메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 94, Issue 4, 2009, Pages 889-947

Virtue and rights in american property law

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 68949122322     PISSN: 00108847     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Note
Times cited : (20)

References (296)
  • 1
    • 84869694860 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • PLATO, THE REPUBLIC 372d4-5 [hereinafter REPUBLIC]; PLATO, THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO 49 (Allan Bloom trans., 2d ed. 1991) [hereinafter REPUBLIC (Bloom trans.)]. Bloom translates the Greek term hyôn as sows; pigs is a more common translation. For Socrates' sketch of the city of comfortable preservation, see REPUBLIC, supra, at 369b5-372d2; REPUBLIC (Bloom trans.), supra at 46-49.
    • PLATO, THE REPUBLIC 372d4-5 [hereinafter REPUBLIC]; PLATO, THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO 49 (Allan Bloom trans., 2d ed. 1991) [hereinafter REPUBLIC (Bloom trans.)]. Bloom translates the Greek term hyôn as "sows"; "pigs" is a more common translation. For Socrates' sketch of the city of comfortable preservation, see REPUBLIC, supra, at 369b5-372d2; REPUBLIC (Bloom trans.), supra at 46-49.
  • 2
    • 68949095715 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See REPUBLIC, supra note 1, at 428e2-429a4; REPUBLIC (Bloom trans.), supra note 1, at 107.
    • See REPUBLIC, supra note 1, at 428e2-429a4; REPUBLIC (Bloom trans.), supra note 1, at 107.
  • 3
    • 68949095609 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See REPUBLIC, supra note 1, at 464b8-465e2; REPUBLIC (Bloom trans.), supra note 1, at 143-45.
    • See REPUBLIC, supra note 1, at 464b8-465e2; REPUBLIC (Bloom trans.), supra note 1, at 143-45.
  • 4
    • 68949178259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gregory S. Alexander, The Social-Obligation Norm in American Property Law, 94 CORNELL L. REV. 745 (2009).
    • Gregory S. Alexander, The Social-Obligation Norm in American Property Law, 94 CORNELL L. REV. 745 (2009).
  • 6
    • 68949134277 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Alexander, supra note 4, at 747-48, 750-51
    • See Alexander, supra note 4, at 747-48, 750-51.
  • 7
    • 84869694859 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Peñalver, supra note 5, at 832-60
    • See Peñalver, supra note 5, at 832-60.
  • 8
    • 68949095714 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For one helpful overview, see Jules L. Coleman, The Grounds of Welfare, 112 YALE LJ. 1511, 1514-20 (2003) (reviewing LOUIS KAPLOW SC STEVEN SHAVELL, FAIRNESS VERSUS WELFARE (2002)). Throughout this Response, I assume that economic analysis integrates explanation, normative prescriptions, and underlying practical philosophy in a manner similar to that in which theories of practical philosophy do. That assumption may seem a category mistake to many readers, but it would be too distracting for me to question the assumption here.
    • For one helpful overview, see Jules L. Coleman, The Grounds of Welfare, 112 YALE LJ. 1511, 1514-20 (2003) (reviewing LOUIS KAPLOW SC STEVEN SHAVELL, FAIRNESS VERSUS WELFARE (2002)). Throughout this Response, I assume that "economic analysis" integrates explanation, normative prescriptions, and underlying practical philosophy in a manner similar to that in which theories of practical philosophy do. That assumption may seem a category mistake to many readers, but it would be too distracting for me to question the assumption here.
  • 9
    • 34248536522 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Transparency and Determinacy in Common Law Adjudication: A Philosophical Defense of Explanatory Economic Analysis, 93
    • Jody S. Kraus, Transparency and Determinacy in Common Law Adjudication: A Philosophical Defense of Explanatory Economic Analysis, 93 VA. L. REV. 287, 357 (2007).
    • (2007) VA. L. REV , vol.287 , pp. 357
    • Kraus, J.S.1
  • 10
    • 68949153498 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For dissenting opinions, consider JULES L. COLEMAN, THE PRACTICE OF PRINCIPLE: IN DEFENCE OF A PRAGMATIST APPROACH TO LEGAL THEORY 1-63 (2001); STEPHEN A. SMITH, CONTRACT THEORY 14-31 (2004).
    • For dissenting opinions, consider JULES L. COLEMAN, THE PRACTICE OF PRINCIPLE: IN DEFENCE OF A PRAGMATIST APPROACH TO LEGAL THEORY 1-63 (2001); STEPHEN A. SMITH, CONTRACT THEORY 14-31 (2004).
  • 11
    • 84869696032 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Peñalver, supra note 5, at 860-86
    • See Peñalver, supra note 5, at 860-86.
  • 13
    • 77956365058 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Eric R. Claeys, Jefferson Meets Coase: Land-Use Torts, Law and Economics, and Natural Property Rights, 85 NOTRE DAME L. REV. (fordicoming 2010), manuscript at 3-4 (George Mason Univ. Sch. Law & Econ. Research Paper No. 08-20, 2008), available at http://ssrn. com/abstract=l 117999.
    • See Eric R. Claeys, Jefferson Meets Coase: Land-Use Torts, Law and Economics, and Natural Property Rights, 85 NOTRE DAME L. REV. (fordicoming 2010), manuscript at 3-4 (George Mason Univ. Sch. Law & Econ. Research Paper No. 08-20, 2008), available at http://ssrn. com/abstract=l 117999.
  • 14
    • 68949153309 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This response uses the term practical philosophy to describe philosophical inquiry studying human action and its proper ends and constraints, For another example of this usage, see Stephen Buckle, Aristotle's Republic or, Why Aristotle's Ethics Is Not Virtue Ethics, 77 PHIL. 565, 575 (2002), As used here, practical philosophy encompasses ethical philosophy, the inquiry into individual human action, and political philosophy, the inquiry into human action by groups organized into cities, nations, and other political communities. The term excludes conceptual philosophy and philosophical investigation into nonhuman phenomena. Most other forms of philosophy are devoted solely to understanding phenomena; practical philosophy makes primary the question of how humans ought to live and act. See ARISTOTLE, NICOMACHEAN ETHICS II.2, at 1103b26-32 [hereinafter NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, ARISTO
    • This response uses the term "practical philosophy" to describe philosophical inquiry studying human action and its proper ends and constraints. (For another example of this usage, see Stephen Buckle, Aristotle's Republic or, Why Aristotle's Ethics Is Not Virtue Ethics, 77 PHIL. 565, 575 (2002).) As used here, "practical philosophy" encompasses "ethical philosophy," the inquiry into individual human action, and "political philosophy," the inquiry into human action by groups organized into cities, nations, and other political communities. The term excludes conceptual philosophy and philosophical investigation into nonhuman phenomena. Most other forms of philosophy are devoted solely to understanding phenomena; practical philosophy makes primary the question of how humans ought to live and act. See ARISTOTLE, NICOMACHEAN ETHICS II.2, at 1103b26-32 [hereinafter NICOMACHEAN ETHICS]; ARISTOTLE, NICOMACHEAN ETHICS 23 (Joe Sachs trans., 2002) [hereinafter NICOMACHEAN ETHICS (Sachs trans.)].
  • 15
    • 84974286205 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral philosophy might be a more fitting term for the subject matter considered here. This Response will use moral when absolutely necessary to do so as a synonym for applying a general metaethics and philosophical approach to a practical situation but will avoid its use otherwise. Some scholars equate moral with ethical so that it excludes the political. In addition, for many readers, the term moral presumes the law conception of ethics that G.E.M. Anscombe deplored and sought to overcome by the recovery of virtue ethics. G.E.M. Anscombe, Modern Moral Philosophy, 33 PHIL. 1, 5 (1958). In that light, the term moral has some built-in tendency in favor of deontological and against consequentialist theories of practical action.
