305 ("Indeed, many preferentialists now stipulate that the preferences which ground welfare must be fully informed.") (quotations omitted);
-
-
-
-
107
-
-
0003045787
-
Quality of life measures in health care and medical ethics
-
Martha Nussbaum & Amartya Sen eds
-
Dan Brock, Quality of Life Measures in Health Care and Medical Ethics, in THE QUALITY OF LIFE 95, 97 n.5 (Martha Nussbaum & Amartya Sen eds., 1993) ("Virtually all discussions of desire or preference satisfaction theories of the good contain some provision for correcting preferences.").
-
(1993)
The Quality of Life
, Issue.5
-
-
Brock, D.1
-
108
-
-
79955384237
-
-
Adler, supra note 54, at 1305
-
See Adler, supra note 54, at 1305.
-
-
-
-
109
-
-
79955442557
-
-
Riis et al., supra note 15, at 7, 8
-
See, e.g., Riis et al., supra note 15, at 7, 8 ("Both patients and controls ... predicted that the difference in mood experienced under healdi versus illness would be large.");
-
-
-
-
110
-
-
79955388925
-
-
Smith et al., supra note, 29 at 691
-
Smith et al., supra note, 29 at 691 (finding that both patients and nonpatients were willing to give up remaining life-years to avoid living with a colostomy).
-
-
-
-
111
-
-
79955439885
-
-
Riis et al., supra note 15, at 7
-
Riis et al., supra note 15, at 7.
-
-
-
-
112
-
-
79955435333
-
-
Id. at 7-8
-
Id. at 7-8 (noting that "patients are themselves not aware of the extent to which they have adapted to their condition").
-
-
-
-
113
-
-
79955390461
-
-
Ubel & Loewenstein supra note 2, at S203-04
-
See Ubel & Loewenstein supra note 2, at S203-04 (noting that patients and healthy persons made similar errors in predicting the impact of disability on happiness).
-
-
-
-
114
-
-
2042464203
-
How happy was I, anyway? A retrospective impact bias
-
Similar heuristics influence a wide array of predicted and remembered pain and pleasure. These schemas dominate predictions, and play a large role in memory as well. The reality of an experience is not irrelevant to the memory of it, but there is a large literature showing pervasive effects of these heuristics on memories of pain and pleasure. See, e.g., Timodly D. Wilson et al., "How Happy Was I, Anyway?" A Retrospective Impact Bias, 21 Soc. COGNITION 421, 431-33 (2003).
-
(2003)
Soc. Cognition
, vol.21
-
-
Wilson, T.D.1
-
115
-
-
79955377041
-
-
Ubel & Loewenstein, supra note 2, at S204-05
-
Ubel & Loewenstein, supra note 2, at S204-05.
-
-
-
-
116
-
-
0003442441
-
-
MARTHA C. NUSSBAUM, WOMEN AND HUMAN DEVELOPMENT: THE CAPABILITIES APPROACH 152-61 (2000) (arguing that philosophers should use common preferences as a heuristic to determine what is good and noting preferences for a state of world are especially diagnostic when the holder of these preferences has experienced all relevant states of the world).
-
(2000)
Women and Human Development: The Capabilities Approach
, pp. 152-161
-
-
Nussbaum, M.C.1
-
117
-
-
79955434687
-
-
Ubel & Loewenstein, supra note 2, at S195
-
Ubel & Loewenstein, supra note 2, at S195.
-
-
-
-
118
-
-
79955385272
-
-
Id. at S205
-
Id. at S205.
-
-
-
-
119
-
-
79955437754
-
-
Id. at S206
-
Id. at S206.
-
-
-
-
120
-
-
79955418873
-
-
NUSSBAUM, supra note 70, at 8, 114
-
See NUSSBAUM, supra note 70, at 8, 114 (noting that an approach based on capabilities rejects an approach based on preferences because it conducts a critique of "die many ways in which habit, fear, low expectations, and unjust background conditions deform people's choices and even their wishes for their own lives").
-
-
-
-
121
-
-
0003583145
-
-
AMARTYA SEN, COMMODITIES AND CAPABILITIES 21 (1985) ("A person who is ill-fed, undernourished, unsheltered and ill can still be high up in the scale of happiness or desire-fulfilment [sic] if he or she has learned to have 'realistic' desires and to take pleasure in small mercies.").
-
(1985)
Commodities and Capabilities
, pp. 21
-
-
Amartya, S.E.N.1
-
122
-
-
0003262134
-
The standard of living: Lecture I, concepts and critiques
-
Geoffrey Hawthorn ed
-
Amartya Sen, The Standard of Living: Lecture I, Concepts and Critiques, in THE STANDARD OF LIVING 1, 8 (Geoffrey Hawthorn ed., 1987).
-
(1987)
The Standard of Living
-
-
Sen, A.1
-
124
-
-
79955403934
-
-
NUSSBAUM, supra note 70, at 72-74
-
See NUSSBAUM, supra note 70, at 72-74 (noting that "we may judge that the absence of capability for a central function is so acute that the person is not really a human being at all, or any longer").
-
-
-
-
127
-
-
79955426480
-
-
NUSSBAUM, supra note 77, at 79, 304-05
-
NUSSBAUM, supra note 77, at 79, 304-05 (noting that there is likely to be an "overlapping consensus" on these capabilities);
-
-
-
-
128
-
-
0002024225
-
Descriptions of inequality: The Swedish approach to welfare research
-
supra note 62
-
Robert Erikson, Descriptions of Inequality: The Swedish Approach to Welfare Research, in THE QUALITY OF LIFE, supra note 62, at 67, 74 ("The . . . components [of well-being] do not constitute a self-evident choice, but similar lists of the essential areas relevant to . . . living look very much the same the world over.").
-
The Quality of Life
-
-
Erikson, R.1
-
129
-
-
79955418379
-
-
NUSSBAUM, supra note 70, at 78-80
-
NUSSBAUM, supra note 70, at 78-80;
-
-
-
-
130
-
-
0344453893
-
Capabilities as fundamental entitlements: Sen and social justice
-
Martha C. Nussbaum, Capabilities as Fundamental Entitlements: Sen and Social Justice, 9 FEMINIST ECON. 33, 41 (2003).
-
(2003)
Feminist Econ.
, vol.9
-
-
Nussbaum, M.C.1
-
131
-
-
33645153008
-
Dworkin on palernalism and well-being
-
T. M. Wilkinson, Dworkin on Palernalism and Well-Being, 16 OXFORD J. LEGAL STUD., 433, 439 (1996)
-
(1996)
Oxford J. Legal Stud.
, vol.16
-
-
Wilkinson, T.M.1
-
133
-
-
79955444906
-
-
See Nussbaum & Sen, supra note 79, at 3, 10
-
See Nussbaum & Sen, supra note 79, at 3, 10.
-
-
-
-
134
-
-
79955454709
-
-
NUSSBAUM, supra note 70, at 76, 83, 101
-
Nussbaum believes that this consensus is rooted in common intuitions about human dignity and human flourishing. See NUSSBAUM, supra note 70, at 76, 83, 101 ("The account of the central capabilities is based on an intuitively powerful idea of truly human functioning that has roots in many different traditions and is independent of any particular metaphysical or religious view.").
-
-
-
-
135
-
-
2942690247
-
-
For some exceptions to this rule, see generally BARRY SCHWARTZ, THE PARADOX OF CHOICE: WHY MORE IS LESS 117-200 (2004) (questioning whether increased opportunities for choice actually makes people happier).
-
(2004)
The Paradox of Choice: Why More is Less
, pp. 117-200
-
-
Schwartz, B.1
-
136
-
-
79955395105
-
-
NUSSBAUM, supra note 70, at 74
-
NUSSBAUM, supra note 70, at 74.
-
-
-
-
137
-
-
79955390460
-
-
Id. at 80
-
Id. at 80.
-
-
-
-
138
-
-
79955378592
-
-
id. at 80 n.85
-
See id. at 80 n.85.
-
-
-
-
139
-
-
79955412006
-
-
id. at 105
-
See id. at 105 (acknowledging the need to concretize her list in order for it to be relevant to policy decisions);
-
-
-
-
140
-
-
79955459208
-
-
Sunstein, supra note 2, at S176 n.7
-
Sunstein, supra note 2, at S176 n.7 (discussing disability as a loss in capabilities and noting that the more concrete and ordinary sense of capabilities "belongs in the same general family" as Nussbaum's more abstract definition of capabilities).
-
-
-
-
141
-
-
79955452226
-
-
Sunstein, supra note 2, at S178
-
Sunstein, supra note 2, at S178.
-
-
-
-
142
-
-
79955384236
-
-
NUSSBAUM, supra note 70, at 74
-
See NUSSBAUM, supra note 70, at 74.
-
-
-
-
143
-
-
79955406435
-
-
id. at 77
-
Nussbaum is well aware of this, and notes items on her list will be construed differently in different societies. See id. at 77. Therefore, the contested issues of value that appear when we try to concretize her list problematize the use of the capabilities approach in the context of tortious loss of physical capabilities, but do not problematize the capabilities approach generally.
