메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 20, Issue 4, 2009, Pages 985-995

The concept of 'law' in global administrative law: A reply to Benedict Kingsbury

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 77952579046     PISSN: 09385428     EISSN: 14643596     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1093/ejil/chp091     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (47)

References (53)
  • 1
    • 33645847470 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Geology of International Law - Governance, Democracy and Legitimacy
    • See, generally, Weiler, 'The Geology of International Law - Governance, Democracy and Legitimacy', 64 Heidelberg Journal of International Law (ZaöRV) (2004) 547.
    • (2004) Heidelberg Journal of International Law (ZaöRV) , vol.64 , pp. 547
    • Weiler1
  • 2
    • 33645890269 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Introduction: Global Governance and Global Administrative Law in the International Legal Order
    • See Krisch and Kingsburg, 'Introduction: Global Governance and Global Administrative Law in the International Legal Order', 17 EJIL (2006) 1
    • (2006) EJIL , vol.17 , pp. 1
    • Krisch1    Kingsburg2
  • 3
    • 33645878922 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Global Administrative Law: The Quest for Principles and Values
    • For a similar observation see, at 209
    • For a similar observation see Harlow, 'Global Administrative Law: The Quest for Principles and Values', 17 EJIL (2006) 187, at 209
    • (2006) EJIL , vol.17 , pp. 187
    • Harlow1
  • 4
    • 84920753360 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Global Administrative Law and The Constitutional Ambition
    • M. Loughlin (ed.), (forthcoming)
    • Krisch, 'Global Administrative Law and The Constitutional Ambition', in M. Loughlin (ed.), The Twilight of Constitutional Law (forthcoming, 2010).
    • (2010) The Twilight of Constitutional Law
    • Krisch1
  • 5
    • 77952567872 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • This is not always the case. The declaration of refugee status by the UNHCR is an individual administrative act.
  • 6
    • 27744557047 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Emergence of Global Administrative Law
    • at 16
    • See Kingsbury, Krisch, and Stewart, 'The Emergence of Global Administrative Law', 68 L and Contemp Probs (2005) 15, at 16
    • (2005) L and Contemp Probs , vol.68 , pp. 15
    • Kingsbury1    Krisch2    Stewart3
  • 7
    • 0142186915 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Administrative Law Unbounded: Reflections on Government and Governance
    • On the pedigree of 'governance' from the pluralistic transformation of American administrative law into an instrument of participation and agreed-upon rule-making see the highly perceptive comments by, at 376
    • On the pedigree of 'governance' from the pluralistic transformation of American administrative law into an instrument of participation and agreed-upon rule-making see the highly perceptive comments by Shapiro, 'Administrative Law Unbounded: Reflections on Government and Governance', 8 Indiana J Global Legal Stud (2001) 369, at 376
    • (2001) Indiana J Global Legal Stud , vol.8 , pp. 369
    • Shapiro1
  • 8
    • 1042291037 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hegemonic International Law Revisited
    • See Alvarez, 'Hegemonic International Law Revisited', 97 AJIL (2003) 873
    • (2003) AJIL , vol.97 , pp. 873
    • Alvarez1
  • 9
    • 33645136625 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Law in a Time of Emergency: States of Emergency and the Temptations of 9/11
    • Scheppele, 'Law in a Time of Emergency: States of Emergency and the Temptations of 9/11', 6 U Pennsylvania J Constitutional L (2004) 1001
    • (2004) U Pennsylvania J Constitutional L , vol.6 , pp. 1001
    • Scheppele1
  • 11
    • 70149119369 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Naming Global Administrative Law
    • For apt remarks as regards this more limited agenda
    • For apt remarks as regards this more limited agenda see Marks, 'Naming Global Administrative Law', 37 Int'l L and Politics (2005) 995
    • (2005) Int'l L and Politics , vol.37 , pp. 995
    • Marks1
  • 12
    • 77952570075 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • goes to great pains to distinguish rule of law principles, such as legality and limited powers, from good governance values, such as transparency and participation. She sees the latter as originating from World Bank and International Monetary Fund policies and denies them the stature of genuine administrative law principles. I can imagine that American scholars would have a different take on this.
