메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 62, Issue 3, 2011, Pages 707-736

How different are originalism and non-originalism?

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 79955364559     PISSN: 00178322     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (37)

References (351)
  • 1
    • 79955387702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • infra Part 1
    • See infra Part 1.
  • 2
    • 79955428476 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • infra Part 1
    • See infra Part 1.
  • 4
    • 73049111064 scopus 로고
    • 384 U.S. 436, 498
    • See, e.g., Miranda v. Arizona, 384 U.S. 436, 498 (1966).
    • (1966) Miranda V. Arizona
  • 5
    • 1842488232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The interpretive force of the constitution's secret drafting history
    • 1113
    • See Vasan Kesavan & Michael Stokes Paulsen, The Interpretive Force of the Constitution's Secret Drafting History, 91 GEO. L.J. 1113, 1134-48 (2003);
    • (2003) Geo. L.J. , vol.91 , pp. 1134-1148
    • Kesavan, V.1    Paulsen, M.S.2
  • 7
    • 79955414139 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • infra notes 38-50 and accompanying text
    • infra notes 38-50 and accompanying text.
  • 8
    • 70349804438 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Living originalism
    • 239, 241
    • See Thomas B. Colby & Peter J. Smith, Living Originalism, 59 DUKE L.J. 239, 241, 242 (2009).
    • (2009) Duke L.J. , vol.59 , pp. 242
    • Colby, T.B.1    Smith, P.J.2
  • 9
    • 79955401104 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • infra notes 52-53 and accompanying text
    • See infra notes 52-53 and accompanying text.
  • 10
    • 79955462170 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • infra notes 54-64 and accompanying text
    • See infra notes 54-64 and accompanying text.
  • 11
    • 79955405299 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • infra notes 54-64 and accompanying text
    • See infra notes 54-64 and accompanying text.
  • 13
    • 79955373314 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • infra note 53 and accompanying text
    • See infra note 53 and accompanying text.
  • 14
    • 79955429608 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • infra note 93 and accompanying text
    • See infra note 93 and accompanying text.
  • 15
    • 79955451136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • infra notes 104-11 and accompanying text
    • See infra notes 104-11 and accompanying text.
  • 16
    • 79955401103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • infra notes 112-30 and accompanying text
    • See infra notes 112-30 and accompanying text.
  • 17
    • 0347851557 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Foreword: The appeal of originalism
    • 773
    • See, e.g., Earl Maltz, Foreword: The Appeal of Originalism, 1987 UTAH L. REV. 773, 779-95;
    • Utah L. Rev. , vol.1987 , pp. 779-795
    • Maltz, E.1
  • 18
    • 79955424886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • infra notes 135-39 and accompanying text
    • infra notes 135-39 and accompanying text.
  • 19
    • 79955376422 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Colby & Smith, supra note 6, at 241-42
    • As will become apparent, the label "originalism" embraces a wide range of interpretive theories, see Colby & Smith, supra note 6, at 241-42, but I use the term here to refer to the family of modern approaches that regard "the discoverable meaning of the Constitution at the time of its initial adoption as authoritative for purposes of constitutional interpretation in the present."
  • 20
    • 79955420247 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Whittington, supra note 5, at 599
    • Whittington, supra note 5, at 599.
  • 21
    • 0038927689 scopus 로고
    • Foreword: The constitution of change-legal fundamentality without fundamentalism
    • 30
    • See Morton J. Horwitz, Foreword: The Constitution of Change-Legal Fundamentality Without Fundamentalism, 107 HARV. L. REV. 30, 44 (1993).
    • (1993) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.107 , pp. 44
    • Horwitz, M.J.1
  • 22
    • 0011298491 scopus 로고
    • 410 U.S. 113, 164
    • See, e.g., Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113, 164 (1973);
    • (1973) Roe V. Wade
  • 24
    • 0013354667 scopus 로고
    • 408 U.S. 238, 239
    • See Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238, 239 (1972).
    • (1972) Furman V. Georgia
  • 25
    • 73049111064 scopus 로고
    • 384 U.S. 436, 498
    • See Miranda v. Arizona, 384 U.S. 436, 498 (1966).
    • (1966) Miranda V. Arizona
  • 27
    • 0003374013 scopus 로고
    • Neutral principles and some first amendment problems
    • 1
    • Robert H. Bork, Neutral Principles and Some First Amendment Problems, 47 IND. L.J. 1, 6-10 (1971).
    • (1971) Ind. L.J. , vol.47 , pp. 6-10
    • Bork, R.H.1
  • 28
    • 79955386687 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BERGER, supra note 21, at 8
    • See, e.g., BERGER, supra note 21, at 8;
  • 29
    • 0346670364 scopus 로고
    • The constitution, original intent, and economic rights
    • 823
    • Robert H. Bork, The Constitution, Original Intent, and Economic Rights, 23 SAN DIEGO L. REV. 823, 823 (1986).
    • (1986) San Diego L. Rev. , vol.23 , pp. 823
    • Bork, R.H.1
  • 30
    • 84874384191 scopus 로고
    • The notion of a living constitution
    • 693
    • See William H. Rehnquist, The Notion of a Living Constitution, 54 TEX. L. REV. 693, 693 (1976).
    • (1976) Tex. L. Rev. , vol.54 , pp. 693
    • Rehnquist, W.H.1
  • 31
    • 0000098233 scopus 로고
    • Originalism: The lesser evil
    • 849
    • Antonin Scalia, Originalism: The Lesser Evil, 57 U. CIN. L. REV. 849, 852-56 (1989).
    • (1989) U. Cin. L. Rev. , vol.57 , pp. 852-856
    • Scalia, A.1
  • 32
    • 79955368180 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bork, supra note 21, at 6-10
    • See Bork, supra note 21, at 6-10;
  • 33
    • 77954717085 scopus 로고
    • Styles in constitutional theory
    • 383.
    • Robert H. Bork, Styles in Constitutional Theory, 26 S. TEX. L.J-383.394-95 (1985).
    • (1985) S. Tex. L.J , vol.26 , pp. 394-395
    • Bork, R.H.1
  • 34
    • 79955399053 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Whittington, supra note 5, at 599
    • Whittington, supra note 5, at 599.
  • 35
    • 79955400089 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 601
    • Id. at 601;
  • 36
    • 79959775810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Biblical literalism and constitutional originalism
    • (forthcoming 2011) (manuscript at 31-35) (on file with the Hastings Law Journal)
    • see also Peter J. Smith & Robert W. Turtle, Biblical Literalism and Constitutional Originalism, 86 NOTRE DAME L. REV. (forthcoming 2011) (manuscript at 31-35) (on file with the Hastings Law Journal).
    • Notre Dame L. Rev. , vol.86
    • Smith, P.J.1    Turtle, R.W.2
  • 37
    • 79955400632 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BERGER, supra note 21, at 296
    • See BERGER, supra note 21, at 296 ("Substitution by the Court of its own value choices for those embodied in the Constitution violates the basic principle of government by consent of the governed.");
  • 38
    • 84935322749 scopus 로고
    • ROBERT H. BORK, THE TEMPTING OF AMERICA: THE POLITICAL SEDUCTION OF THE LAW 143 (1990) ("[O]Only the approach of original understanding meets the criteria that any theory of constitutional adjudication must meet in order to possess democratic legitimacy.").
    • (1990) The Tempting of America: The Political Seduction of the Law , pp. 143
    • Bork, R.H.1
  • 39
    • 84874179257 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On not being "not an originalist"
    • 259, 269
    • Cf. H. Jefferson Powell, On Not Being "Not an Originalist" 7 U. ST. THOMAS L.J. 259, 269, 274 (2010) (praising originalism as "an elegant response to a genuine problem," but rejecting it because it would "open an all but unbridgeable chasm between constitutional decision making" and all other aspects of legal practice).
    • (2010) U. St. Thomas L.J. , vol.7 , pp. 274
    • Jefferson Powell, H.1
  • 40
    • 79955439321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Colby & Smith, supra note 6, at 247-62
    • The evolution of originalist thought has become a familiar story. For more detailed accounts, see Colby & Smith, supra note 6, at 247-62;
  • 41
    • 79955401745 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The sacrifice of the new originalism
    • forthcoming manuscript (on file with the Hastings Law Journal)
    • Thomas B. Colby, The Sacrifice of the New Originalism, 99 GEO. L.J. (forthcoming 2011) (manuscript at 3-26) (on file with the Hastings Law Journal);
    • (2011) Geo. L.J. , vol.99 , pp. 3-26
    • Colby, T.B.1
  • 42
    • 79955420246 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kesavan & Paulsen, supra note 5, at 1134-48
    • Kesavan & Paulsen, supra note 5, at 1134-48;
  • 43
    • 79955434609 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Whittington, supra note 5, at 599-610
    • Whittington, supra note 5, at 599-610.
  • 44
    • 79955387206 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BERGER, supra note 21, at 3
    • BERGER, supra note 21, at 3;
  • 45
    • 79955405829 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bork, supra note 22, at 823
    • Bork, supra note 22, at 823;
  • 46
    • 77954715213 scopus 로고
    • Some new thoughts on an old problem-the role of the intent of the framers in constitutional theory
    • 811
    • Earl Maltz, Some New Thoughts on an Old Problem-The Role of the Intent of the Framers in Constitutional Theory, 63 B.U. L. REV. 811, 811-12 (1983);
    • (1983) B.U. L. Rev. , vol.63 , pp. 811-812
    • Maltz, E.1
  • 47
    • 79955435244 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rehnquist, supra note 23, at 694-97
    • Rehnquist, supra note 23, at 694-97;
  • 48
    • 79955383625 scopus 로고
    • Att'y gen. of the U.S., Address before the D.C. Chapter of the federalist society lawyers division (Nov. 15,1985)
    • [hereinafter SOURCEBOOK]
    • Edwin Meese III, Att'y Gen. of the U.S., Address Before the D.C. Chapter of the Federalist Society Lawyers Division (Nov. 15,1985), in U.S. DEP'T. OF JUSTICE, OFFICE OF LEGAL POLICY, ORIGINAL MEANING JURISPRUDENCE: A SOURCEBOOK app. b at 97 (1987) [hereinafter SOURCEBOOK].
    • (1987) U.S. Dep't. Of Justice, Office of Legal Policy, Original Meaning Jurisprudence: A Sourcebook , pp. 97
    • Meese III, E.1
  • 49
    • 79955412982 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Colby, supra note 30, at 8-13
    • See, e.g., Colby, supra note 30, at 8-13;
  • 50
    • 79955394499 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kesavan & Paulsen, supra note 5, at 1139-40
    • Kesavan & Paulsen, supra note 5, at 1139-40;
  • 51
    • 84978368099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Justice of the U.S. Supreme court, address before the attorney general's conference on economic liberties (June 14,1986)
    • supra note 31, app. c
    • Antonin Scalia, Justice of the U.S. Supreme Court, Address Before the Attorney General's Conference on Economic Liberties (June 14,1986), in SOURCEBOOK, supra note 31, app. c at 106 ("I ought to campaign to change the label from the Doctrine of Original Intent to the Doctrine of Original Meaning.").