-
-
-
-
144
-
-
79955461210
-
-
See infra Part III.B.1
-
See infra Part III.B.1.
-
-
-
-
145
-
-
39049194565
-
A jurisprudence of dysfunction: On the role of "normal species functioning" in disability analysis
-
This determination requires a conceptual baseline, which will most often be the capabilities of the average person. See Ani B. Satz, A Jurisprudence of Dysfunction: On the Role of "Normal Species Functioning" in Disability Analysis, 6 YALE J. HEALTH POL'Y L. & ETHICS 221, 224 (2006) (advocating that the Supreme Court should consider "normal species functioning" when deciding eligibility for protection under the Americans with Disabilities Act).
-
(2006)
Yale J. Health Pol'y L. & Ethics
, vol.6
-
-
Satz, A.B.1
-
147
-
-
59049095054
-
Stimulating personality: Ethical criteria for deep brain stimulation in psychiatric patients and for enhancement purposes
-
Matthis Synofzik & Thomas E. Schlaepfer, Stimulating Personality: Ethical Criteria for Deep Brain Stimulation in Psychiatric Patients and for Enhancement Purposes, 3 BIOTECHNOLOGY J. 1511, 1514 (2008) ("[T]he ethically decisive question is not whether [brain surgery] alters personality or not, but whether it does so in a good or bad way from the patient's very own perspective." (emphasis omitted)).
-
(2008)
Biotechnology J.
, vol.3
-
-
Synofzik, M.1
Schlaepfer, T.E.2
-
148
-
-
33745881334
-
Neurosurgery in parkinson disease: A distressed mind in a repaired body?
-
Consider one patient who received deep brain stimulation (DBS)-a process that involves the implantation of a pacemaker into the brain to help control electrical storms that cause tremors associated with Parkinson's disease. Prior to the procedure, this patient hid her condition from workmates and reported being very committed to work: "As long as I have my work, I still exist; the day I can no longer go to work, it will be as if the curtain came down on my life." M. Schüpbach et al., Neurosurgery in Parkinson Disease: A Distressed Mind in a Repaired Body?, 66 NEUROLOGY 1811, 1812 (2006). After the surgery, her symptoms disappeared. Yet she now wanted to tell others about her condition and did not go back to work. When asked why she did not return to work, she simply said: "I... prefer to spend my time doing other things." Id. It is not clear whether these changes resulted from DBS itself, or instead from the radical lifestyle changes that she underwent when her symptoms disappeared entirely.
-
(2006)
Neurology
, vol.66
-
-
Schüpbach, M.1
-
149
-
-
79955415768
-
-
Synofzik & Schlaepfer, supra, at 1516
-
However, given how little we know about DBS, Synofzik & Schlaepfer, supra, at 1516 (noting that the "longterm cognitive, emotional and behavioral effects of psychiatric DBS are still largely unknown"), and given its invasiveness, it is certainly plausible that DBS itself had a role in altering what this patient valued. A recent conference on bioethics and personal identity further supports the contention that DBS might plausibly alter values. This conference was organized around four fictional case studies, one of which included a mild-mannered republican patient who underwent DBS and later became a gregarious democrat.
-
-
-
-
151
-
-
79955388315
-
-
SACKS, supra note 96, at 98
-
SACKS, supra note 96, at 98.
-
-
-
-
152
-
-
79955427491
-
-
Below, this Article will briefly lay out the argument that the concept of self-altering injury can be integrated into the capabilities approach, as an element of Practical Reason. If this is correct, then the limitations described above are not attributable to the capabilities approach itself, but rather to applications of the capabilities approach that focus too narrowly on the physical consequences of impairment The main thrust of this Article, however, is to develop the concept of self-altering injury independently from the capabilities approach
-
Below, this Article will briefly lay out the argument that the concept of self-altering injury can be integrated into the capabilities approach, as an element of Practical Reason. If this is correct, then the limitations described above are not attributable to the capabilities approach itself, but rather to applications of the capabilities approach that focus too narrowly on the physical consequences of impairment The main thrust of this Article, however, is to develop the concept of self-altering injury independently from the capabilities approach.
-
-
-
-
155
-
-
79955397680
-
-
id. at 33-34
-
See id. at 33-34.
-
-
-
-
156
-
-
0002296027
-
Freedom of the will and the concept of a person
-
Harry G. Frankfurt, Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person, 68 J. PHIL. 5, 6-7 (1971) ("Besides wanting and choosing and being moved to do this or that, men may also want to have (or not to have) certain desires and motives." (emphasis omitted));
-
(1971)
J. Phil.
, vol.68
-
-
Frankfurt, H.G.1
-
157
-
-
0004238267
-
-
see also GERALD DWORKIN, THE THEORY AND PRACTICE OF AUTONOMY 16-20 (1988) (discussing second-order desires and the process of deciding what kind of person to become).
-
(1988)
The Theory and Practice of Autonomy
, pp. 16-20
-
-
Dworkin, G.1
-
158
-
-
79955388823
-
-
DWORKIN, supra note 103, at 20
-
DWORKIN, supra note 103, at 20.
-
-
-
-
159
-
-
79955455712
-
-
Frankfurt, supra note 103, at 11
-
Frankfurt, supra note 103, at 11 (discussing second-order volitions as a specific type of what I refer to above as a second-order desire).
-
-
-
-
161
-
-
0004199157
-
-
MARYA SCHECHTMAN, THE CONSTITUTION OF SELVES 77 (1996) ("[A]ll of the characteristics that are part of a person's history are presumed to contribute to making up her identity. Some, however, play a more central role than others and are more truly expressive of who she is.").
-
(1996)
The Constitution of Selves
, pp. 77
-
-
Schechtman, M.1
-
163
-
-
79955412002
-
-
id. at 30, 32
-
See id. at 30, 32.
-
-
-
-
164
-
-
79955458166
-
-
Id. at 19
-
Id. at 19.
-
-
-
-
165
-
-
79955445402
-
-
id. at 21
-
See id. at 21.
-
-
-
-
166
-
-
79955426033
-
-
id. at 28
-
See id. at 28.
-
-
-
-
167
-
-
79955417369
-
-
Id. at 27
-
Id. at 27.
-
-
-
-
168
-
-
79955460169
-
-
Id. at 18-19
-
Id. at 18-19 (noting that without a framework "nothing is worth doing, the fear is of a terrifying emptiness, a kind of vertigo, or even a fracturing of our world").
-
-
-
-
169
-
-
79955376520
-
-
id. at 31
-
See id. at 31.
-
-
-
-
170
-
-
79955395102
-
-
Id
-
Id. ("[T]he portrait of an agent free from all frameworks . . . spells for us a person in the grip of an appalling identity crisis. ... [A] person without a framework altogether would be outside our space of interlocution; he wouldn't have a stand in the space where the rest of us are. We would see this as pathological.").
-
-
-
-
171
-
-
79955406991
-
-
Gilbert et al., supra note 10, at 619
-
See Gilbert et al., supra note 10, at 619.
-
-
-
-
173
-
-
0022602209
-
The five year outcome of severe blunt head injury: A relative's view
-
N. Brooks etal., The Five Year Outcome of Severe Blunt Head Injury: A Relative's View, 49 J. NEUROLOGY, NEUROSURGERY, & PSYCHIATRY 764, 764 (1986).
-
(1986)
J. Neurology, Neurosurgery, & Psychiatry
, vol.49
-
-
Brooks, N.1
-
174
-
-
79955400698
-
-
Id. at 765
-
Id. at 765;
-
-
-
-
175
-
-
79955413591
-
-
Kendall & Terry, supra note 27, at 103, 104
-
Kendall & Terry, supra note 27, at 103, 104.
-
-
-
-
176
-
-
79955415766
-
-
Kendall & Terry, supra note 27, at 102-03
-
Kendall & Terry, supra note 27, at 102-03.
-
-
-
-
177
-
-
79955417848
-
-
Id. at 105
-
Id. at 105
-
-
-
-
178
-
-
0027288879
-
Psychosocial and executive deficits fouowing closed head injury: Implications for orbital frontal cortex
-
(citing Nils R. Varney & Lynette Menefee, Psychosocial and Executive Deficits FoUowing Closed Head Injury: Implications for Orbital Frontal Cortex, 8 J. HEAD TRAUMA REHABILITATION 32, 35 (1993)).
-
(1993)
J. Head Trauma Rehabilitation
, vol.8
-
-
Varney, N.R.1
Menefee, L.2
-
179
-
-
79955430193
-
-
Id. at 105, 115
-
Although not all head-injury victims will undergo these personality changes, many will. Id. at 105, 115 (suggesting that this heterogeneity is due to differing personality traits and levels of social support).
-
-
-
-
180
-
-
79955449526
-
-
Brooks et al., supra note 118, at 765
-
Brooks et al., supra note 118, at 765 (emphasis omitted).
-
-
-
-
181
-
-
79955462768
-
-
Id. at 767
-
Id. at 767.