    • "Moral" philosophy might be a more fitting term for the subject matter considered here. This Response will use "moral" when absolutely necessary to do so as a synonym for "applying a general metaethics and philosophical approach to a practical situation" but will avoid its use otherwise. Some scholars equate "moral" with "ethical" so that it excludes the "political." In addition, for many readers, the term "moral" presumes the "law conception of ethics" that G.E.M. Anscombe deplored and sought to overcome by the recovery of virtue ethics. G.E.M. Anscombe, Modern Moral Philosophy, 33 PHIL. 1, 5 (1958). In that light, the term "moral" has some built-in tendency in favor of deontological and against consequentialist theories of practical action.
  • 16
    • 68949138378 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Bernard Williams, Morality, The Peculiar Institution, in VIRTUE ETHICS 45, 48-49 (Roger Crisp & Michael Slote eds., 1997) (contrasting utilitarianism with deontology by calling the former a marginal member of the morality system and the latter the central . . . version of morality).
    • See, e.g., Bernard Williams, Morality, The Peculiar Institution, in VIRTUE ETHICS 45, 48-49 (Roger Crisp & Michael Slote eds., 1997) (contrasting utilitarianism with deontology by calling the former "a marginal member of the morality system" and the latter the "central . . . version of morality").
  • 18
    • 68949139647 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id.; Roger Crisp & Michael Slote, Introduction, in VIRTUE ETHICS, supranote 14, at 1, 1-2; Robert B. Louden, Toward a Genealogy of Deontology,'34 J. HIST. PHIL. 571 (1996); Gregory Trianosky, What Is Virtue Ethics All About?, 27 AM. PHIL. Q 335, 338 (1990).
    • See id.; Roger Crisp & Michael Slote, Introduction, in VIRTUE ETHICS, supranote 14, at 1, 1-2; Robert B. Louden, Toward a Genealogy of Deontology,'34 J. HIST. PHIL. 571 (1996); Gregory Trianosky, What Is Virtue Ethics All About?, 27 AM. PHIL. Q 335, 338 (1990).
  • 19
    • 84869696031 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 15, §1. 18
    • Alexander & Moore, supra note 15, §1. 18 Id.
    • Id
    • Alexander1    Moore2
  • 20
    • 68949132385 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., ROSALIND HURSTHOUSE, ON VIRTUE ETHICS 37-38 (1999) (identifying inadequacy in the slogan 'Utilitarianism begins with the Good, deontology with the Right' ) (emphasis added) ; Trianosky, supra note 16, at 335 (listing nine tenets of neo-Kantianism and warning that these tenets are not necessarily Kant's own view and are not always uniformly understood or carefully distinguished by [their] adversaries).
    • See, e.g., ROSALIND HURSTHOUSE, ON VIRTUE ETHICS 37-38 (1999) (identifying "inadequacy in the slogan 'Utilitarianism begins with the Good, deontology with the Right' ") (emphasis added) ; Trianosky, supra note 16, at 335 (listing nine tenets of "neo-Kantianism" and warning that these tenets are "not necessarily Kant's own view" and are not always "uniformly understood or carefully distinguished by [their] adversaries").
  • 21
    • 68949139874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Consider Michael S. Moore's usage in Michael S. Moore, Patrolling the Borders of Consequentialist fustifications: The Scope of Agent-Relative Restrictions, 27 LAW & PHIL. 35 passim (2007).
    • Consider Michael S. Moore's usage in Michael S. Moore, Patrolling the Borders of Consequentialist fustifications: The Scope of Agent-Relative Restrictions, 27 LAW & PHIL. 35 passim (2007).
  • 22
    • 68949093512 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See IMMANUEL KANT, FOUNDATIONS OF THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS 401, at 17 (Lewis White Beck trans., Macmillan Publ'g Co. 2d ed. 1990) (1785) (Thus the moral worth of an action does not lie in the effect which is expected from it or in any principle of action which has to borrow its motive from this expected effect. For all these effects ... could be brought about through other causes and would not require the will of a rational being, while the highest and unconditional good can be found only in such a will.). Here and subsequendy, the first page citation refers to Kant's original pagination (which Beck provides in the margins), the second to the translation in the Beck edition.
    • See IMMANUEL KANT, FOUNDATIONS OF THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS 401, at 17 (Lewis White Beck trans., Macmillan Publ'g Co. 2d ed. 1990) (1785) ("Thus the moral worth of an action does not lie in the effect which is expected from it or in any principle of action which has to borrow its motive from this expected effect. For all these effects ... could be brought about through other causes and would not require the will of a rational being, while the highest and unconditional good can be found only in such a will."). Here and subsequendy, the first page citation refers to Kant's original pagination (which Beck provides in the margins), the second to the translation in the Beck edition.
  • 23
    • 84869707050 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, Consequentialism, in STANFORD ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY §§1, 3 (rev. ed. Spring 2006), http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ consequentialism (citing JEREMY BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION (1789); JOHN STUART MILL, UTILITARIANISM (1861); HENRY SIDGWICK, THE METHODS OF ETHICS (1874)); accord Justin Oakley, Varieties of Virtue Ethics, 9 RATIO 128, 143 (1996).
    • Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, Consequentialism, in STANFORD ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY §§1, 3 (rev. ed. Spring 2006), http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ consequentialism (citing JEREMY BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION (1789); JOHN STUART MILL, UTILITARIANISM (1861); HENRY SIDGWICK, THE METHODS OF ETHICS (1874)); accord Justin Oakley, Varieties of Virtue Ethics, 9 RATIO 128, 143 (1996).
  • 24
    • 68949153272 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KAPLOW & SHAVELL, supra note 8; see also id. at 16-38; accord LIAM MURPHY & THOMAS NAGEL, THE MYTH OF OWNERSHIP 42 (2002) (assuming and applying the distinction between consequentialist and deontological theories of action).
    • KAPLOW & SHAVELL, supra note 8; see also id. at 16-38; accord LIAM MURPHY & THOMAS NAGEL, THE MYTH OF OWNERSHIP 42 (2002) (assuming and applying the distinction between consequentialist and deontological theories of action).
  • 25
    • 68949138364 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • And, more generally, the social science-versus-humanities divide
    • And, more generally, the social science-versus-humanities divide.
  • 26
    • 68949138493 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See JOHN RAWLS, A THEORY OF JUSTICE 23-32 (1971).
    • See JOHN RAWLS, A THEORY OF JUSTICE 23-32 (1971).
  • 27
    • 68949138640 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ROBERT NOZICK, ANARCHY, STATE, AND UTOPIA 28-33, 300-04 (1974).
    • See ROBERT NOZICK, ANARCHY, STATE, AND UTOPIA 28-33, 300-04 (1974).
  • 28
    • 68949095610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., ARTHUR RIPSTEIN, EQUALITY, RESPONSIBILITY, AND THE LAW 4 (1999); ERNEST J. WEINRIB, THE IDEA OF PRIVATE LAW 84-113 (1995).
    • See, e.g., ARTHUR RIPSTEIN, EQUALITY, RESPONSIBILITY, AND THE LAW 4 (1999); ERNEST J. WEINRIB, THE IDEA OF PRIVATE LAW 84-113 (1995).
  • 29
    • 68949095519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KAPLOW & SHAVELL, supra note 8, at 43
    • KAPLOW & SHAVELL, supra note 8, at 43.
  • 31
    • 68949095449 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Coleman, supra note 8, at 1512
    • Coleman, supra note 8, at 1512.
  • 32
    • 68949111585 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, Oakley, supra note 22, at 128
    • See, e.g., Oakley, supra note 22, at 128.
  • 33
    • 68949134267 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Anscombe, supra note 14
    • Anscombe, supra note 14.