    • Source Book , pp. 106
    • Scalia, A.1
  • 52
    • 79955436723 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Colby & Smith, supra note 6, at 250-52
    • Many originalists embraced a focus on the original understanding- sometimes subjective, sometimes objective-during the journey from original intent to original meaning. See Colby & Smith, supra note 6, at 250-52;
  • 53
    • 79955459130 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Colby, supra note 30, at 12-13
    • Colby, supra note 30, at 12-13.
  • 54
    • 0011536201 scopus 로고
    • The misconceived quest for the original understanding
    • 204
    • See, e.g., Paul Brest, The Misconceived Quest for the Original Understanding, 60 B.U. L. REV. 204, 209-22 (1980).
    • (1980) B.U. L. Rev. , vol.60 , pp. 209-222
    • Brest, P.1
  • 55
    • 0042088293 scopus 로고
    • The original understanding of original intent
    • 885
    • See H. Jefferson Powell, The Original Understanding of Original Intent, 98 HARV. L. REV. 885, 948 (1985).
    • (1985) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.98 , pp. 948
    • Jefferson Powell, H.1
  • 56
    • 79955424336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kesavan & Paulsen, supra note 5, at 1132, 1147
    • See, e.g., Kesavan & Paulsen, supra note 5, at 1132, 1147;
  • 57
    • 0039884712 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Common-law courts in a civil law system: The role of the united states federal courts in interpreting the constitution and laws
    • 38 Amy Gutmann ed.
    • Antonin Scalia, Common-Law Courts in a Civil Law System: The Role of the United States Federal Courts in Interpreting the Constitution and Laws, in A MATTER OF INTERPRETATION 3, 17, 38 (Amy Gutmann ed., 1997).
    • (1997) A Matter of Interpretation , vol.3 , pp. 17
    • Scalia, A.1
  • 58
    • 79955372259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kesavan & Paulsen, supra note 5, at 1132
    • See, e.g., Kesavan & Paulsen, supra note 5, at 1132;
  • 59
    • 26644454854 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • When did the constitution become law?
    • 1
    • Gary Lawson & Guy Seidman, When Did the Constitution Become Law?, 77 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 1, 25 (2001).
    • (2001) Notre Dame L. Rev. , vol.77 , pp. 25
    • Lawson, G.1    Seidman, G.2
  • 60
    • 0011534472 scopus 로고
    • The originalism debate: A guide for the perplexed
    • 1085
    • Daniel A. Farber, The Originalism Debate: A Guide for the Perplexed, 49 OHIO ST. L.J. 1085, 1090 (1989) (noting that Powell's evidence demonstrated that the common law method of interpreting text focused on the language's objective meaning in the document, not its author's subjective intent).
    • (1989) Ohio St. L.J. , vol.49 , pp. 1090
    • Farber, D.A.1
  • 61
    • 79955365095 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Whittington, supra note 5, at 602-10
    • Whittington, supra note 5, at 602-10.
  • 62
    • 79955441442 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 609
    • Id. at 609.
  • 63
    • 68149155778 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Original intention public meaning in constitutional interpretation
    • 703
    • See, e.g., Richard S. Kay, Original Intention and Public Meaning in Constitutional Interpretation, 103 Nw. U. L. REV. 703, 704 (2009);
    • (2009) Nw. U. L. Rev. , vol.103 , pp. 704
    • Kay, R.S.1
  • 66
    • 36248967236 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Originalism, popular sovereignty, and reverse stare decisis
    • 1437
    • Compare Kurt T. Lash, Originalism, Popular Sovereignty, and Reverse Stare Decisis, 93 VA. L. REV. 1437, 1440 (2007) ("[T]he most common and most influential justification for originalism[] [is] popular sovereignty and the judicially enforced will of the people."),
    • (2007) Va. L. Rev. , vol.93 , pp. 1440
    • Lash, K.T.1
  • 68
    • 79955444443 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare Scalia, supra note 24, at 863-64
    • Compare Scalia, supra note 24, at 863-64 (arguing that originalism constrains judges, because it "establishes a historical criterion that is conceptually" distinct from the judge's own preferences), with
  • 69
    • 46149103664 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the hypotheses that lie at the foundations of originalism
    • 473
    • John Harrison, On the Hypotheses That Lie at the Foundations of Originalism, 31 HARV. J.L. A PUB. POL'Y 473, 473-76 (2008) ("Can originalism, or any methodology, keep interpreters from interpreting the Constitution along the lines that they think good? ... [I]t cannot...").
    • (2008) Harv. J.L. A Pub. Pol'y , vol.31 , pp. 473-476
    • Harrison, J.1
  • 70
    • 79955409435 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Colby, supra note 30, at 34; infra notes 147-50 and accompanying text
    • See Colby, supra note 30, at 34; infra notes 147-50 and accompanying text.
  • 71
    • 79955451651 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kesavan & Paulsen, supra note 5, at 1127-28
    • See, e.g., Kesavan & Paulsen, supra note 5, at 1127-28 (defending objective original meaning as the object of interpretation but acknowledging that it is legitimate "not to treat 'this Constitution' as authoritative");
  • 72
    • 21744433271 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On reading recipes... and constitutions
    • 1823, (!997)
    • Gary Lawson, On Reading Recipes... and Constitutions, 85 GEO. L.J. 1823, 1835 (!997) ("[I]nterpreting the Constitution and applying the Constitution are two different enterprises.");
    • Geo. L.J. , vol.85 , pp. 1835
    • Lawson, G.1
  • 73
    • 77951769777 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Originalism as a legal enterprise
    • 47
    • Gary Lawson & Guy Seidman, Originalism as a Legal Enterprise, 23 CONST. COMMENT. 47, 53 (2006) (describing the question whether we should "follow the instructions in the Constitution" as a "question of political morality, not of interpretive theory");
    • (2006) Const. Comment. , vol.23 , pp. 53
    • Lawson, G.1    Seidman, G.2
  • 74
    • 79955410876 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Solum, supra note 41, at 30 ("What words mean is one thing; what we should do about their meaning is another.")
    • Solum, supra note 41, at 30 ("What words mean is one thing; what we should do about their meaning is another.").
  • 75
    • 84979495436 scopus 로고
    • 392
    • See, e.g. Letter from Thomas Jefferson to James Madison (Sept. 6, 1789), in 15 THE PAPERS OF THOMAS JEFFERSON 392, 392 (Julian P. Boyd & William H. Gaines, Jr. eds., 1958) ("The question [is] whether one generation of men has a right to bind another....");
    • (1958) The Papers of Thomas Jefferson , vol.15 , pp. 392
    • Boyd, J.P.1    Gaines Jr., W.H.2
  • 76
    • 70349838231 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The perpetual anxiety of living constitutionalism
    • 353
    • see also Ethan J. Leib, The Perpetual Anxiety of Living Constitutionalism, 24 CONST. COMMENT. 353, 358-60 (2007) ("[N] onoriginalists are plagued by anxiety about the dead hand of the past-and think we need to update and affirm the document's underlying principles if it is to be binding on anyone living today.");
    • (2007) Const. Comment. , vol.24 , pp. 358-360
    • Leib, E.J.1
  • 77
    • 56349122114 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • When should original meanings matter?
    • 165
    • Richard A. Primus, When Should Original Meanings Matter?, 107 MICH. L. REV. 165, 192 (2008) ("[G]overning the population of the United States today according to the constitutional understandings of people long since dead should not be understood as showing respect for democratic-enactment authority.").
    • (2008) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.107 , pp. 192
    • Primus, R.A.1
  • 78
    • 1842756163 scopus 로고
    • The constitution of the United States: Contemporary ratification
    • 433
    • See, e.g., William J. Brennan, Jr., The Constitution of the United States: Contemporary Ratification, 27 S. TEX. L. REV. 433, 438 (1985) ("What the constitutional fundamentals meant to the wisdom of other times cannot be the measure to the vision of our time....Our Constitution was not intended to preserve a preexisting society but to make a new one....");
    • (1985) S. Tex. L. Rev. , vol.27 , pp. 438
    • Brennan Jr., W.J.1
  • 79
    • 79955462690 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leib, supra note 45, at 358-60
    • Leib, supra note 45, at 358-60.
  • 80
    • 79955379038 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kesavan & Paulsen, supra note 5, at 1127-28
    • See, e.g., Kesavan & Paulsen, supra note 5, at 1127-28;
  • 81
    • 79955435243 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lawson, supra note 44, at 1824
    • Lawson, supra note 44, at 1824;
  • 82
    • 79955419293 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lawson & Seidman, supra note 44, at 53
    • Lawson & Seidman, supra note 44, at 53;
  • 83
    • 33745418344 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • How to interpret the constitution (and how not to)
    • 2037
    • Michael Stokes Paulsen, How to Interpret the Constitution (and How Not to), 115 YALE L.J. 2037, 2062 (2006).
    • (2006) Yale L.J. , vol.115 , pp. 2062
    • Paulsen, M.S.1
  • 84
    • 79955368179 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lawson, supra note 44, at 1824
    • Lawson, supra note 44, at 1824 ("[A] theory of interpretation allows us to determine what the Constitution truly means, while a theory of adjudication allows us to determine what role, if any, the Constitution's meaning should play in particular decisions.");
  • 85
    • 79955403853 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 1825
    • id. at 1825 ("One can be a strict interpretative originalist and forcefully deny that the Constitution has any political legitimacy."). Lawrence Solum has made a similar argument in distinguishing between "semantic originalism" and "normative originalism."
  • 86
    • 79955387701 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Solum, supra note 41, at 27-33
    • Solum, supra note 41, at 27-33.
  • 87
    • 66449123378 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Originalism is bunk
    • 1
    • Mitchell N. Berman, Originalism Is Bunk, 84 N.Y.U. L. REV. 1, 32 (2009) ("[B]ecause it is not in fact controversial in the contemporary debates over American constitutional interpretation that judges should enforce the law, the non-normative variant of Originalism is not interestingly distinct... from its more common, avowedly normative, cousin.");
    • (2009) N.Y.U. L. Rev. , vol.84 , pp. 32
    • Berman, M.N.1
  • 88
    • 79955431142 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Colby, supra note 30, at 30
    • Colby, supra note 30, at 30 ("[The] response [to the dead-hand problem] is something of a cop out. Our legal system and legal culture presuppose that judges must follow the law, so if the meaning of the Constitution is its original public meaning, then it goes without saying that judges will have to follow it.");
  • 89
    • 79955422313 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leib, supra note 45, at 359
    • Leib, supra note 45, at 359 ("[O]riginal meaning originalism... gives pride of place to the very dead hand living constitutionalists are convinced we must resist to maintain the document's present-day legitimacy."). Jack Balkin, who, as I explain infra, is a new new originalist, has nevertheless argued that, properly conceived, originalism addresses the dead-hand problem just as nimbly as does living constitutionalism.