-
-
-
-
182
-
-
79955441521
-
-
Id. at 765 tbl.2
-
Id. at 765 tbl.2.
-
-
-
-
183
-
-
79955415247
-
-
Id
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
184
-
-
79955459205
-
-
Id
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
185
-
-
79955432738
-
-
Nussbaum, supra note 82, at 41-42
-
See Nussbaum, supra note 82, at 41-42.
-
-
-
-
186
-
-
79955383700
-
-
SACKS, supra note 96, at 141
-
See SACKS, supra note 96, at 141 (reporting on a patient who enjoyed the elevated moods that her neurosyphilis created, and wished to live within this phase of the disease rather than seek a cure that would return her to her original state).
-
-
-
-
187
-
-
0003613516
-
-
John Christman ed
-
This critique of the capabilities approach mirrors John Christman's critique of subjective welfare. He argues that happiness and preference satisfaction are inadequate measures of well-being because people can be made better off by forcibly altering their preferences. This "leave[s] totally out... the special relation that obtains between a person and that person's set of (autonomous) preferences." John Christman, Introduction to THE INNER CITADEL: ESSAYS ON INDIVIDUAL AUTONOMY 3, 17 (John Christman ed., 1989) (emphasis in original).
-
(1989)
Introduction to the Inner Citadel: Essays on Individual Autonomy
-
-
Christman, J.1
-
188
-
-
79955448527
-
-
See Ubel & Loewenstein, supra note 2, at S207-08
-
See Ubel & Loewenstein, supra note 2, at S207-08.
-
-
-
-
189
-
-
79955445912
-
-
Id. at S206
-
Id. at S206.
-
-
-
-
190
-
-
79955401817
-
-
Sunstein, supra note 2, at S179
-
Sunstein, supra note 2, at S179.
-
-
-
-
191
-
-
79955424412
-
-
George Sher ed., Hackett Publ'g 1979
-
JOHN STUART MILL, UTILITARIANISM 10 (George Sher ed., Hackett Publ'g 1979) (1861). Compare Mill's view to Bentham's: "Prejudice apart, the game of push-pin [a simple child's game] is of equal value with the arts and sciences of music and poetry. If the game of push-pin furnish more pleasure, it is more valuable than either."
-
(1861)
Utilitarianism
, pp. 10
-
-
Mill, J.S.1
-
192
-
-
77952208343
-
The rationale of reward
-
John Bowring ed., London, Simpkin, Marshall & Co
-
JEREMY BENTHAM, The Rationale of Reward, in 2 The WORKS OF JEREMY BENTHAM 189, 253 (John Bowring ed., London, Simpkin, Marshall & Co. 1843).
-
(1843)
2 The Works of Jeremy Bentham
-
-
Bentham, J.1
-
194
-
-
79955453719
-
Well-being, categorical deprivation and pleasure
-
Yossi Yonah, Well-Being, Categorical Deprivation and Pleasure, 28 PHILOSOPHIA 233, 243 (2001).
-
(2001)
Philosophia
, vol.28
-
-
Yonah, Y.1
-
195
-
-
57749103456
-
General damages are incoherent, incalculable, incommensurable, and inegalitarian (but otherwise a great idea)
-
Richard Abel, General Damages Are Incoherent, Incalculable, Incommensurable, and Inegalitarian (but Otherwise a Great Idea), 55 DEPAUL L. REV. 253, 277 (2006).
-
(2006)
Depaul L. Rev.
, vol.55
-
-
Abel, R.1
-
196
-
-
79955390459
-
-
BRISON, supra note 1, at 46
-
BRISON, supra note 1, at 46.
-
-
-
-
197
-
-
79955450563
-
-
See supra Part I.A
-
See supra Part I.A.
-
-
-
-
198
-
-
79955402914
-
-
Kendall & Buys, supra note 4, at 17
-
Kendall & Buys, supra note 4, at 17 (citation omitted).
-
-
-
-
199
-
-
27144446341
-
Psychological adaptation to disability: Perspectives from chaos and complexity theory
-
Hanoch Livneh & Randall M. Parker, Psychological Adaptation to Disability: Perspectives from Chaos and Complexity Theory, 49 REHABILITATION COUNSELING BULL. 17, 18 (2005) (describing such "pendular models");
-
(2005)
Rehabilitation Counseling Bull.
, vol.49
-
-
Livneh, H.1
Parker, R.M.2
-
200
-
-
84995119599
-
The body, identity, and self: Adapting to impairment
-
see also Kathy Charmaz, The Body, Identity, and Self: Adapting to Impairment, 36 Soc. Q. 657, 670 (1995) (discussing identity trade-offs);
-
(1995)
Soc. Q.
, vol.36
-
-
Charmaz, K.1
-
201
-
-
17244374712
-
Social psychology of identities
-
Judith A. Howard, Social Psychology of Identities, 26 ANN. REV. SOC. 367, 368 (2000) (discussing the alteration of "self-schemas," that is, "characteristics, preferences, goals, and behavior patterns we [correctly or not] associate with ourselves");
-
(2000)
Ann. Rev. Soc.
, vol.26
-
-
Howard, J.A.1
-
202
-
-
34250058932
-
Reshaping of self: A pendular reconstruction of self and identity among adults with traumatic spinal cord injury
-
Karen K. Yoshida, Reshaping of Self: A Pendular Reconstruction of Self and Identity Among Adults with Traumatic Spinal Cord Injury, 15 Soc. HEALTH & ILLNESS 217, 217, 223 (1993) (discussing the pendular nature of self-identity oscillating between preinjury and postinjury self concepts, and settling on a "middle self).
-
(1993)
Soc. Health & Illness
, vol.15
-
-
Yoshida, K.K.1
-
203
-
-
0036023484
-
Well, I know this is going to sound very strange to you, but I don't see myself as a disabled person: Identity and disability
-
Nick Watson, Well, I Know This is Going to Sound Very Strange to You, but I Don't See Myself as a Disabled Person: Identity and Disability, 17 DISABILITY & SOC'Y 509, 512-13 (2002) ("People who have an impairment or chronic condition . . . suffer a loss of self and go through a process during which they negotiate their lives in such a way as to be as ordinary as possible and so retain some contact with desired life-worlds.").
-
(2002)
Disability & Soc'y
, vol.17
-
-
Watson, N.1
-
204
-
-
84995137615
-
Identity dilemmas of chronically ill men
-
Consistent with the predictions of hedonic adaptation, these changes are often evaluated positively: "[H] ad it not been for my heart attack-I'm grateful it happened now, cause it changed my life considerably and so [I] have a lack of words [to describe it]. Yeah, I thank my heart attack for that. In one way I'm grateful." Kathy Charmaz, Identity Dilemmas of Chronically Ill Men, 35 Soc. Q. 269, 275 (1994) (conducting qualitative interviews with twenty men and eighty women, all with chronic illnesses).
-
(1994)
Soc. Q.
, vol.35
-
-
Charmaz, K.1
-
205
-
-
0033622261
-
Chronic illness as biographical disruption or biographical disruption as chronic illness? Reflections on a core concept
-
See Simon J. Williams, Chronic Illness as Biographical Disruption or Biographical Disruption as Chronic Illness? Reflections on a Core Concept, 22 SOC. HEALTH & ILLNESS 40, 40 (2000).
-
(2000)
Soc. Health & Illness
, vol.22
-
-
Williams, S.J.1
-
206
-
-
0036972982
-
The role of adaptation to disability and disease in health state valuation: A preliminary normative analysis
-
Paul Menzel, Paul Dolan, Jeff Richardson & Jan Abel Olsen, The Role of Adaptation to Disability and Disease in Health State Valuation: A Preliminary Normative Analysis, 55 Soc. Sci. & MED. 2149, 2153 (2002).
-
(2002)
Soc. Sci. & Med.
, vol.55
-
-
Menzel, P.1
Dolan, P.2
Richardson, J.3
Olsen, J.A.4
-
207
-
-
33846796276
-
Quality of life after spinal cord injury: A meta-synthesis of qualitative findings
-
K. Whalley Hammell, Quality of Life After Spinal Cord Injury: A Meta-Synthesis of Qualitative Findings, 45 SPINAL CORD 124, 135 (2007).
-
(2007)
Spinal Cord
, vol.45
-
-
Whalley Hammell, K.1
-
208
-
-
79955431739
-
-
S. Kay Toombs, Disability and the Self, in CHANGING THE SELF: PHILOSOPHIES, TECHNIQUES, AND EXPERIENCES 337, 351 (Thomas M. Brinthaupt & Richard P. Lipka eds., 1994).
-
(1994)
-
-
-
209
-
-
79955403413
-
-
Charmaz, supra note 140, at 276
-
Charmaz, supra note 140, at 276 (emphasis omitted).
-
-
-
-
210
-
-
4644322785
-
Reflections on bodily change: The lived experience of disability
-
S. Kay Toombs ed
-
S. Kay Toombs, Reflections on Bodily Change: The Lived Experience of Disability, in HANDBOOK OF PHENOMENOLOGY AND MEDICINE 247, 254 (S. Kay Toombs ed., 2001) (emphasis in original).