  • 13
  • 14
    • 48049118237 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Developing Democracy beyond the State
    • See, e.g., on the Poverty Reduction Strategy of the International Financial Institutions de Búrca, at 264-266
    • See, e.g., on the Poverty Reduction Strategy of the International Financial Institutions de Búrca, 'Developing Democracy beyond the State', 46 Columbia J Transnat'l L (2008) 221, at 264-266.
    • (2008) Columbia J Transnat'l L , vol.46 , pp. 221
  • 15
    • 0041580951 scopus 로고
    • Die Lehre von den drei Gewalten oder Funktionen des Staates
    • For a discussion of this problem
    • For a discussion of this problem see Kelsen, 'Die Lehre von den drei Gewalten oder Funktionen des Staates', 17 Archiv für Rechts- und Wirtschaftsphilosophie (1923-24) 374
    • (1923) Archiv für Rechts- und Wirtschaftsphilosophie , vol.17 , pp. 374
    • Kelsen1
  • 16
    • 77952577185 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • My bet is that Krisch would raise this objection
  • 17
    • 77952570896 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On accounting standard-setting, S. Cassese et al. (eds), (2nd edn)
    • On accounting standard-setting see S. Cassese et al. (eds), Global Administrative Law: Cases, Materials, Issues (2nd edn, 2008), at 9-13.
    • (2008) Global Administrative Law: Cases, Materials, Issues , pp. 9-13
  • 18
    • 1942482459 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Redundancy of Soft Law
    • See Klabbers, 'The Redundancy of Soft Law', 65 Nordic J Int'l L (1996) 167
    • (1996) Nordic J Int'l L , vol.65 , pp. 167
    • Klabbers1
  • 20
    • 65149092512 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Concept of "Law" in Global Administrative Law
    • See Kingsbury, 'The Concept of "Law" in Global Administrative Law', 20 EJIL (2009) 23
    • (2009) EJIL , vol.20 , pp. 23
    • Kingsbury1
  • 21
    • 3843097697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Inclusive Legal Positivism
    • For a very helpful introduction, J. Coleman and S. Shapiro (eds)
    • For a very helpful introduction see Himma, 'Inclusive Legal Positivism', in J. Coleman and S. Shapiro (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law (2002), at 125-165
    • (2002) The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law , pp. 125-165
    • Himma1
  • 25
    • 77952561079 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • It should be borne in mind that, according to legal positivists, sources of law cannot be tantamount to sources of confusion
  • 26
    • 77952569926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • In other words, a legal system based upon the second-order rule that 'all good laws are valid laws' would be too indeterminate to constitute a relevant social fact, unless of course the meaning of this rule were further specified by conventions
  • 27
    • 77952557145 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Readers need not be reminded of the fact that 'publicness' is a part of the long-established inventory of liberal legal theory
  • 29
    • 77952557791 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • More cautiously, the principle of publicness has been recently explained by Waldron. He believes it to refer to the 'fact' that law represents 'a set of norms made publicly and issued in the name of the public, norms which ordinary people can in some sense appropriate as their own, qua members of the public'
  • 30
    • 77952566155 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 08-35 NYU Public Law & Legal Theory Research Paper Series, available at
    • see Waldron, 'Can There Be a Democratic Jurisprudence', 08-35 NYU Public Law & Legal Theory Research Paper Series (2008), available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1280923, at 14.
    • (2008) Can There Be a Democratic Jurisprudence , pp. 14
    • Waldron1
  • 32
    • 77952557565 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Hence, e.g., the 'legal positivism' advocated by Waldron, supra note 27, is not the type of legal positivism which tries to offer an alternative to normative political philosophy. Rather, in this case certain commendable features of legal positivism are made subservient to a certain vision of how law is supposed to work in a good society. This is reminiscent of the legal positivism of the Republic of Weimar, where it was also understood to be the attitude of those supporting democracy
  • 34
    • 77952561866 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Kingsbury, speaks of 'specific rules of recognition in particular governance regimes'
  • 35
    • 77952559798 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Natural law is that part of law for which reason understands the necessity of its existence
  • 37
    • 0346582090 scopus 로고
    • The Grotian Tradition in International Law
    • See H. Lauterpacht, 'The Grotian Tradition in International Law', 23 British Yrbk Int'l L (1946) 1.