  • 34
    • 68949139930 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 2
    • Id. at 2.
  • 35
    • 68949122240 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ALASDAIR MACINTYRE, Hume on the 'Is' and the 'Ought, ' in AGAINST THE SELF-IMAGES OF THE AGE 109, 124 (Univ. Notre Dame Press, 2d prtg. 1984) (1971).
    • ALASDAIR MACINTYRE, Hume on the 'Is' and the 'Ought, ' in AGAINST THE SELF-IMAGES OF THE AGE 109, 124 (Univ. Notre Dame Press, 2d prtg. 1984) (1971).
  • 36
    • 84970773446 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Michael Walzer, Liberalism and the Art of Separation, 12 POL. THEORY 315, 324 (1984).
    • Michael Walzer, Liberalism and the Art of Separation, 12 POL. THEORY 315, 324 (1984).
  • 37
    • 0030531851 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ingrid Creppell, Locke on Toleration: The Transformation of Constraint, 24 POL. THEORY 200, 201 (1996).
    • Ingrid Creppell, Locke on Toleration: The Transformation of Constraint, 24 POL. THEORY 200, 201 (1996).
  • 38
    • 68949139643 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BARBARA HERMAN, Making Room for Character, in MORAL LITERACY 1-28 (2007). For other defenses of deontological ediics, see BARBARA HERMAN, THE PRACTICE OF MORAL JUDGMENT (1993); ROBERT B. LOUDEN, KANT'S IMPURE ETHICS: FROM RATIONAL BEINGS TO HUMAN BEINCS (2000); ROBERT B. LOUDEN, MORALITY AND MORAL THEORY: A REAPPRAISAL AND REAFFIRMATION (1992); J.B. Schneewind, The Misfortunes of Virtue, 101 ETHICS 42 (1990).
    • See BARBARA HERMAN, Making Room for Character, in MORAL LITERACY 1-28 (2007). For other defenses of deontological ediics, see BARBARA HERMAN, THE PRACTICE OF MORAL JUDGMENT (1993); ROBERT B. LOUDEN, KANT'S IMPURE ETHICS: FROM RATIONAL BEINGS TO HUMAN BEINCS (2000); ROBERT B. LOUDEN, MORALITY AND MORAL THEORY: A REAPPRAISAL AND REAFFIRMATION (1992); J.B. Schneewind, The Misfortunes of Virtue, 101 ETHICS 42 (1990).
  • 39
    • 0039283440 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Buckle, supra note 14, at 566-67 (conceding that Kant treats the virtues); Mardia C. Nussbaum, Virtue Ethics: A Misleading Category?, 3 J. ETHICS 163, 165, 170 (1999) (same); id. at 170 (same for Rawls).
    • See Buckle, supra note 14, at 566-67 (conceding that Kant treats the virtues); Mardia C. Nussbaum, Virtue Ethics: A Misleading Category?, 3 J. ETHICS 163, 165, 170 (1999) (same); id. at 170 (same for Rawls).
  • 40
    • 68949139850 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KANT, supra note 21, at 422, 38
    • KANT, supra note 21, at 422, 38.
  • 41
    • 68949139941 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ARISTOTLE, POLITICS III.6, at 1278b28-30 [hereinafter POLITICS]; ARISTOTLE, THE POLITICS 94 (Carnes Lord trans., Univ. of Chicago Press 1984) [hereinafter POLITICS (Lord trans.)].
    • ARISTOTLE, POLITICS III.6, at 1278b28-30 [hereinafter POLITICS]; ARISTOTLE, THE POLITICS 94 (Carnes Lord trans., Univ. of Chicago Press 1984) [hereinafter POLITICS (Lord trans.)].
  • 42
    • 68949134275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Trianosky, supra note 16, at 339 (complaining that the Kantian tradition does take morality to be autonomous in the extreme); accord Nussbaum, supra note 38, at 173 ([I]f emotions are just subrational stirrings or pushes that have nothing to do with drought or intentionality, there is not much that is interesting to be said about their relationship to ethics. They can be fed or starved, but they cannot be cultivated as parts of a character that has a unitary focus.).
    • See Trianosky, supra note 16, at 339 (complaining that "the Kantian tradition does take morality to be autonomous in the extreme"); accord Nussbaum, supra note 38, at 173 ("[I]f emotions are just subrational stirrings or pushes that have nothing to do with drought or intentionality, there is not much that is interesting to be said about their relationship to ethics. They can be fed or starved, but they cannot be cultivated as parts of a character that has a unitary focus.").
  • 43
    • 68949095448 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RICHARD A. EPSTEIN, PRINCIPLES FOR A FREE SOCIETY: RECONCILING INDIVIDUAL LIBERTY WITH THE COMMON GOOD 15 (1998).
    • RICHARD A. EPSTEIN, PRINCIPLES FOR A FREE SOCIETY: RECONCILING INDIVIDUAL LIBERTY WITH THE COMMON GOOD 15 (1998).
  • 44
    • 0345881750 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Richard A. Epstein, Intellectual Property: Old Boundaries and New Frontiers, 76 IND. LJ. 803, 805-06 (2001).
    • Richard A. Epstein, Intellectual Property: Old Boundaries and New Frontiers, 76 IND. LJ. 803, 805-06 (2001).
  • 45
    • 84869694886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 15, §4. 45
    • Alexander & Moore, supra note 15, §4. 45 Id.
    • Id
    • Alexander1    Moore2
  • 46
    • 68949139888 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JAMES GORDLEY, FOUNDATIONS OF PRIVATE LAW: PROPERTY, TORT, CONTRACT, UNJUST ENRICHMENT 11 (2006).
    • JAMES GORDLEY, FOUNDATIONS OF PRIVATE LAW: PROPERTY, TORT, CONTRACT, UNJUST ENRICHMENT 11 (2006).
  • 47
    • 68949139849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 11-12 (quoting SMITH, supra note 10, at 52 n.16).
    • Id. at 11-12 (quoting SMITH, supra note 10, at 52 n.16).
  • 48
    • 68949138413 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KAPLOW & SHAVELL, supra note 8, at 52
    • KAPLOW & SHAVELL, supra note 8, at 52.
  • 50
    • 68949095517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 58. For a lengdiier critique of Kaplow and Shavell's argument, suggesting that the argument is analytically tautological, see Coleman, supra note 8, at 1525-30
    • Id. at 58. For a lengdiier critique of Kaplow and Shavell's argument, suggesting that the argument is analytically tautological, see Coleman, supra note 8, at 1525-30.
  • 51
    • 68949095518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KAPLOW & SHAVELL, supra note 8, at 52 n.72 (citing J.J.C. Smart, Introduction, in J.J.C. SMART & BERNARD WILLIAMS, UTILITARIANISM: FOR AND AGAINST 5 (1973)).
    • KAPLOW & SHAVELL, supra note 8, at 52 n.72 (citing J.J.C. Smart, Introduction, in J.J.C. SMART & BERNARD WILLIAMS, UTILITARIANISM: FOR AND AGAINST 5 (1973)).
  • 52
    • 84869707117 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See MARGARET JANE RADIN, R EINTERPRETING PROPERTY 108-09 (1993). Until roughly 1985, Epstein was more properly classified as a deontologist. Compare Larry Alexander & Maimón Schwarzschild, TAe Uncertain Relationship Between Libertarianism and Utilitarianism, 19 QUINNIPIAC L. REV. 657 (2000) (critiquing Epstein's current metaethics), with Richard A. Epstein, 7'Ae Uneasy Marriage of Utilitarian and Libertarian Thought, 19 QUINNIPIAC L. REV. 783, 787-90 (2000) (clarifying his utilitarian theory and defending them from Alexander and Schwarzschild's critique). Unless the text (as here) indicates otherwise, when I refer to Epstein, I mean the utilitarian Epstein.