-
(2001)
Handbook of Phenomenology and Medicine
-
-
Kay Toombs, S.1
-
211
-
-
0035513802
-
Components of quality of life for persons with a quadriplegic and paraplegic spinal cord injury
-
Patricia J. Manns & Karen E. Chad, Components of Quality of Life for Persons with a Quadriplegic and Paraplegic Spinal Cord Injury, 11 QUALITATIVE HEALTH RES. 795, 802 (2001);
-
(2001)
Qualitative Health Res.
, vol.11
-
-
Manns, P.J.1
Chad, K.E.2
-
212
-
-
6244279522
-
-
see also ERNEST A HIRSCH, STARTING OVER 164-65 (1977) ("Whatever changes have occurred in me do not touch the core of my 'self,' which has remained pretty much the same. As far as other people are concerned, I think I've remained much as always. Although I realize some changes have occurred, I feel a continuity with the past and have no difficulty recognizing myself as myself, and neither does anyone else.");
-
(1977)
Starting Over
, pp. 164-165
-
-
Hirsch, E.A.1
-
213
-
-
9144272759
-
Quality of life among people with high spinal cord injury living in the community
-
K. Whalley Hammell, Quality of Life Among People with High Spinal Cord Injury Living in the Community, 42 SPINAL CORD 607, 612 (2004) ("The person you were pre-injury is the person you are going to be post-injury-with different values....");
-
(2004)
Spinal Cord
, vol.42
-
-
Whalley Hammell, K.1
-
214
-
-
79955416818
-
-
id. at 613
-
id. at 613 ("I don't really look at myself any different.").
-
-
-
-
215
-
-
79955442556
-
-
Kendall & Buys, supra note 4, at 18
-
See Kendall & Buys, supra note 4, at 18 ("Research has also indicated that there is significant variation both within and across individuals in the speed and quality with which individuals move through the adjustment process." (citation omitted));
-
-
-
-
216
-
-
7444269624
-
Paltterns of psychosocial adaptation to chronic illness and disability: A cluster analytic approach
-
Hanoch Livneh, Sheri M. Lott & Richard F. Antonak, Paltterns of Psychosocial Adaptation to Chronic Illness and Disability: A Cluster Analytic Approach, 9 PSYCHOL. HEALTH & MED. 411, 423 (2004) (describing heterogeneity in coping and adaptation to spinal cord injury).
-
(2004)
Psychol. Health & Med.
, vol.9
-
-
Livneh, H.1
Lott, S.M.2
Antonak, R.F.3
-
217
-
-
79955374442
-
-
Some may instead find that a disability does not substantially affect their ideals and goals
-
Some may instead find that a disability does not substantially affect their ideals and goals.
-
-
-
-
218
-
-
79955406432
-
-
Kendall & Terry, supra note 27, at 102-05
-
Much disability research focuses on the effects that disabilities have on general mood (e.g., causing depression, anxiety, or aggressiveness), as opposed to cataloging the specific changes in commitments that may have occurred. See, e.g., Kendall & Terry, supra note 27, at 102-05 (noting that studies have demonstrated that closed head injury can "have devastating consequences across a range of psychosocial domains"). Because selfalteration is arguably more harmful when one's ideals change, future research should focus on the types of commitments that are altered by disability, and thereby more rigorously test the assertion above that disability can lead to altered ideals and goals.
-
-
-
-
219
-
-
0028287264
-
The experience of spinal cord injury: The individual's perspective - Implications for rehabilitation practice
-
Christine Carpenter, The Experience of Spinal Cord Injury: The Individual's Perspective - Implications for Rehabilitation Practice, 74 PHYSICAL THERAPY 614, 622 (1994);
-
(1994)
Physical Therapy
, vol.74
-
-
Carpenter, C.1
-
220
-
-
79955430697
-
-
Hammell, supra note 143, at 133
-
see also Hammell, supra note 143, at 133 ("By letting go of some 'I ams' (such as 'I am an athlete') and developing others (such as 'I am a father'), a sense of self-worth was enhanced.");
-
-
-
-
221
-
-
79955425510
-
-
Hammell, supra note 147, at 612
-
Hammell, supra note 147, at 612 ("The person you were pre-injury is the person you are going to be post-injury-with different values ....").
-
-
-
-
222
-
-
79955438350
-
-
Hammell, supra note 143, at 135
-
Hammell, supra note 143, at 135.
-
-
-
-
223
-
-
4143129892
-
Psychosocial adjustment to lower-limb amputation: A review
-
See Olga Horgan & Malcolm MacLachlan, Psychosocial Adjustment to Lower-Limb Amputation: A Review, 26 DISABILITY & REHABILITATION 837, 840 (2004) (collecting studies and concluding that "many people without disabilities ignore those with disabilities for fear of saying the wrong thiing or because of experiencing general anxiety and unease in their presence");
-
(2004)
Disability & Rehabilitation
, vol.26
-
-
Horgan, O.1
MacLachlan, M.2
-
224
-
-
79955421338
-
-
id
-
id. ("[A]lmost half of the participants visited friends and relatives less frequently since their amputation and that approximately two-thirds were less likely to go to the cinema, theatre, sport events, library, dances, and shows."
-
-
-
-
225
-
-
0030961235
-
The life style of young persons after lower limb amputation caused by injury
-
(citing H. Burger & C. Marincek, The Life Style of Young Persons After Lower Limb Amputation Caused by Injury, 21 PROSTHETICS & ORTHOTICS INT'L 35, 36 (1997));
-
(1997)
Prosthetics & Orthotics Int'l
, vol.21
-
-
Burger, H.1
Marincek, C.2
-
226
-
-
84995012839
-
Self, identity and radical surgery
-
Michael Kelly, Self, Identity and Radical Surgery, 14 Soc. HEALTH & ILLNESS 390, 404-06 (1992) (reporting interviews with people needing colostomy bags that showed that many believed their disability made sexual relationships more difficult);
-
(1992)
Soc. Health & Illness
, vol.14
-
-
Kelly, M.1
-
227
-
-
79955396672
-
-
Duggan & Dijkers, supra note 9, at 15
-
see also Duggan & Dijkers, supra note 9, at 15 (reporting on cascade effects of injury, which include fears of sexual rejection);
-
-
-
-
228
-
-
79955459724
-
-
Livneh et al., supra note 148, at 415
-
Livneh et al., supra note 148, at 415 (reporting that patients who suffer spinal cord injuries have high subjective wellbeing in a number of areas, but low subjective well-being in employment, sex, and financial situations).
-
-
-
-
229
-
-
76049096345
-
Psychological connectedness and intertemporal choice
-
See Daniel M. Bartels & Lance J. Rips, Psychological Connectedness and Intertemporal Choice, 139 J. EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOL.: GEN. 49, 51 (2010).
-
(2010)
J. Experimental Psychol.: Gen.
, vol.139
-
-
Bartels, D.M.1
Rips, L.J.2
-
230
-
-
79955414223
-
-
id. at 50
-
See id. at 50 (describing the concept of psychological connectedness).
-
-
-
-
232
-
-
79955403411
-
-
id. at 239-43
-
See id. at 239-43.
-
-
-
-
233
-
-
79955448524
-
-
id. at 206, 277, 313
-
id. at 206, 277, 313.
-
-
-
-
234
-
-
79955459204
-
-
Id. at 262
-
A clarifications is in order. Parfit uses the term Relation R to discuss the ways in which people persist through time only as a matter of degree. Id. at 262.
-
-
-
-
235
-
-
79955426477
-
-
Id
-
Parfit identifies two constituitive parts of Relation R: connectedness and continuity. Id.
-
-
-
-
236
-
-
79955378590
-
-
Id. at 206
-
Continuity consists in "overlapping chains" of connectedness. Id. at 206. This article focuses on connectedness rather than continuity because continuity is a function of connectedness, and because Parfit's most relevant discussions involve connectedness.
-
-
-
-
237
-
-
34248074618
-
Disintegrated persons and distributive principles
-
See also David W. Shoemaker, Disintegrated Persons and Distributive Principles, 15 RATIO 58, 75 (2002) ("[O]f the two relations in Relation R we may plausibly believe that psychological connectedness is by far the more important.").
-
(2002)
Ratio
, vol.15
-
-
Shoemaker, D.W.1
-
238
-
-
79955400696
-
-
PARFIT, supra note 156, at 237
-
PARFIT, supra note 156, at 237.
-
-
-
-
239
-
-
79955388821
-
-
id. at 323-30
-
id. at 323-30.
-
-
-
-
240
-
-
79955408496
-
-
Id
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
242
-
-
79955375483
-
-
Bartels & Rips, supra note 154, at 52
-
Bartels & Rips, supra note 154, at 52.
-
-
-
-
243
-
-
79955373920
-
-
id. at 57-58
-
id. at 57-58.
-
-
-
-
244
-
-
79955385268
-
-
Id. at 68
-
Id. at 68.
-
-
-
-
245
-
-
79955395100
-
-
Id
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
246
-
-
79955461703
-
-
see also id. at 61
-
see also id. at 61.