  • 90
    • 41349095913 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Abortion and original meaning
    • 291
    • See Jack M. Balkin, Abortion and Original Meaning, 24 CONST. COMMENT. 291, 303 (2007) ("The Constitution is a great work that spans many lifetimes, a vibrant multi-generational undertaking, in which succeeding generations pledge faith in the constitutional project and exercise fidelity to the Constitution by making the Constitution their own."); see also infra notes 73-84 and accompanying text.
    • (2007) Const. Comment. , vol.24 , pp. 303
    • Balkin, J.M.1
  • 91
    • 79955447336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BERGER, supra note 21, at 364
    • See, e.g., BERGER, supra note 21, at 364 ("A judicial power to revise the Constitution transforms the bulwark of our liberties into a parchment barrier.");
  • 92
    • 79955415164 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bork, supra note 21, at 6
    • Bork, supra note 21, at 6 ("[A] legitimate Court must be controlled by principles exterior to the will of the Justices.").
  • 93
    • 68149180342 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Original methods originalism: A new theory of interpretation and the case against construction
    • 751
    • Because the new new originalists believe that the Constitution's vague provisions require judicial construction in the formulation of legal rules, see infra notes 55-66 and accompanying text, John McGinnis and Michael Rappaport refer to their approach as "constructionist originalism." John O. McGinnis & Michael B. Rappaport, Original Methods Originalism: A New Theory of Interpretation and the Case Against Construction, 103 Nw. U. L. REV. 751, 752 (2009).
    • (2009) Nw. U. L. Rev. , vol.103 , pp. 752
    • McGinnis, J.O.1    Rappaport, M.B.2
  • 94
    • 79955423832 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BERGER, supra note 21, at 99-116
    • See, e.g., BERGER, supra note 21, at 99-116 (rejecting the "open-ended phraseology theory" (internal quotation marks omitted)).
  • 95
    • 79955417780 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BORK, supra note 28, at 166, 178-85
    • Bork also advanced such a view, see BORK, supra note 28, at 166, 178-85 (rejecting the view that the Constitution's open-ended provisions authorize judges to create rights), although, as I explain infra note 76, he appears to be of two minds on this question.
  • 96
    • 79955376960 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balkin, supra note 49, at 304-05
    • Balkin, supra note 49, at 304-05 ("[T]he fact that adopters chose text that features general and abstract concepts is normally the best evidence that they sought to embody general and abstract principles of constitutional law, whose scope, in turn, will have to be fleshed out later on by later generations.");
  • 97
    • 68149163952 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Framework originalism and the living constitution
    • 549
    • Jack M. Balkin, Framework Originalism and the Living Constitution, 103 Nw. U. L. REV. 549, 553 (2009) ("[Constitutional drafters] use standards or principles because they want to channel politics but delegate the details to future generations.");
    • (2009) Nw. U. L. Rev. , vol.103 , pp. 553
    • Balkin, J.M.1
  • 98
    • 79955415700 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 569-75
    • id. at 569-75 (describing the courts' role in construction);
  • 99
    • 33846270376 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scalia's infidelity: A critique of "faint-hearted" originalism
    • 7, 23
    • Randy E. Barnett, Scalia's Infidelity: A Critique of "Faint- Hearted" Originalism, 75 U. CIN. L. REV. 7, 11-13, 23 (2006) [hereinafter Barnett, Scalia's Infidelity] ("That the founders and the authors of the Fourteenth Amendment drafted texts that leave some discretion in application to changing circumstances is not a bug. It's a feature.");
    • (2006) U. Cin. L. Rev. , vol.75 , pp. 11-13
    • Barnett, R.E.1
  • 100
    • 76449101447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Trumping precedent with original meaning: Not as radical as it sounds
    • 257
    • Randy E. Barnett, Trumping Precedent with Original Meaning: Not as Radical as It Sounds, 22 CONST. COMMENT. 257, 264 (2005) [hereinafter Barnett, Trumping Precedent] ("That the Constitution includes more open-ended or abstract provisions, and thereby delegates discretion to judges, does not justify ignoring these portions of the text.").
    • (2005) Const. Comment. , vol.22 , pp. 264
    • Barnett, R.E.1
  • 101
    • 79955395011 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WHITTINGTON, supra note 10, at 7
    • WHITTINGTON, supra note 10, at 7.
  • 104
    • 79955418793 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WHITTINGTON, supra note 10, at 5-14
    • WHITTINGTON, supra note 10, at 5-14;
  • 105
    • 79955406352 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balkin, supra note 53, at 559-60
    • Balkin, supra note 53, at 559-60;
  • 107
    • 68149169422 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • District of Columbia v. Heller and originalism
    • 923
    • Lawrence B. Solum, District of Columbia v. Heller and Originalism, 103 Nw. U. L. REV. 923, 974 (2009);
    • (2009) Nw. U. L. Rev. , vol.103 , pp. 974
    • Solum, L.B.1
  • 108
    • 79955428475 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Solum, supra note 41, at 20, 67-89
    • Solum, supra note 41, at 20, 67-89.
  • 109
    • 79955456178 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Solum, supra note 55, at 967
    • Solum, supra note 55, at 967. Barnett has argued that "constitutional constructions, though not deducible immediately from the text, still may properly be connected to or constrained by it."
  • 110
    • 79955405828 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BARNETT, supra note 55, at 124-25
    • BARNETT, supra note 55, at 124-25;
  • 111
    • 0345818521 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The original meaning of the commerce clause
    • accord Randy E. Barnett, The Original Meaning of the Commerce Clause, 68 U. CHI. L. REV. 101, no (2001) ("[T]hough by definition constructions are not in the Constitution, they can be of the Constitution.").
    • (2001) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.68 , pp. 101
    • Barnett, R.E.1
  • 112
    • 79955409434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WHITTINGTON, supra note 10, at 7
    • WHITTINGTON, supra note 10, at 7. Barnett explains the relationship between interpretation and construction as follows:
  • 113
    • 79955406904 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • [O]riginalism is warranted as a theory of interpretation-that is, as a method of determining the meaning of the words written in the Constitution. For better or worse, knowing the meaning of these words only takes us so far in resolving current cases and controversies. Due either to ambiguity or vagueness, the original meaning of the text may not always determine a unique rule of law to be applied to a particular case or controversy. While not indeterminate, the original meaning can be "underdeterminate." Indeed, because the framers frequently used abstract language, this will often be the case. When this happens, interpretation must be supplemented by constitutional construction-within the bounds established by original meaning. In this manner, construction fills the unavoidable gaps in constitutional meaning when interpretation has reached its limits. Barnett, supra note 56, at 108 (footnote omitted). To be sure, Whittington's claim about construction has been quite modest; he has argued that construction is as much the province of the political branches as it is the province of the courts.
  • 114
    • 79955418792 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WHITTINGTON, supra note 10, at 7-13, 172-73
    • See WHITTINGTON, supra note 10, at 7-13, 172-73.
  • 115
    • 79955443950 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balkin, supra note 53, at 569-75
    • But Balkin, Barnett, and Solum have all made clear that they view constitutional construction as an appropriate task for judges as well. See Balkin, supra note 53, at 569-75;
  • 117
    • 79955401102 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Solum, supra note 55, at 979-80
    • Solum, supra note 55, at 979-80.
  • 118
    • 79955408930 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BARNETT, supra note 55, at 121
    • BARNETT, supra note 55, at 121.
  • 119
    • 79955391945 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 126
    • Id. at 126. In Barnett's view, constitutional legitimacy is accomplished through application of a "presumption of liberty" that promotes a libertarian vision of constitutional meaning.
  • 120
    • 79955391425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 259-69
    • Id. at 259-69.
  • 121
    • 79955385725 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balkin, supra note 53, at 552
    • See Balkin, supra note 53, at 552;
  • 122
    • 79955402308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balkin, supra note 49, at 295
    • Balkin, supra note 49, at 295.
  • 123
    • 79955379564 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balkin, supra note 53, at 604-05
    • Balkin, supra note 53, at 604-05.
  • 124
    • 79955412451 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 585-601
    • See id. at 585-601.
  • 125
    • 79955454632 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 598
    • Id. at 598.
  • 126
    • 79955376959 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 609
    • Id. at 609.
  • 127
    • 79955409433 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WHITTINGTON, supra note 55, at 5
    • WHITTINGTON, supra note 55, at 5 ("Unlike jurisprudential interpretation, construction provides for an element of creativity in construing constitutional meaning.").
  • 128
    • 79955444442 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WHITTINGTON, supra note 10, at 5
    • WHITTINGTON, supra note 10, at 5;
  • 129
    • 79955423831 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McGinnis & Rappaport, supra note 51, at 785
    • see McGinnis & Rappaport, supra note 51, at 785 (arguing that choosing among possible constructions requires reference to "political morality"). Barnett objects to this characterization, because "it suggests that such constructions are themselves completely unconstrained by the determinable original meaning of the text."
  • 130
    • 79955424885 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BARNETT, supra note 55, at 124.
    • BARNETT, supra note 55, at 124.
  • 131
    • 79955459129 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Barnett, Trumping Precedent, supra note 53, at 265
    • But he agrees that there can be a range of permissible constructions, and that judges must choose among them. See Barnett, Trumping Precedent, supra note 53, at 265.
  • 132
    • 70649097995 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Original meaning and constitutional redemption
    • 427
    • See Jack M. Balkin, Original Meaning and Constitutional Redemption, 24 CONST. COMMENT. 427, 443 (2007) ("My Article... attempts to move th[e] analysis along, making salient the logical consequences of the turn to original [public] meaning.").
    • (2007) Const. Comment. , vol.24 , pp. 443
    • Balkin, J.M.1
  • 133
    • 0011535155 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An originalism for nonoriginalists
    • 611
    • See, e.g. Randy E. Barnett, An Originalism for Nonoriginalists, 45 LOY. L. REV. 611, 620 (1999) ("Perhaps most important of all, however, originalism has itself changed-from original intention to original meaning."); Kesavan & Paulsen, supra note 5, at 1132, 1144 (coining the term "original, objective-public-meaning textualism" and defending the approach on the ground that it corrects the "jurisprudence of 'original understanding,'" which changed the "jurisprudence of 'original intent'" before that); Lawson, supra note 44, at 1834 ("[T]he Constitution's meaning is its original public meaning. Other approaches to interpretation are simply wrong."); supra note 32 and accompanying text. As a corollary to their embrace of the objective original meaning as the proper object of interpretation, most new originalists also rejected reliance on the original expected applications in determining constitutional meaning.