    • See MARGARET JANE RADIN, R EINTERPRETING PROPERTY 108-09 (1993). Until roughly 1985, Epstein was more properly classified as a deontologist. Compare Larry Alexander & Maimón Schwarzschild, TAe Uncertain Relationship Between Libertarianism and Utilitarianism, 19 QUINNIPIAC L. REV. 657 (2000) (critiquing Epstein's current metaethics), with Richard A. Epstein, 7'Ae Uneasy Marriage of Utilitarian and Libertarian Thought, 19 QUINNIPIAC L. REV. 783, 787-90 (2000) (clarifying his utilitarian theory and defending them from Alexander and Schwarzschild's critique). Unless the text (as here) indicates otherwise, when I refer to Epstein, I mean the utilitarian Epstein.
  • 53
    • 68949138411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Adverse possession illustrates the deontology trap even if the deontological claim right runs the other way. Assume the squatter's claim to ownership is grounded in a deontological labor-desert right to control and enjoy land he is actually using. That deontological right might then come under pressure from consequentialist considerations about the utility of clear land titles. Among other tilings, clear titles reduce disputes over land and land use, and they simplify commercial land transactions. As in the text, as soon as the consequentialist considerations outweigh the deontological right, the philosophical justification of adverse possession seems weak or incoherent. See RADIN, supra note 52, at 107-09.
    • Adverse possession illustrates the deontology trap even if the deontological claim right runs the other way. Assume the squatter's claim to ownership is grounded in a deontological labor-desert right to control and enjoy land he is actually using. That deontological right might then come under pressure from consequentialist considerations about the utility of clear land titles. Among other tilings, clear titles reduce disputes over land and land use, and they simplify commercial land transactions. As in the text, as soon as the consequentialist considerations outweigh the deontological right, the philosophical justification of adverse possession seems weak or incoherent. See RADIN, supra note 52, at 107-09.
  • 54
    • 68949138361 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 109
    • Id. at 109.
  • 55
    • 68949153312 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 56
    • 68949138464 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Julia Annas, Virtue Ethics, in THE OXFORD HANDBOOK OF ETHICAL THEORY 515 (David Copp ed., 2005).
    • Julia Annas, Virtue Ethics, in THE OXFORD HANDBOOK OF ETHICAL THEORY 515 (David Copp ed., 2005).
  • 57
    • 68949126675 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Or, more specifically, the tradition of political philosophy corresponding to the tradition of ethical philosophy to which Annas is referring. See
    • Or, more specifically, the tradition of political philosophy corresponding to the tradition of ethical philosophy to which Annas is referring. See infra part II.
    • infra , Issue.PART II
  • 58
    • 68949095421 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., GORDLEY, supra note 46, at 148-54 (recounting influence of Aquinas and Scholastic conceptions of use on subsequent property law). See generally STEPHEN BUCKLE, NATURAL LAW AND THE THEORY OF PROPERTY: GROTIUS TO HUME (1991) (tracing the development of property rights in early Enlightenment natural-law and -rights theories).
  • 59
    • 68949095500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For other reference guides, see Rosalind Hursthouse, Virtue Ethics, in STANFORD ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY (rev. ed. Fall 2007), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall 2007/entries/ethics-virtue/; Oakley, supra note 22, at 132-34; Lawrence B. Solum, Natural Justice, 51 AM. J. JURIS. 65, 71 (2006).
    • For other reference guides, see Rosalind Hursthouse, Virtue Ethics, in STANFORD ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY (rev. ed. Fall 2007), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall 2007/entries/ethics-virtue/; Oakley, supra note 22, at 132-34; Lawrence B. Solum, Natural Justice, 51 AM. J. JURIS. 65, 71 (2006).
  • 60
    • 68949139875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HURSTHOUSE, supra note 19, at 1
    • HURSTHOUSE, supra note 19, at 1.
  • 61
    • 84869696027 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Peñalver, supra note 5, at 864
    • Peñalver, supra note 5, at 864.
  • 62
    • 68949138465 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Alexander, supra note 4, at 748
    • See Alexander, supra note 4, at 748.
  • 63
    • 68949139646 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, supra note 14, 1.4, at 1095al6; NICOMACHEAN ETHICS (Sachs trans.), supra note 14, at 3.
    • See NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, supra note 14, 1.4, at 1095al6; NICOMACHEAN ETHICS (Sachs trans.), supra note 14, at 3.
  • 64
    • 84869694884 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hursdiouse, supra note 59, §2. See also id. (The trouble with 'happiness', on any contemporary understanding of it uninfluenced by classically trained writers, is that it connotes somediing which is subjectively determined.).
    • Hursdiouse, supra note 59, §2. See also id. ("The trouble with 'happiness', on any contemporary understanding of it uninfluenced by classically trained writers, is that it connotes somediing which is subjectively determined.").
  • 65
    • 68949139617 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 19, at, I am grateful to Nelson Lund for encouraging me to make this clarification
    • HURSTHOUSE, supra note 19, at 4. I am grateful to Nelson Lund for encouraging me to make this clarification.
    • supra , pp. 4
    • HURSTHOUSE1
  • 66
    • 84869694885 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Buckle, supra note 14, at 565; see also Crisp & Slote, supra note 16, at 2-3 (arguing that virtue etiiicists carve out [their] own niche [by making] essential reference to the rationality of virtue itself); Robert B. Louden, On Some Vices of Virtue Ethics, ¿LAQUO;VIRTUE ETHICS, supra note 14, at 201, 204, 216 (contrasting a mononomic understanding of virtue ethics with one that coordinate [s] irreducible or strong notions of virtue along with strong conceptions of act-focused ethical theories); Nussbaum, supranote 38, at 165, 168 (assuming that deontologists and consequentialists may both draw on virtue ediics).
    • Buckle, supra note 14, at 565; see also Crisp & Slote, supra note 16, at 2-3 (arguing that virtue etiiicists "carve out [their] own niche [by making] essential reference to the rationality of virtue itself"); Robert B. Louden, On Some Vices of Virtue Ethics, ¿LAQUO;VIRTUE ETHICS, supra note 14, at 201, 204, 216 (contrasting a "mononomic" understanding of virtue ethics with one that "coordinate [s] irreducible or strong notions of virtue" along with strong conceptions of act-focused ethical theories); Nussbaum, supranote 38, at 165, 168 (assuming that deontologists and consequentialists may both draw on virtue ediics).
  • 67
    • 84869694880 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., PHILIPPA FOOT, Virtues and Vices, ¿re VIRTUES AND VICES AND OTHER ESSAYS IN MORAL PHILOSOPHY 1,1-2 (2d ed., Oxford Univ. Press 2002) (1978) (arguing that Aristotle and St. Thomas Aquinas are foundational).
    • See, e.g., PHILIPPA FOOT, Virtues and Vices, ¿re VIRTUES AND VICES AND OTHER ESSAYS IN MORAL PHILOSOPHY 1,1-2 (2d ed., Oxford Univ. Press 2002) (1978) (arguing that Aristotle and St. Thomas Aquinas are foundational).
  • 68
    • 68949095552 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See PETER PHILLIPS SIMPSON, VICES, VIRTUES, AND CONSEQUENCES: ESSAYS IN MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 93 (2001) (contrasting neo-Aristotelians who emphasize the Aristotelian with tiiose who emphasize the neo).
    • See PETER PHILLIPS SIMPSON, VICES, VIRTUES, AND CONSEQUENCES: ESSAYS IN MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 93 (2001) (contrasting "neo-Aristotelians" who emphasize the "Aristotelian" with tiiose who emphasize the "neo").