-
-
-
-
247
-
-
79955450706
-
-
Id. at 58
-
Id. at 58.
-
-
-
-
248
-
-
79955378070
-
-
See id. at 59-60
-
See id. at 59-60.
-
-
-
-
249
-
-
79955433705
-
-
Id
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
250
-
-
79955431218
-
-
Id. at 58
-
Id. at 58.
-
-
-
-
251
-
-
79955383699
-
-
Id
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
252
-
-
79955415765
-
-
Id. at 64
-
Id. at 64 ("When people anticipate an important change that might weaken the psychological bonds between their present and future selves, they want upcoming desirable events to happen before the change occurs.").
-
-
-
-
253
-
-
79955369804
-
-
Id
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
254
-
-
79955419816
-
-
In addition to studying traumatic events, this study also asked subjects to consider a fictional student who would undergo a "religious conversion-will be introduced into a new faith and will find spiritual fulfillment in [his or her] God,"
-
In addition to studying traumatic events, this study also asked subjects to consider a fictional student who would undergo a "religious conversion-will be introduced into a new faith and will find spiritual fulfillment in [his or her] God,"
-
-
-
-
255
-
-
79955428561
-
-
id. at 68
-
id. at 68, and would "find out that he was adopted."
-
-
-
-
256
-
-
79955443051
-
-
Id. at 61
-
Id. at 61. Subjects treated these conditions much like they did the other large life events: kidnapping, witnessing war, avalanches, and erroneous cancer diagnoses. Subjects reported low levels of connectedness between the fictional student now and the student after he converted or learned he was adopted. Subjects were also hesitant to shift money from the preconversion student to the postconversion student and from the pre-adoption-revelation self to the post-adoption-revelation-self.
-
-
-
-
257
-
-
79955435332
-
-
Id at 59, 61
-
Id at 59, 61
-
-
-
-
258
-
-
79955368251
-
-
Id. at 60-61
-
Id. at 60-61.
-
-
-
-
259
-
-
79955414734
-
-
Id. at 62-63
-
Id. at 62-63.
-
-
-
-
260
-
-
79955369805
-
-
Id. at 63
-
Id. at 63.
-
-
-
-
261
-
-
79955423911
-
-
Id
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
262
-
-
79955433215
-
-
Id
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
263
-
-
79955456778
-
-
id. at 52
-
id. at 52.
-
-
-
-
264
-
-
79955450705
-
-
This Article focuses solely on people who have ideals and goals that constitute an ongoing life project I refer to these people simply as "adults." The concept of self-alteration would have to be altered to accommodate injuries to children, who probably do not have set ideals or goals. It is also possible that the phenomenon of hedonic adaptation works differently in children than in adults
-
This Article focuses solely on people who have ideals and goals that constitute an ongoing life project I refer to these people simply as "adults." The concept of self-alteration would have to be altered to accommodate injuries to children, who probably do not have set ideals or goals. It is also possible that the phenomenon of hedonic adaptation works differently in children than in adults.
-
-
-
-
265
-
-
79955448526
-
-
Menzel et al., supra note 142, at 2151
-
See Menzel et al., supra note 142, at 2151 ("Realizing that a disease or disability is likely to be chronic, people may adjust their activities. . . . People may adjust not only the activities they select to pursue their goals, but the content and direction of the goals themselves. Their basic interests can change. A paraplegic, for example, may develop an interest in music to replace a previous interest in physical activity.").
-
-
-
-
266
-
-
79955459723
-
-
See supra notes 25-36 and accompanying text
-
See supra notes 25-36 and accompanying text.
-
-
-
-
267
-
-
79955418377
-
-
Bagenstos & Schlanger supra note 2, at 764
-
Bagenstos & Schlanger supra note 2, at 764
-
-
-
-
268
-
-
79955430695
-
The psychology of disability
-
(citing Carolyn L. Vash, The Psychology of Disability, 22 REHABILITATION PSYCHOL. 145, 153 (1975),
-
(1975)
Rehabilitation Psychol.
, vol.22
-
-
Vash, C.L.1
-
270
-
-
79955412001
-
-
id. at 768
-
id. at 768.
-
-
-
-
271
-
-
79955451728
-
-
Menzel et al., supra note 142, at 2151
-
Menzel et al., supra note 142, at 2151 ("The primary meaning of 'adapt' appropriate for the present context of disability and chronic illness is 'to adjust oneself to new or changed circumstances.' This can be articulated even more specifically as changing 'oneself so that one's behavior, attitudes, etc. will conform to new . . . circumstances.' . . . [T]he primary focus of adaptation is on a change in the adapting agent . . . ." (citations omitted)).
-
-
-
-
272
-
-
79955382184
-
-
See Ubel and Loewenstein, supra note 2, at S205
-
See Ubel and Loewenstein, supra note 2, at S205. Even after being convinced that major injuries will not affect their long-term happiness, Ubel and Loewenstein remain convinced that many tort victims sustain substantial harm. They seek to resolve this puzzle by arguing that harm should not be defined solely by happiness and should instead account for lost capabilities.
-
-
-
-
276
-
-
79955447428
-
-
See id. at 194-96
-
See id. at 194-96.
-
-
-
-
277
-
-
79955368250
-
-
See id
-
See id.
-
-
-
-
278
-
-
79955438349
-
-
Id. at 192
-
Id. at 192.
-
-
-
-
279
-
-
79955430694
-
-
See id. at 192, 194-95
-
See id. at 192, 194-95.
-
-
-
-
280
-
-
79955450047
-
-
See id. at 192-93
-
See id. at 192-93.
-
-
-
-
281
-
-
79955408495
-
-
See id. at 193
-
See id. at 193 ("[B]ehaviour is only characterised adequately when we know what the longer and longest-term intentions invoked are ....").
-
-
-
-
282
-
-
79955427490
-
-
See id. at 200-01
-
See id. at 200-01 ("There is no present which is not informed by some image of some future and an image of the future which always presents itself in the form of a telos . . . towards which we are either moving or failing to move in the present").
-
-
-
-
283
-
-
79955383184
-
-
See id. at 199
-
See id. at 199 ("The notion of a history is as fundamental a notion as the notion of an action. Each requires the other.").
-
-
-
-
284
-
-
79955380076
-
-
See id. at 203-04
-
See id. at 203-04.
-
-
-
-
285
-
-
79955430192
-
-
Id
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
286
-
-
79955384762
-
-
See supra notes 108-11 and accompanying text
-
See supra notes 108-11 and accompanying text
-
-
-
-
287
-
-
79955395101
-
-
TAYLOR, supra note 108, at 31
-
See TAYLOR, supra note 108, at 31.
-
-
-
-
288
-
-
79955389951
-
-
id. at 31
-
id. at 31.
-
-
-
-
289
-
-
79955414733
-
-
See id. at 47
-
See id. at 47.
-
-
-
-
290
-
-
79955422391
-
-
Id. at 46-47
-
Id. at 46-47.
-
-
-
-
291
-
-
79955366730
-
-
See id. at 47
-
See id. at 47.
-
-
-
-
292
-
-
79955455709
-
-
HARDCASTLE, supra note 188, at 30
-
HARDCASTLE, supra note 188, at 30 ("[We are] driven to tell narratives .... This is something we cannot help but do, for it is the only way we have of understanding ourselves.");
-
-
-
-
294
-
-
79955392483
-
-
TAYLOR, supra note 108, at 48
-
TAYLOR, supra note 108, at 48;
-
-
-
-
295
-
-
0033474707
-
On Becoming a Person
-
John Barresi, On Becoming a Person, 12 PHIL. PSYCHOL. 79,91 (1999) ("From a phenomenological perspective, it does not matter whether this self that we attribute identity to through time is metaphysically real or mere psychological fiction, what matters is that it is essential to our phenomenology of self ....").
-
(1999)
Phil. Psychol.
, vol.12
-
-
Barresi, J.1
-
296
-
-
0033959237
-
Philosophical conceptions of the self: Implications for cognitive science
-
Arguably, evolutionary pressures have hardwired these tendencies into all humans. See Shaun Gallagher, Philosophical Conceptions of the Self: Implications for Cognitive Science, 4 TRENDS COGNITIVE SCI 14,19 (2000) ("[W]e cannot prevent ourselves from 'inventing' our selves. We are hardwired to become language users, and once we are caught up in the web of language and begin spinning our own stories, we are not totally in control of the product");
-
(2000)
Trends Cognitive Sci
, vol.4
-
-
Gallagher, S.1
-
297
-
-
79955401816
-
-
DENNETT, supra note 206, at 10-11
-
see also DENNETT, supra note 206, at 10-11.
-
-
-
-
298
-
-
79955425508
-
-
SCHECHTMAN, supra note 107, at 98
-
SCHECHTMAN, supra note 107, at 98;
-
-
-
-
299
-
-
77952618032
-
Personal identity, narrative integration, and embodiment
-
Sue Campbell et al. eds
-
Catriona Mackenzie, Personal Identity, Narrative Integration, and Embodiment, in EMBODIMENT AND AGENCY 100, 107 (Sue Campbell et al. eds., 2009).