    • Loy. L. Rev. , vol.45
    • Barnett, R.E.1
  • 134
    • 68149179046 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Two cheers for professor balkin's originalism
    • 663
    • See, e.g., Stephen G. Calabresi & Livia Fine, Two Cheers for Professor Balkin's Originalism, 103 Nw. U. L. REV. 663, 668-72 (2009);
    • (2009) Nw. U. L. Rev. , vol.103 , pp. 668-672
    • Calabresi, S.G.1    Fine, L.2
  • 135
    • 21744451134 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The importance of humility in judicial review: A comment on ronald dworkin's "moral reading" of the constitution
    • 1269
    • Michael W. McConnell, The Importance of Humility in Judicial Review: A Comment on Ronald Dworkin's "Moral Reading" of the Constitution, 65 FORDHAM L. REV. 1269, 1284 (1997);
    • (1997) Fordham L. Rev. , vol.65 , pp. 1284
    • Michael, W.M.1
  • 136
    • 79955422312 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paulsen, supra note 47, at 2059
    • Paulsen, supra note 47, at 2059;
  • 137
    • 79955437673 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 35
    • Antonin Scalia, Response, in MATTER OF INTERPRETATION, supra note 35, at 144. Accordingly, most new originalists claim not to interpret the Constitution by seeking to determine how the Framers of a constitutional provision would have answered a particular question of constitutional law, but instead by seeking the objective original meaning of the text, as measured by the "hypothetical understandings" of an "artificially constructed" "reasonable person" at the time of ratification.
    • Matter of Interpretation , pp. 144
    • Antonin Scalia, R.1
  • 138
    • 79955392408 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lawson & Seidman, supra note 44, at 48
    • Lawson & Seidman, supra note 44, at 48.
  • 139
    • 79955395548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WHITTINGTON, supra note 10, at 182-87
    • See WHITTINGTON, supra note 10, at 182-87;
  • 140
    • 79955454154 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 187
    • id. at 187 ("The level of generality at which terms were defined is not an a priori theoretical question but a contextualized historical one.");
  • 141
    • 0346093223 scopus 로고
    • Abstraction and authority
    • 349
    • Frank H. Easterbrook, Abstraction and Authority, 59 U. CHI. L. REV. 349, 359 (1992) ("Thus the question becomes the level of generality the ratifiers and other sophisticated political actors at the time would have imputed to the text.").
    • (1992) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.59 , pp. 359
    • Easterbrook, F.H.1
  • 142
    • 79955435242 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Calabresi & Fine, supra note 68, at 672-74
    • See, e.g., Calabresi & Fine, supra note 68, at 672-74 ("[Some provisions of the Constitution] employ standards and not rules....It is not an adequate answer in these situations to say, as Justice Scalia sometimes does, that originalist judges ought not to enforce Clauses of this kind because they do not lend themselves to principled judicial application.");
  • 143
    • 79955428474 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McConnell, supra note 68
    • McConnell, supra note 68, at 1280-81 ("A genuine commitment to the semantic intentions of the Framers requires the interpreter to seek the level of generality at which the particular language was understood by its Framers... It is perfectly possible that, upon dispassionate historical investigation, the interpreter would discover that some provisions of the Constitution were understood at a high level of generality..."); infra notes 71-78 and accompanying text.
  • 144
    • 79955368178 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Whittington, supra note 5, at 611
    • See Whittington, supra note 5, at 611 ("[I]t is entirely possible that the principles that the founders meant to embody in the text were fairly abstract.");
  • 145
    • 79955374880 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balkin, supra note 53, at 553
    • Balkin, supra note 53, at 553 ("If [the text of the Constitution] states a standard, we must apply the standard. And if it states a general principle, we must apply the principle.");
  • 146
    • 79955374346 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 53
    • Barnett, Trumping Precedent, supra note 53, at 263 ("[Sometimes] the original meaning is rather abstract, or at a higher level of generality.").
    • Trumping Precedent , pp. 263
    • Barnett1
  • 147
    • 79955365580 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kesavan & Pauken, supra note 5, at 1132
    • New originalists have generally embraced the objective original meaning of the text as the touchstone of interpretation. See, e.g., Kesavan & Pauken, supra note 5, at 1132;
  • 148
    • 0036013296 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Delegation and original meaning
    • 327
    • Gary Lawson, Delegation and Original Meaning, 88 VA. L. REV. 327, 398 (2002);
    • (2002) Va. L. Rev. , vol.88 , pp. 398
    • Lawson, G.1
  • 149
    • 79955435105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scalia, supra note 35, at 38
    • Scalia, supra note 35, at 38. New new originalists have as well.
  • 150
    • 79955452164 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balkin, supra note 53, at 552-55
    • See, e.g., Balkin, supra note 53, at 552-55;
  • 151
    • 79955390384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Barnett, supra note 56, at 105
    • Barnett, supra note 56, at 105;
  • 152
    • 79955442472 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Solum, supra note 55, at 940-41
    • Solum, supra note 55, at 940-41.
  • 153
    • 79955425425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balkin, supra note 67, at 494
    • Balkin, supra note 67, at 494.
  • 154
    • 79955398558 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Whittington, supra note 5, at 608
    • Whittington, supra note 5, at 608.
  • 155
    • 79955401101 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McConnell, supra note 68, at 1280
    • McConnell, supra note 68, at 1280.
  • 156
    • 79955438800 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BORK, supra note 28, at 149
    • 76. BORK, supra note 28, at 149 (arguing that the correct level of generality is the level that "the text and historical evidence warrant"). On this view, the Constitution provides only a "major premise"-that is, a "principle or stated value that the ratifiers wanted to protect"-against which the interpreter must judge the challenged action.
  • 157
    • 79955434608 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 162-63
    • Id. at 162-63.
  • 158
    • 0038082810 scopus 로고
    • 347 U.S. 483
    • Bork famously followed this form of reasoning in attempting to defend Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U.S. 483 (1954), on originalist grounds.
    • (1954) Brown V. Board of Education
  • 159
    • 79955451649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BORK, supra note 28, at 82
    • See BORK, supra note 28, at 82 ("[E]quality and segregation were mutually inconsistent, though the ratifiers did not understand that....The purpose that brought the fourteenth amendment into being was equality...."). In practice, however, Bork has tended to vary the level of generality at which he seeks the original meaning without any explanation about why some provisions should be interpreted at a high level of generality and others should be interpreted at a high level of specificity. For example, he has criticized Griswold and Roe on the ground that contraception is not "covered specifically or by obvious implication by any provision of the Constitution,"
  • 160
    • 79955412981 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 258
    • id. at 258, and "the right to abort, whatever one thinks of it, is not to be found in the Constitution," id. at 112. But though he has never explained why, he reads the Free Speech Clause and the Equal Protection Clause at much higher levels of abstraction.
  • 161
    • 79955421261 scopus 로고
    • 750 F.2d 970,996 D.C. Cir.
    • See Oilman v. Evans, 750 F.2d 970,996 (D.C. Cir. 1984) (en banc) (Bork, J., concurring) ("[The Framers] gave into our keeping the value of preserving free expression and, in particular, the preservation of political expression, which is commonly conceded to be the value at the core of those clauses. Perhaps the framers did not envision libel actions as a major threat to that freedom....But if, over time, the libel action becomes a threat to the central meaning of the first amendment, why should not judges adapt their doctrines?");
    • (1984) Oilman V. Evans
  • 162
    • 79955407902 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BORK, supra note 28, at 82 (Equal Protection Clause)
    • BORK, supra note 28, at 82 (Equal Protection Clause);
  • 163
    • 79955445331 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Harrison, supra note 42, at 479-80
    • Harrison, supra note 42, at 479-80 (noting that Bork's Oilman opinion employs a sort of a "purposivism," originalism that "tak[es] as normative the original purpose" of the First Amendment);
  • 164
    • 77954707040 scopus 로고
    • Originalism without foundations
    • 1373, 1381-82
    • David AJ. Richards, Originalism Without Foundations, 65 N.Y.U. L. REV. 1373, 1381-82 (1990)
    • (1990) N.Y.U. L. Rev. , vol.65
    • Richards, D.A.J.1
  • 165
    • 0003844945 scopus 로고
    • ROBERT BORK
    • (reviewing ROBERT BORK, THE TEMPTING OF AMERICA: THE POLITICAL SEDUCTION OF THE LAW (1990)) (arguing that Bork's high-level-of-generality analysis of Brown is inconsistent with the originalist methodology that he advocates for other questions);
    • (1990) The Tempting of America: The Political Seduction of the Law
  • 166
    • 0040067305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Affirmative action
    • 432 n.25
    • see also Jed Rubenfeld, Affirmative Action, 107 YALE L.J. 427, 432 n.25 (1997) (arguing the same).
    • (1997) Yale L.J. , vol.107 , pp. 427
    • Rubenfeld, J.1
  • 167
    • 79955400631 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reply, originalism and the (merely) human constitution
    • forthcoming
    • Steven D. Smith, Reply, Originalism and the (Merely) Human Constitution, 27 CONST. COMMENT, (forthcoming 2011) (manuscript at 196) (on file with the Hastings Law Journal);
    • (2011) Const. Comment , vol.27 , pp. 196
    • Smith, S.D.1
  • 168
    • 79955367674 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balkin, supra note 49, at 295
    • see also Balkin, supra note 49, at 295 ("Fidelity to the Constitution as law means fidelity to the words of the text, understood in terms of their original meaning, and to the principles that underlie the text.").
  • 169
    • 79955416183 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, supra note 77
    • Smith, supra note 77.
  • 170
    • 79955447335 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WHITTINGTON, supra note 10, at xi
    • See WHITTINGTON, supra note 10, at xi ("I develop an explanation and defense of a theory of constitutional interpretation by the judiciary.");
  • 171
    • 79955391424 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Solum, supra note 41, at 2
    • Solum, supra note 41, at 2 ("This Article offers a theory of constitutional meaning that [] provides a theoretical foundation for original public meaning originalism.").
  • 172
    • 79955420245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Solum, supra note 55
    • To be sure, Solum has used real cases to give context for the application of his theory, see, e.g., Solum, supra note 55, but his interest appears to be mostly theoretical.
  • 173
    • 79955457561 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BARNETT, supra note 55
    • See BARNETT, supra note 55, at 118-21 (level of generality), 121-30 (construction), 355 (libertarianism).
  • 174
    • 79955437199 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 410 U.S. 113(1973)
    • 410 U.S. 113(1973).
  • 175
    • 79955373313 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balkin, supra note 49, at 311-52
    • Balkin, supra note 49, at 311-52.
  • 176
    • 79955367176 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Barnett, supra note 68, at 620-22
    • Barnett appears to have coined the term "new originalism," Barnett, supra note 68, at 620-22;
  • 177
    • 79955417281 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Colby, supra note 30, at 1 n.2
    • Colby, supra note 30, at 1 n.2, and clearly identifies as a new originalist,
  • 178
    • 77954747658 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Underlying principles
    • 405
    • see Randy E. Barnett, Underlying Principles, 24 CONST. COMMENT. 405,405-09 (2007) (describing his embrace of this form of original-meaning originalism). Balkin has tended to eschew the term, but his focus on the original semantic meaning of the text,
    • (2007) Const. Comment. , vol.24 , pp. 405-409
    • Barnett, R.E.1
  • 179
    • 79955371261 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 53
    • see Balkin, Framework Originalism, supra note 53, at 552, places him squarely in the new originalist tent.
    • Framework Originalism , pp. 552
    • Balkin1
  • 180
    • 79955444441 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Barnett, supra, at 410-11
    • See Barnett, supra, at 410-11.
