메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 84, Issue 1, 2009, Pages 1-96

Originalism is Bunk

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 66449123378     PISSN: 00287881     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (142)

References (414)
  • 1
    • 66449129154 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.Daniel A. Farber, The Originalism Debate: A Guide for the Perplexed, 49 OHIO ST. L.J. 1085 (1989).
    • 1.Daniel A. Farber, The Originalism Debate: A Guide for the Perplexed, 49 OHIO ST. L.J. 1085 (1989).
  • 2
    • 66449136489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1085
    • Id. at 1085.
  • 3
    • 66449126148 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 4
    • 66449135303 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Randy E. Barnett, An Originalism for Nonoriginalists, 45 LOY. L. REV. 611, 613 (1999).
    • Randy E. Barnett, An Originalism for Nonoriginalists, 45 LOY. L. REV. 611, 613 (1999).
  • 5
    • 66449086142 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a sampling of commentators who share this assessment, see Lawrence Rosenthal, Does Due Process Have an Original Meaning? On Originalism, Due Process, Procedural Innovation, and Parking Tickets, 60 OKLA. L. REV. 1, 4 n.13 (2007).
    • For a sampling of commentators who share this assessment, see Lawrence Rosenthal, Does Due Process Have an Original Meaning? On Originalism, Due Process, Procedural Innovation, and Parking Tickets, 60 OKLA. L. REV. 1, 4 n.13 (2007).
  • 6
    • 66449083450 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., ANDREI MARMOR, INTERPRETATION AND LEGAL THEORY 155-56 (2d ed. 2005) (characterizing [t]he widespread attraction of 'originalism' [a]s one of the main puzzles about theories of constitutional interpretation, and declaring it quite a mystery why originalism still has the scholarly (and judicial) support that it does).
    • See, e.g., ANDREI MARMOR, INTERPRETATION AND LEGAL THEORY 155-56 (2d ed. 2005) (characterizing "[t]he widespread attraction of 'originalism' [a]s one of the main puzzles about theories of constitutional interpretation," and declaring it "quite a mystery why originalism still has the scholarly (and judicial) support that it does").
  • 7
    • 66449105716 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., id. at 155 ( '[OJriginalism' is not the title of one particular theory of constitutional interpretation but rather the name of a family of diverse ideas, some of which are actually at odds with each other.);
    • See, e.g., id. at 155 (" '[OJriginalism' is not the title of one particular theory of constitutional interpretation but rather the name of a family of diverse ideas, some of which are actually at odds with each other.");
  • 8
    • 66449108187 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GREGORY BASSHAM, ORIGINAL INTENT AND THE CONSTITUTION: A PHILOSOPHICAL STUDY 36 (1992) ([I]t is difficult to state with precision just what originalism asserts, since commentators have characterized the theory in varying and often inconsistent ways.).
    • GREGORY BASSHAM, ORIGINAL INTENT AND THE CONSTITUTION: A PHILOSOPHICAL STUDY 36 (1992) ("[I]t is difficult to state with precision just what originalism asserts, since commentators have characterized the theory in varying and often inconsistent ways.").
  • 9
    • 66449087554 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the latest edition of his co-authored textbook, Farber's Guide for the Perplexed, see supra note 1, appears largely unchanged.
    • In the latest edition of his co-authored textbook, Farber's Guide for the Perplexed, see supra note 1, appears largely unchanged.
  • 10
    • 66449120421 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See DANIEL A. FARBER SUZANNA SHERRY, A HISTORY OF THE AMERICAN CONSTITUTION ch. 14 (2d ed. 2005).
    • See DANIEL A. FARBER SUZANNA SHERRY, A HISTORY OF THE AMERICAN CONSTITUTION ch. 14 (2d ed. 2005).
  • 11
    • 1842488232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Interpretive Force of the Constitution's Secret Drafting History, 91
    • Vasan Kesavan & Michael Stokes Paulsen, The Interpretive Force of the Constitution's Secret Drafting History, 91 GEO. L.J. 1113, 1139 (2003).
    • (2003) GEO. L.J , vol.1113 , pp. 1139
    • Kesavan, V.1    Stokes Paulsen, M.2
  • 12
    • 66449130569 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aileen Kavanagh, Original Intention, Enacted Text, and Constitutional Interpretation,47 AM. J. JURIS. 255, 257 (2002);
    • Aileen Kavanagh, Original Intention, Enacted Text, and Constitutional Interpretation,47 AM. J. JURIS. 255, 257 (2002);
  • 13
    • 66449115411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also David Couzens Hoy. A Hermeneutical Critique of the Originalism/Nonoriginalism istinction, 15 N. KY. L. REV. 479, 479-80 (1988) (expressing similar view).
    • see also David Couzens Hoy. A Hermeneutical Critique of the Originalism/Nonoriginalism istinction, 15 N. KY. L. REV. 479, 479-80 (1988) (expressing similar view).
  • 14
    • 66449123495 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kavanagh, supra note 9, at 257
    • Kavanagh, supra note 9, at 257.
  • 15
    • 66449136176 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • E.g., id. at 255;
    • E.g., id. at 255;
  • 16
    • 66449116514 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Earl Maltz. Foreword: The Appeal of Originalism, 1987 UTAH L. REV. 773, 773.
    • Earl Maltz. Foreword: The Appeal of Originalism, 1987 UTAH L. REV. 773, 773.
  • 17
    • 66449134391 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Barnett, supra note 4, at 635
    • Barnett, supra note 4, at 635.
  • 18
    • 66449136478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Part III.A.
    • See infra Part III.A.
  • 19
    • 66449112370 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Among the best are BASSHAM, supra note 6;
    • Among the best are BASSHAM, supra note 6;
  • 20
    • 84925075968 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DENNIS J. GOLDFORD, THE AMERICAN CONSTITUTION AND THE DEBATE OVER ORIGINALISM (2005);
    • DENNIS J. GOLDFORD, THE AMERICAN CONSTITUTION AND THE DEBATE OVER ORIGINALISM (2005);
  • 21
    • 84895616967 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JOHNATHAN O'NEILL, ORIGINALISM IN AMERICAN LAW AND POLITICS: A CONSTITUTIONAL HISTORY (2005);
    • JOHNATHAN O'NEILL, ORIGINALISM IN AMERICAN LAW AND POLITICS: A CONSTITUTIONAL HISTORY (2005);
  • 23
    • 66449125201 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a nice overview in addition to Farber, supra note 1
    • For a nice overview in addition to Farber, supra note 1,
  • 24
    • 60349119605 scopus 로고
    • Adherence to the Original Intentions in Constitutional Adjudication: Three Objections and Responses, 82
    • see generally
    • see generally Richard S. Kay, Adherence to the Original Intentions in Constitutional Adjudication: Three Objections and Responses, 82 NW. U. L. REV. 226 (1988).
    • (1988) NW. U. L. REV , vol.226
    • Kay, R.S.1
  • 25
    • 66449124916 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Much less comprehensive, but more recent, is Keith E. Whittington, The New Originalism, 2 GEO. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 599 (2004).
    • Much less comprehensive, but more recent, is Keith E. Whittington, The New Originalism, 2 GEO. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 599 (2004).
  • 26
    • 66449124650 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FRANCIS BACON, The Proficience and Advancement of Learning, Divine and Human, in 1 THE WORKS OF FRANCIS BACON 211 (Philadelphia, A. Hart 1871) (1605),
    • FRANCIS BACON, The Proficience and Advancement of Learning, Divine and Human, in 1 THE WORKS OF FRANCIS BACON 211 (Philadelphia, A. Hart 1871) (1605),
  • 27
    • 66449129430 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • quoted in BASSHAM, supra note 6, at 17.
    • quoted in BASSHAM, supra note 6, at 17.
  • 28
    • 0347419788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The ought in this sentence suggests that originalism is a normative thesis, and to a substantial extent it is. Still, when it comes to constitutional theories, a neat dividebetween the normative and purely descriptive is usually elusive. See, e.g., Michael C. Dorf, Integrating Normative and Descriptive Constitutional Theory: The Case of Original Meaning, 85 GEO. L.J. 1765 (1997);
    • The "ought" in this sentence suggests that originalism is a normative thesis, and to a substantial extent it is. Still, when it comes to constitutional theories, a neat dividebetween the normative and purely descriptive is usually elusive. See, e.g., Michael C. Dorf, Integrating Normative and Descriptive Constitutional Theory: The Case of Original Meaning, 85 GEO. L.J. 1765 (1997);
  • 29
    • 0346334463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • How To Choose a Constitutional Theory, 87
    • Richard H. Fallon, Jr., How To Choose a Constitutional Theory, 87 CAL. L. REV. 535, 540-41 (1999);
    • (1999) CAL. L. REV , vol.535 , pp. 540-541
    • Fallon Jr., R.H.1
  • 30
    • 66449093576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also infra Part I.C.4 (discussing denial by some originalists that they mean to express normative claims).
    • see also infra Part I.C.4 (discussing denial by some originalists that they mean to express normative claims).
  • 31
    • 66449097532 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A good history appears in Kesavan & Paulsen, note 8, at
    • A good history appears in Kesavan & Paulsen, supra note 8, at 1134-48.
    • supra , pp. 1134-1148
  • 32
    • 66449093586 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Randy E. Barnett, Trumping Precedent with Original Meaning: Not as Radical as It Sounds, 22 CONST. COMMENT. 257, 257 n.4 (2005)
    • See also Randy E. Barnett, Trumping Precedent with Original Meaning: Not as Radical as It Sounds, 22 CONST. COMMENT. 257, 257 n.4 (2005)
  • 33
    • 66449088741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • endorsing account of Kesavan and Paulsen, note 8
    • (endorsing account of Kesavan and Paulsen, supra note 8).
    • supra
  • 34
    • 0038644942 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For similar tellings of the tale, see generally John Harrison, Forms of Originalism and the Study of History, 26 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 83 (2003),
    • For similar tellings of the tale, see generally John Harrison, Forms of Originalism and the Study of History, 26 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 83 (2003),
  • 35
    • 66449098406 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Whittington, supra note 15
    • and Whittington, supra note 15.
  • 36
    • 66449090274 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Antonin Scalia, Address Before the Attorney General's Conference on Economic Liberties (June 14,1986), in OFFICE OF LEGAL POLICY, U.S. DEP'T OF JUSTICE, ORIGINAL MEANING JURISPRUDENCE: A SOURCEBOOK app. C (1987) [hereinafter DOJ SOURCEBOOK].
    • Antonin Scalia, Address Before the Attorney General's Conference on Economic Liberties (June 14,1986), in OFFICE OF LEGAL POLICY, U.S. DEP'T OF JUSTICE, ORIGINAL MEANING JURISPRUDENCE: A SOURCEBOOK app. C (1987) [hereinafter DOJ SOURCEBOOK].
  • 37
    • 66449088220 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The shift from original intent originalism to original public meaning originalism is traced to Justice Scalia's address by Kesavan and Paulsen, supra note 8, at 1139, 1140 & n.90,
    • The shift from original intent originalism to original public meaning originalism is traced to Justice Scalia's address by Kesavan and Paulsen, supra note 8, at 1139, 1140 & n.90,
  • 38
    • 66449101341 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and by Gary Lawson and Guy Seidman, Originalism as a Legal Enterprise, 23 CONST. COMMENT. 47, 48 & n.10 (2006).
    • and by Gary Lawson and Guy Seidman, Originalism as a Legal Enterprise, 23 CONST. COMMENT. 47, 48 & n.10 (2006).
  • 39
    • 66449102875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In 1990, Bork himself endorsed this shift, explaining that his earlier references to ratifiers' understanding were merely a shorthand formulation for original public meaning. ROBERT H. BORK, THE TEMPTING OF AMERICA: THE POLITICAL SEDUCTION OF THE LAW 144 (1990);
    • In 1990, Bork himself endorsed this shift, explaining that his earlier references to ratifiers' understanding were merely "a shorthand formulation" for original public meaning. ROBERT H. BORK, THE TEMPTING OF AMERICA: THE POLITICAL SEDUCTION OF THE LAW 144 (1990);
  • 41
    • 66449135866 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I believe that weak originalism properly claims a spot in originalist logical space because the position it contests-exclusive non-originalism or anti-originalism-is imaginable. Because that latter position is not a live competitor in contemporary debates, however, readers might fairly doubt that weak originalism falls within the range of positions that anyone has in mind when employing the originalist label. As I will explain shortly, I agree. For that reason, I will reject weak originalism as a candidate for the meaning of originalism simpliciter. But that is not enough, I think, to eject it from the space we are exploring. In any event, nothing about my argument depends upon including weak originalism as a true subset of the class of views properly deemed originalist. If you wish to exclude it at this early stage, feel free
    • I believe that weak originalism properly claims a spot in originalist logical space because the position it contests-"exclusive non-originalism" or "anti-originalism"-is imaginable. Because that latter position is not a live competitor in contemporary debates, however, readers might fairly doubt that weak originalism falls within the range of positions that anyone has in mind when employing the originalist label. As I will explain shortly, I agree. For that reason, I will reject weak originalism as a candidate for the meaning of originalism simpliciter. But that is not enough, I think, to eject it from the space we are exploring. In any event, nothing about my argument depends upon including weak originalism as a true subset of the class of views properly deemed originalist. If you wish to exclude it at this early stage, feel free.
  • 42
    • 52049106873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stephen Griffin calls this same concept exclusive originalism and shares my assessment of its importance to contemporary debates. See Stephen M. Griffin, Rebooting Originalism, 2008 U. ILL. L. REV. 1185,1187, 1197. Griffin's article is especially valuable for its insightful and persuasive critique of originalists for embracing history without historicism-for failing, in short, to adequately accommodate relevant changes in historical context.
    • Stephen Griffin calls this same concept "exclusive originalism" and shares my assessment of its importance to contemporary debates. See Stephen M. Griffin, Rebooting Originalism, 2008 U. ILL. L. REV. 1185,1187, 1197. Griffin's article is especially valuable for its insightful and persuasive critique of originalists for embracing "history without historicism"-for failing, in short, to adequately accommodate relevant changes in historical context.
  • 43
    • 66449135584 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To be sure, exclusive originalists recognize that, for some constitutional provisions, the original meaning (intent or understanding) cannot be identified to the requisite degreeof confidence (whatever that might be) or that, even if the original object can be identified, it is too vague or ambiguous to resolve a dispute. To put the point another way, for some constitutional questions, no sufficiently determinate original meaning (intent or understanding) of the Constitution can be identified. Exclusive originalists prescribe two different courses in such cases. Some advise that courts should conclude, in the name of majoritarianism, that the Constitution permits the governmental action in question. See, e.g., BORK, supra note 20, at 166;
    • To be sure, exclusive originalists recognize that, for some constitutional provisions, the original meaning (intent or understanding) cannot be identified to the requisite degreeof confidence (whatever that might be) or that, even if the original object can be identified, it is too vague or ambiguous to resolve a dispute. To put the point another way, for some constitutional questions, no sufficiently determinate original meaning (intent or understanding) of the Constitution can be identified. Exclusive originalists prescribe two different courses in such cases. Some advise that courts should conclude, in the name of majoritarianism, that the Constitution permits the governmental action in question. See, e.g., BORK, supra note 20, at 166;
  • 44
    • 79956125461 scopus 로고
    • Interpreting the Constitution: Posner on Bork, 44
    • Lino A. Graglia, "Interpreting" the Constitution: Posner on Bork, 44 STAN. L. REV. 1019, 1044 (1992);
    • (1992) STAN. L. REV , vol.1019 , pp. 1044
    • Graglia, L.A.1
  • 45
    • 33745418344 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Michael Stokes Paulsen, How To Interpret the Constitution (and How Not To), 115 YALE LJ. 2037, 2057 (2006). Others would permit courts to announce more determinate constitutional meaning with the proviso that, in so doing, they would create new meaning for purposes of constitutional law but would not be engaged in interpreting constitutional meaning.
    • Michael Stokes Paulsen, How To Interpret the Constitution (and How Not To), 115 YALE LJ. 2037, 2057 (2006). Others would permit courts to announce more determinate constitutional meaning with the proviso that, in so doing, they would create new meaning for purposes of constitutional law but would not be engaged in interpreting constitutional meaning.
  • 46
    • 66449085184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, Barnett, supra note 4, at 645-46;
    • See, e.g., Barnett, supra note 4, at 645-46;
  • 47
    • 70349580560 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There Is No Textualist Position, 42
    • Lexical originalists permit courts to announce constitutional meaning when the originalist object is not discoverable and do not insist that, in such cases, courts are necessarily engaged in something other than constitutional interpretation
    • Stanley Fish, There Is No Textualist Position, 42 SAN DIEGO L. REV. 629, 640 (2005). Lexical originalists permit courts to announce constitutional meaning when the originalist object is not discoverable and do not insist that, in such cases, courts are necessarily engaged in something other than constitutional interpretation.
    • (2005) SAN DIEGO L. REV , vol.629 , pp. 640
    • Fish, S.1
  • 48
    • 66449102018 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The term moderate originalism appears frequently in the literature. My use is, I think, consistent with Farber's, but not with others'. See Farber, supra note 1, at 1086 (A moderate originalist might well view factors [other than original intent] as potentially important, particularly when the evidence of intent is unclear.). To Paul Brest, for example, moderate originalism is not the view that original meaning has some form of priority over non-original meaning short of true lexical priority. It is the view that interpreters should inquire into framers' intent conceived at a relatively high level of generality.
    • The term "moderate originalism" appears frequently in the literature. My use is, I think, consistent with Farber's, but not with others'. See Farber, supra note 1, at 1086 ("A moderate originalist might well view factors [other than original intent] as potentially important, particularly when the evidence of intent is unclear."). To Paul Brest, for example, "moderate originalism" is not the view that original meaning has some form of priority over non-original meaning short of true lexical priority. It is the view that interpreters should inquire into framers' intent conceived at a relatively high level of generality.
  • 49
    • 0011536201 scopus 로고
    • The Misconceived Quest for the Original Understanding, 60
    • Paul Brest, The Misconceived Quest for the Original Understanding, 60 B.U. L. REV. 204, 222-23 (1980).
    • (1980) B.U. L. REV , vol.204 , pp. 222-223
    • Brest, P.1
  • 50
    • 0346789945 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Yet more confusingly, what Brest calls moderate originalism, Cass Sunstein calls soft originalism, a term I will attach to an entirely different concept. See Cass R. Sunstein, Five Theses on Originalism, 19 HARV. J.L. PUB. POL'Y 311, 313 (1996) ([T]he soft originalist will take the Framers' understanding at a certain level of abstraction of generality.).
    • Yet more confusingly, what Brest calls "moderate originalism," Cass Sunstein calls "soft originalism," a term I will attach to an entirely different concept. See Cass R. Sunstein, Five Theses on Originalism, 19 HARV. J.L. PUB. POL'Y 311, 313 (1996) ("[T]he soft originalist will take the Framers' understanding at a certain level of abstraction of generality.").
  • 51
    • 66449133461 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (And for a third meaning of soft originalism that differs from both Sunstein's and mine, see GOLDFORD, supra note 14, at 9, which uses the term to denote the ratifiers' understanding originalism, specifically in contrast to the framers' intent originalism.) In short, to avoid confusion, readers well versed in the originalism literature are especially cautioned to attend to my stipulated definitions.
    • (And for a third meaning of "soft originalism" that differs from both Sunstein's and mine, see GOLDFORD, supra note 14, at 9, which uses the term to denote the ratifiers' understanding originalism, specifically in contrast to the framers' intent originalism.) In short, to avoid confusion, readers well versed in the originalism literature are especially cautioned to attend to my stipulated definitions.
  • 52
    • 66449125484 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • David Hoy employs the labels weak, moderate, and strong originalism to distinguish among theories that treat original intent as, respectively, necessary to support a judgment of unconstitutionality, sufficient, and both necessary and sufficient. Hoy, supra note 9, at 483-85
    • David Hoy employs the labels weak, moderate, and strong originalism to distinguish among theories that treat original intent as, respectively, necessary to support a judgment of unconstitutionality, sufficient, and both necessary and sufficient. Hoy, supra note 9, at 483-85.
  • 53
    • 66449115426 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It follows that the particular originalist thesis under consideration would be soft lexical original intent originalism
    • It follows that the particular originalist thesis under consideration would be soft lexical original intent originalism.
  • 54
    • 66449133462 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The hard/soft distinction is cousin to Aileen Kavanagh's proposed distinction between direct and indirect arguments for originalism. See Kavanagh, supra note 9, at 259 (defining direct arguments for originalism as establish[ing] a positive link between Framers' intent and proper interpretation and indirect arguments as merely show[ing] that originalism is one of the possible ways of answering to a difficulty which afflicts all methods of interpretation).
    • The hard/soft distinction is cousin to Aileen Kavanagh's proposed distinction between "direct" and "indirect" arguments for originalism. See Kavanagh, supra note 9, at 259 (defining "direct" arguments for originalism as "establish[ing] a positive link between Framers' intent and proper interpretation" and "indirect" arguments as "merely show[ing] that originalism is one of the possible ways of answering to a difficulty which afflicts all methods of interpretation").
  • 55
    • 66449097842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But even if my hope proves unrealized in your case-even if you're left doubting that there is a coherent or useful distinction to be drawn in this vicinity-my core arguments remain unaffected. The hard/soft distinction is advanced to facilitate our assessment of the extant arguments for strong originalism. Yet, however we classify those arguments, the question of fundamental importance is whether they are successful.
    • But even if my hope proves unrealized in your case-even if you're left doubting that there is a coherent or useful distinction to be drawn in this vicinity-my core arguments remain unaffected. The hard/soft distinction is advanced to facilitate our assessment of the extant arguments for strong originalism. Yet, however we classify those arguments, the question of fundamental importance is whether they are successful.
  • 56
    • 0346044966 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a not wholly atypical rant, see Lillian R. BeVier, The Integrity and Impersonality of Originalism, 19 HARV. J.L. PUB. POL'Y 283, 287 (1996): The hypocrisy of many of the nonoriginalists' arguments, the deliberate masking of their real agenda, the lack of candor, the absence of respect for (or even acknowledgment of) law as a constraint-all of these features exert a corrupting influence on the very idea of law itself.
    • For a not wholly atypical rant, see Lillian R. BeVier, The Integrity and Impersonality of Originalism, 19 HARV. J.L. PUB. POL'Y 283, 287 (1996): "The hypocrisy of many of the nonoriginalists' arguments, the deliberate masking of their real agenda, the lack of candor, the absence of respect for (or even acknowledgment of) law as a constraint-all of these features exert a corrupting influence on the very idea of law itself."
  • 57
    • 66449121246 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This distinction, generally overlooked, is noted in BASSHAM, supra note 6, at 19-21
    • This distinction, generally overlooked, is noted in BASSHAM, supra note 6, at 19-21.