  • 69
    • 68949095405 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See SIMON BLACKBURN, THE OXFORD DICTIONARY OF PHILOSOPHY 304 (1996) [hereinafter OXFORD DICTIONARY OF PHILOSOPHY] .
    • See SIMON BLACKBURN, THE OXFORD DICTIONARY OF PHILOSOPHY 304 (1996) [hereinafter OXFORD DICTIONARY OF PHILOSOPHY] .
  • 70
    • 33748192320 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ancient Ethical Theory
    • See, Fall
    • See Richard Parry, Ancient Ethical Theory, in STANFORD ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY §1 (Fall 2004), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2004/entries/ediics-ancient/.
    • (2004) STANFORD ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY §1
    • Parry, R.1
  • 71
    • 68949138404 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Hursthouse, supra note 59
    • See Hursthouse, supra note 59.
  • 72
    • 85008566291 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Virtue Consequentialism, 17
    • See, e.g
    • See, e.g., Ben Bradley, Virtue Consequentialism, 17 UTILITAS 282, 282-83 (2005).
    • (2005) UTILITAS , vol.282 , pp. 282-283
    • Bradley, B.1
  • 73
    • 68949153385 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See OXFORD DICTIONARY OF PHILOSOPHY, supra note 69, at 394
    • See OXFORD DICTIONARY OF PHILOSOPHY, supra note 69, at 394.
  • 74
    • 84869707048 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, supra note 14, 1.7, at 1098al6-18; NICOMACHEAN ETHICS (Sachs trans.), supra note 14, at 12; accord Crisp & Slote, supra note 16, at 2 (describing Aristotie as having perhaps one of the most radical virtue ediics ever, since he can be understood to be saying that there is reo¿A¿reg-wortíi having in life except the exercise of the virtues).
    • NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, supra note 14, 1.7, at 1098al6-18; NICOMACHEAN ETHICS (Sachs trans.), supra note 14, at 12; accord Crisp & Slote, supra note 16, at 2 (describing Aristotie as having "perhaps one of the most radical virtue ediics ever, since he can be understood to be saying that there is reo¿A¿reg-wortíi having in life except the exercise of the virtues").
  • 75
    • 68949111586 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See JONATHAN LEAR, ARISTOTLE: THE DESIRE TO UNDERSTAND 154-55 (1988) (The aim of the Nicomachean Ethics is to give one a reflective understanding of how one can achieve happiness by living an ethical life within society) (citing NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, supra note 14, 1.2, at 1094al8-25) (emphasis added)); accord JULIA DRIVER, UNEASY VIRTUE 70 (2001).
    • See JONATHAN LEAR, ARISTOTLE: THE DESIRE TO UNDERSTAND 154-55 (1988) ("The aim of the Nicomachean Ethics is to give one a reflective understanding of how one can achieve happiness by living an ethical life within society") (citing NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, supra note 14, 1.2, at 1094al8-25) (emphasis added)); accord JULIA DRIVER, UNEASY VIRTUE 70 (2001).
  • 76
    • 68949095600 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Fred D. Miller Jr., Property Rights in Aristotle, in ARISTOTLE'S POLITICS: CRITICAL ESSAYS 121, 125 (Richard Kraut & Steven Skultety eds., 2005) (quoting ARISTOTLE, RHETORIC 1360bl4-17); accord OXFORD DICTIONARY OF PHILOSOPHY, supra note 69, at 127 (suggesting that it is possible to understand virtue ediics in such a manner that the equation between acting virtuously and flourishing is broken).
    • See, e.g., Fred D. Miller Jr., Property Rights in Aristotle, in ARISTOTLE'S POLITICS: CRITICAL ESSAYS 121, 125 (Richard Kraut & Steven Skultety eds., 2005) (quoting ARISTOTLE, RHETORIC 1360bl4-17); accord OXFORD DICTIONARY OF PHILOSOPHY, supra note 69, at 127 (suggesting that it is possible to understand virtue ediics in such a manner that the "equation between acting virtuously and flourishing is broken").
  • 77
    • 68949095669 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Oakley, supra note 22, at 138-39
    • See Oakley, supra note 22, at 138-39.
  • 78
    • 68949095712 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, supra note 14, I.8-.9, at 1099al3-17, 1099b25-28; NICOMACHEAN ETHICS (Sachs trans.), supra note 14, at 14, 15.
    • See NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, supra note 14, I.8-.9, at 1099al3-17, 1099b25-28; NICOMACHEAN ETHICS (Sachs trans.), supra note 14, at 14, 15.
  • 79
    • 68949139939 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LEAR, supra note 75, at 164
    • LEAR, supra note 75, at 164.
  • 80
    • 68949095412 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ALASDAIR MACINTYRE, AFTER VIRTUE 191 (2d ed. 1984) (emphasis removed); see also id. at 184 (defining an internal means to a human end as one in which the end cannot be adequately characterized independendy of a characterization of the means).
    • ALASDAIR MACINTYRE, AFTER VIRTUE 191 (2d ed. 1984) (emphasis removed); see also id. at 184 (defining an "internal" means to a human end as one in which "the end cannot be adequately characterized independendy of a characterization of the means").
  • 81
    • 68949153491 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 196
    • Id. at 196.
  • 82
    • 68949095501 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Bernard H. Baumrin, Aristotle's Ethical Intuitionism, 42 THE NEW SCHOLASTICISM 1, 5,12 (1967) (classifying Aristode as a deontologist, while defining deontologist to refer to any nonconsequentialist theory); Nussbaum, supra note 38, at 168-69 (suggesting that virtue ethics consists of anti-utilitarians and anti-Kantians).
    • See, e.g., Bernard H. Baumrin, Aristotle's Ethical Intuitionism, 42 THE NEW SCHOLASTICISM 1, 5,12 (1967) (classifying Aristode as a deontologist, while defining "deontologist" to refer to any nonconsequentialist theory); Nussbaum, supra note 38, at 168-69 (suggesting that virtue ethics consists of anti-utilitarians and anti-Kantians).
  • 83
    • 68949138376 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BUCKLE, supra note 58, at 70, 71
    • BUCKLE, supra note 58, at 70, 71.
  • 84
    • 68949138495 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oakley, supra note 22, at 133
    • Oakley, supra note 22, at 133.
  • 85
    • 68949138365 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, note 51, at, describing act-utilitarian theory
    • See, e.g., Smart, supra note 51, at 9-12, 30-57 (describing act-utilitarian theory).
    • supra
    • Smart1
  • 86
    • 33745300095 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See note 22, §§discussing the hedonism inherent in classic utilitarianism
    • See Sinnott-Armstrong, supra note 22, §§(discussing the hedonism inherent in classic utilitarianism).
    • supra
    • Armstrong, S.1
  • 87
    • 68949153299 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2 SAMUEL PUFENDORF, DE JURE NATURAE ET GENTIUM LIBRI OCTO II.3.10, at 195 (CH. Oldfather & W.A. Oldfather trans., Clarendon Press 1934) (1688).
    • 2 SAMUEL PUFENDORF, DE JURE NATURAE ET GENTIUM LIBRI OCTO II.3.10, at 195 (CH. Oldfather & W.A. Oldfather trans., Clarendon Press 1934) (1688).
  • 88
    • 68949153489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BUCKLE, supra note 58, at 68 (citing 2 PUFENDORF, supra note 87, II.3.10, at 195).
    • See BUCKLE, supra note 58, at 68 (citing 2 PUFENDORF, supra note 87, II.3.10, at 195).
  • 89
    • 68949138405 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Nussbaum, supra note 38, at 168 (noting that many virtue theorists question utilitiarianism's narrowly technical conception of reason).
    • See Nussbaum, supra note 38, at 168 (noting that many virtue theorists "question" utilitiarianism's "narrowly technical conception of reason").
  • 90
    • 68949134268 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 182.