  • 181
    • 79955436722 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balkin, supra note 49, at 293
    • Balkin has been quite aware of this implication of his work. He has argued that the "choice between original meaning and living constitutionalism... is a false choice," Balkin, supra note 49, at 293, and that the project of living constitutionalism (a synonym for non-originalism) is essentially a project of construction and thus entirely consistent with a commitment to the original meaning.
  • 182
    • 79955430633 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balkin, supra note 53, at 559-60
    • Balkin, supra note 53, at 559-60.
  • 183
    • 79955455136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Barnett, supra note 68
    • Barnett similarly originally described his version of originalism as an "originalism for nonoriginalists." Barnett, supra note 68;
  • 184
    • 79955399052 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Solum, supra note 41, at 164-67
    • see also Solum, supra note 41, at 164-67 (discussing the relationship between living constitutionalism and originalism).
  • 185
    • 79955395547 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Colby & Smith, supra note 6, at 244-45
    • See Colby & Smith, supra note 6, at 244-45.
  • 186
    • 34250175164 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A pragmatic defense of originalism
    • 391 n.36
    • See, e.g., John O. McGinnis & Michael B. Rappaport, A Pragmatic Defense of Originalism, 101 Nw. U. L. REV. 383, 391 n.36 (2007) ("[J]udges of various ideologies cannot be expected to reach agreement on any alternative method.");
    • (2007) Nw. U. L. Rev. , vol.101 , pp. 383
    • McGinnis, J.O.1    Rappaport, M.B.2
  • 187
    • 79955423298 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scalia, supra note 35, at 45
    • Scalia, supra note 35, at 45 ("[Non-originalists] divide into as many camps as there are individual views of the good, the true, and the beautiful.");
  • 188
    • 79955446850 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scalia, supra note 24, at 855
    • Scalia, supra note 24, at 855 ("[I]t is not very helpful to tell a judge to be a 'non-originalist,' [because non-originalism] represents agreement on nothing except what is the wrong approach.").
  • 189
    • 79955374879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Berman, supra note 49, at 24
    • Berman, supra note 49, at 24
  • 190
    • 84925075968 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ; see also DENNIS J. GOLDFORD, THE AMERICAN CONSTITUTION AND THE DEBATE OVER ORIGINALISM 139 (2005) ("The characteristic and controversial move of originalism... [is] that the original understanding of the constitutional text always trumps any contrary understanding of that text in succeeding generations.").
    • (2005) The American Constitution and the Debate over Originalism , pp. 139
    • Goldford, D.J.1
  • 191
    • 79955366651 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g.. SOURCEBOOK, supra note 31, 7
    • See, e.g.. SOURCEBOOK, supra note 31, at 7 ("[A]II [non-originalists] reject original meaning as relevant to constitutional interpretation....").
  • 192
    • 79955410476 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Powell, supra note 29
    • See Powell, supra note 29.
  • 193
    • 79955389864 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Berman, supra note 49, at 24-25
    • See, e.g., Berman, supra note 49, at 24-25 ("Not a single self-identifying non-originalist of whom I'm aware argues that original meaning has no bearing on proper judicial constitutional interpretation. To the contrary, even those scholars most closely identified with non-originalism... explicitly assign original meaning or intentions a significant role in the interpretive enterprise.");
  • 194
    • 0346044955 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The political function of originalist ambiguity
    • 487
    • Richard H. Fallon, Jr., The Political Function of Originalist Ambiguity, 19 HARV. J.L. A PUB. POL'Y 487, 488 (1996) ("[M]ost views-my own included-assume that original understanding and purposes are relevant to constitutional interpretation. Differences emerge only over how, and how weightily, these considerations enter the interpretive matrix.");
    • (1996) Harv. J.L. A Pub. Pol'y , vol.19 , pp. 488
    • Fallon Jr., R.H.1
  • 195
    • 79955399051 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Farber, supra note 37, at 1086
    • Farber, supra note 37, at 1086 ("Almost no one believes that the original understanding is wholly irrelevant to modern-day constitutional interpretation.");
  • 196
    • 0347419824 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Common law constitutional interpretation
    • 877
    • David A. Strauss, Common Law Constitutional Interpretation, 63 U. CHI. L. REV. 877, 880-81 (1996) (noting that "[virtually everyone agrees" that text and original meaning matter in constitutional interpretation).
    • (1996) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.63 , pp. 880-881
    • Strauss, D.A.1
  • 197
    • 79955368177 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U.S. CONST, art. II, §1, cl. 5
    • See U.S. CONST, art. II, §1, cl. 5 ("[N]either shall any person be eligible to that Office who shall not have attained to the Age of thirty five Years....");
  • 198
    • 79955391423 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balkin, supra note 49, at 305
    • see also Balkin, supra note 49, at 305 (offering this example);
  • 199
    • 79955374346 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Barnett, supra note 53
    • Barnett, Trumping Precedent, supra note 53, at 263 (same);
    • Trumping Precedent , pp. 263
  • 200
    • 60349119605 scopus 로고
    • Adherence to the original intentions in constitutional adjudication: Three objections and responses
    • Richard Kay, Adherence to the Original Intentions in Constitutional Adjudication: Three Objections and Responses, Nw. U. L. REV. 226, 263 (1988) (same).
    • (1988) Nw. U. L. Rev. , vol.226 , pp. 263
    • Kay, R.1
  • 201
    • 79955368702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U.S. CONST, art. IV, §4
    • U.S. CONST, art. IV, §4 ("The United States shall guarantee to every State in this Union a Republican Form of Government....").
  • 203
    • 84919548693 scopus 로고
    • A constructivist coherence theory of constitutional interpretation
    • 1189
    • see Richard H. Fallon, Jr., A Constructivist Coherence Theory of Constitutional Interpretation, 100 HARV. L. REV. 1189, 1189-90 (1987).
    • (1987) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.100 , pp. 1189-1190
    • Fallon Jr., R.H.1
  • 204
    • 67650804513 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The balkanization of originalism
    • 10
    • As noted above, Balkin has recognized this implication of his work. See supra note 84. Others have observed in passing that new new originalism tends to collapse the distinction between originalism and non-originalism. See James E. Fleming, The Balkanization of Originalism, 67 MD. L. REV. 10, 10-11 (2007) ("[Balkin's originalism] is for all intents and purposes equivalent to Dworkin's moral reading [of the Constitution].");
    • (2007) Md. L. Rev. , vol.67 , pp. 10-11
    • Fleming, J.E.1
  • 205
    • 70349840610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The second amendment, heller, and originalist jurisprudence
    • 1343
    • Nelson Lund, The Second Amendment, Heller, and Originalist Jurisprudence, 56 UCLA L. REV. 1343, 1371 (2009) ("An interpretive approach that can so readily produce such diametrically opposite results dissolves the distinction between originalism and living constitutionalism.");
    • (2009) Ucla L. Rev. , vol.56 , pp. 1371
    • Lund, N.1
  • 206
    • 79955440862 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, supra note 77
    • Smith, supra note 77 ("[On the Balkin view,] [t]he difference between originalism and 'living Constitutionalism' has vanished...."). Solum anticipated these developments years ago, during the early days of original-meaning originalism, when he argued that there is "no meaningful distinction between originalist and nonoriginalist theories of constitutional interpretation."
  • 207
    • 0345959157 scopus 로고
    • Originalism as transformative politics
    • 1599
    • Lawrence B. Solum, Originalism as Transformative Politics, 63 TUL. L. REV. 1599, 1603 (1989). Solum recognized that non-originalist theories still inevitably pay substantial attention to the original meaning, and that any plausible originalist theory, including one that seeks the original meaning at the level of "general principle,"
    • (1989) Tul. L. Rev. , vol.63 , pp. 1603
    • Solum, L.B.1
  • 208
    • 79955425979 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 1612
    • id. at 1612, in practice, will be forced to use non-originalist tools to decide cases. Id. at 1621-22;
  • 209
    • 79955378495 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Solum, supra note 41, at 166-67
    • accord Solum, supra note 41, at 166-67 (discussing the "compatabilist account" of the relationship between living constitutionalism and originalism);
  • 210
    • 79955367175 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fallon, supra note 90, at 488
    • cf. Fallon, supra note 90, at 488 ("[His version of non-originalism] stands as a stark alternative to some versions of originalism, but is rather close to several others that have claimed the designation.").
  • 211
    • 79955366103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Farber, supra note 37, at 1087
    • See Farber, supra note 37, at 1087 ("[Originalists] who focus on the framers' general principles ... may be difficult to distinguish from non-originalists...." (footnote omitted));
  • 212
    • 79955414663 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A century lost: The end of the originalism debate
    • 411
    • see also Eric J. Segall, A Century Lost: The End of the Originalism Debate, 15 CONST. COMMENT. 411, 432-33 (1998) ("This move from specific intentions to general principles... eliminates any meaningful distinction between originalism and nonoriginalism because the Constitution's broad phrases are defined at a level of generality that makes them useless in hard cases for anything other than symbolic purposes.").
    • (1998) Const. Comment. , vol.15 , pp. 432-433
    • Segall, E.J.1
  • 213
    • 79955405827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balkin, supra note 67, at 483-85, 511
    • See supra note 64 and accompanying text; see also Balkin, supra note 67, at 483-85, 511 (referring to Bobbitt's modalities);
  • 214
    • 79955419292 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (last modified May 16, 2010)
    • Lawrence Solum, Legal Theory Lexicon 063: Interpretation and Construction, LEGAL THEORY BLOG, http://lsolum.typepad.com/legal-theory-lexicon/ 2008/04/legal-theoryle.html (last modified May 16, 2010) ("[T]he interpretation-construction distinction opens the door for a partial reconciliation of originalism with living constitutionalism: the Constitution can live in the 'construction zone' where the linguistic meaning of the Constitution underdetermines results.").
    • Legal Theory Lexicon 063: Interpretation and Construction
    • Solum, L.1
  • 215
    • 79955377990 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra notes 58-64 and accompanying text
    • See supra notes 58-64 and accompanying text.
  • 216
    • 79955385724 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Berman, supra note 49, at 66
    • Berman, supra note 49, at 66.
  • 217
    • 79955429002 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leib, supra note 45, at 359-60
    • See Leib, supra note 45, at 359-60. It is also possible for a focus on the principles underlying the text to lead to conclusions that are inconsistent with the text itself, an approach that arguably is inconsistent with new new originalism as well.
  • 218
    • 79955387205 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Barnett, supra note 83, at 413-14
    • See Barnett, supra note 83, at 413-14.
  • 219
    • 79955413516 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leib, supra note 45, at 356-61
    • See Leib, supra note 45, at 356-61 (arguing that even Balkin's originalism is fundamentally different from living constitutionalism, because it places dispositive weight on history in some cases);
  • 221
    • 79955446849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Colby, supra note 30, at 46-47
    • 101. See Colby, supra note 30, at 46-47 (arguing that non-originalists generally invoke the Constitution's underlying principles in order to "give the indeterminate text a meaning (or if you prefer, construction) that is suitable for modern circumstances"). It is perhaps more useful to conceive of approaches to constitutional interpretation as falling along a spectrum based on the weight accorded to the original meaning. Mitchell Berman, for example, has noted that non-originalism is "modest," and generally "does not hold that original meaning, when discoverable, should be irrelevant to judicial interpretation, or even that its relevance should be slight."