  • 58
    • 66449131079 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (framers' intent vs. ratifiers' understanding vs. public meaning) x (weak vs. moderate vs. lexical vs. exclusive) x (hard vs. soft) x (judicial vs. official vs. universal).
    • (framers' intent vs. ratifiers' understanding vs. public meaning) x (weak vs. moderate vs. lexical vs. exclusive) x (hard vs. soft) x (judicial vs. official vs. universal).
  • 59
    • 66449128401 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, I have lumped together as moderate originalism all theses that would assign a presumption to the originalist focus of any weight greater than ordinary but short of conclusive. This is to recognize fewer differences than the law often feels comfortable in distinguishing, Equal Protection doctrine, to take one salient example, subdivides weighty state interests between the important and the compelling, We could, therefore, replace moderate originalism with the subvarieties medium weight originalism and heavy weight originalism, where even the latter is weaker than either of the two variants of strong originalism. And many more subtle distinctions might helpfully emerge once self-professed originalists abandon strong originalism and focus their formidable energies and intellects on the presently undertheorized space of moderate originalism. I have also noted that hard originalism comes in what we might call o
    • For example, I have lumped together as "moderate originalism" all theses that would assign a presumption to the originalist focus of any weight greater than ordinary but short of conclusive. This is to recognize fewer differences than the law often feels comfortable in distinguishing. (Equal Protection doctrine, to take one salient example, subdivides weighty state interests between the "important" and the "compelling.") We could, therefore, replace moderate originalism with the subvarieties "medium weight originalism" and "heavy weight originalism," where even the latter is weaker than either of the two variants of strong originalism. And many more subtle distinctions might helpfully emerge once self-professed originalists abandon strong originalism and focus their formidable energies and intellects on the presently undertheorized space of moderate originalism. I have also noted that hard originalism comes in what we might call "ordinary hard" and "super hard" variants. Similarly, original intent originalism could be broken into two variants: those that focus on the intent of the text's actual authors and those that focus on the collective intent of all persons at the Philadelphia Convention.
  • 60
    • 84888467546 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 202
    • See infra note 202.
    • See infra
  • 61
    • 66449094858 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a particularly revealing display of some of the dimensions on which originalisms can differ, and to illustrate how these differences can easily escape our attention, compare the slight differences in definition across two editions of the Farber Sherry constitutional history textbook already cited. The initial 1990 edition announces that [o]riginalists are committed to the view that original intent is not only relevant but authoritative, that we are in some sense obligated to follow the intent of the framers. DANIEL A. FARBER SUZANNA SHERRY, A HISTORY OF THE AMERICAN CONSTITUTION 374 (1st ed. 1990).
    • For a particularly revealing display of some of the dimensions on which originalisms can differ, and to illustrate how these differences can easily escape our attention, compare the slight differences in definition across two editions of the Farber Sherry constitutional history textbook already cited. The initial 1990 edition announces that "[o]riginalists are committed to the view that original intent is not only relevant but authoritative, that we are in some sense obligated to follow the intent of the framers." DANIEL A. FARBER SUZANNA SHERRY, A HISTORY OF THE AMERICAN CONSTITUTION 374 (1st ed. 1990).
  • 62
    • 66449110722 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In subtle contrast, the 2005 second edition describes originalists as committed to the view that the historical perspective is not only relevant but at least sometimes authoritative, that contemporary judges are in some sense obligated to follow the views of the framers. FARBER SHERRY, supra note 7, at 526. On the dimension of object, the authors have shifted from a position that emphasizes original intent toward one that is agnostic among the competing candidates; on the dimension of subject, they shift from universal originalism (marked by we) to judicial originalism; and on the dimension of strength, they have effected a modest equivocation by inserting the qualifier at least sometimes.
    • In subtle contrast, the 2005 second edition describes originalists as "committed to the view that the historical perspective is not only relevant but at least sometimes authoritative, that contemporary judges are in some sense obligated to follow the views of the framers." FARBER SHERRY, supra note 7, at 526. On the dimension of object, the authors have shifted from a position that emphasizes original intent toward one that is agnostic among the competing candidates; on the dimension of subject, they shift from universal originalism (marked by "we") to judicial originalism; and on the dimension of strength, they have effected a modest equivocation by inserting the qualifier "at least sometimes."
  • 63
    • 66449096713 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Barnett, supra note 4, at 613
    • Barnett, supra note 4, at 613.
  • 64
    • 66449115093 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Christopher L. Eisgruber, Early Interpretations & Original Sins, 95MICH. L. REV. 2005, 2013 (1997).
    • Christopher L. Eisgruber, Early Interpretations & Original Sins, 95MICH. L. REV. 2005, 2013 (1997).
  • 65
    • 0041557883 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Most Dangerous Branch, 105
    • Martin S. Flaherty, The Most Dangerous Branch, 105 YALE L.J. 1725, 1812 (1996).
    • (1996) YALE L.J , vol.1725 , pp. 1812
    • Flaherty, M.S.1
  • 66
    • 66449119833 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ANTONIN SCALIA, A MATTER OF INTERPRETATION: FEDERAL COURTS AND THE LAW 38 (Amy Gutmann ed., 1997).
    • ANTONIN SCALIA, A MATTER OF INTERPRETATION: FEDERAL COURTS AND THE LAW 38 (Amy Gutmann ed., 1997).
  • 67
    • 0038548382 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I agree with those who urge that distinguishing original intent from original meaning is less significant than often claimed. See, e.g, Caleb Nelson, Originalism and Interpretive Conventions, 70 U. CHI. L. REV. 519, 549 n.133 2003
    • I agree with those who urge that distinguishing original intent from original meaning is less significant than often claimed. See, e.g., Caleb Nelson, Originalism and Interpretive Conventions, 70 U. CHI. L. REV. 519, 549 n.133 (2003).
  • 68
    • 66449136480 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed, I suspect that originalists who extol original meaning as a solvent are subject to embarrassment as it becomes increasingly clear that many of the most difficult problems of contemporary constitutional jurisprudence involve the resolution of neither word-level ambiguity nor disputes over the semantics of discrete constitutional clauses or sentences. As others have argued, and as recent cases involving the war on terror reinforce, whatever value originalism will have for horizontal separation of power controversies is more likely to come from inquiries into original purposes or intentions than from original public meaning. See, e.g., Flaherty, supra note 37, at 1812-13.
    • Indeed, I suspect that originalists who extol original meaning as a solvent are subject to embarrassment as it becomes increasingly clear that many of the most difficult problems of contemporary constitutional jurisprudence involve the resolution of neither word-level ambiguity nor disputes over the semantics of discrete constitutional clauses or sentences. As others have argued, and as recent cases involving the war on terror reinforce, whatever value originalism will have for horizontal separation of power controversies is more likely to come from inquiries into original purposes or intentions than from original public meaning. See, e.g., Flaherty, supra note 37, at 1812-13.
  • 69
    • 66449103425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see, e.g., Steven G. Calabresi & Saikrishna B. Prakash, The President's Power To Execute the Laws, 104 YALE L.J. 541 (1994) (arguing that original public meaning originalism presents overwhelming case for unitary executive).
    • But see, e.g., Steven G. Calabresi & Saikrishna B. Prakash, The President's Power To Execute the Laws, 104 YALE L.J. 541 (1994) (arguing that original public meaning originalism presents overwhelming case for unitary executive).
  • 70
    • 66449102320 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The same is true of vertical separation of powers disputes, as the Court has belatedly appreciated the importance of the Necessary and Proper Clause for cases it had previously conceived of as involving the Commerce Clause alone. Compare, e.g, United States v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549, 558-59 (1995, discussing third category of Commerce Clause power without even mentioning Necessary and Proper Clause, and Pierce County v. Guillen, 537 U.S. 129, 147 n.9 (2003, upholding federal law that regulated intrastate activities for purpose of protecting instrumentalities of interstate commerce, while expressly disavowing reliance on Necessary and Proper Clause, with Gonzalez v. Raich, 545 U.S. 1, 22 2005, emphasizing that regulation of intrastate activities must depend upon Necessary and Proper Clause, It is implausible that proper resolution of cases of this sort will turn on the original public meaning of the word proper
    • The same is true of vertical separation of powers disputes, as the Court has belatedly appreciated the importance of the Necessary and Proper Clause for cases it had previously conceived of as involving the Commerce Clause alone. Compare, e.g., United States v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549, 558-59 (1995) (discussing third category of Commerce Clause power without even mentioning Necessary and Proper Clause), and Pierce County v. Guillen, 537 U.S. 129, 147 n.9 (2003) (upholding federal law that regulated intrastate activities for purpose of protecting instrumentalities of interstate commerce, while expressly disavowing reliance on Necessary and Proper Clause), with Gonzalez v. Raich, 545 U.S. 1, 22 (2005) (emphasizing that regulation of intrastate activities must depend upon Necessary and Proper Clause). It is implausible that proper resolution of cases of this sort will turn on the original public meaning of the word "proper."
  • 71
    • 66449101055 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Larry Solum thinks that I misread Scalia. According to Solum, Scalia is pointing out merely that Originalists, unlike their opponents, believe that the semantic meaning of the Constitution does not change; he is saying nothing about the Constitution's legal meaning. See Lawrence B. Solum, Semantic Originalism 11 n.31 (111. Pub. Law & Legal TheoryResearch Papers Series No. 07-24, 2008), available at ssrn.com/abstract=l 120244.
    • Larry Solum thinks that I misread Scalia. According to Solum, Scalia is pointing out merely that Originalists, unlike their opponents, believe that the semantic meaning of the Constitution does not change; he is saying nothing about the Constitution's legal meaning. See Lawrence B. Solum, Semantic Originalism 11 n.31 (111. Pub. Law & Legal TheoryResearch Papers Series No. 07-24, 2008), available at ssrn.com/abstract=l 120244.
  • 72
    • 66449084895 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I believe that Solum is mistaken. See infra Part I.C.4.
    • I believe that Solum is mistaken. See infra Part I.C.4.
  • 73
    • 84977003581 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 14, at, emphasis added
    • GOLDFORD, supra note 14, at 139 (emphasis added).
    • supra , pp. 139
    • GOLDFORD1
  • 74
    • 66449135854 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., RAOUL BERGER, GOVERNMENT BY JUDICIARY: THE TRANSFORMATION OF THE FOURTEENTH AMENDMENT 3 (1977)
    • See, e.g., RAOUL BERGER, GOVERNMENT BY JUDICIARY: THE TRANSFORMATION OF THE FOURTEENTH AMENDMENT 3 (1977)
  • 75
    • 66449107730 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ([T]he 'original intention' of the Framers is binding on the Court BORK, supra note 20, at 5 (arguing that judges are bound by the only thing that can be called law, the principles of the text, whether Constitution or statute, as generally understood at the enactment);
    • ("[T]he 'original intention' of the Framers is binding on the Court BORK, supra note 20, at 5 (arguing that judges are "bound by the only thing that can be called law, the principles of the text, whether Constitution or statute, as generally understood at the enactment");
  • 76
    • 66449117099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also, e.g., DOJ SOURCEBOOK, supra note 19, at 2 ([C]ourts must construe the Constitution according to its original meaning.).
    • see also, e.g., DOJ SOURCEBOOK, supra note 19, at 2 ("[C]ourts must construe the Constitution according to its original meaning.").
  • 77
    • 66449109322 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I have included here only a tiny sample of these scholars' characterizations of Originalism. See, e.g., RANDY E. BARNETT, RESTORING THE LOST CONSTITUTION: THE PRESUMPTION OF LIBERTY 4 (2004) ([B]y committing ourselves to a written constitution, we commit ourselves to adhere to the original meaning of the text and any later amendments.);
    • I have included here only a tiny sample of these scholars' characterizations of Originalism. See, e.g., RANDY E. BARNETT, RESTORING THE LOST CONSTITUTION: THE PRESUMPTION OF LIBERTY 4 (2004) ("[B]y committing ourselves to a written constitution, we commit ourselves to adhere to the original meaning of the text and any later amendments.");
  • 78
    • 66449106258 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Calabresi & Prakash, supra note 38, at 551-52 ([T]he text of the Constitution, as originally understood by the people who ratified it, is the fundamental law of the land. The meaning of all legal writings depends on their texts, as they were objectively understood by the people who enacted or ratified them. Originalists do not give priority to the plain dictionary meaning of the Constitution's text because they like grammar more than history. They give priority to it because they believe that it and it alone is law. (footnotes omitted));
    • Calabresi & Prakash, supra note 38, at 551-52 ("[T]he text of the Constitution, as originally understood by the people who ratified it, is the fundamental law of the land. The meaning of all legal writings depends on their texts, as they were objectively understood by the people who enacted or ratified them. Originalists do not give priority to the plain dictionary meaning of the Constitution's text because they like grammar more than history. They give priority to it because they believe that it and it alone is law." (footnotes omitted));
  • 79
    • 0042578750 scopus 로고
    • The Rise and Rise of the Administrative State, 107
    • 0]riginalist interpretivism is not simply one method of interpretation among many-it is the only method that is suited to discovering the actual meaning of the relevant text
    • Gary Lawson, The Rise and Rise of the Administrative State, 107 HARV. L. REV. 1231, 1250 (1994) ("[0]riginalist interpretivism is not simply one method of interpretation among many-it is the only method that is suited to discovering the actual meaning of the relevant text.");
    • (1994) HARV. L. REV , vol.1231 , pp. 1250
    • Lawson, G.1
  • 80
    • 66449094859 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Original Interpretive Principles as the Core of Originalism, 24 CONST
    • Originalism] requires that judges interpret the document based only on its original meaning
    • John O. McGinnis & Michael Rappaport, Original Interpretive Principles as the Core of Originalism, 24 CONST. COMMENT. 371, 374 (2007) ("[Originalism] requires that judges interpret the document based only on its original meaning.");
    • (2007) COMMENT , vol.371 , pp. 374
    • McGinnis, J.O.1    Rappaport, M.2
  • 81
    • 66449110151 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 8, at, 0]riginal meaning textualism is the only method of interpreting the Constitution
    • Kesavan & Paulsen, supra note 8, at 1142 ("[0]riginal meaning textualism is the only method of interpreting the Constitution.");
    • supra , pp. 1142
    • Kesavan1    Paulsen2
  • 82
    • 0041557892 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Unoriginalism's Law Without Meaning, 15 CONST
    • When we accept some text as law, we also commit to the law's original meanings. Indeed, to embrace the legitimacy of words as law without their original, ordinary meanings is to embrace nothing
    • Saikrishna B. Prakash, Unoriginalism's Law Without Meaning, 15 CONST. COMMENT. 529, 544 (1998) ("When we accept some text as law, we also commit to the law's original meanings. Indeed, to embrace the legitimacy of words as law without their original, ordinary meanings is to embrace nothing.");
    • (1998) COMMENT , vol.529 , pp. 544
    • Prakash, S.B.1
  • 83
    • 66449091391 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also, e.g., MICHAEL J. PERRY, THE CONSTITUTION IN THE COURTS: LAW OR POLITICS? 32 (1994) (The constitutional text as originally understood should be deemed authoritative for purposes of constitutional adjudication.).
    • see also, e.g., MICHAEL J. PERRY, THE CONSTITUTION IN THE COURTS: LAW OR POLITICS? 32 (1994) ("The constitutional text as originally understood should be deemed authoritative for purposes of constitutional adjudication.").
  • 84
    • 66449119543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Part I.C.5.
    • See infra Part I.C.5.
  • 85
    • 41349095913 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Abortion and Original Meaning, 24 CONST
    • Constitutional interpretation by judges requires fidelity to the Constitution as law. Fidelity to the Constitution as law means fidelity to the words of the text, understood in terms of their original meaning, and to the principles that underlie the text, See, e.g
    • See, e.g., Jack M. Balkin, Abortion and Original Meaning, 24 CONST. COMMENT. 291, 295 (2007) ("Constitutional interpretation by judges requires fidelity to the Constitution as law. Fidelity to the Constitution as law means fidelity to the words of the text, understood in terms of their original meaning, and to the principles that underlie the text.").
    • (2007) COMMENT , vol.291 , pp. 295
    • Balkin, J.M.1
  • 86
    • 66449133158 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AMERICAN HERITAGE DICTIONARY OF THE ENGLISH LANGUAGE 655-56 (4th ed. 2000) (defining fidelity as [e]xact correspondence with fact or with a given quality, condition, or event and explaining that fidelity implies the unfailing fulfillment of one's duties and obligations and strict adherence to vows or promises);
    • AMERICAN HERITAGE DICTIONARY OF THE ENGLISH LANGUAGE 655-56 (4th ed. 2000) (defining fidelity as "[e]xact correspondence with fact or with a given quality, condition, or event" and explaining that "fidelity implies the unfailing fulfillment of one's duties and obligations and strict adherence to vows or promises");
  • 87
    • 66449123785 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WEBSTER'S THIRD NEW INTERNATIONAL DICTIONARY 845 (1993) (Fidelity implies strict and continuing faithfulness as to an obligation, trust, or duty.).
    • WEBSTER'S THIRD NEW INTERNATIONAL DICTIONARY 845 (1993) ("Fidelity implies strict and continuing faithfulness as to an obligation, trust, or duty.").
  • 88
    • 66449085490 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Brest, supra note 24, at 204 (describing Originalism as theory that accords binding authority to the text of the Constitution or the intentions of its adopters);
    • See, e.g., Brest, supra note 24, at 204 (describing Originalism as theory that "accords binding authority to the text of the Constitution or the intentions of its adopters");
  • 89
    • 66449120683 scopus 로고
    • The Positivist Foundations of Originalism: An Account and Critique, 71
    • noting diversity of originalist views, but identifying as core premise of Originalism that the role of judges in constitutional cases is simply and exclusively to discover and give effect to the meaning of the Constitution as embodied in the constitutional text and the original intentions of the founders
    • James A. Gardner, The Positivist Foundations of Originalism: An Account and Critique, 71 B.U. L. REV. 1, 7 (1991) (noting diversity of originalist views, but identifying as core premise of Originalism that "the role of judges in constitutional cases is simply and exclusively to discover and give effect to the meaning of the Constitution as embodied in the constitutional text and the original intentions of the founders").
    • (1991) B.U. L. REV , vol.1 , pp. 7
    • Gardner, J.A.1
  • 90
    • 66449088205 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In what is possibly the only book-length investigation of the historical development of originalist jurisprudence, Johnathan O'Neill characterizes Originalism as comprising several closely related claims about the authoritative source of American constitutional law, among them an insist[ence] that interpreters be bound by the meaning the document had for those who gave it legal authority. O'NEILL, supra note 14, at 1-2 (2005);
    • In what is possibly the only book-length investigation of the historical development of originalist jurisprudence, Johnathan O'Neill characterizes Originalism as comprising "several closely related claims about the authoritative source of American constitutional law," among them an "insist[ence] that interpreters be bound by the meaning the document had for those who gave it legal authority." O'NEILL, supra note 14, at 1-2 (2005);
  • 91
    • 66449101342 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also, e.g., JOHN H. GARVEY, T. ALEXANDER ALEINIKOFF & DANIEL A. FARBER, MODERN CONSTITUTIONAL THEORY: A READER 91 (5th ed. 2004) (describing Originalism as view that the original intent of the framers ought to control constitutional interpretation);
    • see also, e.g., JOHN H. GARVEY, T. ALEXANDER ALEINIKOFF & DANIEL A. FARBER, MODERN CONSTITUTIONAL THEORY: A READER 91 (5th ed. 2004) (describing Originalism as view "that the original intent of the framers ought to control constitutional interpretation");
  • 92
    • 33644697469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Marshall Court and the Originalist's Dilemma, 90
    • Originalism is a theory of constitutional interpretation that assigns dispositive weight to the original understanding of the Constitution or the constitutional provision at issue
    • Peter J. Smith, The Marshall Court and the Originalist's Dilemma, 90 MINN. L. REV. 612, 619 (2006) ("Originalism is a theory of constitutional interpretation that assigns dispositive weight to the original understanding of the Constitution or the constitutional provision at issue.").
    • (2006) MINN. L. REV , vol.612 , pp. 619
    • Smith, P.J.1
  • 93
    • 66449099911 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Admittedly, I am not sure how to prove this claim to those who remain skeptical notwithstanding the supportive quotations I have already presented and those I will marshal later in the Article. So any reader who doubts my rendering of Originalism as strong originalism-because she believes, for example, that most references to Originalism mean something else (say, moderate originalism) or that usage is so variable as to render any generalization false-ought to read the term Originalism in this Article to mean strong originalism by stipulation. For example, the title of this Article would become Strong Originalism is Bunk. Any reader who thinks that so few originalists defend strong originalism as to make its repudiation uninteresting should probably stop reading now.Even readers who accept that a sufficiently large percentage of scholarly and judicial advocates for originalism simpliciter (including a sufficiently large number of the most prominent among them) mean th
    • Admittedly, I am not sure how to prove this claim to those who remain skeptical notwithstanding the supportive quotations I have already presented and those I will marshal later in the Article. So any reader who doubts my rendering of Originalism as strong originalism-because she believes, for example, that most references to Originalism mean something else (say, moderate originalism) or that usage is so variable as to render any generalization false-ought to read the term Originalism in this Article to mean strong originalism by stipulation. For example, the title of this Article would become "Strong Originalism is Bunk." Any reader who thinks that so few originalists defend strong originalism as to make its repudiation uninteresting should probably stop reading now.Even readers who accept that a sufficiently large percentage of scholarly and judicial advocates for originalism simpliciter (including a sufficiently large number of the most prominent among them) mean thereby to endorse strong originalism-enough to justify their critics in likewise treating originalism simpliciter to mean strong originalism-might still question whether that is the more desirable course. That is, even if I am justified in equating Originalism with strong originalism, one might prefer to retire the term originalism, when used without modification, and speak instead of more narrowly and particularly defined neighborhoods within originalist space. This proposal has much to recommend it. It likely would facilitate greater clarity of thought and a greater likelihood of successful communication between writer and reader. However, I do not embrace that advice here-the title does, after all, promise a critique of "originalism" and not of "strong originalism"-only because for a critic of strong originalism to take that first step would amount to something like unilateral disarmament: Persons who become aware of the Article's existence but who don't read it (a class that, however small, will nonetheless dwarf the class of persons who do read it) are apt to suppose that it targets a (perhaps minor) variant of originalism, leaving the core of originalism unscathed. If and when self-described originalists make clear to their readers either that the form of originalism they defend is "strong originalism" and not something that can meaningfully be rendered as originalism proper or originalism simpliciter, or (even better!) that they disavow strong originalism in favor of something more modest, then I will happily announce that the concept of originalism proper has no usable meaning, least of all that it should be construed as strong originalism.