    • See id. at 182.
  • 91
    • 68949138583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ROBERT P. GEORGE, MAKING MEN MORAL: CIVIL LIBERTIES AND PUBLIC MORALITY 13 (1993).
    • ROBERT P. GEORGE, MAKING MEN MORAL: CIVIL LIBERTIES AND PUBLIC MORALITY 13 (1993).
  • 92
    • 68949095659 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • E.g., Crisp & Slote, supra note 16, at 3; Louden, supra note 66, at 205; see, e.g., Buckle, supra note 14, at 569 & n.12.
    • E.g., Crisp & Slote, supra note 16, at 3; Louden, supra note 66, at 205; see, e.g., Buckle, supra note 14, at 569 & n.12.
  • 93
    • 84869696024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Daniel Statman, Introduction to Virtue Ethics, in VIRTUE ETHICS: A CRITICAL READER 3, 3-5 (Daniel Statman ed., 1997) (explaining why standard utilitarianism presumes a moral duty to act independent of agent-relative considerations); see also Alexander & Moore, supra note 15, §2.1 (defining agent-centered and agent-relative).
    • See Daniel Statman, Introduction to Virtue Ethics, in VIRTUE ETHICS: A CRITICAL READER 3, 3-5 (Daniel Statman ed., 1997) (explaining why standard utilitarianism presumes a moral duty to act independent of agent-relative considerations); see also Alexander & Moore, supra note 15, §2.1 (defining "agent-centered" and "agent-relative").
  • 94
    • 68949153274 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oakley, supra note 22, at 131
    • Oakley, supra note 22, at 131.
  • 95
    • 68949153492 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 133
    • Id. at 133.
  • 96
    • 68949139803 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 144
    • Id. at 144.
  • 97
    • 68949139645 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 143-44
    • Id. at 143-44.
  • 98
    • 68949134276 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 2 PUFENDORF, supra note 87,1.2.4, at 24.
    • See 2 PUFENDORF, supra note 87,1.2.4, at 24.
  • 99
    • 68949139847 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 11.3.10, at
    • See id. 11.3.10, at 196.
  • 100
    • 68949095515 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BUCKLE, supra note 58, at 67
    • BUCKLE, supra note 58, at 67.
  • 101
    • 68949095711 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2 PUFENDORF, supra note 87, II.3.10, at 195.
    • 2 PUFENDORF, supra note 87, II.3.10, at 195.
  • 102
    • 68949153384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BUCKLE, supra note 58, at 62-74
    • See BUCKLE, supra note 58, at 62-74.
  • 103
    • 0347874937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • James Griffin, Virtue Ethics and Environs, 18 Soc. PHIL. & POL'Y 56, 63 (1998).
    • James Griffin, Virtue Ethics and Environs, 18 Soc. PHIL. & POL'Y 56, 63 (1998).
  • 104
    • 68949153311 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 60-61.
    • See id. at 60-61.
  • 106
    • 68949138639 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • THOMAS HURKA, PERFECTIONISM 60 (1993); see id. at 55-60.
    • THOMAS HURKA, PERFECTIONISM 60 (1993); see id. at 55-60.
  • 107
    • 68949138454 scopus 로고
    • Pursuing the Good-Indirectly, 95
    • Larry Alexander, Pursuing the Good-Indirectly, 95 ETHICS 315, 329 (1985).
    • (1985) ETHICS , vol.315 , pp. 329
    • Alexander, L.1
  • 108
    • 68949132363 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hurka acknowledges this argument in HURKA, supra note 106, at 59.
    • Hurka acknowledges this argument in HURKA, supra note 106, at 59.
  • 109
    • 68949095559 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., HURSTHOUSE, supra note 19, at 120 (acknowledging the possibility that one can add on an Aristotelian account of the emotions to a Kantian account of deontic obligations).
    • See, e.g., HURSTHOUSE, supra note 19, at 120 (acknowledging the possibility that one can "add on an Aristotelian account of the emotions" to a Kantian account of deontic obligations).
  • 110
    • 68949153488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One could develop an aretaic justification of property rights, and some have done so. See, e.g., Miller, supra note 76, at 124-26. Such justifications are so foreign to modern conceptual categories, however, that it would be distracting to rely on them as part of what is meant to be a meat-and-potatoes example relevant in contemporary law. I use Pufendorf as a substitute because he writes early enough to be close to the metheval tradition, in which virtue was a dominant category in political thought, but also late enough to speak in modern accents regarding natural rights. See infra note 167 and sources cited therein.
    • One could develop an aretaic justification of property rights, and some have done so. See, e.g., Miller, supra note 76, at 124-26. Such justifications are so foreign to modern conceptual categories, however, that it would be distracting to rely on them as part of what is meant to be a meat-and-potatoes example relevant in contemporary law. I use Pufendorf as a substitute because he writes early enough to be close to the metheval tradition, in which virtue was a dominant category in political thought, but also late enough to speak in modern accents regarding natural rights. See infra note 167 and sources cited therein.
  • 111
    • 68949139846 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 2 PUFENDORF, supra note 87, IV.3.1, at 524.
    • See 2 PUFENDORF, supra note 87, IV.3.1, at 524.
  • 112
    • 68949134273 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BUCKLE, supra note 58, at 92
    • BUCKLE, supra note 58, at 92.
  • 113
    • 68949095513 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 2 PUFENDORF, supra note 87, IV.4.2, at 532; accord BUCKLE, supra note 58, at 96-97.
    • See 2 PUFENDORF, supra note 87, IV.4.2, at 532; accord BUCKLE, supra note 58, at 96-97.
  • 114
    • 68949138406 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 2 PUFENDORF, supra note 87, IV.4.6, at 539-40.
    • See 2 PUFENDORF, supra note 87, IV.4.6, at 539-40.
  • 115
    • 68949139877 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id.; accord BUCKLE, supra note 58, at 100-01.
    • See id.; accord BUCKLE, supra note 58, at 100-01.
  • 116
    • 68949139841 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 2 PUFENDORF, supra note 87, IV.4.6, at 539-40; accord BUCKLE, supra note 58, at 102-03.
    • See 2 PUFENDORF, supra note 87, IV.4.6, at 539-40; accord BUCKLE, supra note 58, at 102-03.
  • 117
    • 68949139931 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 2 PUFENDORF, supra note 87, IV.3.6, at 531; accord BUCKLE, supra note 58, at 92 & n.148.
    • See 2 PUFENDORF, supra note 87, IV.3.6, at 531; accord BUCKLE, supra note 58, at 92 & n.148.
  • 118
    • 68949153383 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WEINRIB, supra note 27, at 176
    • WEINRIB, supra note 27, at 176.
  • 119
    • 84869711089 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In facque v. Sternberg Homes, Inc., for example, a mobile-home company trespassed across the vacant and unused field of a retired couple to deliver a mobile-home on time when the public road was blocked by snow. Steenberg Homes was making productive use of the field, the Jacques were not, and the crossing caused the Jacques no actual harm. Yet the Jacques were entitled to a trespass cause of action and $100,000 in punitive damages. 563 N.W.2d 154 (Wis. 1997). The holding reinforced an exclusionary regime, but the facts seem to justify an exception respecting Steenberg Homes's harmless and productive use of the Jacques' exclusionary right.
    • In facque v. Sternberg Homes, Inc., for example, a mobile-home company trespassed across the vacant and unused field of a retired couple to deliver a mobile-home on time when the public road was blocked by snow. Steenberg Homes was making productive use of the field, the Jacques were not, and the crossing caused the Jacques no actual harm. Yet the Jacques were entitled to a trespass cause of action and $100,000 in punitive damages. 563 N.W.2d 154 (Wis. 1997). The holding reinforced an exclusionary regime, but the facts seem to justify an exception respecting Steenberg Homes's harmless and productive use of the Jacques' exclusionary right.