-
(2009)
Embodiment and Agency
-
-
Mackenzie, C.1
-
300
-
-
0004267657
-
-
One scholar uses the example of a woman who thinks of herself as ugly, but then begins to evaluate the evidence in the mirror. See ROY SCHAFER, RETELLING A LIFE 10 (1992).
-
(1992)
Retelling a Life
, pp. 10
-
-
Schafer, R.O.Y.1
-
301
-
-
0003296941
-
The self as a center of narrative gravity
-
Frank S. Kessel et al. eds
-
Daniel C. Dennett, The Self as a Center of Narrative Gravity, in SELF AND CONSCIOUSNESS: MULTIPLE PERSPECTIVES 103, 106-07 (Frank S. Kessel et al. eds., 1992) (noting that the concept of a self that is created through narrative is similar to abstract concepts in physics like centers of gravity-both are fictions, but both are extremely useful in trying to understand the object of study).
-
(1992)
Self and Consciousness: Multiple Perspectives
-
-
Dennett, D.C.1
-
302
-
-
79955429685
-
-
DEGRAZIA, supra note 100, at 84-86
-
For discussions of the constraints that culture puts on an individual's self-narrative, see DEGRAZIA, supra note 100, at 84-86,
-
-
-
-
303
-
-
79955380073
-
-
SCHAFER, supra note 209, at 53-55, and
-
SCHAFER, supra note 209, at 53-55, and
-
-
-
-
304
-
-
79955413068
-
-
SCHECHTMAN, supra note 107, at 95
-
SCHECHTMAN, supra note 107, at 95.
-
-
-
-
305
-
-
79955365182
-
-
See supra notes 157-59 and accompanying text
-
See supra notes 157-59 and accompanying text
-
-
-
-
306
-
-
79955426478
-
-
DEGRAZIA, supra note 100, at 80
-
DEGRAZIA, supra note 100, at 80.
-
-
-
-
307
-
-
79955401309
-
-
MACINTYRE, supra note 189, at 202
-
MACINTYRE, supra note 189, at 202.
-
-
-
-
308
-
-
79955393030
-
-
See DEGRAZIA, supra note 100, at 80-82, 89, 107.
-
See DEGRAZIA, supra note 100, at 80-82, 89, 107.
-
-
-
-
309
-
-
79955364657
-
-
See supra note 146 and accompanying text.
-
See supra note 146 and accompanying text.
-
-
-
-
310
-
-
79955369803
-
-
SCHECHTMAN, supra note 107, at 88 (emphasis in original).
-
SCHECHTMAN, supra note 107, at 88 (emphasis in original).
-
-
-
-
311
-
-
79955407468
-
-
Mackenzie, supra note 208, at 114 ("[A] condition of possibility of this narrative is that we have an integrated . . . conception of ourselves as embodied agents.").
-
Mackenzie, supra note 208, at 114 ("[A] condition of possibility of this narrative is that we have an integrated . . . conception of ourselves as embodied agents.").
-
-
-
-
312
-
-
79955395632
-
-
See id. at 116.
-
See id. at 116.
-
-
-
-
313
-
-
79955412000
-
-
Id. at 118.
-
Id. at 118.
-
-
-
-
314
-
-
0003620361
-
-
("[T]he appearance of the sickness marks a radical redirection of the trajectory of the life story.").
-
HOWARD BRODY, STORIES OF SICKNESS 2 (2003) ("[T]he appearance of the sickness marks a radical redirection of the trajectory of the life story.").
-
(2003)
Stories of Sickness
, pp. 2
-
-
Brody, H.1
-
315
-
-
79955457651
-
-
See DWORKIN, supra note 103, at 6 ("'[A]utonomy' is used in an exceedingly broad fashion. . . . About the only features held constant from one author to another are that autonomy is a feature of persons and that it is a desirable quality to have.");
-
See DWORKIN, supra note 103, at 6 ("'[A]utonomy' is used in an exceedingly broad fashion. . . . About the only features held constant from one author to another are that autonomy is a feature of persons and that it is a desirable quality to have.");
-
-
-
-
316
-
-
79955430693
-
-
JOEL FEINBERG, supra note 101, at 27-51 (1986) (describing four common meanings of "autonomy" and listing twelve sub-aspects of one of them). For another comprehensive account of autonomy
-
JOEL FEINBERG, supra note 101, at 27-51 (1986) (describing four common meanings of "autonomy" and listing twelve sub-aspects of one of them). For another comprehensive account of autonomy,
-
-
-
-
318
-
-
0004212235
-
-
For a discussion of the closely related concept of freedom, see generally (attempting to define freedom and the core meaning attendant to all of its different usages).
-
For a discussion of the closely related concept of freedom, see generally TIM GRAY, FREEDOM (1991) (attempting to define freedom and the core meaning attendant to all of its different usages).
-
(1991)
Freedom
-
-
Gray, T.I.M.1
-
319
-
-
79955414732
-
-
FEINBERG, supra note 101, at 28.
-
FEINBERG, supra note 101, at 28.
-
-
-
-
320
-
-
79955436308
-
-
See Christman, supra note 129, at 3, 5-6 (suggesting that self-governance is th conceptual core of Feinberg's list, and that self-determination is at the core of self-governance)
-
See Christman, supra note 129, at 3, 5-6 (suggesting that self-governance is th conceptual core of Feinberg's list, and that self-determination is at the core of self-governance);
-
-
-
-
321
-
-
84856553557
-
Autonomy and the "Inner Self, "
-
supra note 129, at 77, 78 ("[T] o exercise one's freedom in such a way as to order one's life according to a plan or conception which fully expresses one's own choices ... is the heart of our notion of autonomy.").
-
see also Robert Young, Autonomy and the "Inner Self, " in THE INNER CITADEL: ESSAYS ON INDIVIDUAL AUTONOMY, supra note 129, at 77, 78 ("[T] o exercise one's freedom in such a way as to order one's life according to a plan or conception which fully expresses one's own choices ... is the heart of our notion of autonomy.").
-
The Inner Citadel: Essays on Individual Autonomy
-
-
Young, R.1
-
322
-
-
79955453184
-
-
See FEINBERG, supra note 101, at 33-35
-
See FEINBERG, supra note 101, at 33-35;
-
-
-
-
323
-
-
79955386753
-
-
see also GRAY, supra note 221, at 52. In Richard Fallon's terminology, self-determination is a descriptive rather than ascriptive sense of autonomy.
-
see also GRAY, supra note 221, at 52. In Richard Fallon's terminology, self-determination is a descriptive rather than ascriptive sense of autonomy.
-
-
-
-
324
-
-
84937306799
-
Two senses of autonomy
-
(defining descriptive autonomy as "the extent to which they are meaningfully 'selfgoverned' in a universe shaped by causal forces"). "Descriptive autonomy gives us a warranted sense that our lives are at least pardy of our own making, not the mere product of external forces. It also provides the foundation for pride and satisfaction in a life welllived."
-
See Richard H. Fallon, Jr., Two Senses of Autonomy, 46 STAN. L. REV. 875, 877-78 (1994) (defining descriptive autonomy as "the extent to which they are meaningfully 'selfgoverned' in a universe shaped by causal forces"). "Descriptive autonomy gives us a warranted sense that our lives are at least pardy of our own making, not the mere product of external forces. It also provides the foundation for pride and satisfaction in a life welllived."
-
(1994)
Stan. L. Rev.
, vol.46
-
-
Fallon Jr., R.H.1
-
325
-
-
79955388921
-
-
Id. at 899.
-
Id. at 899.
-
-
-
-
326
-
-
79955428003
-
-
See FEINBERG, supra note 101, at 33
-
See FEINBERG, supra note 101, at 33;
-
-
-
-
328
-
-
79955391501
-
-
RAZ, supra note 225, at 372; Fallon, supra note 224, at 877 (arguing that descriptive autonomy is a matter of degree and depends in part on the number of options available). This Article sets aside the question of whether determinism undermines the possibility of free will and hence undermines self-determination. For a discussion of these issues and a defense of the possibility of self-determination, see DEGRAZIA, supra note 100, at 89-106.
-
RAZ, supra note 225, at 372; Fallon, supra note 224, at 877 (arguing that descriptive autonomy is a matter of degree and depends in part on the number of options available). This Article sets aside the question of whether determinism undermines the possibility of free will and hence undermines self-determination. For a discussion of these issues and a defense of the possibility of self-determination, see DEGRAZIA, supra note 100, at 89-106.
-
-
-
-
329
-
-
79955397145
-
-
FEINBERG, supra note 101, at 33 ("A person is authentic to the extent that....[H]e can and does alter his convictions for reasons of his own ...."); GRAY, supra note 221, at 53.
-
FEINBERG, supra note 101, at 33 ("A person is authentic to the extent that....[H]e can and does alter his convictions for reasons of his own ...."); GRAY, supra note 221, at 53.