  • 94
    • 66449098639 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the remainder of this Article, for expositional ease, I will generally refer only to original meaning, with the understanding that my comments also apply to original intent and original understanding (or any other possible originalist object) unless the context makes clear otherwise. Likewise, I will generally omit the parenthetical qualification about judicial precedent. In doing so, I will not mean to deny the empirical fact that contemporary Originalists divide over the propriety of judges adhering to judicial precedents that they now believe to be inconsistent with original meanings. I will, however, raise some doubts about whether Originalists who recognize this one exception to strong originalism have good arguments for going this far but no farther. See infra Part I.C.5
    • For the remainder of this Article, for expositional ease, I will generally refer only to original meaning, with the understanding that my comments also apply to original intent and original understanding (or any other possible originalist object) unless the context makes clear otherwise. Likewise, I will generally omit the parenthetical qualification about judicial precedent. In doing so, I will not mean to deny the empirical fact that contemporary Originalists divide over the propriety of judges adhering to judicial precedents that they now believe to be inconsistent with original meanings. I will, however, raise some doubts about whether Originalists who recognize this one exception to strong originalism have good arguments for going this far but no farther. See infra Part I.C.5.
  • 96
    • 66449109047 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dred Scott v. Sandford, 60 U.S. (19 How.) 393, 426 (1856). Given the universal opprobrium that attaches to Dred Scott, it is unsurprising that Originalists would seek to disavow it. Some argue, accordingly, that Taney got the original meaning of the relevant constitutional provisions wrong.
    • Dred Scott v. Sandford, 60 U.S. (19 How.) 393, 426 (1856). Given the universal opprobrium that attaches to Dred Scott, it is unsurprising that Originalists would seek to disavow it. Some argue, accordingly, that Taney got the original meaning of the relevant constitutional provisions wrong.
  • 97
    • 66449113225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BORK, supra note 20, at 30;
    • BORK, supra note 20, at 30;
  • 99
    • 66449104842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This could be correct; I quote from Dred Scott because it contains a particularly clear and forceful statement of strong originalism, not to defeat Originalism by showing that it compelled the result in Dred Scott. In a most shameless display of the adage that the best defense is a good offense, however, Originalists have frequently sought to turn tables on their opponents by laying Dred Scott at the feet of the non-originalists, as when then-Justice Rehnquist described it as [t]he apogee of the living Constitution doctrine during the nineteenth century. William H. Rehnquist, The Notion of a Living Constitution, 54 TEX. L. REV. 693, 700 1976
    • This could be correct; I quote from Dred Scott because it contains a particularly clear and forceful statement of strong originalism, not to defeat Originalism by showing that it compelled the result in Dred Scott. In a most shameless display of the adage that the best defense is a good offense, however, Originalists have frequently sought to turn tables on their opponents by laying Dred Scott at the feet of the non-originalists, as when then-Justice Rehnquist described it as "[t]he apogee of the living Constitution doctrine during the nineteenth century." William H. Rehnquist, The Notion of a Living Constitution, 54 TEX. L. REV. 693, 700 (1976).
  • 100
    • 66449092420 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (For an astute assessment and criticism, see generally Christopher L. Eisgruber, Dred Again: Originalism's Forgotten Past, 10 CONST. COMMENT. 37 (1993).)
    • (For an astute assessment and criticism, see generally Christopher L. Eisgruber, Dred Again: Originalism's Forgotten Past, 10 CONST. COMMENT. 37 (1993).)
  • 101
    • 66449137986 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Representative is the contention of the Meese Justice Department that, although Taney paid lip service to originalism, in fact the decision was plainly the result of [non-originalism]. DOJ SOURCEBOOK, supra note 19, at 58.
    • Representative is the contention of the Meese Justice Department that, although Taney "paid lip service" to originalism, in fact the decision "was plainly the result of [non-originalism]." DOJ SOURCEBOOK, supra note 19, at 58.
  • 102
    • 66449130556 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This extraordinary contention rests on the claim that Taney's opinion relies, not on the original meaning of the due process clause, but on the extraconstitutional notion of substantive due process. Id. at 58-59
    • This extraordinary contention rests on the claim that "Taney's opinion relies, not on the original meaning of the due process clause, but on the extraconstitutional notion of substantive due process." Id. at 58-59.
  • 103
    • 66449124661 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This argument is doubly unpersuasive. First and more significantly, although Taney did conclude that the Missouri Compromise violated slaveholders' due process rights, the passage quoted above serves an entirely different conclusion-namely, that black persons could not avail themselves of federal diversity jurisdiction because they could not be citizens of the United States within the original meaning of Article III, Section 2. That constitutional ruling was independently sufficient to drive the result in Dred Scott and occupied a far more central role in Taney's opinion. Moreover, it is one that many historians believe Taney got right-even if he plainly overreached in asserting that free blacks had not been recognized as citizens in any states at any time. For a careful discussion, see Mark A. Graber, Desperately Ducking Slavery: Dred Scott and Contemporary Constitutional Theory, 14 CONST. COMMENT. 271, 294-302 1997
    • This argument is doubly unpersuasive. First and more significantly, although Taney did conclude that the Missouri Compromise violated slaveholders' due process rights, the passage quoted above serves an entirely different conclusion-namely, that black persons could not avail themselves of federal diversity jurisdiction because they could not be "citizens" of the United States within the original meaning of Article III, Section 2. That constitutional ruling was independently sufficient to drive the result in Dred Scott and occupied a far more central role in Taney's opinion. Moreover, it is one that many historians believe Taney got right-even if he plainly overreached in asserting that free blacks had not been recognized as citizens in any states at any time. For a careful discussion, see Mark A. Graber, Desperately Ducking Slavery: Dred Scott and Contemporary Constitutional Theory, 14 CONST. COMMENT. 271, 294-302 (1997).
  • 104
    • 66449137737 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To be sure, others are unpersuaded. See, e.g., DAVID P. CURRIE, THE CONSTITUTION IN THE SUPREME COURT: THE FIRST HUNDRED YEARS, 1789-1888, at 266 (1985)
    • To be sure, others are unpersuaded. See, e.g., DAVID P. CURRIE, THE CONSTITUTION IN THE SUPREME COURT: THE FIRST HUNDRED YEARS, 1789-1888, at 266 (1985)
  • 105
    • 66449096141 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Taney's arguments against the citizenship of free blacks, left a good deal to be desired, But for an Originalist to claim, as Michael McConnell has, that Dred Scott was wrong, plainly wrong, not just as a moral matter, but as a legal decision, McConnell, supra, at 1174, is more than Originalist premises can support.Second,although Originalists routinely denounce substantive due process as perhaps the plainest of non-originalist sins, the history is far more complicated than they let on. Here, again, is the DOJ Sourcebook:At a minimum, original meaning jurisprudence limits the range of acceptable choices. The precise original meaning of the due process clause, for example, might be difficult to determine, but at the very least we should be able to agree that the clause is limited to process, and does not entitle courts to conduct a substantive review of the wisdom of legislation
    • ("Taney's arguments against the citizenship of free blacks . left a good deal to be desired."). But for an Originalist to claim, as Michael McConnell has, that "Dred Scott was wrong, plainly wrong, not just as a moral matter, but as a legal decision," McConnell, supra, at 1174, is more than Originalist premises can support.Second,although Originalists routinely denounce substantive due process as perhaps the plainest of non-originalist sins, the history is far more complicated than they let on. Here, again, is the DOJ Sourcebook:At a minimum, original meaning jurisprudence limits the range of acceptable choices. The precise original meaning of the due process clause, for example, might be difficult to determine, but at the very least we should be able to agree that the clause is limited to process, and does not entitle courts to conduct a substantive review of the wisdom of legislation.
  • 106
    • 66449092207 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DOJ SOURCEBOOK, supra note 19, at 7-8. That's a reasonable conclusion for a textualist to reach, but not one that an Originalist ought to take too quickly for granted given the plausible contentions that the framing generation treated due process of law as a legal term of art roughly synonymous with the Magna Carta's prohibition on certain deprivations except by the law of the land and that both phrases had substantive as well as procedural content.
    • DOJ SOURCEBOOK, supra note 19, at 7-8. That's a reasonable conclusion for a textualist to reach, but not one that an Originalist ought to take too quickly for granted given the plausible contentions that the framing generation treated "due process of law" as a legal term of art roughly synonymous with the Magna Carta's prohibition on certain deprivations except by "the law of the land" and that both phrases had substantive as well as procedural content.
  • 107
    • 0347683535 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally John Harrison, Substantive Due Process and the Constitutional Text, 83 VA. L. REV. 493, 542-55 (1997) (concluding that whether Due Process Clauses were generally understood this way in 1791 or 1868 remains open question);
    • See generally John Harrison, Substantive Due Process and the Constitutional Text, 83 VA. L. REV. 493, 542-55 (1997) (concluding that whether Due Process Clauses were generally understood this way in 1791 or 1868 remains open question);
  • 108
    • 66449086410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Robert E. Riggs, Substantive Due Process in 1791,1990 WIS. L. REV. 941 (concluding that educated persons in 1791 probably would have understood Due Process Clause to impose both substantive and procedural limitations on state action).
    • Robert E. Riggs, Substantive Due Process in 1791,1990 WIS. L. REV. 941 (concluding that educated persons in 1791 probably would have understood Due Process Clause to impose both substantive and procedural limitations on state action).
  • 109
    • 66449137453 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Living constitutionalism is frequently characterized, by proponents and critics, as the view that, at least with respect to constitutional provisions centrally concerned with moral values like liberty and equality, courts ought to follow evolving or contemporary norms. See generally GOLDFORD, supra note 14, at 57-61.
    • Living constitutionalism is frequently characterized, by proponents and critics, as the view that, at least with respect to constitutional provisions centrally concerned with moral values like liberty and equality, courts ought to follow evolving or contemporary norms. See generally GOLDFORD, supra note 14, at 57-61.
  • 110
    • 0031319994 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thus one respected commentator presents constitutional interpreters as faced with a simple binary choice: whether American constitutionalism, obligates interpreters to base decisions on what the framers had in mind when they wrote the Constitution or whether it obligates interpreters to adapt general constitutional principles to changing circumstances or more enlightened sensibilities. Howard Gillman, The Collapse of Constitutional Originalism and the Rise of the Notion of the Living Constitution in the Course of American State-Building, 11 STUD. AM. POL. DEV. 191,192 1997, If, as Gillman plausibly claims, the latter option represents living constitutionalism, then its nonidentity with non-originalism is clear, for nonoriginalists qua non-originalists need not recognize a general obligation to endorse updated or enlightened constitutional interpretations; though they necessarily reject the obliga
    • Thus one respected commentator presents constitutional interpreters as faced with a simple binary choice: "whether American constitutionalism ... obligates interpreters to base decisions on what the framers had in mind when they wrote the Constitution or whether it obligates interpreters to adapt general constitutional principles to changing circumstances or more enlightened sensibilities." Howard Gillman, The Collapse of Constitutional Originalism and the Rise of the Notion of the "Living Constitution" in the Course of American State-Building, 11 STUD. AM. POL. DEV. 191,192 (1997). If, as Gillman plausibly claims, the latter option represents living constitutionalism, then its nonidentity with non-originalism is clear, for nonoriginalists qua non-originalists need not recognize a general obligation to endorse updated or "enlightened" constitutional interpretations; though they necessarily reject the obligation that strong originalists embrace, they need not replace it with some form of competing obligation.
  • 111
    • 66449111792 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Consistency would dictate that the opponents of Originalism be called nonoriginalists. In this Article, though, I bow to convention and simplicity by omitting the capitalization.
    • Consistency would dictate that the opponents of Originalism be called "nonoriginalists." In this Article, though, I bow to convention and simplicity by omitting the capitalization.
  • 112
    • 66449083448 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Farber, supra note 1, at 1086 (defining non-originalists as those who do not find original intent dispositive of contemporary constitutional questions);
    • See, e.g., Farber, supra note 1, at 1086 (defining non-originalists as those who "do not find original intent dispositive of contemporary constitutional questions");
  • 113
    • 66449103436 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kesavan & Paulsen, supra note 8, at 1126 (defining non-originalists as theorists who believe that constitutional interpretation should not be limited by the intentions of the Framers, the understandings of the Ratifiers, or evidence of the original meaning of the words and phrases of the text).
    • Kesavan & Paulsen, supra note 8, at 1126 (defining non-originalists as "theorists who believe that constitutional interpretation should not be limited by the intentions of the Framers, the understandings of the Ratifiers, or evidence of the original meaning of the words and phrases of the text").
  • 114
    • 66449125478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This observation is far from novel, see, e.g, Farber, supra note 1, at 1086;
    • This observation is far from novel, see, e.g., Farber, supra note 1, at 1086;
  • 115
    • 66449098957 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 9, at, but warrants repetition nonetheless
    • Kavanagh, supra note 9, at 256, but warrants repetition nonetheless.
    • supra , pp. 256
    • Kavanagh1
  • 116
    • 66449106800 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Brest, supra note 24, at 237 & n.124 (observing that [t]he nonoriginalist treats the text and original history as presumptively binding and limiting, but as neither a necessary nor sufficient condition for constitutional decisionmaking and adding that there are some instances in which the nonoriginalist presumption of fidelity to the text and original understanding is very unlikely to be rebutted);
    • See, e.g., Brest, supra note 24, at 237 & n.124 (observing that "[t]he nonoriginalist treats the text and original history as presumptively binding and limiting, but as neither a necessary nor sufficient condition for constitutional decisionmaking" and adding that "there are some instances in which the nonoriginalist presumption of fidelity to the text and original understanding is very unlikely to be rebutted");
  • 117
    • 0347419824 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Common Law Constitutional Interpretation, 63
    • observing that [v]irtually everyone agrees that the specific intentions of the Framers count for something and seeming to approve of practice in which they count for something but not everything
    • David A. Strauss, Common Law Constitutional Interpretation, 63 U. CHI. L. REV. 877, 881 (1996) (observing that "[v]irtually everyone agrees that the specific intentions of the Framers count for something" and seeming to approve of practice in which they count "for something but not everything");
    • (1996) U. CHI. L. REV , vol.877 , pp. 881
    • Strauss, D.A.1
  • 118
    • 66449135302 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Laurence H. Tribe, Comment, in SCALIA, supra note 38, at 93 (agreeing that many constitutional provisions fairly conceived as architectural probably must be taken to have a fixed meaning that it is the task of the faithful interpreter, whether a judge or anyone else, to identify and preserve).
    • Laurence H. Tribe, Comment, in SCALIA, supra note 38, at 93 (agreeing that many constitutional provisions fairly conceived as architectural "probably must be taken to have a fixed meaning that it is the task of the faithful interpreter, whether a judge or anyone else, to identify and preserve").
  • 119
    • 66449128990 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Perhaps relying on sentiments such as these, one commentator has recently observed that [i]t is common ground amongst originalists and non-originalists alike that the Constitution means what the Framers intended it to mean. Kavanagh, supra note 9, at 274;
    • Perhaps relying on sentiments such as these, one commentator has recently observed that "[i]t is common ground amongst originalists and non-originalists alike that the Constitution means what the Framers intended it to mean." Kavanagh, supra note 9, at 274;
  • 120
    • 66449130295 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. GOLDFORD, supra note 14, at 77. 78 ([N]onoriginalists tacitly accept the originalist premise that ['theconstitutional text'] and ['the original understanding of the constitutional text'] are equivalent ). I find this not only mistaken but truly inexplicable.
    • cf. GOLDFORD, supra note 14, at 77. 78 ("[N]onoriginalists tacitly accept the originalist premise that ['theconstitutional text'] and ['the original understanding of the constitutional text'] are equivalent "). I find this not only mistaken but truly inexplicable.
  • 121
    • 66449134117 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Parts II.B.l, III.B.2.
    • See infra Parts II.B.l, III.B.2.
  • 122
    • 66449106268 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, Barnett, supra note 4, at 615-17;
    • See, e.g., Barnett, supra note 4, at 615-17;
  • 123
    • 66449105995 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jonathan R. Macey,Originalism as an Ism, 19 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 301, 301 (1996) ([T]heveryconstitutional scholars who decry originalism most loudly rush to use originalist arguments when they serve their purposes.).
    • Jonathan R. Macey,Originalism as an "Ism," 19 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 301, 301 (1996) ("[T]heveryconstitutional scholars who decry originalism most loudly rush to use originalist arguments when they serve their purposes.").
  • 124
    • 66449111251 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Part I.C.2.
    • See infra Part I.C.2.
  • 126
    • 66449122962 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To escape the fallacy, one might propose that the originalism Greenberg and Litman have in mind in the first sentence cannot be strong originalism, for otherwise they would speak of, for example, the doctrine's contention, rather than its core notion. That is, the qualifier core might suggest that originalism, in the first sentence, is broader than strong originalism. And if so, then the originalism in the first sentence might be the same as it is in the third, namely moderate originalism. This route out of the fallacy won't work, for it depends on the odd claim that the core notion of moderate originalism is strong originalism.
    • To escape the fallacy, one might propose that the originalism Greenberg and Litman have in mind in the first sentence cannot be strong originalism, for otherwise they would speak of, for example, the "doctrine's contention," rather than its "core notion." That is, the qualifier core might suggest that originalism, in the first sentence, is broader than strong originalism. And if so, then the originalism in the first sentence might be the same as it is in the third, namely moderate originalism. This route out of the fallacy won't work, for it depends on the odd claim that "the core notion of moderate originalism is strong originalism."
  • 127
    • 66449101355 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reaching the same conclusion is BASSHAM, supra note 6, at 21.
    • Reaching the same conclusion is BASSHAM, supra note 6, at 21.
  • 128
    • 66449137734 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Originalism and Its Discontents (Plus a Thought or Two About Abortion), 24 CONST
    • See generally
    • See generally Mitchell N. Berman, Originalism and Its Discontents (Plus a Thought or Two About Abortion), 24 CONST. COMMENT. 383 (2007).
    • (2007) COMMENT , vol.383
    • Berman, M.N.1
  • 129
    • 66449110944 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The literature exploring how social movements affect constitutional change has exploded in recent years, propelled by the work of scholars such as Jack Balkin, Bill Eskridge, Willy Forbath, Robert Post, and Reva Siegel. For a recent discussion, see the Brennan Center Jorde Symposium on Constitutional Law, 94 CAL. L. REV. 1323 2006
    • The literature exploring how social movements affect constitutional change has exploded in recent years, propelled by the work of scholars such as Jack Balkin, Bill Eskridge, Willy Forbath, Robert Post, and Reva Siegel. For a recent discussion, see the Brennan Center Jorde Symposium on Constitutional Law, 94 CAL. L. REV. 1323 (2006).
  • 130
    • 34047195725 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Copious citation to the burgeoning scholarship can be found in the lead lecture of that symposium, Reva B. Siegel, Constitutional Culture, Social Movement Conflict and Constitutional Change: The Case of the De Facto ERA, 94 CAL. L. REV. 1323, 1328 n.13 (2006). For my money, it is in the descriptive analysis and normative theorizing of the two-way interaction between judicial and popular constitutional understanding, and not in its focus on extrajudicial constitutional understandings alone, that the trend toward popular constitutionalism is likely to prove most interesting and profitable.
    • Copious citation to the burgeoning scholarship can be found in the lead lecture of that symposium, Reva B. Siegel, Constitutional Culture, Social Movement Conflict and Constitutional Change: The Case of the De Facto ERA, 94 CAL. L. REV. 1323, 1328 n.13 (2006). For my money, it is in the descriptive analysis and normative theorizing of the two-way interaction between judicial and popular constitutional understanding, and not in its focus on extrajudicial constitutional understandings alone, that the trend toward "popular constitutionalism" is likely to prove most interesting and profitable.
  • 131
    • 34547574288 scopus 로고
    • Decision Rules and Conduct Rules: On Acoustic Separation in Criminal Law, 97
    • On acoustic separation, see generally
    • On "acoustic separation," see generally Meir Dan-Cohen, Decision Rules and Conduct Rules: On Acoustic Separation in Criminal Law, 97 HARV. L. REV. 625 (1984).
    • (1984) HARV. L. REV , vol.625
    • Dan-Cohen, M.1
  • 132
    • 66449095841 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Balkin, supra note 44, at 292, 338;
    • See Balkin, supra note 44, at 292, 338;
  • 133
    • 66449105439 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also, e.g., KERMIT ROOSEVELT III, THE MYTH OF JUDICIAL ACTIVISM: MAKING SENSE OF SUPREME COURT DECISIONS 47-52 (2006);
    • see also, e.g., KERMIT ROOSEVELT III, THE MYTH OF JUDICIAL ACTIVISM: MAKING SENSE OF SUPREME COURT DECISIONS 47-52 (2006);
  • 134
    • 66449089025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kavanagh, supra note 9, at 265
    • Kavanagh, supra note 9, at 265.
  • 135
    • 66449133766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Greenberg & Litman, supra note 60
    • See Greenberg & Litman, supra note 60.
  • 136
    • 66449132197 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This argument is elaborated in Berman, supra note 63, at 384-85
    • This argument is elaborated in Berman, supra note 63, at 384-85.
  • 137
    • 21744451134 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Importance of Humility in Judicial Review: A Comment on Ronald Dworkin's "Moral Reading" of the Constitution, 65
    • Michael W. McConnell, The Importance of Humility in Judicial Review: A Comment on Ronald Dworkin's "Moral Reading" of the Constitution, 65 FORDHAM L. REV. 1269, 1284 (1997).
    • (1997) FORDHAM L. REV , vol.1269 , pp. 1284
    • McConnell, M.W.1
  • 138
    • 66449113552 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Possibly the one partial exception to the latter assertion is Jed Rubenfeld, who has long urged that judges are obligated to follow originally intended applications of constitutional provisions, but asymmetrically. If the original purpose or understanding of a provision was to apply to some particular set of facts, he argues, then judges must abide by those foundational Application Understandings. In contrast, if the original understanding was that a provision would not apply to some particular set of facts, such foundational NoApplication Understandings can be freely disregarded. See generally JED RUBENFELD, REVOLUTION BY JUDICIARY: THE STRUCTURE OF AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW 2005, For example, because a foundational Application Understanding behind the First Amendment was to prohibit prior restraints, that particular expectation demands our continued fidelity. But
    • Possibly the one partial exception to the latter assertion is Jed Rubenfeld, who has long urged that judges are obligated to follow originally intended applications of constitutional provisions, but asymmetrically. If the original purpose or understanding of a provision was to apply to some particular set of facts, he argues, then judges must abide by those foundational "Application Understandings." In contrast, if the original understanding was that a provision would not apply to some particular set of facts, such foundational "NoApplication Understandings" can be freely disregarded. See generally JED RUBENFELD, REVOLUTION BY JUDICIARY: THE STRUCTURE OF AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW (2005). For example, because a foundational Application Understanding behind the First Amendment was to prohibit prior restraints, that particular expectation demands our continued fidelity. But that a No-Application Understanding might have been that the First Amendment did not protect nude dancing imposes no demand on contemporary constitutional interpreters. Although I am not ultimately persuaded that strong deference is owed even to Application Understandings, I emphatically exempt Rubenfeld's intriguing and provocative theory from my "bad view" verdict.