  • 222
    • 79955424884 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Berman, supra note 49, at 24
    • Berman, supra note 49, at 24.
  • 223
    • 79955441441 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 10-12
    • Similarly, he notes that originalists vary in the strength of their claims about the role of original meaning in interpretation. See id. at 10-12. He concludes that what distinguishes Originalism (with a capital O) from non-originalism is the "thesis that original meaning either is the only proper target of judicial constitutional interpretation or that it has at least lexical priority over any other candidate meanings that the text might bear," and that "nothing that transpires after ratification of a particular constitutional provision, save a subsequent constitutional amendment, has operative (as opposed to evidential) bearing on what courts ought to identify as constitutional meaning."
  • 224
    • 79955402837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 22
    • Id. at 22. As Berman acknowledges, however, one can be a "strong" originalist and still conclude that some constitutional provisions were "originally understood at a level of generality too high to permit effective resolution of disputes.
  • 225
    • 79955454153 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 30
    • " Id. at 30. It is with these originalists that I am concerned here. And to the extent that some of those originalists believe that there is a nontrivial number of constitutional provisions whose original meaning was objectively expressed at a high level of generality, their approach to interpretation tends to shrink the gap between originalism and non-originalism that Berman so astutely describes.
  • 226
    • 79955370226 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fallon, supra note 90, at 491
    • See Fallon, supra note 90, at 491 ("In its moderate versions, originalism appears to differ from its competitors mostly as a matter of degree....").
  • 227
    • 79955381015 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra notes 18-20 and accompanying text
    • See supra notes 18-20 and accompanying text.
  • 229
    • 79955460604 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Calabresi & Fine, supra note 68, at 669
    • Calabresi & Fine, supra note 68, at 669 ("What judges must be faithful to is the enacted law, not the expectations of the parties who wrote the law.").
  • 230
    • 79955399554 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 672-73
    • Id. at 672-73.
  • 231
    • 79955447334 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 698
    • Id. at 698.
  • 232
    • 79955430113 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 692-98
    • Id. at 692-98. Gregory Bassham has made a similar claim about the Due Process Clause of the Fifth Amendment. In his view, although the language "may be abstract," its original meaning "was as fixed and definite as the common law could make a phrase."
  • 233
    • 79955385197 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BASSHAM, supra note 104, at 73-74
    • BASSHAM, supra note 104, at 73-74
  • 235
    • 79955445833 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paulsen, supra note 47, at 2046-48
    • 109. See Paulsen, supra note 47, at 2046-48 (rejecting the view that the Ninth Amendment might protect particular unenumerated rights, and arguing that the "proper" textualist meaning of the Amendment is that the specification of rights in the Constitution did not "work a pro tanto repeal of state law rights possessed against state governments"). In addition, Justice Scalia has suggested that the Equal Protection Clause speaks with the requisite specificity to overcome the objection that Brown was wrong because segregation was accepted at the time of the ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment. In Rutan v. Republican Party of Illinois, he argued that "when a practice not expressly prohibited by the text of the Bill of Rights bears the endorsement of a long tradition of open, widespread, and unchallenged use that dates back to the beginning of the Republic, we have no proper basis for striking it down." 497 U.S. 62, 95 (1990) (Scalia, J., dissenting). He then responded to Justice Stevens's charge that such an approach would have mandated the conclusion that segregation does not violate the Equal Protection Clause by arguing that Brown v. Board of Education does not demonstrate "the dangerous consequences of this principle," because tradition has a role "in giving content only to ambiguous constitutional text."
  • 236
    • 79955433149 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rutan, 497 U.S. at 95, n.1 (citing 347 U.S. 483 (1954))
    • Rutan, 497 U.S. at 95, n.1 (citing 347 U.S. 483 (1954)). In his view, the Equal Protection Clause and "the Thirteenth Amendment's abolition of the institution of black slavery [left] no room for doubt that laws treating people differently because of their race"-and in particular laws segregating on the basis of race-"are invalid."
  • 237
    • 79955411407 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 238
    • 79955448436 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BASSHAM, supra note 104, at 74
    • See BASSHAM, supra note 104, at 74 (arguing that the Free Speech Clause contains a "clear and reasonably determinate standard").
  • 239
    • 79955459128 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paulsen, supra note 47, at 2056
    • See Paulsen, supra note 47, at 2056 ("[The rules of originalism] do not answer all questions, but they answer a lot of them."); Scalia, supra note 35, at 45 ("Often-indeed, I dare say usuaUy-[the original meaning of the text] is easy to discern and simple to apply.").
  • 240
    • 79955401100 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scalia, supra note 35, at 45
    • Justice Scalia has tempered this claim by acknowledging that "[s]ometimes (though not very often) there will be disagreement regarding the original meaning; and sometimes there will be disagreement as to how that original meaning applies to new and unforeseen phenomena." Scalia, supra note 35, at 45;
  • 241
    • 79955436721 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scalia, supra note 24, at 856
    • see also Scalia, supra note 24, at 856 ("[Originalism's] greatest defect... is the difficulty of applying it correctly.... [I]t is often exceedingly difficult to plumb the original understanding of an ancient text.").
  • 242
    • 79955388740 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SOURCEBOOK, supra note 31, at 28
    • But Justice Scalia and others expect these instances to be "exceedingly rare." SOURCEBOOK, supra note 31, at 28.
  • 243
    • 79955397058 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scalia, supra note 35, at 46
    • As Justice Scalia has stated, the "originalist, if he does not have all the answers, has many of them." Scalia, supra note 35, at 46;
  • 244
    • 79955432676 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kay, supra note 91, at 258
    • see also Kay, supra note 91, at 258 ("The good faith application of original intentions will resolve many cases in ways which are relatively free from doubt.").
  • 245
    • 79955417280 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BORK, supra note 28, at 144
    • Although Bork began as an old originalist, see Boric, supra note 22, at 826 (urging fidelity to the original intentions), he eventually appears to have embraced many of the tenets of the new originalism, a shift that he described as simply a clarification of his earlier work, see BORK, supra note 28, at 144.
  • 246
    • 79955406351 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id
    • He rejected the quest for original intent and instead urged a focus on the objective original understanding, id.,
  • 247
    • 79955387204 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 150
    • and he argued that an originalist should seek the original meaning at "the level of generality that interpretation of the words, structure, and history of the Constitution fairly supports." Id. at 150;
  • 248
    • 79955423830 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 76
    • see also supra note 76 and accompanying text. Notwithstanding his arguments about the level of generality, however, Bork apparently concluded that certain provisions of the Constitution were so abstract (and thus obscure) that judges should simply decline to enforce them.
  • 249
    • 79955364586 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BORK, supra note 28, at 166.
    • BORK, supra note 28, at 166.
  • 250
    • 79955440329 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kesavan & Paulsen, supra note 5, at 1127, 1134-48
    • See Kesavan & Paulsen, supra note 5, at 1127, 1134-48 (defending "original public meaning textualism" and describing its place in the evolution of originalism);
  • 251
    • 79955418791 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 1139
    • id. at 1139 (using the term "new originalism" to describe "original meaning textualism").
  • 252
    • 68149124923 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Does the constitution prescribe rules for its own construction?
    • 881
    • Michael Stokes Paulsen, Does the Constitution Prescribe Rules for Its Own Construction?, 103 Nw. U. L. REV. 857, 881 (2009).
    • (2009) Nw. U. L. Rev. , vol.103 , pp. 857
    • Paulsen, M.S.1
  • 253
    • 50949108484 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A government of adequate powers
    • 995
    • Michael Stokes Paulsen, A Government of Adequate Powers, 31 HARV. J.L. A PUB. POL'Y 991, 995 (2008).
    • (2008) Harv. J.L. A Pub. Pol'y , vol.31 , pp. 991
    • Paulsen, M.S.1
  • 254
    • 79955392407 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paulsen, supra note 47, at 2057
    • Paulsen, supra note 47, at 2057;
  • 255
    • 79955430112 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • accord Paulsen, supra note 115, at 881
    • accord Paulsen, supra note 115, at 881 ("[T]he Constitution's text itself suggests, as a practical matter, a default rule of interpretation where the constitutional text is unspecific: popular republican self-government. ");
  • 256
    • 0042059531 scopus 로고
    • Constitutional interpretation
    • 633
    • see abo Lino A. Graglia, Constitutional Interpretation, 44 SYRACUSE L. REV. 631, 633 (1993) ("The absence of a clear constitutional basis for invalidation of a political choice should mean that the choice is not invalid-");
    • (1993) Syracuse L. Rev. , vol.44 , pp. 631
    • Graglia, L.A.1
  • 257
    • 0348243792 scopus 로고
    • On reading the constitution
    • 361
    • Michael W. McConnell, On Reading the Constitution, 73 CORNELL L. REV. 359, 361 (1987) ("If the judge... concludes that he cannot tell whether a challenged governmental action is forbidden by the Constitution, then he is free to leave the determination of the legal rule to the elected authorities.").
    • (1987) Cornell L. Rev. , vol.73 , pp. 359
    • McConnell, M.W.1
  • 258
    • 70349692613 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The intrinsically corrupting influence of precedent
    • 296
    • 118. Michael Stokes Paulsen, The Intrinsically Corrupting Influence of Precedent, 22 CONST. COMMENT. 289, 296 n.18 (2005);
    • (2005) Const. Comment. , vol.22 , Issue.18 , pp. 289
    • Paulsen, M.S.1
  • 259
    • 79955380497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kesavan & Paulsen, supra note 5, at 1129-30 n.54
    • accord Kesavan & Paulsen, supra note 5, at 1129-30 n.54 ("[W]here there is a range of equally legitimate interpretations, and the political branches have chosen one of them, there is no basis for the courts to invalidate the political branches' choice.");
  • 260
    • 79955402307 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paulsen, supra note 116, at 995
    • Paulsen, supra note 116, at 995 ("[T]he more indeterminate or under-determinate the range of a constitutional provision, the broader the duty of the courts to defer to what the legislature has enacted.");
  • 261
    • 79955448435 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paulsen, supra note 115, at 882
    • Paulsen, supra note 115, at 882 ("Unspecific texts do not warrant abstracting more specific principles. The Constitution's structure suggests the opposite rule: Unspecific texts, to the extent of their un-specificity, permit a range of legitimate interpretation and application by political decisionmakers.").
  • 262
    • 79955438168 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paulsen, supra note 115, at 881-82
    • Paulsen bases this "rule against abstraction" on the fact that the Constitution is written and specifically identifies "this Constitution" as supreme law. Paulsen, supra note 115, at 881-82.
  • 263
    • 79955426416 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lund, supra note 94, at 1372
    • Nelson Lund similarly has recognized that the constitutional text often does not resolve concrete questions, and that in such cases, there is no "algorithm" for deciding the question. Lund, supra note 94, at 1372.