-
-
-
-
330
-
-
79955407983
-
-
For a brief overview of the potential differences between some of these formulations see Christman, supra note 129, at 6-7.
-
For a brief overview of the potential differences between some of these formulations see Christman, supra note 129, at 6-7.
-
-
-
-
331
-
-
79955444039
-
-
RAZ, supra note 225, at 369 ("The autonomous person is a (part) author of his own life. The ideal of personal autonomy is the vision of people controlling, to some degree, their own destiny, fashioning it through successive decisions throughout their lives.");
-
RAZ, supra note 225, at 369 ("The autonomous person is a (part) author of his own life. The ideal of personal autonomy is the vision of people controlling, to some degree, their own destiny, fashioning it through successive decisions throughout their lives.");
-
-
-
-
332
-
-
1842624735
-
The concept of autonomy
-
supra note 129, at ("It is only when a person identifies with the influences that motivate him, assimilates them to himself. . . that these influences are to be identified as 'his.'").
-
Gerald Dworkin, The Concept of Autonomy, in THE INNER CITADEL: ESSAYS ON INDIVIDUAL AUTONOMY, supra note 129, at 54, 60 ("It is only when a person identifies with the influences that motivate him, assimilates them to himself. . . that these influences are to be identified as 'his.'").
-
The Inner Citadel: Essays on Individual Autonomy
-
-
Dworkin, G.1
-
333
-
-
79955416816
-
-
FEINBERG, supra note 101, at 34.
-
FEINBERG, supra note 101, at 34.
-
-
-
-
334
-
-
79955372348
-
-
See id. at 34-37.
-
See id. at 34-37.
-
-
-
-
335
-
-
33744518593
-
Mitigation and the capital defendant who wants to die: A study in the rhetoric of autonomy and the hidden discourse of collective responsibility
-
("The healthy individual's acquisition of greater and greater responsibility as he or she moves through adolescence into adulthood cultivates the capacity and the freedom to navigate through life, through the various institutional, social, political, circumstantial forces that are often beyond the individual's immediate control. The sacredness of the navigation resides in the importance it bears in bringing thematic unity, coherence, and integrity to living.").
-
Daniel R. Williams, Mitigation and the Capital Defendant Who Wants to Die: A Study in the Rhetoric of Autonomy and the Hidden Discourse of Collective Responsibility, 57 HASTINGS L.J. 693, 709 (2006) ("The healthy individual's acquisition of greater and greater responsibility as he or she moves through adolescence into adulthood cultivates the capacity and the freedom to navigate through life, through the various institutional, social, political, circumstantial forces that are often beyond the individual's immediate control. The sacredness of the navigation resides in the importance it bears in bringing thematic unity, coherence, and integrity to living.").
-
(2006)
Hastings L.J.
, vol.57
-
-
Daniel, R.W.1
-
336
-
-
79955409519
-
-
Cf. GRAY, supra note 221, at 35 (noting that if a person were completely free to choose her own language, she would be unable to express herself)
-
Cf. GRAY, supra note 221, at 35 (noting that if a person were completely free to choose her own language, she would be unable to express herself) ;
-
-
-
-
337
-
-
0345279829
-
A critique of the ideals of liberty
-
(describing liberty as noninterfer-ence and noting that limits to noninterference with certain aspects of life may be important to maximize liberty generally).
-
H. J. McCloskey, A Critique of the Ideals of Liberty, 74 MIND 483, 486-87 (1965) (describing liberty as noninterfer-ence and noting that limits to noninterference with certain aspects of life may be important to maximize liberty generally).
-
(1965)
Mind
, vol.74
-
-
McCloskey, H.J.1
-
338
-
-
79955381656
-
-
("[T]he context of individual choice is the range of options passed down to us by our culture. Deciding how to lead our lives is, in the first instance, a matter of exploring the possibilities made available by our culture.");
-
See WILL KYMUCKA, MULTICULTURAL CITIZENSHIP: A LIBERAL THEORY OF MINORITY RIGHTS 126 (1995) ("[T]he context of individual choice is the range of options passed down to us by our culture. Deciding how to lead our lives is, in the first instance, a matter of exploring the possibilities made available by our culture.");
-
(1995)
Multicultural Citizenship: A Liberal Theory of Minority Rights
, pp. 126
-
-
Kymucka, W.1
-
339
-
-
5944263605
-
Personal autonomy and the paradox of feminine socialization
-
(highlighting the role of gender in constructing values).
-
Diana T. Meyers, Personal Autonomy and the Paradox of Feminine Socialization, 84 J. PHIL. 619, 622-24 (1987) (highlighting the role of gender in constructing values).
-
(1987)
J. Phil.
, vol.84
-
-
Meyers, D.T.1
-
340
-
-
79955438244
-
-
See FEINBERG, supra note 101, at 38-39.
-
See FEINBERG, supra note 101, at 38-39.
-
-
-
-
341
-
-
79955456264
-
-
See Meyers, supra note 234, at 624.
-
See Meyers, supra note 234, at 624.
-
-
-
-
342
-
-
79955388313
-
-
FEINBERG, supra note 101, at 32 ("To the degree to which a person is autonomous he is not merely the mouthpeice of other persons or forces. Rather his tastes, opinions, ideals, goals, values, and preferences are all authentically his.").
-
FEINBERG, supra note 101, at 32 ("To the degree to which a person is autonomous he is not merely the mouthpeice of other persons or forces. Rather his tastes, opinions, ideals, goals, values, and preferences are all authentically his.").
-
-
-
-
344
-
-
0004273805
-
-
(arguing that people give meaning to their lives by carrying out a life plan); RAZ, supra note 225, at 370, 400-29
-
See ROBERT NOZICK, ANARCHY, STATE, AND UTOPIA 48-51 (1974) (arguing that people give meaning to their lives by carrying out a life plan); RAZ, supra note 225, at 370, 400-29;
-
(1974)
Anarchy, State, and Utopia
, pp. 48-51
-
-
Nozick, R.1
-
345
-
-
0003030413
-
A note on freedom and flexibility
-
K. Basu et al. eds., The capabilities approach, too, recognizes the value of self-determination. One of the fundamental capabilities on Nussbaum's objective list is Practical Reason. NUSSBAUM, supra note 70, at 82. This includes the freedom and opportunity to develop one's own sense of the good. Id. Practical reason is, for Nussbaum, one of the two most fundamental capabilities.
-
Kenneth J. Arrow, A Note on Freedom and Flexibility, in CHOICE, WELFARE AND DEVELOPMENT 7, 7-16 (K. Basu et al. eds., 1995). The capabilities approach, too, recognizes the value of self-determination. One of the fundamental capabilities on Nussbaum's objective list is Practical Reason. NUSSBAUM, supra note 70, at 82. This includes the freedom and opportunity to develop one's own sense of the good. Id. Practical reason is, for Nussbaum, one of the two most fundamental capabilities.
-
(1995)
Choice, Welfare and Development
-
-
Arrow, K.J.1
-
346
-
-
79955403412
-
-
Id.
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
349
-
-
0033270098
-
Religion and state-a fresh theoretical start
-
Autonomy can also provide a reason to give preference-satisfaction moral weight; if preferences are not somehow your own, then it is less clear why it would be wrong or harmful to prevent you from satisfying them.
-
Gidon Sapir, Religion and State-A Fresh Theoretical Start, 75 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 579, 609 (1999). Autonomy can also provide a reason to give preference-satisfaction moral weight; if preferences are not somehow your own, then it is less clear why it would be wrong or harmful to prevent you from satisfying them.
-
(1999)
Notre Dame L. Rev.
, vol.75
-
-
Sapir, G.1
-
350
-
-
79955395099
-
-
See Christman, supra note 129, at 19.
-
See Christman, supra note 129, at 19.
-
-
-
-
351
-
-
79955382182
-
-
FEINBERG, supra note 101, at 35-37.
-
FEINBERG, supra note 101, at 35-37.
-
-
-
-
352
-
-
79955396671
-
-
note
-
242 This Article does not take a position on whether constraints that only remove morally repugnant options can constitute harms. Raz qualified his valorization of autonomy by arguing that autonomy only contributes to well-being if it is used to pursue the good. RAZ, supra note 225, at 381. Similarly, Nussbaum and Sen argue that capabilities to do evil are not valuable. See NUSSBAUM, supra note 70, at 83 ("Not all actual human abilities exert a moral claim [to be given the opportunity to develop], only the ones that have been evaluated as valuable from an ethical viewpoint (The capacity for cruelty, for example, does not figure on the list [of fundamental capabilities].)"); id. at 81 (noting that capabilities are valuable when they are used to choose lives that people "have reason to value"); SEN, supra note 80, at 65 (noting that freedom is reduced by eliminating options that a people have "reasonably defendable" preferences for). This Article presumes that the vast majority of commitments that tort victims hold are not morally repugnant or evil. RAZ, supra note 225, at 381 ("A moral theory which recognizes the value of autonomy inevitably upholds a pluralistic view. It admits the value of a large number of greatly differing pursuits among which individuals are free to choose."). Therefore, constraints on maintaining these commitments can count as harms regardless of whether all or only some constraints on autonomy cause harm.