  • 139
    • 66449107060 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RONALD DWORKIN, A MATTER OF PRINCIPLE 57 (1985).
    • RONALD DWORKIN, A MATTER OF PRINCIPLE 57 (1985).
  • 140
    • 66449110731 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is Tribe's paraphrase of Dworkin. See Tribe, supra note 56, at 67
    • This is Tribe's paraphrase of Dworkin. See Tribe, supra note 56, at 67.
  • 141
    • 0346581461 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is a widely expressed sentiment, see, e.g., Sanford Levinson, The Limited Relevance of Originalism in the Actual Performance of Legal Roles, 19 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 495, 496 (1996) ([W]e are all originalists.);
    • It is a widely expressed sentiment, see, e.g., Sanford Levinson, The Limited Relevance of Originalism in the Actual Performance of Legal Roles, 19 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 495, 496 (1996) ("[W]e are all originalists.");
  • 142
    • 66449112678 scopus 로고
    • The Legitimacy of Particular Conceptions of Constitutional Interpretation, 11
    • Michael J. Perry, The Legitimacy of Particular Conceptions of Constitutional Interpretation, 11 VA. L. REV. 669, 718 (1991)
    • (1991) VA. L. REV , vol.669 , pp. 718
    • Perry, M.J.1
  • 143
    • 66449089405 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ([W]e are all originalists now-or should be.), but one that should provoke concern. As Gregory Bassham observed, In any important debate, whenever one side declares 'We are all x now,' it is a pretty safe bet that the debate has taken a wrong turn-or that someone is trying to pull a fast one. Gregory Bassham, Justice Scalia's Equitable Constitution, 33 J.C. & U.L. 143, 154 (2006). In my view, the we are all originalists claim takes several wrong turns, the most common being the failure to recognize the signal importance of what I have called the dimension of strength.
    • ("[W]e are all originalists now-or should be."), but one that should provoke concern. As Gregory Bassham observed, "In any important debate, whenever one side declares 'We are all x now,' it is a pretty safe bet that the debate has taken a wrong turn-or that someone is trying to pull a fast one." Gregory Bassham, Justice Scalia's Equitable Constitution, 33 J.C. & U.L. 143, 154 (2006). In my view, the "we are all originalists" claim takes several wrong turns, the most common being the failure to recognize the signal importance of what I have called the dimension of strength.
  • 144
    • 66449131937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Originalist Sin
    • See, e.g, May 5, at
    • See, e.g., Jeffrey Rosen, Originalist Sin, NEW REPUBLIC, May 5, 1997, at 26
    • (1997) NEW REPUBLIC , pp. 26
    • Rosen, J.1
  • 145
    • 66449105441 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (reviewing JACK N. RAKOVE ORIGINAL MEANINGS: POLITICS AND IDEAS IN THE MAKING OF THE CONSTITUTION (1996),
    • (reviewing JACK N. RAKOVE ORIGINAL MEANINGS: POLITICS AND IDEAS IN THE MAKING OF THE CONSTITUTION (1996),
  • 146
    • 66449096724 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and SCALIA, supra note 38 (We are all originalists now. That is to say, most judges and legal scholars who want to remain within the boundaries of respectable constitutional discourse agree that the original meaning of the Constitution and its amendments has some degree of pertinence to the question of what the Constitution means today.). If I'm right that what its advocates mean by originalism is strong originalism, then weak and moderate originalists are not originalists, in the relevant sense.
    • and SCALIA, supra note 38) ("We are all originalists now. That is to say, most judges and legal scholars who want to remain within the boundaries of respectable constitutional discourse agree that the original meaning of the Constitution and its amendments has some degree of pertinence to the question of what the Constitution means today."). If I'm right that what its advocates mean by "originalism" is strong originalism, then weak and moderate originalists are not originalists, in the relevant sense.
  • 147
    • 66449086055 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The issue I address here should not be confused with the related but distinct problem that arises when bona fide intentions turn out to conflict with each other. Consider Bork's famously unpersuasive effort to establish that Brown v. Board of Education is consistent with originalism. That argument claims that the original intent or understanding of the Equal Protection Clause incorporated the principle of equality, or equality before the law, and that the ratifiers intended to preserve racial segregation given their (mistaken) belief that it furnished such equality
    • The issue I address here should not be confused with the related but distinct problem that arises when bona fide intentions turn out to conflict with each other. Consider Bork's famously unpersuasive effort to establish that Brown v. Board of Education is consistent with originalism. That argument claims that the original intent or understanding of the Equal Protection Clause incorporated the principle of "equality," or "equality before the law," and that the ratifiers intended to preserve racial segregation given their (mistaken) belief that it furnished such equality.
  • 148
    • 66449114207 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BORK, supra note 20, at 81-83. This situation too might be said to present judges with a choice about which intent-the specific or the general-to privilege. In fact, I think cases such as this present a conflict between intended meaning and intended or expected applications and that all or almost all originalists arecommitted to the former. In any event, this type of situation is distinct from that in which an interpreter might wish to interpret some constitutional concept or principle at a level of abstraction different from what was originally meant or intended. I am focusing on the latter situation.
    • BORK, supra note 20, at 81-83. This situation too might be said to present judges with a choice about which intent-the specific or the general-to privilege. In fact, I think cases such as this present a conflict between intended meaning and intended or expected applications and that all or almost all originalists arecommitted to the former. In any event, this type of situation is distinct from that in which an interpreter might wish to interpret some constitutional concept or principle at a level of abstraction different from what was originally meant or intended. I am focusing on the latter situation.
  • 149
    • 66449114510 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., BORK, supra note 20, at 149 (The role of a judge committed to the philosophy of original understanding is not to 'choose a level of abstraction.' [A] judge should state the principle at the level of generality that the text and historical evidence warrant.);
    • See, e.g., BORK, supra note 20, at 149 ("The role of a judge committed to the philosophy of original understanding is not to 'choose a level of abstraction.' [A] judge should state the principle at the level of generality that the text and historical evidence warrant.");
  • 150
    • 66449103172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WHITTINGTON, supra note 14, at 187 ([T]he search for intention must be guided by the historical evidence itself. The level of generality at which terms were defined is not an a priori theoretical question but a contextualized historical one.).
    • WHITTINGTON, supra note 14, at 187 ("[T]he search for intention must be guided by the historical evidence itself. The level of generality at which terms were defined is not an a priori theoretical question but a contextualized historical one.").
  • 151
    • 84963456897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 23 and accompanying text
    • See supra note 23 and accompanying text.
    • See supra
  • 152
    • 66449098652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Nelson, supra note 38, at 547 ([M]embers of the founding generation do not seem to have anticipated constant reinterpretation of the Constitution[T]hey expected subsequent practice to liquidate the indeterminacy and to produce a fixed meaning for the future.).
    • See generally Nelson, supra note 38, at 547 ("[M]embers of the founding generation do not seem to have anticipated constant reinterpretation of the Constitution[T]hey expected subsequent practice to liquidate the indeterminacy and to produce a fixed meaning for the future.").
  • 153
    • 66449108183 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Whittington, supra note 15, at 611 ([I]t is entirely possible that the principles that the founders meant to embody in the text were fairly abstract. It is also possible that the founders merely meant to delegate discretion to future decisionmakers to act on a given subject matter with very little guidance). In correspondence, Dick Fallon questions whether all Originalists need accept this possibility. That they might not, he offers, suggests another dimension of variability within originalist logical space.
    • See, e.g., Whittington, supra note 15, at 611 ("[I]t is entirely possible that the principles that the founders meant to embody in the text were fairly abstract. It is also possible that the founders merely meant to delegate discretion to future decisionmakers to act on a given subject matter with very little guidance"). In correspondence, Dick Fallon questions whether all Originalists need accept this possibility. That they might not, he offers, suggests another dimension of variability within originalist logical space.
  • 154
    • 66449108755 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • E-mail from Richard H. Fallon, Jr., Ralph S. Tyler, Jr. Professor of Constitutional Law, Harvard Law School, to author (Feb. 5, 2008, 15:24 CST) (on file with the New York University Law Review).
    • E-mail from Richard H. Fallon, Jr., Ralph S. Tyler, Jr. Professor of Constitutional Law, Harvard Law School, to author (Feb. 5, 2008, 15:24 CST) (on file with the New York University Law Review).
  • 155
    • 66449094205 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Rosenthal, supra note 4, at 2 (arguing that original understanding of Due Process Clause was as directive for courts to evolve common law of requisite procedures for deprivation of liberty and property interests).
    • Cf. Rosenthal, supra note 4, at 2 (arguing that original understanding of Due Process Clause was as directive for courts to evolve common law of requisite procedures for deprivation of liberty and property interests).
  • 156
    • 66449127824 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Still, it is an overstatement to conclude that [t]his move from specific intentions to general principles eliminates any meaningful distinction between originalism and nonoriginalism. Eric J. Segall, A Century Lost: The End of the Originalism Debate, 15 CONST. COMMENT. 411, 432 (1998).
    • Still, it is an overstatement to conclude that "[t]his move from specific intentions to general principles eliminates any meaningful distinction between originalism and nonoriginalism." Eric J. Segall, A Century Lost: The End of the Originalism Debate, 15 CONST. COMMENT. 411, 432 (1998).
  • 157
    • 66449108184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gary Lawson is perhaps the best example. See generally, e.g., Gary Lawson, On Reading Recipes and Constitutions, 85 GEO. L.J. 1823 (1997).
    • Gary Lawson is perhaps the best example. See generally, e.g., Gary Lawson, On Reading Recipes and Constitutions, 85 GEO. L.J. 1823 (1997).
  • 158
    • 66449107729 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Solum, supra note 39
    • Solum, supra note 39.
  • 159
    • 66449088216 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Antonin Scalia, Originalism: The Lesser Evil, 57 U. CIN. L. REV. 849, 862 (1989).
    • See, e.g., Antonin Scalia, Originalism: The Lesser Evil, 57 U. CIN. L. REV. 849, 862 (1989).
  • 160
    • 66449129151 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Condition (b) is required by the fact that everybody recognizes that stare decisis is not an inexorable command, especially in constitutional cases. For Scalia's views of constitutional stare decisis, see, for example, BMW of North America, Inc. v. Gore, 517 U.S. 559, 599 (1996) (Scalia, J., dissenting), Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pennsylvania v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 982-83 (1992) (Scalia, J. concurring in judgment in part and dissenting in part), and Walton v. Arizona, 497 U.S. 639, 672-73 (1990) (Scalia, J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment).
    • Condition (b) is required by the fact that everybody recognizes that stare decisis is not an inexorable command, especially in constitutional cases. For Scalia's views of constitutional stare decisis, see, for example, BMW of North America, Inc. v. Gore, 517 U.S. 559, 599 (1996) (Scalia, J., dissenting), Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pennsylvania v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 982-83 (1992) (Scalia, J. concurring in judgment in part and dissenting in part), and Walton v. Arizona, 497 U.S. 639, 672-73 (1990) (Scalia, J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment).
  • 161
    • 66449113831 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Can Originalism Be Reconciled with Precedent? A Symposium on Stare Decisis, 22 CONST. COMMENT. 257 (2005).
    • See, e.g., Can Originalism Be Reconciled with Precedent? A Symposium on Stare Decisis, 22 CONST. COMMENT. 257 (2005).
  • 162
    • 66449093585 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The argument that many judicial constitutional precedents are irreversible and that stare decisis thus presents a challenge to originalism was perhaps first pressed in Henry Paul Monaghan, Stare Decisis and Constitutional Adjudication, 88 COLUM. L. REV. 723 1988
    • The argument that many judicial constitutional precedents are irreversible and that stare decisis thus presents a challenge to originalism was perhaps first pressed in Henry Paul Monaghan, Stare Decisis and Constitutional Adjudication, 88 COLUM. L. REV. 723 (1988).
  • 163
    • 66449132192 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It was contested in Gary Lawson, The Constitutional Case Against Precedent, 17 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 23 (1994).
    • It was contested in Gary Lawson, The Constitutional Case Against Precedent, 17 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 23 (1994).
  • 164
    • 66449135014 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The classic study is EVERETT SOMERVILLE BROWN, THE CONSTITUTIONAL HISTORY OF THE LOUISIANA PURCHASE: 1803-1812 (1920).
    • The classic study is EVERETT SOMERVILLE BROWN, THE CONSTITUTIONAL HISTORY OF THE LOUISIANA PURCHASE: 1803-1812 (1920).
  • 165
    • 0037228366 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a recent argument (challenging conventional wisdom) that Jefferson's own doubts on this score were well founded, see generally Robert Knowles, The Balance of Forces and the Empire of Liberty: States' Rights and the Louisiana Purchase, 88 IOWA L. REV. 343 (2003).
    • For a recent argument (challenging conventional wisdom) that Jefferson's own doubts on this score were well founded, see generally Robert Knowles, The Balance of Forces and the Empire of Liberty: States' Rights and the Louisiana Purchase, 88 IOWA L. REV. 343 (2003).
  • 166
    • 66449135301 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., James E. Ryan, Does It Take a Theory? Originalism, Active Liberty, and Minimalism, 58 STAN. L. REV. 1623, 1628 n.31, 1631 (2006) (intimating that Scalia views stare decisis as only exception to Originalism).
    • See, e.g., James E. Ryan, Does It Take a Theory? Originalism, Active Liberty, and Minimalism, 58 STAN. L. REV. 1623, 1628 n.31, 1631 (2006) (intimating that Scalia views stare decisis as only exception to Originalism).
  • 167
    • 66449130292 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See SCALIA, supra note 38, at 138-40 (acknowledging that some judicial precedents are effectively irreversible, and urging that stare decisis is not part of [his] originalist philosophy; it is a pragmatic exception to it).
    • See SCALIA, supra note 38, at 138-40 (acknowledging that some judicial precedents "are effectively irreversible," and urging that "stare decisis is not part of [his] originalist philosophy; it is a pragmatic exception to it").
  • 168
    • 66449105131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scalia, supra note 82, at 861
    • Scalia, supra note 82, at 861.
  • 169
    • 66449106797 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 170
    • 33846270376 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Randy Barnett notes, Scalia proves unfaithful to the original meaning of the text in yet a third way: [H]e is willing to ignore the original meaning of those portions of the Constitution that do not meet his criteria of the rule of law as the law of rules. Randy E. Barnett, Scalia's Infidelity: A Critique of Faint-Hearted Originalism, 75 U. CIN. L. REV. 7, 13 2006, Barnett is surely right that, when original meaning is not sufficiently rule-like to suit his tastes, Scalia often abandons the former in favor of more rule-like doctrine that better constrains judges in future cases. However, I'm disposed to treat this fact, not as a qualification to, or modification of, his basal commitment to Originalism, but as evidence that, at root, Scalia is not truly an Originalist but rather a rulist
    • As Randy Barnett notes, Scalia "proves unfaithful to the original meaning of the text" in yet a third way: "[H]e is willing to ignore the original meaning of those portions of the Constitution that do not meet his criteria of the rule of law as the law of rules." Randy E. Barnett, Scalia's Infidelity: A Critique of "Faint-Hearted" Originalism, 75 U. CIN. L. REV. 7, 13 (2006). Barnett is surely right that, when original meaning is not sufficiently rule-like to suit his tastes, Scalia often abandons the former in favor of more rule-like doctrine that better constrains judges in future cases. However, I'm disposed to treat this fact, not as a qualification to, or modification of, his basal commitment to Originalism, but as evidence that, at root, Scalia is not truly an Originalist but rather a rulist.
  • 171
    • 65349115630 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constitutional Precedent Viewed Through the Lens of Hartian Positivist Jurisprudence, 86
    • See, e.g
    • See, e.g., Richard H. Fallon, Jr., Constitutional Precedent Viewed Through the Lens of Hartian Positivist Jurisprudence, 86 N.C. L. REV. 1107, 1132 (2008).
    • (2008) N.C. L. REV , vol.1107 , pp. 1132
    • Fallon Jr., R.H.1
  • 172
    • 66449103437 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mark Greenberg, The Standard Picture and Its Discontents 5 (UCLA Sch. of Law Research Paper No. 08-07, 2008), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1103569.
    • Mark Greenberg, The Standard Picture and Its Discontents 5 (UCLA Sch. of Law Research Paper No. 08-07, 2008), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1103569.
  • 173
    • 66449121796 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 8
    • Id. at 8.
  • 174
    • 66449135582 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 10
    • Id. at 10.
  • 175
    • 66449093888 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is an observation made frequently by my colleague Sandy Levinson. See, e.g, Sanford Levinson, Why Professor Lynch Asks the Right Questions, 31 SETON HALL L. REV. 45, 48 2000
    • This is an observation made frequently by my colleague Sandy Levinson. See, e.g., Sanford Levinson, Why Professor Lynch Asks the Right Questions, 31 SETON HALL L. REV. 45, 48 (2000).
  • 177
    • 66449109902 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Greenberg's view, incidentally, the standard picture is a naive oversimplification. Rather, he would view the content of law as a complex function of, or operation upon, legal sources. Determining what the law is, then, depends upon the successful completion of at least three fairly discrete tasks: identifying legal sources; interpreting these sources to ascertain their meanings; and combining or integrating these meanings, or these sources, to constitute the law. On this jurisprudential account, there is no one-to-one relationship between a legal text and the law, thereby (it seems to me) problematizing the very concept of constitutional law. That is, constitutional law is distinguished from other forms of law, not in the simple way that it is the meaning (semantic, linguistic, or legal) of the Constitution, but in a more functional sense as being the supreme law. Though I won't pursue the issue further, it seems plain to me that to adopt this view would make the Originalist
    • On Greenberg's view, incidentally, the standard picture is a naive oversimplification. Rather, he would view the content of law as a complex function of, or operation upon, legal sources. Determining what the law is, then, depends upon the successful completion of at least three fairly discrete tasks: identifying legal sources; interpreting these sources to ascertain their meanings; and combining or integrating these meanings, or these sources, to constitute the law. On this jurisprudential account, there is no one-to-one relationship between a legal text and the law, thereby (it seems to me) problematizing the very concept of constitutional law. That is, constitutional law is distinguished from other forms of law, not in the simple way that it is the meaning (semantic, linguistic, or legal) of the Constitution, but in a more functional sense as being the supreme law. Though I won't pursue the issue further, it seems plain to me that to adopt this view would make the Originalist case harder not easier. Surely one who extols Originalism as a means to limit judicial subjectivity is not likely to smile on a theory that recognizes multiple sources of constitutional law.
  • 178
    • 66449093886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Barnett, supra note 4, at 650;
    • Cf. Barnett, supra note 4, at 650;
  • 179
    • 66449093582 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Farber, supra note 1, at 1097 ([A]n originalist might take into account not only judicial precedents but also the changing views of those adopting later constitutional provisions. For example, those who ratified the fourteenth amendment's due process clause may have had a broader concept of the meaning of due process than their predecessors who adopted the fifth amendment's due process clause. Yet it would be incongruous to give the two due process clauses different interpretations today.);
    • Farber, supra note 1, at 1097 ("[A]n originalist might take into account not only judicial precedents but also the changing views of those adopting later constitutional provisions. For example, those who ratified the fourteenth amendment's due process clause may have had a broader concept of the meaning of due process than their predecessors who adopted the fifth amendment's due process clause. Yet it would be incongruous to give the two due process clauses different interpretations today.");
  • 180
    • 66449137143 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tribe, supra note 56, at 86-87.One recently proposed solution that I do feel confident in rejecting is that the original meaning of a constitutional amendment is constituted by the hypothetical understandings of a reasonable person at the time of ratification of the 1787 Constitution.
    • Tribe, supra note 56, at 86-87.One recently proposed solution that I do feel confident in rejecting is that the original meaning of a constitutional amendment is constituted by the hypothetical understandings of a reasonable person at the time of ratification of the 1787 Constitution.
  • 181
    • 66449110452 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Lawson & Seidman, supra note 19, at 75-76 (Though the matter is hardly free of doubt, we offer the suggestion that the reasonable person of 1788-the original 'We the People of the United States'-is the reference point for all interpretative issues until the document itself otherwise specifies.).
    • See Lawson & Seidman, supra note 19, at 75-76 ("Though the matter is hardly free of doubt, we offer the suggestion that the reasonable person of 1788-the original 'We the People of the United States'-is the reference point for all interpretative issues until the document itself otherwise specifies.").
  • 182
    • 66449113223 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This strikes me as a fair characterization of extant arguments for Originalism. I do not want to insist, though, that there is no possible room for arguments that are not most fairly classified as consequentialist and yet that are more perspicuously viewed as soft than as hard. See infra note 198 and accompanying text
    • This strikes me as a fair characterization of extant arguments for Originalism. I do not want to insist, though, that there is no possible room for arguments that are not most fairly classified as consequentialist and yet that are more perspicuously viewed as soft than as hard. See infra note 198 and accompanying text.
  • 183
    • 66449121801 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • And keep in mind that the hard/soft distinction is advanced only as a potentially useful classificatory tool. The core argument of this Article-that existing arguments for Originalism are extremely unpersuasive and that the likelihood of ultimately successful arguments is remote-does not depend upon it. See supra note 28.
    • And keep in mind that the hard/soft distinction is advanced only as a potentially useful classificatory tool. The core argument of this Article-that existing arguments for Originalism are extremely unpersuasive and that the likelihood of ultimately successful arguments is remote-does not depend upon it. See supra note 28.
  • 184
    • 66449133166 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Many theorists have conceived of constitutional adjudication as consisting of two distinct steps, both prior to the application of law to facts to reach a case-specific holding. Originalists like Keith Whittington and Randy Barnett, for example, argue that when constitutional interpretation produces meaning that is vague or ambiguous, other legal actors, including judges, can make the law more determinate through a process of constitutional construction. See generally KEITH E. WHITTINGTON, CONSTITUTIONAL CONSTRUCTION (1999);
    • Many theorists have conceived of constitutional adjudication as consisting of two distinct steps, both prior to the application of law to facts to reach a case-specific holding. Originalists like Keith Whittington and Randy Barnett, for example, argue that when constitutional interpretation produces meaning that is vague or ambiguous, other legal actors, including judges, can make the law more determinate through a process of "constitutional construction." See generally KEITH E. WHITTINGTON, CONSTITUTIONAL CONSTRUCTION (1999);
  • 185
    • 66449092436 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Barnett, supra note 4. Kim Roosevelt and I have argued that courts often (and permissibly) craft decision rules that facilitate the case-by-case application of courtinterpreted constitutional meaning by minimizing some of the costs produced by the fact that constitutional law is judicially enforced.
    • Barnett, supra note 4. Kim Roosevelt and I have argued that courts often (and permissibly) craft "decision rules" that facilitate the case-by-case application of courtinterpreted constitutional meaning by minimizing some of the costs produced by the fact that constitutional law is judicially enforced.