  • 264
    • 79955416182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Unlike Paulsen and Bork, however, Lund argues that "a conscientiously originalist court has no choice but to decide the issue in light of the purpose of the provision as that purpose was understood by those who adopted it." Id.
  • 265
    • 79955421260 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1371
    • Lund has nevertheless criticized Balkin's new new originalism, because a "moderately clever and determined practitioner of such 'originalism' should be able to get just about any result that a living constitutionalist might desire." Id. at 1371.
  • 266
    • 79955380496 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paulsen, supra note 116, at 995
    • Paulsen, supra note 116, at 995.
  • 267
    • 79955374345 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kay, supra note 40, at 723-24
    • Kay, supra note 40, at 723-24 (discussing Balkin's work).
  • 268
    • 79955398119 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 721
    • Id. at 721.
  • 269
    • 79955418790 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 725
    • See id. at 725 ("[R]elying on an artificial concept instead of on an actual historical event inevitably enlarges the field of such imaginative reconstructions.").
  • 270
    • 79955404334 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 721
    • Id. at 721 ("The discovery of indeterminacies in otherwise originalist interpretation has been the 'little gap' through which a broad range of judicial choice has been perceived.");
  • 271
    • 79955453117 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 721 n.76
    • id. at 721 n.76 ("The absence of determinate meaning has been explicitly linked to the practice of 'constitutional construction' whereby interpreters are obliged to extend the binding force of the Constitution beyond its linguistic meaning.").
  • 272
    • 79955405298 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, supra note 40, at 1
    • Smith, supra note 40, at 1.
  • 273
    • 79955387700 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, supra note 77
    • Smith, supra note 77.
  • 274
    • 79955431141 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 189
    • See id. at 189 ("[Jack Balkin] has advocated... an approach which, by interpreting the Constitution's original meaning to embrace a set of open-ended principles, is able to justify pretty much any results that the most ardently progressive constitutional heart could desire.").
  • 275
    • 79955390888 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 198
    • Smith instead suggests an approach that would limit constitutional meaning to "what the human beings who enacted the provision thought it meant," id. at 198, which is quite similar (even if not necessarily identical) to the original-expected-applications approach that most new originalists have rejected.
  • 276
    • 79955368176 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note
    • See supra note
  • 277
    • 79955447333 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McGinnis & Rappaport, supra note 51, at 751
    • McGinnis and Rappaport have promoted "original methods
  • 278
    • 79955413515 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 752, 758-65
    • This approach mediates between original-intent originalism and original-meaning originalism, see id. at 752, 758-65,
  • 279
    • 79955439320 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 755
    • and rests for its normative justification in large part on the fact that the Constitution is the product of a "strict supermajoritarian process." Id. at 755;
  • 280
    • 79955444823 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McGinnis & Rappaport, supra note 86, at 384-91
    • see also McGinnis & Rappaport, supra note 86, at 384-91.
  • 281
    • 79955406903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McGinnis & Rappaport, supra note 51, at 773
    • McGinnis & Rappaport, supra note 51, at 773 ("[A]dvocates of construction have not provided evidence that anyone embraced construction at the time of the Constitution's enactment, and we have been able to find none. To the contrary, the evidence that we have found suggests that interpreters believed that ambiguity and vagueness could be resolved through the applicable interpretive rules, and thus through originalist methods.").
  • 282
    • 79955448434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 784
    • Id. at 784;
  • 283
    • 79955426415 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 783
    • see also id. at 783 ("Because there is no legally required or even accepted method for determining how to resolve questions of construction, judges are likely to determine how to engage in construction based on their own views.").
  • 284
    • 79955393443 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Colby & Smith, supra note 6, at 258
    • See Colby & Smith, supra note 6, at 258.
  • 285
    • 79955442975 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 248-55
    • See id. at 248-55.
  • 286
    • 79955387203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kesavan & Paulsen, supra note 5, at 1145-48
    • See Kesavan & Paulsen, supra note 5, at 1145-48.
  • 287
    • 79955367673 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Colby & Smith, supra note 6, at 260-62
    • See Colby & Smith, supra note 6, at 260-62.
  • 288
    • 0347575726 scopus 로고
    • Some reflections on interpretivism
    • 6-8
    • See, e.g., Raoul Berger, Some Reflections on Interpretivism, 55 GEO. WASH. L. REV. 1, 6-8 (1986) ("I would caution against judicial choices of levels of generality. Ascending the ladder of generality obliterates those limits [on judicial power].");
    • (1986) Geo. Wash. L. Rev. , vol.55 , pp. 1
    • Berger, R.1
  • 289
    • 79955450481 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 10-11
    • id. at 10-11 ("Frequently there will be cases where general language is not illuminated by legislative history, where the evidence of original intention is ambiguous, looks both ways, or is altogether lacking. There the judge must, as Justice Holmes observed, legislate 'interstitially,' or as Cardozo put it, fill 'the open spaces in the law.'" (footnotes omitted)
  • 290
    • 77950632940 scopus 로고
    • 244 U.S. 205, 221
    • (quoting S. Pac. Co. v. Jensen, 244 U.S. 205, 221 (1917);
    • (1917) S. Pac. Co. V. Jensen
  • 292
    • 79955391422 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BERGER, supra note 21, at 99-116
    • see also BERGER, supra note 21, at 99-116 (criticizing the "'open-ended' phraseology theory" of interpretation); Kay, supra note 91, at 264 (discussing the relationship between the level of generality of the constitutional text and original intentions).
  • 293
    • 79955434607 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bork, supra note 21, at 2, 8
    • Bork, supra note 21, at 2, 8;
  • 294
    • 79955382611 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Maltz, supra note 15, at 789
    • see also Maltz, supra note 15, at 789 ("[U]nlike nonoriginalist theories, at its core originalism does not depend on extralegal, nonneutral justifications. Instead, it is premised on internal legal conventions developed without regard to some specific political agenda unrelated to the nature of judging itself.");
  • 295
    • 0346044966 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The integrity and impersonality of originalism
    • 286
    • cf. Lillian R. Be Vier, The Integrity and Impersonality of Originalism, 19 HARV. J.L. A PUB. POL'Y 283, 286 (1996) ("Integrity characterizes a judicial process based on originalism, [whereas] its lack is one of the chief deficiencies of its alternatives.").
    • (1996) Harv. J.L. A Pub. Pol'y , vol.19 , pp. 283
    • Be Vier, L.R.1
  • 296
    • 77954733636 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A progressive alternative to textualism and originalism?
    • 2415 [hereinafter McConnell, derive Liberty]
    • Michael W. McConnell, Active Liberty: A Progressive Alternative to Textualism and Originalism?, 119 HARV. L. REV. 2387, 2415 (2006) [hereinafter McConnell, derive Liberty]
    • (2006) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.119 , pp. 2387
    • McConnell, M.W.1    Liberty, A.2
  • 298
    • 84929064717 scopus 로고
    • The role of democratic politics in transforming moral convictions into law
    • 1525 [hereinafter McConnell, Role of Democratic Politics]
    • Michael W. McConnell, The Role of Democratic Politics in Transforming Moral Convictions into Law, 98 YALE LJ. 1501, 1525 (1989) [hereinafter McConnell, Role of Democratic Politics]
    • (1989) Yale LJ. , vol.98 , pp. 1501
    • McConnell, M.W.1
  • 299
    • 0347979147 scopus 로고
    • (reviewing MICHAEL J. PERRY, MORALITY, POLITICS AND LAW (1988)) ("The appeal of originalism is that the moral principles so applied will be the foundational principles of the American Republic... and not the political-moral principles of whomever happens to occupy the judicial office.");
    • (1988) MORALITY, POLITICS and LAW
    • Perry, M.J.1
  • 300
    • 79551507752 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why originalism won't die-common mistakes in competing theories of judicial interpretation
    • 161
    • see also Tara Smith, Why Originalism Won't Die-Common Mistakes in Competing Theories of Judicial Interpretation, 2 DUKE J. CONST. L. A PUB. POL'Y 159, 161 (2007) ("The deeper reason that Originalism will not die, I think, is that it has staked out the moral high ground, championing the objectivity of interpretation that is essential to the ideal of the rule of law.").
    • (2007) Duke J. Const. L. A Pub. Pol'y , vol.2 , pp. 159
    • Smith, T.1
  • 301
    • 79955456177 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Maltz, supra note 15, at 794
    • Maltz, supra note 15, at 794.
  • 302
    • 79955430111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bork, supra note 21, at 6
    • See, e.g., Bork, supra note 21, at 6 ("[A] legitimate Court must be controlled by principles exterior to the will of the Justices.");
  • 303
    • 79955413514 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scalia, supra note 24, at 863-64
    • Scalia, supra note 24, at 863-64 (arguing that originalism limits the likelihood that "judges will mistake their own predilections for the law," because it relies on historical facts outside of any judge's particular preferences, whereas non-originalism "plays precisely to this weakness");
  • 304
    • 0038977510 scopus 로고
    • Law without mind
    • 106
    • Steven D. Smith, Law Without Mind, 88 MICH. L. REV. 104, 106 (1989) ("A central concern of originalism is that judges be constrained by the law rather than be left free to act according to their own lights, a course that originalists regard as essentially lawless.").
    • (1989) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.88 , pp. 104
    • Smith, S.D.1
  • 305
    • 79955435104 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BeVier, supra note 135, at 286
    • See, e.g., BeVier, supra note 135, at 286 ("Integrity characterizes a judicial process based on originalism, and its lack is one of the chief deficiencies of its alternatives.");
  • 306
    • 79955457560 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scalia, supra note 24, at 854
    • Scalia, supra note 24, at 854 ("The principal theoretical defect of nonoriginalism... is its incompatibility with the very principle that legitimizes judicial review of constitutionality.");
  • 307
    • 79955423297 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 136
    • McConnell, Active Liberty, supra note 136, at 2387-88 (arguing that originalists "offer a principled justification for the pattern of decisions they favor," but that non-originalists "have yet to propound a comparable theory").
    • Active Liberty , pp. 2387-2388
    • McConnell1
  • 309
    • 0345820934 scopus 로고
    • The constitution and the intentions of the framers: The limits of historical analysis
    • 397
    • Paul Finkelman, The Constitution and the Intentions of the Framers: The Limits of Historical Analysis, 50 U. PITT. L. REV. 349, 397 (1989) (same).
    • (1989) U. Pitt. L. Rev. , vol.50 , pp. 349
    • Finkelman, P.1
  • 310
    • 79955422843 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Berger, supra note 134, at 1
    • Berger, supra note 134, at 1.
  • 311
    • 0040161705 scopus 로고
    • The forum of principle
    • 498
    • See, e.g., Ronald Dworkin, The Forum of Principle, 56 N.Y.U. L. REV. 469, 498 (1981) ("[J]udges cannot discover [the original] intention without building or adopting one conception of constitutional intention rather than another, without, that is, making the decisions of political morality they were meant to avoid.").