  • 120
    • 68949132382 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 2 PUFENDORF, supra note 87,1.2.4, at 24. This is a fact that James Gordley overlooks. Gordley explains adverse possession on the ground that when an owner does not intend to put property to productive use, he does not have ownership in its true sense. GORDLEY, supra note 46, at 144. To make this explanation satisfying, Gordley must explain why trespass law at its core endows owners with ownership of land they have not yet used.
    • See 2 PUFENDORF, supra note 87,1.2.4, at 24. This is a fact that James Gordley overlooks. Gordley explains adverse possession on the ground that "when an owner does not intend to put property to productive use, he does not have ownership in its true sense." GORDLEY, supra note 46, at 144. To make this explanation satisfying, Gordley must explain why trespass law at its core endows owners with ownership of land they have not yet used.
  • 121
    • 68949134274 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • l21 Cf. Carol M. Rose, Possession as the Origin of Property, 52 U. CHI. L. REV. 73, 81-82 (1985) (justifying the same result in economic utilitarian terms).
    • l21 Cf. Carol M. Rose, Possession as the Origin of Property, 52 U. CHI. L. REV. 73, 81-82 (1985) (justifying the same result in economic utilitarian terms).
  • 122
    • 84869711091 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Golden Press, Inc. v. Rylands, 235 P.2d 592, 595 (Colo. 1951) (suggesting that, when a court considers whether to refrain from entering an injunction ordering the removal of a trespassory encroachment, it should enter the injunction if the trespasser encroached in bad faith, irrespective of the balance of hardships); Jacque v. Steenberg Homes, Inc., 563 N.W.2d at 157-58,163-66 upholding a $100,000 punitive damage award
    • See, e.g., Golden Press, Inc. v. Rylands, 235 P.2d 592, 595 (Colo. 1951) (suggesting that, when a court considers whether to refrain from entering an injunction ordering the removal of a trespassory encroachment, it should enter the injunction if the trespasser encroached in bad faith, irrespective of the balance of hardships); Jacque v. Steenberg Homes, Inc., 563 N.W.2d at 157-58,163-66 (upholding a $100,000 punitive damage award
  • 123
    • 68949138375 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • against a bad-faidi trespasser even though the trespass caused no physical damage to the owner's property and allowed the trespasser to complete a contract that a severe blizzard would otterwise have made impossible to perform.
    • against a bad-faidi trespasser even though the trespass caused no physical damage to the owner's property and allowed the trespasser to complete a contract that a severe blizzard would otterwise have made impossible to perform).
  • 124
    • 68949139845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In this regard virtue theories may help respond to a challenge issued by Jules Coleman: to understand bodi utilitarian welfare and deontic claims of justice and fairness in light of more fundamental human interests
    • In this regard virtue theories may help respond to a challenge issued by Jules Coleman: to understand bodi utilitarian welfare and deontic claims of justice and fairness in light of more fundamental human interests:
  • 125
    • 68949153382 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Once we realize that welfare is connected to a person's interests-what is good for him, and not merely to what he desires or to his gratification or joy-it should be clear that whatever it is in that account that explains the value of welfare explains as well the importance of the law's regulating human affairs according to various principles of justice and fairness. Coleman, supra note 8, at 1543.
    • Once we realize that welfare is connected to a person's interests-what is good for him, and not merely to what he desires or to his gratification or joy-it should be clear that whatever it is in that account that explains the value of welfare explains as well the importance of the law's regulating human affairs according to various principles of justice and fairness. Coleman, supra note 8, at 1543.
  • 126
    • 68949187538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See RICHARD A. POSNER, ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF LAW 78-79 (7th ed. 2007). I use Posner's justification of adverse possession as a point of contact not with economic analysis generally but rather with act-utilitarian modes of justification. Economic analysis, conducted differently with proper regard for informational and act-specific limitations, avoids many of these problems. I understand this to be an important point of Henry E. Smith's contribution to this theme Issue, see Henry E. Smidi, Mind the Gap: The Indirect Relation Between Ends and Means in American Property Law, 94 CORNELL L. REV. 959 (2009).
    • See RICHARD A. POSNER, ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF LAW 78-79 (7th ed. 2007). I use Posner's justification of adverse possession as a point of contact not with economic analysis generally but rather with act-utilitarian modes of justification. Economic analysis, conducted differently with proper regard for informational and act-specific limitations, avoids many of these problems. I understand this to be an important point of Henry E. Smith's contribution to this theme Issue, see Henry E. Smidi, Mind the Gap: The Indirect Relation Between Ends and Means in American Property Law, 94 CORNELL L. REV. 959 (2009).
  • 127
    • 84869711086 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See POSNER, supra note 124, at 31-32 (discussing the dynamic influences of property law on ownership and investment). 126 Peñalver, supra note 5, at 832-60. 127 Id. at 861.
    • See POSNER, supra note 124, at 31-32 (discussing the "dynamic" influences of property law on ownership and investment). 126 Peñalver, supra note 5, at 832-60. 127 Id. at 861.
  • 129
    • 68949144461 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Specifically, the title owner's right to be free from trespassory invasions seems the product of a formal rule justified by universal prescriptions made by Kantian deontology. Non-Kantian deontological approaches might take a more nuanced approach than the deontological approach assumed in text. Among othet tilings, deontological approaches might establish a series of priorities for different relevant norms (for the use of land, for the formal control of unused but still-owned land, and so forth), which might generate a series of rules of decision.
    • Specifically, the title owner's right to be free from trespassory invasions seems the product of a formal rule justified by universal prescriptions made by Kantian deontology. Non-Kantian deontological approaches might take a more nuanced approach than the "deontological" approach assumed in text. Among othet tilings, deontological approaches might establish a series of priorities for different relevant norms (for the use of land, for the formal control of unused but still-owned land, and so forth), which might generate a series of rules of decision.
  • 130
    • 37349130380 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For criticisms, see Louden, supra note 66; Christopher W. Gowans, Virtue and Nature, 25 Soc. PHIL & POL'Y 28, 29 (2008); Statman, supra note 93, §5, at 18-22.
    • For criticisms, see Louden, supra note 66; Christopher W. Gowans, Virtue and Nature, 25 Soc. PHIL & POL'Y 28, 29 (2008); Statman, supra note 93, §5, at 18-22.
  • 131
    • 68949153490 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., BUCKLE, supra note 58, at 70 n.61 (explaining why [n]atural law theories are . . . essentially non-Kantian, in large part because psychological intelligibility is ... a non-accidental feature of such theories).
    • See, e.g., BUCKLE, supra note 58, at 70 n.61 (explaining why "[n]atural law theories are . . . essentially non-Kantian," in large part because "psychological intelligibility is ... a non-accidental feature" of such theories).
  • 132
    • 68949153273 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alexander, supra note 4, at 747
    • Alexander, supra note 4, at 747.
  • 133
    • 68949139640 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Eric R. Claeys, Property 101: Is Property a Thing or a Bundle?, 32 SEATTLE U.L. REV. 617 (2009) (reviewing THOMAS W. MERRILL & HENRY E. SMITH, PROPERTY: PRINCIPLES AND POLICIES (2007)) (critiquing the right to exclude conception in favor of a conception of an exclusive right to determine the use of property); Larissa Katz, Exclusion and Exclusivity in Property Law, 58 U. TORONTO LJ. 275 (2008) (proposing an exclusive right of agenda-setting); Adam Mossoff, Wliat Is Property? Putting the Pieces Back Together, 45 ARIZ. L. REV. 371 (2003) (proposing an exclusive right of use).