  • 186
    • 66449127825 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ROOSEVELT, supra note 66, at ch. 2;
    • See ROOSEVELT, supra note 66, at ch. 2;
  • 187
    • 1842664236 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constitutional Decision Rules, 90
    • Mitchell N. Berman, Constitutional Decision Rules, 90 VA. L. REV. 1 (2004);
    • (2004) VA. L. REV , vol.1
    • Berman, M.N.1
  • 188
    • 66449091122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Mitchell N. Berman, Aspirational Rights and the Two-Output Thesis, 119 HARV. L. REV. F. 220, 221 (2006), http://www.harvardlawreview.org/forum/issues/119/march06/berman.pdf ([J]udicial review requires devices that direct courts how to decide whether [judgedetermined constitutional] meaning is met.).
    • see also Mitchell N. Berman, Aspirational Rights and the Two-Output Thesis, 119 HARV. L. REV. F. 220, 221 (2006), http://www.harvardlawreview.org/forum/issues/119/march06/berman.pdf ("[J]udicial review requires devices that direct courts how to decide whether [judgedetermined constitutional] meaning is met.").
  • 189
    • 66449114832 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dick Fallon, Henry Monaghan, and Larry Sager have advanced broadly similar accounts of how courts refine or supplement constitutional norms or propositions. See RICHARD H. FALLON, JR., IMPLEMENTING THE CONSTITUTION 1-12, 76-77 (2001) (distinguishing constitutional norms from implementing doctrine);
    • Dick Fallon, Henry Monaghan, and Larry Sager have advanced broadly similar accounts of how courts refine or supplement constitutional norms or propositions. See RICHARD H. FALLON, JR., IMPLEMENTING THE CONSTITUTION 1-12, 76-77 (2001) (distinguishing constitutional norms from implementing doctrine);
  • 190
    • 38949116558 scopus 로고
    • The Supreme Court, 1974 Term-Foreword: Constitutional Common Law, 89
    • distinguishing constitutional common law from Marbury-shielded constitutional exegesis
    • Henry P. Monaghan, The Supreme Court, 1974 Term-Foreword: Constitutional Common Law, 89 HARV. L. REV. 1, 30-31 (1975) (distinguishing "constitutional common law" from "Marbury-shielded constitutional exegesis");
    • (1975) HARV. L. REV , vol.1 , pp. 30-31
    • Monaghan, H.P.1
  • 191
    • 66449089027 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lawrence Gene Sager, Fair Measure: The Legal Status of Underenforced Constitutional Norms, 91 HARV. L. REV. 1212, 1213-14 (1978) (distinguishing judge-announced [institutional] constructs from consti-tutional norms). All such accounts, I believe, recognize two conceptually distinct stages of constitutional adjudication (even if the courts rarely expressly distinguish the two in the course of their opinions). When I speak of constitutional interpretation, I am referring to the initial and conceptually distinct step of deriving legal meaning or legal content from the constitutional text.
    • Lawrence Gene Sager, Fair Measure: The Legal Status of Underenforced Constitutional Norms, 91 HARV. L. REV. 1212, 1213-14 (1978) (distinguishing judge-announced "[institutional] constructs" from "consti-tutional norms"). All such accounts, I believe, recognize two conceptually distinct stages of constitutional adjudication (even if the courts rarely expressly distinguish the two in the course of their opinions). When I speak of constitutional "interpretation," I am referring to the initial and conceptually distinct step of deriving legal meaning or legal content from the constitutional text.
  • 192
    • 66449090282 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a compact and reasonably accessible overview of debates over interpretation in philosophy and literary theory, see GUYORA BINDER & ROBERT WEISBERG, LITERARY CRITICISMS OF LAW ch. 2 2000
    • For a compact and reasonably accessible overview of debates over interpretation in philosophy and literary theory, see GUYORA BINDER & ROBERT WEISBERG, LITERARY CRITICISMS OF LAW ch. 2 (2000).
  • 193
    • 66449085784 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Symposium, Interpretation, 58 S. CAL. L. REV. 1 (1985). An excellent electronic source is the Johns Hopkins Online Guide to Literary Theory and Criticism, http://litguide.press.jhu.edu/ (last visited Feb. 22, 2009).
    • See also Symposium, Interpretation, 58 S. CAL. L. REV. 1 (1985). An excellent electronic source is the Johns Hopkins Online Guide to Literary Theory and Criticism, http://litguide.press.jhu.edu/ (last visited Feb. 22, 2009).
  • 194
    • 66449117107 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • M2 See infra note 103.
    • M2 See infra note 103.
  • 196
    • 66449083165 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As this passage suggests, Knapp and Michaels are best read to take the first position identified in the text accompanying supra note 102
    • As this passage suggests, Knapp and Michaels are best read to take the first position identified in the text accompanying supra note 102.
  • 197
    • 66449098403 scopus 로고
    • generally Steven Knapp & Walter Benn Michaels, A Reply to Our Critics, 9
    • further developing this position, In doing so, they part ways with their intentionalist predecessor E.D. Hirsch who, they say, adopts the second
    • See also generally Steven Knapp & Walter Benn Michaels, A Reply to Our Critics, 9 CRITICAL INQUIRY 790 (1983) (further developing this position). In doing so, they part ways with their intentionalist predecessor E.D. Hirsch who, they say, adopts the second.
    • (1983) CRITICAL INQUIRY , vol.790
  • 198
    • 66449116810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally E.D. HIRSCH, JR., VALIDITY IN INTERPRETATION (1967).
    • See generally E.D. HIRSCH, JR., VALIDITY IN INTERPRETATION (1967).
  • 199
    • 62749138931 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intention Is All There Is: A Critical Analysis of Aharon Barak's Purposive Interpretation in Law, 29
    • Stanley Fish, Intention Is All There Is: A Critical Analysis of Aharon Barak's Purposive Interpretation in Law, 29 CARDOZO L. REV. 1109, 1127 (2008).
    • (2008) CARDOZO L. REV , vol.1109 , pp. 1127
    • Fish, S.1
  • 200
    • 66449127292 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1122. Oddly, Fish's greatest fame as a literary theorist derives from his role as a proponent of reader-response criticism, which is usually understood to be firmly antiintentionalist. In a postscript to a recent French edition of his famous collection of essays, Is There a Text in This Class?, however, Fish explains that his earlier work erroneously conflated descriptive and normative accounts of interpretation.
    • Id. at 1122. Oddly, Fish's greatest fame as a literary theorist derives from his role as a proponent of reader-response criticism, which is usually understood to be firmly antiintentionalist. In a postscript to a recent French edition of his famous collection of essays, Is There a Text in This Class?, however, Fish explains that his earlier work erroneously conflated descriptive and normative accounts of interpretation.
  • 201
    • 84868937178 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See STANLEY EUGENE FISH, Postscript to QUAND LIRE C'EST FAIRE: L'AUTORITÉ DES COMMUNAUTÉS INTERPRETATIVES [IS THERE A TEXT IN THIS CLASS? THE AUTHORITY OF INTERPRETIVE COMMUNITIES] (Etienne Dobenesque trans., 2007).
    • See STANLEY EUGENE FISH, Postscript to QUAND LIRE C'EST FAIRE: L'AUTORITÉ DES COMMUNAUTÉS INTERPRETATIVES [IS THERE A TEXT IN THIS CLASS? THE AUTHORITY OF INTERPRETIVE COMMUNITIES] (Etienne Dobenesque trans., 2007).
  • 202
    • 66449099536 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • His present view is that interpretive communities do drive what is taken as a successful interpretation in any given time and place but that the true or correct interpretation is always and necessarily the meaning that the author intended. See id
    • His present view is that interpretive communities do drive what is taken as a successful interpretation in any given time and place but that the true or correct interpretation is always and necessarily the meaning that the author intended. See id.
  • 203
    • 66449085179 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I don't describe the converse as necessarily false only because intentionalism does not itself have anything to say about whether and when somebody should endeavor to interpret a text. A constitutional theorist who embraces intentionalism but who rejects the view (common though it is) that the appropriate relationship between court-announced constitutional law and the constitutional text is properly described as involving interpretation need not be an Originalist. See infra note 109.
    • I don't describe the converse as necessarily false only because intentionalism does not itself have anything to say about whether and when somebody should endeavor to interpret a text. A constitutional theorist who embraces intentionalism but who rejects the view (common though it is) that the appropriate relationship between court-announced constitutional law and the constitutional text is properly described as involving interpretation need not be an Originalist. See infra note 109.
  • 204
    • 66449115423 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Graglia, supra note 23, at 1024;
    • Graglia, supra note 23, at 1024;
  • 206
    • 66449130566 scopus 로고
    • Three Mistakes About Interpretation, 92
    • T]he meaning of a text is always what its authors intended it to mean
    • Paul Campos, Three Mistakes About Interpretation, 92 MICH. L. REV. 388, 397 (1993) ("[T]he meaning of a text is always what its authors intended it to mean .").
    • (1993) MICH. L. REV , vol.388 , pp. 397
    • Campos, P.1
  • 207
    • 66449083721 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although intentionalists necessarily focus on the intentions of the text's authors and therefore favor intent over public meaning, it does not necessarily follow that they urge inquiry into the intent of the framers as opposed to that of the ratifiers. It all depends on whom we identify as the Constitution's authors. If we conceive of the author as the ratifiers, then intentionalism can support original ratifiers' intent originalism. See, e.g, Larry Alexander, All or Nothing at All? The Intentions of Authorities and the Authority of Intentions [hereinafter Alexander, All or Nothing at All, in LAW AND INTERPRETATION: ESSAYS IN LEGAL PHILOSOPHY 357, 363 (Andrei Marmor ed, 1995, hereinafter LAW AND INTERPRETATION, arguing that meaning intended by authorities who author legal text should control);
    • Although intentionalists necessarily focus on the intentions of the text's authors and therefore favor intent over public meaning, it does not necessarily follow that they urge inquiry into the intent of the framers as opposed to that of the ratifiers. It all depends on whom we identify as the Constitution's authors. If we conceive of the author as the ratifiers, then intentionalism can support original ratifiers' intent originalism. See, e.g., Larry Alexander, All or Nothing at All? The Intentions of Authorities and the Authority of Intentions [hereinafter Alexander, All or Nothing at All?], in LAW AND INTERPRETATION: ESSAYS IN LEGAL PHILOSOPHY 357, 363 (Andrei Marmor ed., 1995) [hereinafter LAW AND INTERPRETATION] (arguing that meaning intended by authorities who author legal text should control);
  • 208
    • 66449104276 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Not a Matter of Interpretation, 42
    • Njothing in the logic of interpretation itself can tell us which of those stages [of drafting, ratification, and judicial review] should count as the one that confers on the text the meaning we are trying to interpret
    • Steven Knapp & Walter Benn Michaels, Not a Matter of Interpretation, 42 SAN DIEGO L. REV. 651, 667 (2005) ("[Njothing in the logic of interpretation itself can tell us which of those stages [of drafting, ratification, and judicial review] should count as the one that confers on the text the meaning we are trying to interpret.").
    • (2005) SAN DIEGO L. REV , vol.651 , pp. 667
    • Knapp, S.1    Benn Michaels, W.2
  • 209
    • 0347936426 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Larry Alexander, Originalism, or Who Is Fred, 19 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 321, 325-26 (1996, seeming to endorse possibility that persons whose intentions count for purposes of constitutional interpretation could be neither framers nor ratifiers but rather average speakers of English in 1787, This point will bear greater significance later. In any event, whether the authors whose intentions intentionalist-Originalists seek to discover are the framers or the ratifiers or somebody else, intentionalist-Originalists focus on subjective intentions, not objective public meanings. Yet, surprisingly, one prominent Originalist seems to deny precisely that. Michael Paulsen has recently protested that it is a caricature of originalism to portray it as a version of crude intentionalism that focuses on the specific subjective intentions or expectations of individuals as to how a provision might be applied. I
    • But see Larry Alexander, Originalism, or Who Is Fred?, 19 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 321, 325-26 (1996) (seeming to endorse possibility that persons whose intentions count for purposes of constitutional interpretation could be neither framers nor ratifiers but rather average speakers of English in 1787). This point will bear greater significance later. In any event, whether the "authors" whose intentions intentionalist-Originalists seek to discover are the framers or the ratifiers (or somebody else), intentionalist-Originalists focus on subjective intentions, not objective public meanings. Yet, surprisingly, one prominent Originalist seems to deny precisely that. Michael Paulsen has recently protested that it is "a caricature of originalism" to portray it as "a version of crude intentionalism that focuses on the specific subjective intentions or expectations of individuals as to how a provision might be applied." Instead, he says, originalists "focus[ ] on the objective linguistic meaning of the words of a text (taken in historical context)."
  • 210
    • 66449110736 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paulsen, supra note 23, at 2059
    • Paulsen, supra note 23, at 2059.
  • 211
    • 66449111793 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is a false dichotomy. As I have already suggested, see supra Part I.C.2, Paulsen is right to deny that contemporary originalists focus on the subjectively intended or expected applications of the text. But he is wrong to suggest that it follows that contemporary originalism is focused exclusively on public meaning and not subjective intentions. It does not follow because authors can have intentions about applications and intentions about meaning, and these need not be the same thing
    • This is a false dichotomy. As I have already suggested, see supra Part I.C.2, Paulsen is right to deny that contemporary originalists focus on the subjectively intended or expected applications of the text. But he is wrong to suggest that it follows that contemporary originalism is focused exclusively on public meaning and not subjective intentions. It does not follow because authors can have intentions about applications and intentions about meaning, and these need not be the same thing.
  • 212
    • 66449100234 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally BASSHAM, supra note 6, at 29 (distinguishing among an author's scope beliefs, counterfactual scope beliefs, and semantic intentions);
    • See generally BASSHAM, supra note 6, at 29 (distinguishing among an author's scope beliefs, counterfactual scope beliefs, and semantic intentions);
  • 213
    • 66449134398 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McConnell, supra note 69, at 1284-85 (criticizing Dworkin for failing to distinguish between framers' expectations about specific applications and moral and political principles they intended to express). Not only does the conclusion not logically follow, it is empirically false.
    • McConnell, supra note 69, at 1284-85 (criticizing Dworkin for failing to distinguish between framers' "expectations about specific applications" and "moral and political principles they intended to express"). Not only does the conclusion not logically follow, it is empirically false.
  • 214
    • 66449128114 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Lawson & Seidman, supra note 19, at 49 n.12 (recognizing that [t]here are notable dissenters who continue to focus on concrete historical intentions rather than public meaning).
    • See, e.g., Lawson & Seidman, supra note 19, at 49 n.12 (recognizing that "[t]here are notable dissenters who continue to focus on concrete historical intentions" rather than public meaning).
  • 215
    • 66449128113 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To be sure, this view does not present originalism as inescapable, full stop. It is not internal to an intentionalist theory of constitutional interpretation that courts engaging in constitutional adjudication must engage in constitutional interpretation. The possibility remains, for example, that constitutional adjudication ought to proceed without regard for the Constitution's meaning, that we could have constitutional adjudication without constitutional interpretation. A view of this sort still qualifies as a form of hard originalism, however, for I have defined that term to encompass, in addition to the (super hard) view that originalist interpretation follows from either necessary or conceptual truths, the (ordinary hard) possibility that such interpretation is logically necessary given a set of premises that, while not themselves necessary, are in fact noncontroversial
    • To be sure, this view does not present originalism as inescapable, full stop. It is not internal to an intentionalist theory of constitutional interpretation that courts engaging in constitutional adjudication must engage in constitutional interpretation. The possibility remains, for example, that constitutional adjudication ought to proceed without regard for the Constitution's meaning, that we could have constitutional adjudication without constitutional interpretation. A view of this sort still qualifies as a form of hard originalism, however, for I have defined that term to encompass, in addition to the (super hard) view that originalist interpretation follows from either necessary or conceptual truths, the (ordinary hard) possibility that such interpretation is logically necessary given a set of premises that, while not themselves necessary, are in fact noncontroversial.
  • 216
    • 0346044959 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paul F. Campos, A Text Is Just a Text, 19 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 327, 327-28 (1996);
    • Paul F. Campos, A Text Is Just a Text, 19 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 327, 327-28 (1996);
  • 217
    • 66449127558 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also, e.g., STEVEN D. SMITH, LAW'S QUANDARY 106-07 (2004) (discussing inter-pretation of recipe);
    • see also, e.g., STEVEN D. SMITH, LAW'S QUANDARY 106-07 (2004) (discussing inter-pretation of recipe);
  • 218
    • 33646858686 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • is That English You're Speaking? Why Intention Free Interpretation Is an Impossibility, 41
    • discussing interpretation of order in restaurant
    • Larry Alexander & Saikrishna Prakash, "is That English You're Speaking?" Why Intention Free Interpretation Is an Impossibility, 41 SAN DIEGO L. REV. 967, 975 (2004) (discussing interpretation of order in restaurant).
    • (2004) SAN DIEGO L. REV , vol.967 , pp. 975
    • Alexander, L.1    Prakash, S.2
  • 219
    • 66449095166 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This point is forcefully emphasized in, for example, Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, Word Meaning in Legal Interpretation, 42 SAN DIEGO L. REV. 465, 468 2005
    • This point is forcefully emphasized in, for example, Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, Word Meaning in Legal Interpretation, 42 SAN DIEGO L. REV. 465, 468 (2005).
  • 220
    • 66449119557 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Even the New Critics who launched the assault on intentionalism in the first half of the last century were arguing about how to interpret literary works. They acknowledged that many texts ought to be interpreted in accordance with the apparent intent of their authors. See, e.g., BINDER & WEISBERG, supra note 101, at 117.
    • Even the New Critics who launched the assault on intentionalism in the first half of the last century were arguing about how to interpret literary works. They acknowledged that many texts ought to be interpreted in accordance with the apparent intent of their authors. See, e.g., BINDER & WEISBERG, supra note 101, at 117.
  • 221
    • 66449123264 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As the prominent New Critic Monroe Beardsley emphasized: No one can deny that there are many practical occasions on which our task is precisely to try to discover authorial meaning, or intention: When there is a difficulty in reading a will or a love letter, or in grasping an oral promise or instruction, our primary concern is with authorial meaning. MONROE C. BEARDSLEY, THE POSSIBILITY OF CRITICISM 31 (1970).
    • As the prominent New Critic Monroe Beardsley emphasized: No one can deny that there are many practical occasions on which our task is precisely to try to discover authorial meaning, or intention: When there is a difficulty in reading a will or a love letter, or in grasping an oral promise or instruction, our primary concern is with authorial meaning. MONROE C. BEARDSLEY, THE POSSIBILITY OF CRITICISM 31 (1970).
  • 222
    • 66449100523 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part I.B.2.
    • See supra Part I.B.2.
  • 223
    • 66449102630 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The most familiar distinction, initially proposed by Paul Grice half a century ago, lies between speaker's meaning and sentence meaning. See PAUL GRICE, STUDIES IN THE WAY OF WORDS chs. 5-6 (1989). Yet theorists continue to debate exactly how Grice meant to distinguish these two types of meaning and whether the distinction, as Grice is best understood to have drawn it, can be defended.
    • The most familiar distinction, initially proposed by Paul Grice half a century ago, lies between speaker's meaning and sentence meaning. See PAUL GRICE, STUDIES IN THE WAY OF WORDS chs. 5-6 (1989). Yet theorists continue to debate exactly how Grice meant to distinguish these two types of meaning and whether the distinction, as Grice is best understood to have drawn it, can be defended.
  • 224
    • 0010082317 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Stephen Neale, Paul Grice and the Philosophy of Language, 15 LINGUISTICS & PHIL. 509 (1992). I will eschew the terms speaker's meaning and sentence meaning to try to reduce the risk that I be understood to incorporate aspects of the Gricean intentionalist apparatus.
    • See generally Stephen Neale, Paul Grice and the Philosophy of Language, 15 LINGUISTICS & PHIL. 509 (1992). I will eschew the terms "speaker's meaning" and "sentence meaning" to try to reduce the risk that I be understood to incorporate aspects of the Gricean intentionalist apparatus.
  • 225
    • 66449101747 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jerrold Levinson, Intention and Interpretation: A Last Look, in INTENTION AND INTERPRETATION 221, 222-23 (Gary Iseminger ed., 1992).
    • Jerrold Levinson, Intention and Interpretation: A Last Look, in INTENTION AND INTERPRETATION 221, 222-23 (Gary Iseminger ed., 1992).
  • 226
    • 0346044961 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Fred Schauer has put the point: Yet if language is [intentionalist] in this sense, it is hard to imagine why a word or a phrase is a piece of evidence of one intention rather than another intention. Then, for language to be evidence of something rather than something else, it must have some independent capacity without circular reference to the subject of which it is evidence. To put it somewhat more simply, the ability of language to be evidence of something presupposes that language, according to rules of language or according to conventions of language, can carry meaning. If language itself can carry meaning, however, then it turns out that as a descriptive account of language, intentionalism] is not plausible. Frederick Schauer, Defining Originalism, 19 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 343, 344 1996
    • As Fred Schauer has put the point: Yet if language is [intentionalist] in this sense, it is hard to imagine why a word or a phrase is a piece of evidence of one intention rather than another intention. Then, for language to be evidence of "something" rather than "something else," it must have some independent capacity without circular reference to the subject of which it is evidence. To put it somewhat more simply, the ability of language to be evidence of something presupposes that language, according to rules of language or according to conventions of language, can carry meaning. If language itself can carry meaning, however, then it turns out that as a descriptive account of language, [intentionalism] is not plausible. Frederick Schauer, Defining Originalism, 19 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 343, 344 (1996).
  • 227
    • 79955255543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Colin Lyas, Wittgensteinian Intentions, in INTENTION AND INTERPRETATION, supra note 114, at 132, 146-47.
    • See, e.g., Colin Lyas, Wittgensteinian Intentions, in INTENTION AND INTERPRETATION, supra note 114, at 132, 146-47.
  • 228
    • 66449120418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the qualification that this argument works only when (as is usually the case) the author's intentions are linguistic in character, see George Dickie & W. Kent Wilson, The Intentional Fallacy: Defending Beardsley, 53 J. AESTHETICS & ART CRITICISM 233, 237-38 (1995).
    • For the qualification that this argument works only when (as is usually the case) the author's intentions are linguistic in character, see George Dickie & W. Kent Wilson, The Intentional Fallacy: Defending Beardsley, 53 J. AESTHETICS & ART CRITICISM 233, 237-38 (1995).
  • 229
    • 84901579335 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Richard Shusterman, Interpreting with Pragmatist Intentions, in INTENTION AND INTERPRETATION, supra note 114, at 167, 168.
    • Richard Shusterman, Interpreting with Pragmatist Intentions, in INTENTION AND INTERPRETATION, supra note 114, at 167, 168.