    • (1981) N.Y.U. L. Rev. , vol.56 , pp. 469
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 312
    • 78650525993 scopus 로고
    • Construing the constitution
    • 29
    • Edwin Meese III, Construing the Constitution, 19 U.C. DAVIS L. REV. 22, 29 (1985).
    • (1985) U.C. Davis L. Rev. , vol.19 , pp. 22
    • Meese III, E.1
  • 313
    • 79955403852 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fallon, supra note 93, at 1213
    • See, e.g., Fallon, supra note 93, at 1213 ("[Particular interpretations of the framers' group intent... embody implicit or explicit normative judgments.").
  • 314
    • 79955423296 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scalia, supra note 31, at 106
    • Scalia, supra note 31, at 106.
  • 315
    • 79955401744 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fallon, supra note 90, at 492
    • See, e.g., Fallon, supra note 90, at 492 ("[Originalism is] perhaps most often a political or rhetorical stalking horse for a set of substantive positions with respect to a relatively narrow set of constitutional issues in the current age.");
  • 316
    • 33846165790 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Originalism as a political practice: The right's living constitution
    • 561
    • Robert Post & Reva Siegel, Originalism as a Political Practice: The Right's Living Constitution, 75 FORDHAM L. REV. 545, 561 (2006) ("As a political practice that developed in the 1980s, originalism seeks, more or less blatantly, to alter the Constitution so as to infuse it with conservative political principles.").
    • (2006) Fordham L. Rev. , vol.75 , pp. 545
    • Post, R.1    Siegel, R.2
  • 317
    • 0346675678 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Originalism as an "Ism,"
    • 301
    • Jonathan R. Macey, Originalism as an "Ism," 19 HARV. J.L. A PUB. POL'Y 301, 301 (1996) ("[A]mong constitutional law scholars at elite schools, the idea of being an originalist is tantamount to being some sort of intellectual Luddite.");
    • (1996) Harv. J.L. A Pub. Pol'y , vol.19 , pp. 301
    • Macey, J.R.1
  • 318
    • 79955384678 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Maltz, supra note 15, at 773
    • Maltz, supra note 15, at 773.
  • 319
    • 79955439814 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Colby, supra note 30, at 34
    • Colby, supra note 30, at 34.
  • 320
    • 79955457559 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Barnett, supra note 68, at 613
    • Barnett, supra note 68, at 613.
  • 321
    • 79955400630 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Colby, supra note 30, at 41
    • 150. Colby's account, which is devastating, relies in large part on the theoretical refinements described above. But although Colby acknowledges that "[o]n the ground... it is getting harder and harder to tell originalism and nonoriginalism apart," he resists the claim that these refinements have collapsed the distinction between originalism and non-originalism, stressing that "[i]n theory... the New Originalism still differs from its nonoriginalist rivals in important ways in terms of its understanding of constitutional meaning, constitutional legitimacy, and the proper role of the judiciary in our constitutional system." Colby, supra note 30, at 41.
  • 322
    • 79955443949 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 6-7
    • This is surely correct, if one excludes new new originalism from "New Originalism." But Colby treats essentially all of the developments in originalist theory since the days of Berger-including the claims by new originalists such as Lawson and Paulsen and the more capacious claims by Barnett, Balkin, and Solum about levels of generality and construction-as the accepted wisdom of new originalism. See id. at 6-7 (acknowledging that "only a few [originalists] have explicitly embraced all of the "significant theoretical moves" that marked the evolution from the old to the new originalism, but focusing on the "collective[]" effects of these theoretical moves);
  • 323
    • 79955453116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 67
    • id. at 67 (noting that not all originalists have endorsed "the full New Originalist theoretical package").
  • 324
    • 79955398557 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Colby & Smith, supra note 6, at 258
    • He is not necessarily wrong to do so; it is, after all, becoming almost impossible to keep track of all the variations in originalist thought, and in any event, there is "no official gatekeeper" to apply a test for originalist (or new originalist) purity. See Colby & Smith, supra note 6, at 258.
  • 325
    • 65349150496 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Selling originalism
    • 672
    • But as I have explained, new originalism itself is becoming a deeply contested concept, and many (and perhaps most) new originalists have distanced themselves from the broader implications of the new new originalists' claims. See Jamal Greene, Selling Originalism, 97 GEO. L.J. 657, 672 (2009) ("I am not convinced that an originalist 'school' can be identified that has all of [the] characteristics [of the new originalism]-").
    • (2009) Geo. L.J. , vol.97 , pp. 657
    • Greene, J.1
  • 326
    • 79955388739 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra notes 89-101
    • See supra notes 89-101 and accompanying text.
  • 327
    • 79955399553 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Barnett, supra note 83, at 414, 416
    • There is some debate over whether the new new originalists are intentionally trying to be subversive, hoisting new originalists on their own petard and forcing them to acknowledge the logical consequences of their theory. See Barnett, supra note 83, at 414, 416 (predicting that some originalists will charge that Balkin is trying to preserve "an unvarnished living constitutionalism" while claiming the "mantle of originalism" (internal quotation marks omitted));
  • 328
    • 79955410475 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Colby, supra note 30, at 40
    • Colby, supra note 30, at 40 ("One might be tempted to speculate that what is really going on here is not that originalism has fundamentally changed, but rather that several former nonoriginalists have jumped on the originalism bandwagon, and have attempted to co-opt the 'originalist' label for their owned decidedly nonoriginalist purposes.");
  • 329
    • 79955445330 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, supra note 77, at 194-95
    • Smith, supra note 77, at 194-95 (questioning whether Balkin's conversion to originalism is "sincere or... strategic").
  • 330
    • 1842706616 scopus 로고
    • Constitutional interpretation and the problem of history
    • 915
    • It is true that some of the new new originalists did not identify as originalists until recently. See J.M. Balkin, Constitutional Interpretation and the Problem of History, 63 N.Y.U. L. REV. 911, 915 (1988) ("I do not agree with Berger's theory of constitutional interpretation...");
    • (1988) N.Y.U. L. Rev. , vol.63 , pp. 911
    • Balkin, J.M.1
  • 331
    • 79955375401 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Barnett, supra note 83, at 405
    • Barnett, supra note 83, at 405 ("All the time I was doing my earliest writings on the Ninth Amendment and the Second Amendment, I considered myself a nonoriginalist.").
  • 332
    • 79955412450 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith, supra note 77, at 195, 196
    • But precisely because the versions of originalism that they offer are modest and not significantly different than most versions of non-originalism, there is perhaps little reason to doubt the sincerity of their commitments. Smith, supra note 77, at 195, 196.
  • 333
    • 79955450480 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fallon, supra note 90, at 492
    • Several commentators have argued that originalism is more a political movement than an interpretive methodology. See, e.g., Fallon, supra note 90, at 492;
  • 334
    • 79955370225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Greene, supra note 150, at 702
    • Greene, supra note 150, at 702;
  • 335
    • 79955386686 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Post & Siegel, supra note 146, at 561
    • Post & Siegel, supra note 146, at 561.
  • 336
    • 79955449973 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 155- 539 U.S. 558 (2003)
    • 155- 539 U.S. 558 (2003).
  • 337
    • 79955391421 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 410 U.S. 113(1973)
    • 410 U.S. 113(1973).
  • 338
    • 79955367174 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Calabresi & Fine, supra note 68, at 692-98
    • See Calabresi & Fine, supra note 68, at 692-98;
  • 339
    • 46649109946 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Substantive due process after Gonzales v. Carhart
    • 1531-41
    • Steven G. Calabresi, Substantive Due Process After Gonzales v. Carhart, 106 MICH. L. REV. 1517, 1531-41 (2008);
    • (2008) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.106 , pp. 1517
    • Calabresi, S.G.1
  • 340
    • 57649217112 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lawrence, the fourteenth amendment, and the supreme court's reliance on foreign constitutional law: An originalist reappraisal
    • 1107-15
    • Steven G. Calabresi, Lawrence, the Fourteenth Amendment, and the Supreme Court's Reliance on Foreign Constitutional Law: An Originalist Reappraisal, 65 OHIO ST. L.J. 1097, 1107-15 (2004);
    • (2004) Ohio St. L.J. , vol.65 , pp. 1097
    • Calabresi, S.G.1
  • 341
    • 79955384154 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paulsen, supra note 47, at 2047-48
    • cf. Paulsen, supra note 47, at 2047-48 (arguing that the Ninth Amendment is a narrow provision that makes clear that the enumeration of rights running against the federal government does not "work a pro tanto repeal of state law rights possessed against state governments").
  • 342
    • 68249146167 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The fatally flawed theory of the unbundled executive
    • 1704
    • See Steven G. Calabresi & Nicholas Terrell, The Fatally Flawed Theory of the Unbundled Executive, 93 MINN. L. REV. 1696, 1704 n.45 (2009);
    • (2009) Minn. L. Rev. , vol.93 , Issue.45 , pp. 1696
    • Calabresi, S.G.1    Terrell, N.2
  • 343
    • 79955398556 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lawson, supra note 72, at 395
    • see also Lawson, supra note 72, at 395 (arguing that the Necessary and Proper Clause "textually embodies a nondelegation principle").
  • 344
    • 79955421259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paulsen, supra note 116, at 995
    • See Paulsen, supra note 116, at 995;
  • 345
    • 79955433618 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra notes 116-19
    • supra notes 116-19 and accompanying text.
  • 346
    • 78149349862 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 130 S. Ct. 876, 925-29
    • See Citizens United v. FEC, 130 S. Ct. 876, 925-29 (2010) (Scalia, J., concurring) (discussing the original meaning of the First Amendment);
    • (2010) Citizens United V. FEC
    • Scalia, J.1
  • 347
    • 79955442974 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paulsen, supra note 116, at 993 & n.9
    • see also Paulsen, supra note 116, at 993 & n.9
  • 348
    • 70849134440 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 540 U.S. 93
    • (describing McConnell v. FEC, 540 U.S. 93 (2003), as an "atrocit[y]"). To be fair, Paulsen has been unusually willing to follow his approach to open-ended provisions, even when it leads to results that are generally anathema to political conservatives.
    • (2003) McConnell V. FEC
  • 349
    • 79955460603 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 991-95
    • See id. at 991-95 (arguing that the faithful application of his version of original public meaning textualism requires the conclusion that "the powers conferred on the national government are huge, sweeping, overlapping, and, when taken together, very nearly comprehensive").
  • 350
    • 22644435831 scopus 로고
    • The supreme court of the United States: Bulwark of a limited constitution
    • 464
    • Edwin Meese, III, The Supreme Court of the United States: Bulwark of a Limited Constitution, 27 S. TEX. L. REV. 455, 464 (1986).
    • (1986) S. Tex. L. Rev. , vol.27 , pp. 455
    • Meese III, E.1
  • 351
    • 79955383624 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scalia, supra note 35, at 38-39
    • See, e.g., Scalia, supra note 35, at 38-39 (discussing the "Great Divide" in constitutional interpretation between originalists and non-originalists).


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.