    • (1946) British Yrbk Int'l L , vol.23 , pp. 1
    • Lauterpacht, H.1
  • 38
    • 77952569366 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a similar observation that Kingsbury supports a morally more ambitious conception of international law than he is ready to concede, H.S. Richardson and M.S. Williams (eds), at 214
    • For a similar observation that Kingsbury supports a morally more ambitious conception of international law than he is ready to concede see Scheuerman, '"The Centre Cannot Hold": A Response to Benedict Kingsbury', in H.S. Richardson and M.S. Williams (eds), Moral Universalism and Pluralism (2009) 205, at 214.
    • (2009) "The Centre Cannot Hold": A Response to Benedict Kingsbury Moral Universalism and Pluralism , pp. 205
    • Scheuerman1
  • 40
    • 77952566156 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Kingsbury explains his preference for legal positivism quite straightforwardly as following from the need to 'provide a baseline acceptability in the absence of agreement on content-based (or truth-based) criteria for determining what law is'
  • 41
    • 77952568827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • This is paradoxical, for it is they who are supposed to apply the law. How can they cash in on their promise to say what the law is if they are not concerned about what it is they call 'law'?
  • 42
    • 77952569662 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • This explains why, contrary to the expressed confidence of those calling themselves legal pragmatists, there can be no 'legal pragmatism', that is, a jurisprudence which does not address what type of justification there might be for having recourse to law without sources. The usual suspects are natural law theory, romantic historicism, and evolution of rationality. The first has much currency, but remains notoriously intuitionistic; the second is intellectually fascinating, but dead; and defending the third would require very detailed study of the development of legal institutions.
  • 43
    • 0009115887 scopus 로고
    • Pragmatism, Rights Answers, and True Banality
    • On pragmatism, M. Brint and W. Weaver (eds)
    • On pragmatism see Dworkin, 'Pragmatism, Rights Answers, and True Banality', in M. Brint and W. Weaver (eds), Pragmatism in Law and Society (1991) 359.
    • (1991) Pragmatism in Law and Society , pp. 359
    • Dworkin1
  • 44
    • 77952563368 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • It is quite telling that the most useful and brilliant B.H. Bix, Dictionary of Legal Theory (2004) does not have an entry for 'sanctions'. When it comes to 'coercion' the reader is referred to 'duress'. It is amazing to see this happening in a legal culture where the criminal justice system is a far cry from being lenient or mild. It reveals something about the mentality of the discipline.
  • 45
    • 79954086688 scopus 로고
    • It is, of course, not the case that the element is not paid attention to by some working in the Anglo-American tradition: see, e.g., (ed. K. I. Winston)
    • It is, of course, not the case that the element is not paid attention to by some working in the Anglo-American tradition: see, e.g., L. Fuller, The Principles of Social Order: Selected Essays (ed. K. I. Winston, 1981), at 234
    • (1981) The Principles of Social Order: Selected Essays , pp. 234
    • Fuller, L.1
  • 49
    • 85178212178 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Developing the Publicness of Public International Law: Towards a Legal Framework for Global Governance Activities
    • For a similar intervention, available at
    • For a similar intervention see von Bogdandy, Dann, and Goldmann, 'Developing the Publicness of Public International Law: Towards a Legal Framework for Global Governance Activities', 9 German LJ (2008), available at: www.germanlawjournal.com/pdf/Vol09No11/PDF_Vol_09_No_11_1375-1400_Articles_von%20Bogdandy_Dann_Goldmann.pdf.
    • (2008) German LJ , pp. 9
    • von Bogdandy1    Dann2    Goldmann3
  • 50
    • 77952555560 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • I understand that this statement would require further qualification as regards so-called 'privileges'
  • 51
    • 77952555297 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • In his work Jellinek famously distinguished several such status: along with the status libertatis created by negative rights also the status activus of citizens and the status positivus of those having positive rights against the state
  • 52
    • 77952572784 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • stating that GAL does not take domestic administrative law as its norm, but merely as inspiration and contrast
  • 53
    • 84905890630 scopus 로고
    • Towards Relative Normativity in International Law?
    • See Weil, 'Towards Relative Normativity in International Law?', 77 AJIL (1983) 413
    • (1983) AJIL , vol.77 , pp. 413
    • Weil1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.