  • 230
    • 66449124408 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I say seem because, in correspondence, Jonathan Gingerich has argued that this example doesn't rebut intentionalism because the reasons for interpreting a text in any given context rest on the author's intention. E-mail from Jonathan Gingerich, J.D. Candidate, Harvard Law School, to author Jan. 19, 2008, 20:38:00 EST, on file with the New York University Law Review, In particular, we interpret the announcement to mean midnight instead of noon only because its author intended the text to mean whatever a competent speaker of the language would ordinarily understand it to mean. First and foremost, Gingerich supposes, she intended to put people on notice, and while she may also have intended that 12:00 a.m. mean noon. the former intention was more important to her than the latter. If she were to read the text after it had been published, she would probably agree that it meant midnight. So, the intentionalist could say, when we ascribe th
    • I say "seem" because, in correspondence, Jonathan Gingerich has argued that this example doesn't rebut intentionalism because the reasons for interpreting a text in any given context rest on the author's intention. E-mail from Jonathan Gingerich, J.D. Candidate, Harvard Law School, to author (Jan. 19, 2008, 20:38:00 EST) (on file with the New York University Law Review). In particular, we interpret the announcement to mean midnight instead of noon only because its author intended the text to mean whatever a competent speaker of the language would ordinarily understand it to mean. First and foremost, Gingerich supposes, she intended to put people on notice, and while she may also have intended that "12:00 a.m." mean "noon." the former intention was more important to her than the latter. If she were to read the text after it had been published, she would probably agree that it meant midnight. So, the intentionalist could say, when we ascribe the utterance meaning to a text, we're doing so because we've decided that the author of the text intended it to have whatever meaning it would ordinarily be given by a competent speaker of the language, and that this intention was more important to the author than other, possibly conflicting, intentions about the meaning of particular words. I think this effort to avoid a conflict between intentionalists and their opponents does not succeed because it is an entirely contingent question whether the author of the announcement did intend the text to mean "whatever a competent speaker of the language would ordinarily understand it to mean." That could be, but I don't think that it must be, and I believe that our disposition to interpret the text to mean midnight doesn't depend on whether the author did in fact have the intention Gingerich posits. If the author (perhaps unreasonably) continues to insist that the announcement ought to be interpreted and enforced in accordance with utterer's meaning, I maintain that most of us would just respond that, actually, the announcement means midnight, and be done with it-withoutbothering to reconcile this fact with any other intentions the author might (or might not) have had.
  • 231
    • 66449092437 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a representative argument that proceeds along the following lines, see Alexander & Prakash, supra note 110, at 974-82
    • For a representative argument that proceeds along the following lines, see Alexander & Prakash, supra note 110, at 974-82.
  • 232
    • 66449084318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fish, supra note 23, at 635
    • Fish, supra note 23, at 635.
  • 233
    • 66449129439 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alexander & Prakash, supra note 110, at 967
    • Alexander & Prakash, supra note 110, at 967.
  • 234
    • 66449095842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Michael S. Moore, Interpreting Interpretation, in LAW AND INTERPRETATION, supra note 108, at 1, 8;
    • See, e.g., Michael S. Moore, Interpreting Interpretation, in LAW AND INTERPRETATION, supra note 108, at 1, 8;
  • 235
    • 66449115703 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sinnott-Armstrong, supra note 111, at 474-77
    • Sinnott-Armstrong, supra note 111, at 474-77.
  • 236
    • 84890018746 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moderate Versus Strong Intentionalism: Knapp and Michaels Revisited, 42
    • arguing that authorial intention to convey meaning is necessary for text to have meaning but not sufficient to establish what that meaning is, See, e.g
    • See, e.g., Jeffrey Goldsworthy, Moderate Versus Strong Intentionalism: Knapp and Michaels Revisited, 42 SAN DIEGO L. REV. 669, 670 (2005) (arguing that authorial intention to convey meaning is necessary for text to have meaning but not sufficient to establish what that meaning is);
    • (2005) SAN DIEGO L. REV , vol.669 , pp. 670
    • Goldsworthy, J.1
  • 237
    • 47349125424 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 114, at, distinguishing semantic from categorial intentions
    • Levinson, supra note 114, at 232 (distinguishing semantic from categorial intentions).
    • supra , pp. 232
    • Levinson1
  • 238
    • 66449124924 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Fish, supra note 23, at 632-33 (Words alone, without an animating intention, do not have power, do not have semantic shape, and are not yet language; and when someone tells you (as a textualist always will) that he or she is able to construe words apart from intention and then proceeds (triumphantly) to do it, what he or she will really have done is assumed an intention without being aware of having done so. (italics in original omitted)).
    • See Fish, supra note 23, at 632-33 ("Words alone, without an animating intention, do not have power, do not have semantic shape, and are not yet language; and when someone tells you (as a textualist always will) that he or she is able to construe words apart from intention and then proceeds (triumphantly) to do it, what he or she will really have done is assumed an intention without being aware of having done so." (italics in original omitted)).
  • 239
    • 66449131648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fish, supra note 104, at 1129
    • Fish, supra note 104, at 1129.
  • 240
    • 66449089985 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1133
    • Id. at 1133.
  • 241
    • 66449126715 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1138 n.98 (citation omitted). Although the passage above recognizes only three possible interpretive objects-authorial intention, inherent textual meaning, and the interpreter's desires-elsewhere Fish has contemplated a somewhat richer menu of alternatives: Nor, he added (in that earlier formulation), does a text mean what is specified by the conventions of the day because conventions do not have intentions and they do not author texts. Nor does it mean what the ordinary or ideal or reasonable interpreter would mean by the words because none of those authored the text either, and declaring any one of them the author by fiat would amount to rewriting, not interpreting.
    • Id. at 1138 n.98 (citation omitted). Although the passage above recognizes only three possible interpretive objects-authorial intention, inherent textual meaning, and the interpreter's desires-elsewhere Fish has contemplated a somewhat richer menu of alternatives: "Nor," he added (in that earlier formulation), does a text mean what is specified by the conventions of the day because conventions do not have intentions and they do not author texts. Nor does it mean what the ordinary or ideal or reasonable interpreter would mean by the words because none of those authored the text either, and declaring any one of them the author by fiat would amount to rewriting, not interpreting.
  • 242
    • 66449098119 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fish, supra note 23, at 644-45. But these arguments for rejecting, as the target of interpretation, the meanings that conventions and hypothetical reasonable interpreters (or speakers) seem to direct are circular: That conventions do not have intentions and do not author texts is a reason why a text does not mean what the conventions prescribe only on the assumption that authorial intentions are the key to meaning. That one who would identify a text's meaning as what would be meant by an ordinary or ideal or reasonable interpreter effectively declares one of them the author by fiat and assumes that the meaning must come from the author and nowhere else. But both assumptions capture precisely what is in dispute.
    • Fish, supra note 23, at 644-45. But these arguments for rejecting, as the target of interpretation, the meanings that conventions and hypothetical reasonable interpreters (or speakers) seem to direct are circular: That conventions do not have intentions and do not author texts is a reason why a text does not mean what the conventions prescribe only on the assumption that authorial intentions are the key to meaning. That one who would identify a text's meaning as what would be meant by an ordinary or ideal or reasonable interpreter effectively declares one of them the author by fiat and assumes that the meaning must come from the author and nowhere else. But both assumptions capture precisely what is in dispute.
  • 243
    • 66449130568 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Knapp & Michaels, supra note 108, at 664
    • Knapp & Michaels, supra note 108, at 664.
  • 244
    • 66449122386 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is the overarching theme of HIRSCH, supra note 103
    • This is the overarching theme of HIRSCH, supra note 103.
  • 245
    • 66449087929 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., DOJ SOURCEBOOK, supra note 19, at 4 ([I]f the courts go beyond the original meaning of the Constitution . [t]hey transform our constitutional democracy into a judicial aristocracy, and abandon the rule of law based on a judge's subjective notions of what is best for society.);
    • See, e.g., DOJ SOURCEBOOK, supra note 19, at 4 ("[I]f the courts go beyond the original meaning of the Constitution . [t]hey transform our constitutional democracy into a judicial aristocracy, and abandon the rule of law based on a judge's subjective notions of what is best for society.");
  • 246
    • 66449107726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Barnett, supra note 4, at 651 (presenting strong originalism as only alternative to allowing government officials to give meaning to Constitution in their unfettered discretion).
    • Barnett, supra note 4, at 651 (presenting strong originalism as only alternative to allowing government officials to give meaning to Constitution "in their unfettered discretion").
  • 247
    • 66449097003 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fish, supra note 23, at 644
    • Fish, supra note 23, at 644.
  • 248
    • 84901577655 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Joseph Margolis, Robust Relativism, in INTENTION AND INTERPRETATION, supra note 114, at 41.
    • Joseph Margolis, Robust Relativism, in INTENTION AND INTERPRETATION, supra note 114, at 41.
  • 249
    • 66449088504 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 48
    • Id. at 48.
  • 250
    • 66449095545 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some texts might occupy more than one category of utterance-either by virtue of an author's multiple categorial intentions or perhaps given needs of different audiences. An expatriate poet working as a spy might pen verse that is intended to function both as an elegy and as a report about the enemy's munitions capacity. As a clandestine report, the text's meaning is utterer's meaning; as a poem, its meaning might be something else.
    • Some texts might occupy more than one category of utterance-either by virtue of an author's multiple categorial intentions or perhaps given needs of different audiences. An expatriate poet working as a spy might pen verse that is intended to function both as an elegy and as a report about the enemy's munitions capacity. As a clandestine report, the text's meaning is utterer's meaning; as a poem, its meaning might be something else.
  • 251
    • 66449112676 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This view bears some similarity to Andrei Marmor's, the principal difference being that he would describe interpretations that do not seek to attribute to a text the meaning actually intended by its author as attributions of counterfactual intentions to fictitious or stipulated authors. See MARMOR, supra note 5, at 21-25
    • This view bears some similarity to Andrei Marmor's, the principal difference being that he would describe interpretations that do not seek to attribute to a text the meaning actually intended by its author as attributions of counterfactual intentions to fictitious or stipulated authors. See MARMOR, supra note 5, at 21-25.
  • 252
    • 66449086139 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A kindred view has been advanced under the caption hypothetical intentionalism in Levinson, supra note 114.
    • A kindred view has been advanced under the caption "hypothetical intentionalism" in Levinson, supra note 114.
  • 253
    • 84901584552 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Daniel O. Nathan, Irony, Metaphor, and the Problem of Intention, in INTENTION AND INTERPRETATION, supra note 114, at 183, 202 n.29 (citing works);
    • See also Daniel O. Nathan, Irony, Metaphor, and the Problem of Intention, in INTENTION AND INTERPRETATION, supra note 114, at 183, 202 n.29 (citing works);
  • 254
    • 34248916058 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • William E. Tolhurst, On What a Text Is and How It Means, 19 BRIT. J. AESTHETICS 3, 11-12 (1979). As I understand it, Marmor's approach and others like it preserve the structure or grammar of intentionalism but abandon its substance. I am weakly disposed to find the fictitious author device unnecessary and potentially misleading. But hypothetical intentionalism is enough to defeat Originalism.
    • William E. Tolhurst, On What a Text Is and How It Means, 19 BRIT. J. AESTHETICS 3, 11-12 (1979). As I understand it, Marmor's approach and others like it preserve the structure or "grammar" of intentionalism but abandon its substance. I am weakly disposed to find the fictitious author device unnecessary and potentially misleading. But hypothetical intentionalism is enough to defeat Originalism.
  • 255
    • 66449130006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Saikrishna Prakash, Radicals in Tweed Jackets: Why Extreme Left-Wing Law Professors Are Wrong for America, 106 COLUM. L. REV. 2207, 2224 (2006) (If we have -identified some method of finding meaning in inconsequential documents, we can apply the same method to finding meaning in consequential documents.).
    • Cf. Saikrishna Prakash, Radicals in Tweed Jackets: Why Extreme Left-Wing Law Professors Are Wrong for America, 106 COLUM. L. REV. 2207, 2224 (2006) ("If we have -identified some method of finding meaning in inconsequential documents, we can apply the same method to finding meaning in consequential documents.").
  • 256
    • 66449096140 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I note in passing that utterance meaning and ludic meaning together describe a broad terrain that might, with profit, be more finely subdivided
    • I note in passing that utterance meaning and ludic meaning together describe a broad terrain that might, with profit, be more finely subdivided.
  • 257
    • 66449100798 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare Gerald Postema's explanation of how the collaborative nature of the common law disciplines analogical reasoning: While it is always individuals who participate in analogical reasoning in law, they proceed with a keen sense that they deliberate, as Hart put it, not each for his own part only, but as members of a larger whole, This capacity for reflective judgment is a social capacity, the ability to reason from a body of supposed shared experiences to solutions to new practical problems, to judge what one has good reason to believe others in the community would also regard as reasonable and fitting. These judgments can be made with confidence, not because one is a good predictor of other's behaviour, but because one understands at a concrete level the common life in which they all participate. Gerald J. Postema, Philosophy of the Common Law, in THE OXFORD HANDBOOK OF JURISPRUDENCE AND PHILOSOPHY OF LAW
    • Compare Gerald Postema's explanation of how "the collaborative nature of" the common law disciplines analogical reasoning: While it is always individuals who participate in analogical reasoning in law, they proceed with a keen sense that they deliberate, as Hart put it, not each for his own part only, but as members of a larger whole. . . . This capacity for reflective judgment is a social capacity, the ability to reason from a body of supposed shared experiences to solutions to new practical problems, to judge what one has good reason to believe others in the community would also regard as reasonable and fitting. These judgments can be made with confidence, not because one is a good predictor of other's behaviour, but because one understands at a concrete level the common life in which they all participate. Gerald J. Postema, Philosophy of the Common Law, in THE OXFORD HANDBOOK OF JURISPRUDENCE AND PHILOSOPHY OF LAW 588, 607 (Jules Coleman & Scott Shapiro eds., 2002) (citation omitted). I am making a broadly similar claim about the interpretation of legal texts.
  • 258
    • 36348993722 scopus 로고
    • Rules for Originalists, 73
    • H. Jefferson Powell, Rules for Originalists, 73 VA. L. REV. 659, 697 (1987).
    • (1987) VA. L. REV , vol.659 , pp. 697
    • Jefferson Powell, H.1
  • 259
    • 66449132741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fish, supra note 104, at 1138 n.98 (emphasis added).
    • Fish, supra note 104, at 1138 n.98 (emphasis added).
  • 260
    • 66449094869 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1122. To this, the intentionalist might reply that even if some interpreters (like judges) might possibly be searching for the understandings of a text held by some other community of interpreters, members of that community must themselves be searching for some meanings, and those meanings cannot be contemporary meanings without circularity. And if the members of the community whose understandings judges seek are themselves aiming for the originally intended meanings, then, even if judicial interpreters can possibly be searching for popular understanding, they are properly described as searching for beliefs about intentionalist meanings. On this account, intentionalist meanings remain essential, though they are filtered, or provide meaning at one remove.
    • Id. at 1122. To this, the intentionalist might reply that even if some interpreters (like judges) might possibly be searching for the understandings of a text held by some other community of interpreters, members of that community must themselves be searching for some meanings, and those meanings cannot be contemporary meanings without circularity. And if the members of the community whose understandings judges seek are themselves aiming for the originally intended meanings, then, even if judicial interpreters can possibly be searching for popular understanding, they are properly described as searching for beliefs about intentionalist meanings. On this account, intentionalist meanings remain essential, though they are filtered, or provide meaning at one remove.
  • 261
    • 66449125752 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Campos, supra note 107, at 391-92. This argument fails, for nonjudicial interpreters might not be searching for original meanings, let alone original intentions about meaning. They might, e.g., be self-consciously constructing meaning. Or they might naively believe that language just has meaning. Or they might be searching for what a contemporary community with which they affiliate or identify takes the Constitution to mean. In short, the community need not have a theory at all. They might have only customs and patterns of practice. I know it when I see it might make for bad constitutional doctrine but need not be a false description of how ordinary people evaluate a proffered interpretation of a text's meaning.
    • See, e.g., Campos, supra note 107, at 391-92. This argument fails, for nonjudicial interpreters might not be searching for original meanings, let alone original intentions about meaning. They might, e.g., be self-consciously constructing meaning. Or they might naively believe that language "just has" meaning. Or they might be searching for what a contemporary community with which they affiliate or identify takes the Constitution to mean. In short, the community need not have a theory at all. They might have only customs and patterns of practice. "I know it when I see it" might make for bad constitutional doctrine but need not be a false description of how ordinary people evaluate a proffered interpretation of a text's meaning.
  • 262
    • 66449085787 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Knapp & Michaels, supra note 108, at 666 n.37.
    • Knapp & Michaels, supra note 108, at 666 n.37.
  • 263
    • 66449117840 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 667 (Legal texts are often the products of multiple stages of drafting and ratification, not to mention the revision that some say occurs in judicial review. But nothing in the logic of interpretation itself can tell us which of those stages should count as the one that confers on the text the meaning we are trying to interpret when we try to obey the law or to adjudicate it.).
    • See id. at 667 ("Legal texts are often the products of multiple stages of drafting and ratification, not to mention the revision that some say occurs in judicial review. But nothing in the logic of interpretation itself can tell us which of those stages should count as the one that confers on the text the meaning we are trying to interpret when we try to obey the law or to adjudicate it.").
  • 264
    • 66449112944 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I don't see any obvious basis for allowing judicial decisions purporting to interpret the Constitution to count as a re-authoring of the text while categorically excluding purported constitutional interpretations that occur outside the courts-whether in the halls of Congress, the op-ed pages of the nation's newspapers, or the coffee shops and Internet chatrooms frequented by the American public. See supra Part I.C.5.
    • I don't see any obvious basis for allowing judicial decisions purporting to interpret the Constitution to count as a re-authoring of the text while categorically excluding purported constitutional interpretations that occur outside the courts-whether in the halls of Congress, the op-ed pages of the nation's newspapers, or the coffee shops and Internet chatrooms frequented by the American public. See supra Part I.C.5.
  • 265
    • 66449103174 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arguments from authority often appear intermingled with arguments from legitimacy. See, e.g., Barnett, supra note 4, pts. 1-3;
    • Arguments from authority often appear intermingled with arguments from legitimacy. See, e.g., Barnett, supra note 4, pts. 1-3;
  • 266
    • 66449092742 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kay, supra note 15, at 228, 232-34. Little needs to be said about the legitimacy-based arguments. If sociological legitimacy is at issue, then whether non-originalist interpretation enjoys legitimacy, and how much, are empirical questions-in fact, empirical questions the answers to which originalist scholarship does more to (try to?) effect than to resolve. If the theorists mean that non-originalist interpretation lacks normative legitimacy then it is a conclusion, not an argument. Presumably, the argument that would support such a conclusion sounds in authority, good consequences, or some combination of the two.
    • Kay, supra note 15, at 228, 232-34. Little needs to be said about the legitimacy-based arguments. If sociological legitimacy is at issue, then whether non-originalist interpretation enjoys legitimacy, and how much, are empirical questions-in fact, empirical questions the answers to which originalist scholarship does more to (try to?) effect than to resolve. If the theorists mean that non-originalist interpretation lacks normative legitimacy then it is a conclusion, not an argument. Presumably, the argument that would support such a conclusion sounds in authority, good consequences, or some combination of the two.
  • 267
    • 66449132491 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WHITTINGTON, supra note 14, at 46
    • WHITTINGTON, supra note 14, at 46.
  • 268
    • 66449114206 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id
    • id.
  • 269
    • 84869650625 scopus 로고
    • The Constitution as Scripture, 37
    • Thomas C. Grey, The Constitution as Scripture, 37 STAN. L. REV. 1, 14-15 (1984).
    • (1984) STAN. L. REV , vol.1 , pp. 14-15
    • Grey, T.C.1
  • 270
    • 66449090861 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GOLDFORD, supra note 14, at 77
    • GOLDFORD, supra note 14, at 77.
  • 271
    • 66449104275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WHITTINGTON, supra note 14, at 50
    • WHITTINGTON, supra note 14, at 50.
  • 272
    • 66449115963 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 49
    • Id. at 49.
  • 273
    • 66449098958 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Whittington also provides extensive argument, grounded in the nature of popular sovereignty, to support the proposition that we should treat the Constitution as binding. See id. at 128-35.
    • Whittington also provides extensive argument, grounded in the nature of popular sovereignty, to support the proposition that we should treat the Constitution as binding. See id. at 128-35.
  • 274
    • 66449088217 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the most part, we can safely put that aspect of his argument aside, careful and illuminating as it is, because no parties to the academic or judicial debate seem to disagree. See, e.g., GOLDFORD, supra note 14, at 74-75;
    • For the most part, we can safely put that aspect of his argument aside, careful and illuminating as it is, because no parties to the academic or judicial debate seem to disagree. See, e.g., GOLDFORD, supra note 14, at 74-75;
  • 275
    • 65349089138 scopus 로고
    • The Authority of the Constitution and Its Meaning: A Preface to a Theory of Constitutional Interpretation, 58
    • What does warrant mention, however, is the conclusion to Whittington's analysis, where he moves from arguing that respect for popular sovereignty justifies our treating the Constitution as authoritative to contending that it also requires originalism as the proper method of constitutional interpretation
    • Larry Simon, The Authority of the Constitution and Its Meaning: A Preface to a Theory of Constitutional Interpretation, 58 S. CAL. L. REV. 603, 606 (1985). What does warrant mention, however, is the conclusion to Whittington's analysis, where he moves from arguing that respect for popular sovereignty justifies our treating the Constitution as authoritative to contending that it also requires originalism as the proper method of constitutional interpretation.
    • (1985) S. CAL. L. REV , vol.603 , pp. 606
    • Simon, L.1
  • 276
    • 66449108445 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See WHITTINGTON, supra note 14, at 152-59
    • See WHITTINGTON, supra note 14, at 152-59.
  • 277
    • 66449097840 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I discuss that argument infra Part III.A.1.
    • I discuss that argument infra Part III.A.1.
  • 278
    • 66449102632 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also, e.g., Barnett, supra note 4, at 636 (We are bound [to respect the original meaning of the Constitution] because we today . . . profess our commitment to a written constitution, and original meaning interpretation follows inexorably from that commitment.).
    • See also, e.g., Barnett, supra note 4, at 636 ("We are bound [to respect the original meaning of the Constitution] because we today . . . profess our commitment to a written constitution, and original meaning interpretation follows inexorably from that commitment.").
  • 279
    • 66449123797 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WHITTINGTON, supra note 14, at 61
    • WHITTINGTON, supra note 14, at 61.
  • 280
    • 66449104560 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 61-62
    • Id. at 61-62.
  • 281
    • 66449118974 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 62-65
    • Id. at 62-65.
  • 282
    • 66449089028 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 78-79
    • Id. at 78-79.