-
-
-
-
353
-
-
79955369278
-
Harm, history, and counterfactuals
-
RAZ, supra note 225, at 413 ("Depriving a person of opportunities or of the ability to use them is a way of causing him harm."). Stephen Perry asks us to consider a Miss America contestant who is kidnapped and prevented from competing. See According to Perry, she is harmed because her kidnappers have robbed her of an opportunity to compete.
-
RAZ, supra note 225, at 413 ("Depriving a person of opportunities or of the ability to use them is a way of causing him harm."). Stephen Perry asks us to consider a Miss America contestant who is kidnapped and prevented from competing. See Stephen Perry, Harm, History, and Counterfactuals, 40 SAN DIEGO L. REV. 1283, 1292-93 (2003). According to Perry, she is harmed because her kidnappers have robbed her of an opportunity to compete.
-
(2003)
San Diego L. Rev.
, vol.40
-
-
Perry, S.1
-
354
-
-
79955410046
-
-
As an aside, this Article does not take a position on whether constraints caused by cultural or economic forces-as opposed to individual tortious conduct-should be labeled "harms." But using the term harm in these cases is certainly comprehensible, and is not obviously misplaced. For discussions of similar debates about the proper scope of the term "freedom,"
-
Id. In Joel Feinberg's terminology, she has been harmed because her interest in competing has been thwarted. JOEL FEINBERG, 1 THE MORAL LIMITS OF THE CRIMINAL LAW: HARM TO OTHERS 92-93 (1984). As an aside, this Article does not take a position on whether constraints caused by cultural or economic forces-as opposed to individual tortious conduct-should be labeled "harms." But using the term harm in these cases is certainly comprehensible, and is not obviously misplaced. For discussions of similar debates about the proper scope of the term "freedom,"
-
(1984)
The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law: Harm to Others
, vol.1
, pp. 92-93
-
-
Feinberg, J.1
-
355
-
-
84935815016
-
'Constraints on freedom' as a descriptive concept
-
A further clarification may be in order here. This Article does provide an account of which human actions trigger tort liability. It relies on existing tort doctrine to make this determination, and focuses on the harms that result from these actions.
-
see Felix Oppenheim, 'Constraints on Freedom' as a Descriptive Concept, 95 ETHICS 305, 305-06 (1985). A further clarification may be in order here. This Article does provide an account of which human actions trigger tort liability. It relies on existing tort doctrine to make this determination, and focuses on the harms that result from these actions.
-
(1985)
Ethics
, vol.95
-
-
Oppenheim, F.1
-
356
-
-
85022741161
-
Wrongful life, procreative responsibility, and the significance of harm
-
Seana Valentine Shiffrin, Wrongful Life, Procreative Responsibility, and the Significance of Harm, 5 LEGAL THEORY 117, 123-24 (1999).
-
(1999)
Legal Theory
, vol.5
-
-
Shiffrin, S.V.1
-
357
-
-
0001457823
-
Being free to act, and being a free man
-
(arguing that the cost of acting is relevant to determining whether someone is "free" to do so); Oppenheim, supra note 243, at 305, 307-08 (discussing "practical impossibility" in the context of defining freedom);
-
See S. I. Benn & W. L. Weinstein, Being Free to Act, and Being a Free Man, 80 MIND 194, 208-09 (1971) (arguing that the cost of acting is relevant to determining whether someone is "free" to do so); Oppenheim, supra note 243, at 305, 307-08 (discussing "practical impossibility" in the context of defining freedom);
-
(1971)
Mind
, vol.80
-
-
Benn, S.I.1
Weinstein, W.L.2
-
358
-
-
20444469722
-
Dollars and death
-
("[W]hen people have few or bad options, their choices might not count as voluntary.").
-
Eric A Posner & Cass R. Sunstein, Dollars and Death, 72 U. CHI. L. REV. 537, 565 (2005) ("[W]hen people have few or bad options, their choices might not count as voluntary.").
-
(2005)
U. Chi. L. Rev.
, vol.72
-
-
Posner, E.A.1
Sunstein, C.R.2
-
359
-
-
0031787509
-
Suicide in a spinal cord injured population: Its relation to functional status
-
Andreas Hartkopp et al., Suicide in a Spinal Cord Injured Population: Its Relation to Functional Status, 79 ARCHIVES PHYSICAL MED. REHABILITATION 1356, 1356 (1998).
-
(1998)
Archives Physical Med. Rehabilitation
, vol.79
-
-
Hartkopp, A.1
-
360
-
-
79955445400
-
-
See id. at 1356, 1358 (summarizing previous studies finding that victims of spinal cord injury have suicide rates 3.3-4.9 times greater than the general population, and reporting a suicide rate from a Danish sample that was 4.6 times higher than the general population, controlling for gender, age, and year)
-
See id. at 1356, 1358 (summarizing previous studies finding that victims of spinal cord injury have suicide rates 3.3-4.9 times greater than the general population, and reporting a suicide rate from a Danish sample that was 4.6 times higher than the general population, controlling for gender, age, and year);
-
-
-
-
361
-
-
0033773542
-
Causes of death after spinal cord injury
-
(reporting suicide rates for an Australian sample that were 4.4 times those of the general population, controlling for age and sex).
-
RJ Soden et al., Causes of Death After Spinal Cord Injury, 38 SPINAL CORD 604, 605 (2000) (reporting suicide rates for an Australian sample that were 4.4 times those of the general population, controlling for age and sex).
-
(2000)
Spinal Cord
, vol.38
-
-
Soden, R.J.1
-
362
-
-
79955393031
-
-
Smith & Sparkes, supra note 9, at 619-20.
-
Smith & Sparkes, supra note 9, at 619-20.
-
-
-
-
363
-
-
79955406430
-
-
Gilbert et al., supra note 10, at 619. See generally WILSON, supra note 117, at 38-40 (explaining the "psychological immune system").
-
Gilbert et al., supra note 10, at 619. See generally WILSON, supra note 117, at 38-40 (explaining the "psychological immune system").
-
-
-
-
364
-
-
79955439405
-
-
note
-
250 The preceding discussion should begin to show how the harms of self-altering injury could be integrated into the capabilities approach: the freedom or opportunity to maintain one's commitments is arguably a fundamental capability. Nussbaum lists Practical Reason as one of the two most important capabilities. NUSSBAUM, supra note 70, at 82. Practical Reason includes "[b]eing able to form a conception of the good and to engage in critical reflection about the planning of one's life." Id. at 79. The pressures of severe physical disability do not reduce one's capacity or ability to form a conception of the good, or reduce one's ability to critically reason. But Nussbaum uses her list to defend a minimal threshold of freedom that all people deserve. Id. at 86. Given her focus on threshold levels, it is not surprising that she phrases her explication of Practical Reason in terms of being "able" to form a conception of the good. It seems fair to suggest that scholars should interpret Practical Reason more broadly to encompass matters of degree. Thus one's free-dom and opportunity to exercise practical reason (and choose a good life) is reduced when some ideals, goals, and preferences are placed out of reach. Expanding the scope of Practical Reason to include the freedom and opportunity to maintain one's conception of the good would seem to be another appropriate interpretation. Taken together, this would suggest that the freedom and opportunity to maintain one's commitments would be a fundamental capability. Given the importance of self-determination, and the links between self-determination and the maintenance of commitments, it seems likely that an "overlapping consensus" about the fundamental nature of this freedom could form. See NUSSBAUM, supra note 77, at 79, 304-05.
-
-
-
-
365
-
-
79955390970
-
-
One need not accept Nussbaum's list of fundamental capabilities, or accept the proposed interpretation of Practical Reason above, to accept the viability of self-altering injury. This explains why this Article has focused on developing the notion of self-altering injury separately from the capabilities approach. All that is required is the (hopefully unobjectionable) assertion that forced changes in one's commitments are harms
-
One need not accept Nussbaum's list of fundamental capabilities, or accept the proposed interpretation of Practical Reason above, to accept the viability of self-altering injury. This explains why this Article has focused on developing the notion of self-altering injury separately from the capabilities approach. All that is required is the (hopefully unobjectionable) assertion that forced changes in one's commitments are harms.
-
-
-
-
366
-
-
79955371319
-
-
This Article does not explore the implications of self-altering injuries for compensatory, corrective justice, and civil recourse theories of tort law. These issues are left for future work.
-
This Article does not explore the implications of self-altering injuries for compensatory, corrective justice, and civil recourse theories of tort law. These issues are left for future work.
-
-
-
-
368
-
-
0000087278
-
Decoupling liability: Optimal incentives for care and litigation
-
For a general discussion of decoupling compensatory recoveries from deterrence payments, see A Mitchell Polinsky & Yeon-Koo Che, Decoupling Liability: Optimal Incentives for Care and Litigation, 22 RAND J. ECON. 562, 566 (1991).
-
(1991)
Rand J. Econ.
, vol.22
-
-
Mitchell Polinsky, A.1
Che, Y.-K.2
|