  • 284
    • 66449118115 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 285
    • 84868937176 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare AUSTL. CONST, ch. VIII, §128 (The Constitution shall not be altered except in the following manner . . . .),
    • Compare AUSTL. CONST, ch. VIII, §128 ("The Constitution shall not be altered except in the following manner . . . ."),
  • 287
    • 66449109334 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jeffrey Goldsworthy, Interpreting the Constitution in Its Second Century, 24 MELB. U. L. REV. 677, 683 (2000) [hereinafter Goldsworthy, Interpreting the Constitution].
    • Jeffrey Goldsworthy, Interpreting the Constitution in Its Second Century, 24 MELB. U. L. REV. 677, 683 (2000) [hereinafter Goldsworthy, Interpreting the Constitution].
  • 288
    • 0347301540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is just the kernel of Goldsworthy's more elaborate and sophisticated argument. Interested readers should also consult Jeffrey Goldsworthy, Raz on Constitutional Interpretation, 22 LAW & PHIL. 167 2003
    • This is just the kernel of Goldsworthy's more elaborate and sophisticated argument. Interested readers should also consult Jeffrey Goldsworthy, Raz on Constitutional Interpretation, 22 LAW & PHIL. 167 (2003),
  • 289
    • 66449086707 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Jeffrey Goldsworthy, Originalism in Constitutional Interpretation, 25 FED. L. REV. 1 (1997).
    • and Jeffrey Goldsworthy, Originalism in Constitutional Interpretation, 25 FED. L. REV. 1 (1997).
  • 291
    • 66449083720 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 684-85
    • Id. at 684-85.
  • 292
    • 66449099925 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 685
    • Id. at 685.
  • 293
    • 66449136487 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This claim is developed further in DANIEL A. FARBER & SUZANNA SHERRY, JUDGMENT CALLS: PRINCIPLE AND POLITICS IN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW 2009, Elsewhere, I have put forth the tentative view that law in general can be fruitfully conceived of in terms of practice-constrained argumentation
    • This claim is developed further in DANIEL A. FARBER & SUZANNA SHERRY, JUDGMENT CALLS: PRINCIPLE AND POLITICS IN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW (2009). Elsewhere, I have put forth the tentative view that law in general can be fruitfully conceived of in terms of practice-constrained argumentation.
  • 294
    • 66449089983 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Mitchell N. Berman, Constitutional Theory and the Rule of Recognition: Toward a Fourth Theory of Law, in THE U.S. CONSTITUTION AND THE RULE OF RECOGNITION (Matthew D. Adler & Kenneth Einar Himma eds., forthcoming 2009).
    • See Mitchell N. Berman, Constitutional Theory and the Rule of Recognition: Toward a Fourth Theory of Law, in THE U.S. CONSTITUTION AND THE RULE OF RECOGNITION (Matthew D. Adler & Kenneth Einar Himma eds., forthcoming 2009).
  • 295
    • 66449135297 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., JOSEPH RAZ, THE MORALITY OF FREEDOM pt. I (1986).
    • See, e.g., JOSEPH RAZ, THE MORALITY OF FREEDOM pt. I (1986).
  • 296
    • 66449088501 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Joseph Raz, On the Authority and Interpretation of Constitutions: Some Preliminaries, in CONSTITUTIONALISM: PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS 152 (Larry Alexander ed., 1998).
    • See generally Joseph Raz, On the Authority and Interpretation of Constitutions: Some Preliminaries, in CONSTITUTIONALISM: PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS 152 (Larry Alexander ed., 1998).
  • 298
    • 66449101065 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A similar argument appears in PERRY, supra note 42, at 48.
    • A similar argument appears in PERRY, supra note 42, at 48.
  • 299
    • 66449117108 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AMERICAN HERITAGE DICTIONARY OF THE ENGLISH LANGUAGE, supra note 45, at 1793;
    • AMERICAN HERITAGE DICTIONARY OF THE ENGLISH LANGUAGE, supra note 45, at 1793;
  • 300
    • 66449103438 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also, e.g., WEBSTER'S THIRD NEW INTERNATIONAL DICTIONARY, supra note 45, at 2370 (defining then as soon after that : immediately after that).
    • see also, e.g., WEBSTER'S THIRD NEW INTERNATIONAL DICTIONARY, supra note 45, at 2370 (defining "then" as "soon after that : immediately after that").
  • 301
    • 66449127023 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, Farber, supra note 1, at 1105
    • See, e.g., Farber, supra note 1, at 1105
  • 302
    • 66449093301 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ('[T]ext and original understanding exert the strongest claims when they are contemporary and thus likely to reflect current values and beliefs, or simply the expressed will of a current majority ....' (quoting Brest, supra note 24, at 229));
    • ("'[T]ext and original understanding exert the strongest claims when they are contemporary and thus likely to reflect current values and beliefs, or simply the expressed will of a current majority ....'" (quoting Brest, supra note 24, at 229));
  • 303
    • 84928220188 scopus 로고
    • The Authority of the Framers of the Constitution: Can Originalist Interpretation Be Justified?, 73
    • The strength of arguments against the Court's deviating from originalist interpretation of amendments decreases with the passage of time
    • Larry G. Simon, The Authority of the Framers of the Constitution: Can Originalist Interpretation Be Justified?, 73 CAL. L. REV. 1482, 1537 (1985) ("The strength of arguments against the Court's deviating from originalist interpretation of amendments decreases with the passage of time.").
    • (1985) CAL. L. REV , vol.1482 , pp. 1537
    • Simon, L.G.1
  • 304
    • 84868940729 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The highest judicial tribunals in Canada have, since 1930, consistently interpreted Canada's Constitution (and, later, its Charter of Rights) as a living tree capable of growth and expansion. Edwards v. Att'y Gen. for Can., [1930] A.C. 124, 136 (P.C.) (appeal taken from Can.); see also Reference re Same-Sex Marriage, [2004] 3 S.C.R. 698, 2004 SCC 79, ¶ 22 (Can.), available at http://www.canlii.org/en/ca/scc/doc/2004/2004scc79/ 2004scc79.pdf.
    • The highest judicial tribunals in Canada have, since 1930, consistently interpreted Canada's Constitution (and, later, its Charter of Rights) as "a living tree capable of growth and expansion." Edwards v. Att'y Gen. for Can., [1930] A.C. 124, 136 (P.C.) (appeal taken from Can.); see also Reference re Same-Sex Marriage, [2004] 3 S.C.R. 698, 2004 SCC 79, ¶ 22 (Can.), available at http://www.canlii.org/en/ca/scc/doc/2004/2004scc79/ 2004scc79.pdf.
  • 305
    • 84868957573 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The South African Constitution provides by its own terms that it can be interpreted in accordance with contemporary international norms. See S. AFR. CONST. 1996 ch. II, §391
    • The South African Constitution provides by its own terms that it can be interpreted in accordance with contemporary international norms. See S. AFR. CONST. 1996 ch. II, §39(1).
  • 306
    • 66449125755 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, the judgment possibly attractive is intended to withhold a verdict. For sober criticism of the Canadian jurisprudence, see generally Grant Huscroft, A Constitutional Work in Progress? The Charter and the Limits of Progressive Interpretation, 23 SUP. CT. L. REV. 2D 413 2004
    • Of course, the judgment "possibly attractive" is intended to withhold a verdict. For sober criticism of the Canadian jurisprudence, see generally Grant Huscroft, A Constitutional "Work in Progress"? The Charter and the Limits of Progressive Interpretation, 23 SUP. CT. L. REV. 2D 413 (2004).
  • 307
    • 66449110734 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BORK, supra note 20, at 143
    • BORK, supra note 20, at 143.
  • 308
    • 66449137148 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although these arguments frequently appear under the heading of social contract theories, I eschew that term because it is variously deployed to capture each of the two variants I have now distinguished. Compare, e.g, Dorf, supra note 17, at 1766, 1771 describing social contractarianism as justification for displacement of legislative action by unelected judiciary
    • Although these arguments frequently appear under the heading of "social contract" theories, I eschew that term because it is variously deployed to capture each of the two variants I have now distinguished. Compare, e.g., Dorf, supra note 17, at 1766, 1771 (describing social contractarianism as justification for displacement of legislative action by unelected judiciary),
  • 309
    • 66449117111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • with R. George Wright, Dependence and Hierarchy Among Constitu-tional Theories, 70 BROOK. L. REV. 141, 178 & n.248 (2004) (presenting social contractarianism as basis for requirement that original understanding be adhered to).
    • with R. George Wright, Dependence and Hierarchy Among Constitu-tional Theories, 70 BROOK. L. REV. 141, 178 & n.248 (2004) (presenting social contractarianism as basis for requirement that original understanding be adhered to).
  • 310
    • 66449086140 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is a political conception of democracy. The conception of democracy that Tocqueville emphasized was social-it referred to social conditions, not political institutions. See generally ALEXIS DE TOCQUEVILLE, DEMOCRACY IN AMERICA Harvey C, Mansfield & Delba Winthrop eds. & trans, Univ. of Chi. Press 2000, 1835
    • This is a political conception of democracy. The conception of democracy that Tocqueville emphasized was social-it referred to social conditions, not political institutions. See generally ALEXIS DE TOCQUEVILLE, DEMOCRACY IN AMERICA (Harvey C, Mansfield & Delba Winthrop eds. & trans., Univ. of Chi. Press 2000) (1835).
  • 311
    • 66449102332 scopus 로고
    • Bork and Beethoven, 42
    • Richard A. Posner, Bork and Beethoven, 42 STAN. L. REV. 1365, 1370 (1990).
    • (1990) STAN. L. REV , vol.1365 , pp. 1370
    • Posner, R.A.1
  • 312
    • 84902644147 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a powerful and nuanced argument that judicial review promotes democracy, properly understood, see LAWRENCE G. SAGER, JUSTICE IN PLAINCLOTHES: A THEORY OF AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONAL PRACTICE 194-221 (2004), in which the author argues that constitutional adjudication embodies and furthers democratic values by affording each member of the political community a fair and equal right to participate in rights contestation.
    • For a powerful and nuanced argument that judicial review promotes democracy, properly understood, see LAWRENCE G. SAGER, JUSTICE IN PLAINCLOTHES: A THEORY OF AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONAL PRACTICE 194-221 (2004), in which the author argues that constitutional adjudication embodies and furthers democratic values by affording each member of the political community a fair and equal right to participate in rights contestation.
  • 313
    • 66449104010 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Samuel Freeman, Original Meaning, Democratic Interpretation, and the Constitution, 21 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 3, 14, 25, 28 (1992) (emphasizing Constitution's political role as public charter expressing values and terms of political association that democratic citizens could reasonably accept, and arguing that democratic values are best respected when these fundamental terms of association are contested through public deliberation, not by appeal to original meanings).
    • See also Samuel Freeman, Original Meaning, Democratic Interpretation, and the Constitution, 21 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 3, 14, 25, 28 (1992) (emphasizing Constitution's political role as public charter expressing values and terms of political association that democratic citizens could reasonably accept, and arguing that democratic values are best respected when these fundamental terms of association are contested through public deliberation, not by appeal to original meanings).
  • 314
    • 66449128691 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WHITTINGTON, supra note 14, at 156
    • WHITTINGTON, supra note 14, at 156.
  • 315
    • 66449090284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This argument broadly parallels Goldsworthy's argument in supra Part II.B.2
    • This argument broadly parallels Goldsworthy's argument in supra Part II.B.2.
  • 316
    • 66449118692 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: FOUNDATIONS 6-7 (1991) (advancing dualist conception of American democracy, pursuant to which the People govern only during periodic moments of constitutional politics, with their government governing during ordinary times).
    • Cf. BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: FOUNDATIONS 6-7 (1991) (advancing "dualist" conception of American democracy, pursuant to which "the People" govern only during periodic moments of "constitutional politics," with their government governing during ordinary times).
  • 317
    • 66449112367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One might be tempted to rejoin that, if a supermajority of Americans both understand P to stand for X, and prefer X to Y, then the supermajority can be expected to constitutionalize X in the form of a new constitutional amendment, so a judicial refusal to interpret P to mean X incurs no cost in the currency of popular sovereignty. This is unsound: A supermajority could favor X to an extent sufficient to implicate democratic values even if it is not quite large enough or sufficiently well-distributed geographically to secure a constitutional amendment.
    • One might be tempted to rejoin that, if a supermajority of Americans both understand P to stand for X, and prefer X to Y, then the supermajority can be expected to constitutionalize X in the form of a new constitutional amendment, so a judicial refusal to interpret P to mean X incurs no cost in the currency of popular sovereignty. This is unsound: A supermajority could favor X to an extent sufficient to implicate democratic values even if it is not quite large enough or sufficiently well-distributed geographically to secure a constitutional amendment.
  • 318
    • 66449100522 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This reply to the popular sovereignty/social contractarian argument for Originalism is developed at greater length in Simon, supra note 168, at 1495-505
    • This reply to the popular sovereignty/social contractarian argument for Originalism is developed at greater length in Simon, supra note 168, at 1495-505.
  • 319
    • 84886342665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • quoted text accompanying note 174
    • See supra quoted text accompanying note 174.
    • See supra
  • 320
    • 66449105714 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AMERICAN HERITAGE DICTIONARY OF THE ENGLISH LANGUAGE, supra note 45, at 522
    • AMERICAN HERITAGE DICTIONARY OF THE ENGLISH LANGUAGE, supra note 45, at 522.
  • 321
    • 66449106266 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That is not the same thing as saying that they will think it pointless to engage in constitutional deliberation. This is essentially the upshot of the first objection I registered.
    • That is not the same thing as saying that they will think it pointless to engage in "constitutional deliberation." This is essentially the upshot of the first objection I registered.
  • 322
    • 66449102034 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am grateful to Peter Smith for this point
    • I am grateful to Peter Smith for this point.
  • 323
    • 66449120123 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WHITTINGTON, supra note 14, at 154
    • WHITTINGTON, supra note 14, at 154.
  • 325
    • 66449126145 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (reviewing FALLON, supra note 100) ([P]rominent originalists claim that only originalism can safeguard the rule of law . . . .).
    • (reviewing FALLON, supra note 100) ("[P]rominent originalists claim that only originalism can safeguard the rule of law . . . .").
  • 326
    • 84924150998 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An excellent analysis of the ideal, and its interrelated themes, is BRIAN Z. TAMANAHA, ON THE RULE OF LAW: HISTORY, POLITICS, THEORY 2004
    • An excellent analysis of the ideal, and its interrelated themes, is BRIAN Z. TAMANAHA, ON THE RULE OF LAW: HISTORY, POLITICS, THEORY (2004).
  • 327
    • 66449129735 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a more extensive reply to rule of law arguments for Originalism, see Simon, supra note 168, at 1519-35
    • For a more extensive reply to rule of law arguments for Originalism, see Simon, supra note 168, at 1519-35.
  • 328
    • 66449107061 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Graglia, supra note 23, at 1020 (describing Originalism as almost selfevidently correct ... a virtual axiom of our legal-political system, necessary to distinguish the judicial from the legislative function).
    • See, e.g., Graglia, supra note 23, at 1020 (describing Originalism as "almost selfevidently correct ... a virtual axiom of our legal-political system, necessary to distinguish the judicial from the legislative function").
  • 329
    • 66449088768 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We have seen that this is Graglia's view. See supra note 107 and accompanying text. So his claim that non-originalist judicial constitutional interpretation violates the principle of separation of powers is parasitic upon the proposition that nonintentionalist interpretation is self-contradictory.
    • We have seen that this is Graglia's view. See supra note 107 and accompanying text. So his claim that non-originalist judicial constitutional interpretation violates the principle of separation of powers is parasitic upon the proposition that nonintentionalist interpretation is self-contradictory.
  • 330
    • 66449091673 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Youngstown Sheet & Tube Co. v. Sawyer, 343 U.S. 579, 635 (1952) (Jackson, J., concurring).
    • Youngstown Sheet & Tube Co. v. Sawyer, 343 U.S. 579, 635 (1952) (Jackson, J., concurring).
  • 331
    • 66449115420 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Posner, supra note 173, at 1381 (discussing Bork's apparent view of matter);
    • See, e.g., Posner, supra note 173, at 1381 (discussing Bork's apparent view of matter);
  • 332
    • 66449103173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scalia, supra note 82, at 852
    • Scalia, supra note 82, at 852.
  • 333
    • 66449084605 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Dorf, supra note 17, at 1772 (making same point about Originalist appeals to legitimacy).
    • Cf. Dorf, supra note 17, at 1772 (making same point about Originalist appeals to "legitimacy").
  • 334
    • 66449128989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Graglia, supra note 23, at 1026 (arguing that democracy is served when judge-restraining originalism permits the results of the democratic political process to stand).
    • See, e.g., Graglia, supra note 23, at 1026 (arguing that democracy "is served when judge-restraining originalism permits the results of the democratic political process to stand").
  • 335
    • 66449110453 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., WHITTINGTON, supra note 14, at 44 ([J]udicial restraint . . . may not be consistent with ... originalism per se.);
    • See, e.g., WHITTINGTON, supra note 14, at 44 ("[J]udicial restraint . . . may not be consistent with ... originalism per se.");
  • 336
    • 66449117842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Maltz, supra note 11, at 775 (arguing that abstract constitutional guarantee of rights and courts' enforcement of such rights are two separate inquiries).
    • Maltz, supra note 11, at 775 (arguing that abstract constitutional guarantee of rights and courts' enforcement of such rights are "two separate inquiries").
  • 337
    • 66449101354 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, United States v. Morrison, 529 U.S. 598 (2000, Thomas, J, concurring, invoking purported original understanding of Commerce Clause to strike down congressional legislation, in contrast to dissenters who, emphasizing non-originalist arguments, would uphold legislation, United States v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549 (1995, same, Maryland v. Craig, 497 U.S. 836, 860-61 (1990, Scalia, J, dissenting, relying on purported original meaning of Confrontation Clause to advocate invalidation of state procedures allowing testimony of young children in sexual abuse cases by closed-circuit television, Morrison v. Olson, 487 U.S. 654, 697-99 (1987, Scalia, J, dissenting, arguing that original understanding of executive power renders Independent Counsel Act unconstitutional, Garcia v. San Antonio Metro. Transit Auth, 469 U.S. 528, 568-72, 581-83 1985, Powell, J, dissenting, relying on purported original understanding of Tenth Amendment to argue for striking down congressiona
    • See, e.g., United States v. Morrison, 529 U.S. 598 (2000) (Thomas, J., concurring) (invoking purported original understanding of Commerce Clause to strike down congressional legislation, in contrast to dissenters who, emphasizing non-originalist arguments, would uphold legislation); United States v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549 (1995) (same); Maryland v. Craig, 497 U.S. 836, 860-61 (1990) (Scalia, J., dissenting) (relying on purported original meaning of Confrontation Clause to advocate invalidation of state procedures allowing testimony of young children in sexual abuse cases by closed-circuit television); Morrison v. Olson, 487 U.S. 654, 697-99 (1987) (Scalia, J., dissenting) (arguing that original understanding of executive power renders Independent Counsel Act unconstitutional); Garcia v. San Antonio Metro. Transit Auth., 469 U.S. 528, 568-72, 581-83 (1985) (Powell, J., dissenting) (relying on purported original understanding of Tenth Amendment to argue for striking down congressional legislation that majority upheld); INS v. Chadha, 462 U.S. 919, 946-51, 967-68 (1983) (relying on purported original understanding of presentment, bicameralism, and separation of powers to strike down one-House veto legislation, over non-originalist dissent); Home Bldg. & Loan Ass'n v. Blaisdell, 290 U.S. 398, 449, 453-54 (1934) (Sutherland, J., dissenting) (relying on original understanding of Contracts Clause to contend that state legislation upheld by majority is unconstitutional).
  • 338
    • 66449088767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. 1 F.A. HAYEK, LAW, LEGISLATION, AND LIBERTY 116 (1973) ([J]udicial decisions may in fact be more predictable if the judge is also bound by generally held views of what is just, even when they are not supported by the letter of the law, than when he is restricted to deriving his decisions only from those among accepted beliefs which have found expression in the written law.).
    • Cf. 1 F.A. HAYEK, LAW, LEGISLATION, AND LIBERTY 116 (1973) ("[J]udicial decisions may in fact be more predictable if the judge is also bound by generally held views of what is just, even when they are not supported by the letter of the law, than when he is restricted to deriving his decisions only from those among accepted beliefs which have found expression in the written law.").
  • 339
    • 66449133167 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 272 U.S. 52, 136 (1926).
    • 272 U.S. 52, 136 (1926).
  • 340
    • 66449135865 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Scalia, supra note 82, at 852
    • See Scalia, supra note 82, at 852.
  • 341
    • 66449092743 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz, supra note 165, at 174
    • Raz, supra note 165, at 174.
  • 342
    • 66449091119 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, GOLDFORD, supra note 14, at 88-89;
    • See, e.g., GOLDFORD, supra note 14, at 88-89;
  • 343
    • 66449107062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz, supra note 165, at 186
    • Raz, supra note 165, at 186.
  • 344
    • 34250175164 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Pragmatic Defense of Originalism, 101
    • John O. McGinnis & Michael B. Rappaport, A Pragmatic Defense of Originalism, 101 NW. U. L. REV. 383, 383 (2007).
    • (2007) NW. U. L. REV , vol.383 , pp. 383
    • McGinnis, J.O.1    Rappaport, M.B.2
  • 345
    • 66449085786 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Others have argued that consequences broadly conceived supply the touchstone for evaluating any theory of legal interpretation. See, e.g., Posner, supra note 173, at 1373, 1379 & n.76;
    • Others have argued that consequences broadly conceived supply the touchstone for evaluating any theory of legal interpretation. See, e.g., Posner, supra note 173, at 1373, 1379 & n.76;
  • 346
    • 66449120690 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Simon, supra note 150, at 613-14;
    • Simon, supra note 150, at 613-14;
  • 347
    • 66449112677 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cass R. Sunstein, Of Snakes and Butterflies: A Reply, 106 COLUM. L. REV. 2234, 2238 (2006, I am disposed to think this is correct because I think it implausible that any single interpretive approach would be the subject of a deontological obligation or is entailed by the right understanding of concepts such as law, meaning, or interpretation. If the claim is true, however, it can only be so if we conceive the consequences potentially at issue broadly enough to encompass not only the value of the particular holdings that a given theory reaches (or is likely to reach) but also all the long-term and indirect effects that different interpretive postures and methods produce. Moreover, I would hope that a comparative consequentialist evaluation of different interpretive theories could take into account qualities attaching to the act of interpretation itself-as, for example, whether it exemplifies a judicial virtue or vice. But I am open to being persua
    • Cass R. Sunstein, Of Snakes and Butterflies: A Reply, 106 COLUM. L. REV. 2234, 2238 (2006). I am disposed to think this is correct because I think it implausible that any single interpretive approach would be the subject of a deontological obligation or is entailed by the right understanding of concepts such as law, meaning, or interpretation. If the claim is true, however, it can only be so if we conceive the consequences potentially at issue broadly enough to encompass not only the value of the particular holdings that a given theory reaches (or is likely to reach) but also all the long-term and indirect effects that different interpretive postures and methods produce. Moreover, I would hope that a comparative consequentialist evaluation of different interpretive theories could take into account qualities attaching to the act of interpretation itself-as, for example, whether it exemplifies a judicial virtue or vice. But I am open to being persuaded otherwise. (I am grateful to David Bernard and Ben Zipursky for provoking my doubts on this score.)
  • 348
    • 66449129153 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McGinnis & Rappaport, supra note 199, at 396
    • McGinnis & Rappaport, supra note 199, at 396.
  • 349
    • 66449087000 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Most notably, it seems to me that McGinnis and Rappaport's interesting analysis goes more toward establishing (a) that entrenchments are more likely to be good if adopted via supermajoritarian procedures than if adopted via merely majoritarian procedures, than (b) that the expected consequences of the original meaning are likely to be better than the expected consequences of some other candidate meaning when measured at the time of interpretation. Secondly, and independently, I worry that the authors are insufficiently sensitive to the fact that the 1789 Constitution was ratified as a whole, not provision by provision. This fact would seem to mitigate very substantially the extent to which its supermajoritarian passage bears on the goodness of any given part of the text, making their argument as a whole much less persuasive with respect to judicial interpretation of the articles than with respect to the amendments.
    • Most notably, it seems to me that McGinnis and Rappaport's interesting analysis goes more toward establishing (a) that entrenchments are more likely to be good if adopted via supermajoritarian procedures than if adopted via merely majoritarian procedures, than (b) that the expected consequences of the original meaning are likely to be better than the expected consequences of some other candidate meaning when measured at the time of interpretation. Secondly, and independently, I worry that the authors are insufficiently sensitive to the fact that the 1789 Constitution was ratified as a whole, not provision by provision. This fact would seem to mitigate very substantially the extent to which its supermajoritarian passage bears on the goodness of any given part of the text, making their argument as a whole much less persuasive with respect to judicial interpretation of the articles than with respect to the amendments. Finally, I am not wholly persuaded by the authors' efforts, see id. at 394-95, to rebut the objection that the heuristic value of the supermajoritarian process is diminished by the exclusion of large segments of the population (most notably women and blacks, but also unpropertied white males) from participating in the drafting or ratifying of most of the text.
  • 350
    • 37749002378 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some of these objections, and others as well, are elaborated in Ethan J. Leib, Why Supermajoritarianism Does Not Illuminate the Interpretive Debate Between Originalists and Non-originalists, 101 NW. U. L. REV. 1905 (2007).
    • Some of these objections, and others as well, are elaborated in Ethan J. Leib, Why Supermajoritarianism Does Not Illuminate the Interpretive Debate Between Originalists and Non-originalists, 101 NW. U. L. REV. 1905 (2007).
  • 351
    • 67749091987 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 199, at, emphasis added
    • McGinnis & Rappaport, supra note 199, at 386 (emphasis added).
    • supra , pp. 386
    • McGinnis1    Rappaport2
  • 353
    • 66449137735 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (explaining that their argument requires that judges interpret the document based only on its original meaning).
    • Id. (explaining that their argument "requires that judges interpret the document based only on its original meaning").
  • 354
    • 66449137993 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 391
    • Id. at 391.
  • 355
    • 66449109059 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 391 n.37.
    • Id. at 391 n.37.
  • 356
    • 66449084906 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Barnett, supra note 4, at 617;
    • Barnett, supra note 4, at 617;
  • 357
    • 66449115422 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Farber, supra note 1, at 1102-03.
    • see also Farber, supra note 1, at 1102-03.
  • 358
    • 66449104561 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am grateful to Larry Laudan for suggesting this example
    • I am grateful to Larry Laudan for suggesting this example.
  • 359
    • 66449091120 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I criticize Hart's account in Berman, supra note 163.
    • I criticize Hart's account in Berman, supra note 163.
  • 360
    • 66449103732 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scalia, supra note 82, at 855
    • Scalia, supra note 82, at 855.
  • 361
    • 66449137147 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The point of this more precise formulation is to recognize that a non-originalist judge of a more minimalist bent might announce a bottom-line conclusion or might craft implementing judicial doctrine, both without announcing an understanding of constitutional meaning. Cf. supra note 100 (discussing various carvings of meaning/doctrine distinction).
    • The point of this more precise formulation is to recognize that a non-originalist judge of a more minimalist bent might announce a bottom-line conclusion or might craft implementing judicial doctrine, both without announcing an understanding of constitutional meaning. Cf. supra note 100 (discussing various carvings of meaning/doctrine distinction).
  • 362
    • 66449110946 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That is not to deny, of course, that the judge must have reasons for her interpretation and also an obligation to provide them publicly, in her opinion. But one can recognize considerations as reasons without having endorsed a more comprehensive set of general principles-a theory-from which those reasons follow.
    • That is not to deny, of course, that the judge must have reasons for her interpretation and also an obligation to provide them publicly, in her opinion. But one can recognize considerations as reasons without having endorsed a more comprehensive set of general principles-a theory-from which those reasons follow.
  • 363
    • 66449118402 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I take no position on whether other works that are designed to persuade a general audience to reject Originalism are properly criticized for failing to offer a clear, easily digested alternative. For such a criticism, see Ryan, supra note 86, at 1627, criticizing recent books by Justice Breyer and by Cass Sunstein on precisely this ground. For recent ruminations on the Right's largely successful deployment of Originalism to mobilize conservative politics,
    • I take no position on whether other works that are designed to persuade a general audience to reject Originalism are properly criticized for failing to offer a clear, easily digested alternative. For such a criticism, see Ryan, supra note 86, at 1627, criticizing recent books by Justice Breyer and by Cass Sunstein on precisely this ground. For recent ruminations on the Right's largely successful deployment of Originalism to mobilize conservative politics,
  • 364
    • 33846165790 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see generally Robert Post & Reva Siegel, Originalism as a Political Practice: The Right's Living Constitutionalism, 75 FORDHAM L. REV. 545 (2006), and Jamal Greene, Selling Originalism (Sept. 29, 2008) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1273640.
    • see generally Robert Post & Reva Siegel, Originalism as a Political Practice: The Right's Living Constitutionalism, 75 FORDHAM L. REV. 545 (2006), and Jamal Greene, Selling Originalism (Sept. 29, 2008) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1273640.
  • 365
    • 66449120419 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tribe, supra note 56, at 71-72
    • Tribe, supra note 56, at 71-72.
  • 366
    • 66449131384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 72-73
    • Id. at 72-73.
  • 367
    • 0346280521 scopus 로고
    • Pluralism in Constitutional Interpretation, 72
    • See, e.g
    • See, e.g., Stephen M. Griffin, Pluralism in Constitutional Interpretation, 72 TEX. L. REV. 1753 (1994).
    • (1994) TEX. L. REV , vol.1753
    • Griffin, S.M.1
  • 368
    • 66449108754 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, Dorf, supra note 17, at 1787-96
    • See, e.g., Dorf, supra note 17, at 1787-96.
  • 369
    • 66449121535 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Farber, supra note 1, at 1103-04.
    • Farber, supra note 1, at 1103-04.
  • 370
    • 66449096431 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Whittington, supra note 15, at 608. Of course, I'm claiming that Whittington's characterization of McConnell is mistaken.
    • Whittington, supra note 15, at 608. Of course, I'm claiming that Whittington's characterization of McConnell is mistaken.
  • 371
    • 66449099535 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McConnell, supra note 69, at 1292
    • McConnell, supra note 69, at 1292.
  • 372
    • 66449137994 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Scalia, supra note 82, at 862-63 ([T]he central practical defect of nonoriginalism is fundamental and irreparable: the impossibility of achieving any consensus on what, precisely, is to replace original meaning, once that is abandoned.). As Larry Solum has pointed out, this analysis betrays a double standard in suggesting that consensus on a single non-originalist approach is impossible without considering the possibility of achieving consensus on a single Originalist approach. Both are possible; neither is easy.
    • See Scalia, supra note 82, at 862-63 ("[T]he central practical defect of nonoriginalism is fundamental and irreparable: the impossibility of achieving any consensus on what, precisely, is to replace original meaning, once that is abandoned."). As Larry Solum has pointed out, this analysis betrays a double standard in suggesting that consensus on a single non-originalist approach is impossible without considering the possibility of achieving consensus on a single Originalist approach. Both are possible; neither is easy.
  • 373
    • 44449166753 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constitutional Possibilities, 83
    • Lawrence B. Solum, Constitutional Possibilities, 83 IND. L.J. 307, 334-35 (2008);
    • (2008) IND. L.J , vol.307 , pp. 334-335
    • Solum, L.B.1
  • 374
    • 66449091402 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Thomas B. Colby & Peter J. Smith, Living Originalism 1 (July 28, 2008) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1090282 (noting that proponents of Originalism assume that 'originalism' represents a single, coherent constitutional theory, against which are arrayed the disparate non-originalist alternatives). This double standard is a staple in the Originalist literature.
    • see also Thomas B. Colby & Peter J. Smith, Living Originalism 1 (July 28, 2008) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1090282 (noting that proponents of Originalism assume "that 'originalism' represents a single, coherent constitutional theory, against which are arrayed the disparate non-originalist alternatives"). This double standard is a staple in the Originalist literature.
  • 375
    • 66449117110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., McGinnis & Rappaport, supra note 199, at 391 n.36 (defending Originalism in part because judges of various ideologies cannot be expected to reach agreement on any alternative method).
    • See, e.g., McGinnis & Rappaport, supra note 199, at 391 n.36 (defending Originalism in part because "judges of various ideologies cannot be expected to reach agreement on any alternative method").
  • 376
    • 66449086056 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., BERGER, supra note 41, at 314-15 (noting that employment of nonoriginalist intepretations reduces the Constitution to an empty shell into which each shifting judicial majority pours its own preferences);
    • See, e.g., BERGER, supra note 41, at 314-15 (noting that employment of nonoriginalist intepretations "reduces the Constitution to an empty shell into which each shifting judicial majority pours its own preferences");
  • 377
    • 66449131385 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BORK, supra note 20, at 155 (No other method of constitutional adjudication [besides 'the approach of original understanding'] can confine courts to a defined sphere of authority . . . .);
    • BORK, supra note 20, at 155 ("No other method of constitutional adjudication [besides 'the approach of original understanding'] can confine courts to a defined sphere of authority . . . .");
  • 378
    • 66449132194 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SCALIA, supra note 38, at 46 (The originalist, if he does not have all the answers, has many of them. . . . For the evolutionist, on the other hand, every question is an open question . . . .);
    • SCALIA, supra note 38, at 46 ("The originalist, if he does not have all the answers, has many of them. . . . For the evolutionist, on the other hand, every question is an open question . . . .");
  • 379
    • 66449091674 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 51, at 698 (Once we have abandoned the idea that the authority of the courts to declare laws unconstitutional is somehow tied to the language of the Constitution .... [j]udges [become]
    • Rehnquist, supra note 51, at 698 ("Once we have abandoned the idea that the authority of the courts to declare laws unconstitutional is somehow tied to the language of the Constitution .... [j]udges [become]... a roving commission to second-guess Congress, state legislatures, and state and federal administrative officers . . . .").
    • a roving commission to second-guess Congress, state legislatures, and state and federal administrative officers . . . .)
    • Rehnquist1
  • 380
    • 66449084320 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, RAKOVE, supra note 72, at 6-7, 340;
    • See, e.g.. RAKOVE, supra note 72, at 6-7, 340;
  • 381
    • 66449109625 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gordon S. Wood, Ideology and the Origins of Liberal America, 44 WM. & MARY Q. 628, 632-33 (1987).
    • Gordon S. Wood, Ideology and the Origins of Liberal America, 44 WM. & MARY Q. 628, 632-33 (1987).
  • 382
    • 66449112096 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Macey, supra note 58, at 302, 304
    • Macey, supra note 58, at 302, 304.
  • 383
    • 66449104562 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 302
    • Id. at 302.
  • 384
    • 66449102035 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a discussion of this view, see supra note 48
    • For a discussion of this view, see supra note 48.
  • 385
    • 66449107063 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To be sure, Originalists might be trying to create external enforcement by nominating or confirming as Justices only those persons who proclaim fidelity to strong originalism, or even by threatening to impeach Justices who depart from strong originalism. Until impeachment on such a basis becomes a genuine weapon, however, the point in text remains
    • To be sure, Originalists might be trying to create external enforcement by nominating or confirming as Justices only those persons who proclaim fidelity to strong originalism, or even by threatening to impeach Justices who depart from strong originalism. Until impeachment on such a basis becomes a genuine weapon, however, the point in text remains.
  • 386
    • 84963456897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 127 and accompanying text
    • See supra note 127 and accompanying text.
    • See supra
  • 387
    • 0031351191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A position of this sort is loosely suggested by arguments in Gary Lawson, A Farewell to Principles, 82 IOWA L. REV. 893, 897-903 (1997).
    • A position of this sort is loosely suggested by arguments in Gary Lawson, A Farewell to Principles, 82 IOWA L. REV. 893, 897-903 (1997).
  • 388
    • 66449128690 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833,1000 (1992) (Scalia, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part).
    • Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833,1000 (1992) (Scalia, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part).
  • 389
    • 66449135300 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Macey, supra note 58, at 304 (emphasizing indeterminacy of originalism and acknowledging that there is something much worse about willful originalism than other sorts of outcome-oriented judging . . . because other sorts of outcome-oriented judging are more honest).
    • Macey, supra note 58, at 304 (emphasizing indeterminacy of originalism and acknowledging that "there is something much worse about willful originalism than other sorts of outcome-oriented judging . . . because other sorts of outcome-oriented judging are more honest").
  • 390
    • 66449105715 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Graglia, supra note 23, at 1031
    • Graglia, supra note 23, at 1031.
  • 391
    • 66449121534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., BeVier, supra note 29, at 286-87 (Integrity characterizes a judicial process based on originalism and its lack is one of the chief deficiencies of its alternatives. Many proponents of originalism bemoan the discrepancy between what the Court does-and what its nonoriginalist cheerleaders urge it to do-and what it says it does. The originalists urge upon the Court the simple virtue of candor.).
    • See, e.g., BeVier, supra note 29, at 286-87 ("Integrity characterizes a judicial process based on originalism and its lack is one of the chief deficiencies of its alternatives. Many proponents of originalism bemoan the discrepancy between what the Court does-and what its nonoriginalist cheerleaders urge it to do-and what it says it does. The originalists urge upon the Court the simple virtue of candor.").
  • 392
    • 66449083163 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Several examples are provided in William P. Marshall, Conservatives and the Seven Sins of Judicial Activism, 73 U. COLO. L. REV. 1217, 1229-32 (2002).
    • Several examples are provided in William P. Marshall, Conservatives and the Seven Sins of Judicial Activism, 73 U. COLO. L. REV. 1217, 1229-32 (2002).
  • 393
    • 66449130565 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Parents Involved in Cmty. Sch. v. Seattle Sch. Dist. No. 1, 127 S. Ct. 2738, 2768-88 (2007) (Thomas, J., concurring); Grutter v. Bollinger, 539 U.S. 306, 346-49 (2003) (Scalia, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part);
    • Parents Involved in Cmty. Sch. v. Seattle Sch. Dist. No. 1, 127 S. Ct. 2738, 2768-88 (2007) (Thomas, J., concurring); Grutter v. Bollinger, 539 U.S. 306, 346-49 (2003) (Scalia, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part);
  • 394
    • 66449135012 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 349-78 (Thomas, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part); Gratz v. Bollinger, 539 U.S. 244, 281 (2003) (Thomas, J., concurring).
    • id. at 349-78 (Thomas, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part); Gratz v. Bollinger, 539 U.S. 244, 281 (2003) (Thomas, J., concurring).
  • 395
    • 66449119849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Grutter, 539 U.S. at 349 (Scalia, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part).
    • Grutter, 539 U.S. at 349 (Scalia, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part).
  • 396
    • 66449134397 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 378 (Thomas, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part);
    • Id. at 378 (Thomas, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part);
  • 397
    • 66449135299 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Seattle Sch. Dist., 127 S. Ct. at 2782, 2787-88 (Thomas, J., concurring) (quoting Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U.S. 537, 559 (1896) (Harlan, J., dissenting)).
    • Seattle Sch. Dist., 127 S. Ct. at 2782, 2787-88 (Thomas, J., concurring) (quoting Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U.S. 537, 559 (1896) (Harlan, J., dissenting)).
  • 398
    • 66449093302 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., ANDREW KULL, THE COLOR-BLIND CONSTITUTION 82 (1992) (Bingham's preference-shared by the Thirty-ninth Congress and by most of our government authorities, most of the time since-was to retain the discretion to discriminate by race as appropriate.);
    • See, e.g., ANDREW KULL, THE COLOR-BLIND CONSTITUTION 82 (1992) ("Bingham's preference-shared by the Thirty-ninth Congress and by most of our government authorities, most of the time since-was to retain the discretion to discriminate by race as appropriate.");
  • 399
    • 0040067305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Affirmative Action, 107
    • providing examples of Reconstruction Era federal statutes that made special provision for colored poor and for colored soldiers and sailors
    • Jed Rubenfeld, Affirmative Action, 107 YALE L.J. 427, 430-31 (1997) (providing examples of Reconstruction Era federal statutes that made special provision for "colored" poor and for "colored" soldiers and sailors);
    • (1997) YALE L.J , vol.427 , pp. 430-431
    • Rubenfeld, J.1
  • 400
    • 0043103273 scopus 로고
    • Affirmative Action and the Legislative History of the Fourteenth Amendment, 71
    • noting that [t]he contemporaneous creation of the race-conscious Freedman's Bureau programs and the [F]ourteenth [A]mendment illuminates the amendment's meaning as allowing race-conscious policies
    • Eric Schnapper, Affirmative Action and the Legislative History of the Fourteenth Amendment, 71 VA. L. REV. 753, 789 (1985) (noting that "[t]he contemporaneous creation of the race-conscious Freedman's Bureau programs and the [F]ourteenth [A]mendment illuminates the amendment's meaning" as allowing race-conscious policies).
    • (1985) VA. L. REV , vol.753 , pp. 789
    • Schnapper, E.1
  • 401
    • 0036434497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Robert M. Howard & Jeffrey A. Segal, An Original Look at Originalism, 36 LAW & SOC'Y REV. 113,133 (2002) (describing authors' conclusion after analyzing 895 cases over eight Supreme Court terms from 1979 through 1994).
    • Robert M. Howard & Jeffrey A. Segal, An Original Look at Originalism, 36 LAW & SOC'Y REV. 113,133 (2002) (describing authors' conclusion after analyzing 895 cases over eight Supreme Court terms from 1979 through 1994).
  • 402
    • 66449106267 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BeVier, supra note 29, at 287 (quoting RICHARD A. POSNER, OVERCOMING LAW 245 (1995)).
    • BeVier, supra note 29, at 287 (quoting RICHARD A. POSNER, OVERCOMING LAW 245 (1995)).
  • 403
    • 84963456897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • notes 99 and 200
    • See supra notes 99 and 200.
    • See supra
  • 404
    • 66449112946 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kay, supra note 15, at 288
    • Kay, supra note 15, at 288.
  • 405
    • 66449087553 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 291-92
    • Id. at 291-92.
  • 406
    • 66449095544 scopus 로고
    • The Failure of Attacks on Constitutional Originalism, 4 CONST
    • For a similarly restrained defense of Originalism that appeared at just about the same time, see
    • For a similarly restrained defense of Originalism that appeared at just about the same time, see Earl M. Maltz, The Failure of Attacks on Constitutional Originalism, 4 CONST. COMMENT. 43 (1987).
    • (1987) COMMENT , vol.43
    • Maltz, E.M.1
  • 407
    • 66449089984 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a non-originalist argument that emphasizes how a clear-eyed assessment of who our judges are, or are likely to be, should bear on the choice of constitutional theory, see Fallon, supra note 17, at 562-72
    • For a non-originalist argument that emphasizes how a clear-eyed assessment of who our judges are, or are likely to be, should bear on the choice of constitutional theory, see Fallon, supra note 17, at 562-72.
  • 408
    • 66449119554 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fred Schauer diagnosed this problem a decade ago. Because nothing about originalism is obligatory as a matter of language or necessary to the very idea of having something that we call a constitution, Schauer explained, it turns out that we are then engaged in a range of political, moral, social, and institutional design questions to which there is more than one answer. Schauer, supra note 115, at 345. Originalists, he continued, have therefore failed to heed the teachings of legal realism: [O]ne of the lessons of legal realism is a continuing skepticism about the tendency of legal actors, lawyers, judges, and legal scholars to disguise in the language of necessity what are in fact political, social, moral, economic, philosophical, or policy choices. Nowhere is this tendency more apparent than in the many discussions of originalism. This tendency is due, in part, to the fall of both the proponents and opponents of originalism into the trap that the legal
    • Fred Schauer diagnosed this problem a decade ago. Because "nothing about originalism is obligatory as a matter of language or necessary to the very idea of having something that we call a constitution," Schauer explained, "it turns out that we are then engaged in a range of political, moral, social, and institutional design questions to which there is more than one answer." Schauer, supra note 115, at 345. Originalists, he continued, have therefore failed to heed the teachings of legal realism: [O]ne of the lessons of legal realism is a continuing skepticism about the tendency of legal actors, lawyers, judges, and legal scholars to disguise in the language of necessity what are in fact political, social, moral, economic, philosophical, or policy choices. Nowhere is this tendency more apparent than in the many discussions of originalism. This tendency is due, in part, to the fall of both
  • 409
    • 66449102885 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 345-46
    • Id. at 345-46.
  • 410
    • 66449116250 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Posner, supra note 173, at 1368-69 (criticizing Bork's defense of Originalism for its militance and dogmatism, and viewing his frequent use of religious imagery as symptom of desire to place the issue outside the boundaries of rational debate).
    • Cf. Posner, supra note 173, at 1368-69 (criticizing Bork's defense of Originalism for its "militance and dogmatism," and viewing his frequent use of religious imagery as symptom of desire "to place the issue outside the boundaries of rational debate").
  • 411
    • 66449098404 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kesavan & Paulsen, supra note 8, at 1142
    • Kesavan & Paulsen, supra note 8, at 1142.
  • 412
    • 66449085489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lawson, supra note 42, at 1250
    • Lawson, supra note 42, at 1250.
  • 413
    • 66449129734 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BORK, supra note 20, at 143
    • BORK, supra note 20, at 143.
  • 414
    • 0041557892 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Unoriginalism's Law Without Meaning, 15 CONST
    • Saikrishna B. Prakash, Unoriginalism's Law Without Meaning, 15 CONST. COMMENT. 529, 529-31 (1998).
    • (1998) COMMENT , vol.529 , pp. 529-531
    • Prakash, S.B.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.