    • See Eric R. Claeys, Property 101: Is Property a Thing or a Bundle?, 32 SEATTLE U.L. REV. 617 (2009) (reviewing THOMAS W. MERRILL & HENRY E. SMITH, PROPERTY: PRINCIPLES AND POLICIES (2007)) (critiquing the right to exclude conception in favor of a conception of an exclusive right to determine the use of property); Larissa Katz, Exclusion and Exclusivity in Property Law, 58 U. TORONTO LJ. 275 (2008) (proposing an exclusive right of agenda-setting); Adam Mossoff, Wliat Is Property? Putting the Pieces Back Together, 45 ARIZ. L. REV. 371 (2003) (proposing an exclusive right of use).
  • 135
    • 84869696019 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Peñalver, supra note 5, at 826
    • See Peñalver, supra note 5, at 826.
  • 136
    • 68949138494 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Smith, supra note 124
    • See Smith, supra note 124.
  • 137
    • 68949136426 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Part V.C.
    • See infra Part V.C.
  • 138
    • 68949139798 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Smith, supra note 124, at 967
    • See Smith, supra note 124, at 967.
  • 139
    • 84869707043 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HURSTHOUSE, supra note 19, at 5. Hursthouse dtnks that the topic of justice, personal and political, is not only contested but also corrupted. See id.; see also Rosalind Hursthouse, Virtue Ethics, STANFORD ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY §4 (rev. ed. Fall 2007), http://plato.stanford.edu/ archives/fall2007/entries/ettics-virtue (Although Plato and Aristotie can be great inspirations as far as [virtue ethics are] concerned, neither, on the face of it, are attractive sources of insight where politics is concerned.).
    • HURSTHOUSE, supra note 19, at 5. Hursthouse dtnks that the topic of justice, personal and political, is not only contested but also "corrupted." See id.; see also Rosalind Hursthouse, Virtue Ethics, STANFORD ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY §4 (rev. ed. Fall 2007), http://plato.stanford.edu/ archives/fall2007/entries/ettics-virtue ("Although Plato and Aristotie can be great inspirations as far as [virtue ethics are] concerned, neither, on the face of it, are attractive sources of insight where politics is concerned.").
  • 140
    • 68949153493 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Alexander, supra note 4, at 751 n.13.
    • See Alexander, supra note 4, at 751 n.13.
  • 141
    • 68949144462 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See MARTHA C. NUSSBAUM, WOMEN AND HUMAN DEVELOPMENT: THE CAPABILITIES APPROACH 7-8 (2000) (arguing for a form of political liberalism in connection with the capabilities idea).
    • See MARTHA C. NUSSBAUM, WOMEN AND HUMAN DEVELOPMENT: THE CAPABILITIES APPROACH 7-8 (2000) (arguing for "a form of political liberalism in connection with the capabilities idea").
  • 142
    • 68949132374 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Giving Way: Martha Nussbaum and the Morality of Privation, 8
    • reviewing NUSSBAUM, supra note 142, complaining that Nussbaum seems to assume that every moral good should become a constitutional guarantee, See
    • See John Lewis, Giving Way: Martha Nussbaum and the Morality of Privation, 8 U. CHI. L. SCH. ROUNDTABLE 215, 216, 217 (2001) (reviewing NUSSBAUM, supra note 142) (complaining that Nussbaum "seems to assume that every moral good should become a constitutional guarantee").
    • (2001) U. CHI. L. SCH. ROUNDTABLE , vol.215 , Issue.216 , pp. 217
    • Lewis, J.1
  • 143
    • 68949138499 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Fred D. Miller, Jr., Virtue and Rights in Aristotle's Best Regime, in VALUES AND VIRTUES: ARISTOTELIANISM IN CONTEMPORARY ETHICS 67 (Timothy Chappell ed., 2006).
    • See Fred D. Miller, Jr., Virtue and Rights in Aristotle's Best Regime, in VALUES AND VIRTUES: ARISTOTELIANISM IN CONTEMPORARY ETHICS 67 (Timothy Chappell ed., 2006).
  • 144
    • 68949095704 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 67
    • Id. at 67.
  • 145
    • 68949132375 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Crisp & Slote, supra note 16, at 25
    • Crisp & Slote, supra note 16, at 25.
  • 146
    • 68949122323 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gregory S. Alexander, The Complex Core of Property, 94 CORNELL L. REV. 1063 ( 2009), at 1068.
    • Gregory S. Alexander, The Complex Core of Property, 94 CORNELL L. REV. 1063 ( 2009), at 1068.
  • 147
    • 68949153275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The laws seem to be the works of the political art. NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, supra note 14, X.9, at 1181a23; NICOMACHEAN ETHICS (Sachs trans.), supra note 14, at 200.
    • "The laws seem to be the works of the political art." NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, supra note 14, X.9, at 1181a23; NICOMACHEAN ETHICS (Sachs trans.), supra note 14, at 200.
  • 148
    • 84869696018 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Peñalver, supra note 5, at n.168; accord Alexander, supra note 4, at 760-61.
    • Peñalver, supra note 5, at n.168; accord Alexander, supra note 4, at 760-61.
  • 149
    • 68949139641 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although I cite Aristotle heavily in this Part and the next, I am not prepared to suggest that I am interpreting Aristotle accurately on all the points covered in this Response. It suffices for my argument that Aristotle makes a number of observations and normative prescriptions about the relations between law and politics and that these observations are so sensible that they should be considered in complete analyses of virtue politics
    • Although I cite Aristotle heavily in this Part and the next, I am not prepared to suggest that I am interpreting Aristotle accurately on all the points covered in this Response. It suffices for my argument that Aristotle makes a number of observations and normative prescriptions about the relations between law and politics and that these observations are so sensible that they should be considered in complete analyses of virtue politics.
  • 150
    • 68949138455 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, supra note 14, X.9, at 1181b20-22; NICOMACHEAN ETHICS (Sachs trans.), supra note 14, at 200. Sachs uses constitution though I prefer political regime.
    • NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, supra note 14, X.9, at 1181b20-22; NICOMACHEAN ETHICS (Sachs trans.), supra note 14, at 200. Sachs uses "constitution" though I prefer "political regime."
  • 151
    • 68949153300 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See POLITICS, supra note 40, VIII, at 1337a-42b; POLITICS (Lord trans.), supra note 40, at 229-41.
    • See POLITICS, supra note 40, VIII, at 1337a-42b; POLITICS (Lord trans.), supra note 40, at 229-41.
  • 152
    • 68949138497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, supra note 14, II.2, at 1103b27-29; NICOMACHEAN ETHICS (Sachs trans.), supra note 14, at 23.
    • NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, supra note 14, II.2, at 1103b27-29; NICOMACHEAN ETHICS (Sachs trans.), supra note 14, at 23.
  • 153
    • 68949132376 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, supra note 14, X.9, 1179bl0; NICOMACHEAN ETHICS (Sachs trans.), supra note 14, at 196.
    • See NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, supra note 14, X.9, 1179bl0; NICOMACHEAN ETHICS (Sachs trans.), supra note 14, at 196.
  • 154
    • 68949122242 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, supranote 14, X.9, at 1179a33-80al4; NICOMACHEAN ETHICS (Sachs trans.), supra note 14, at 196-97.
    • See NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, supranote 14, X.9, at 1179a33-80al4; NICOMACHEAN ETHICS (Sachs trans.), supra note 14, at 196-97.
  • 155
    • 68949139932 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • At least, as long as he does not violate any laws in the process
    • At least, as long as he does not violate any laws in the process.
  • 156
    • 68949095601 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See POLITICS, supra note 40,1.1, at 1252al-6; POLITICS (Lord trans.), supra note 40, at 35.
    • See POLITICS, supra note 40,1.1, at 1252al-6; POLITICS (Lord trans.), supra note 40, at 35.
  • 157
    • 84869696012 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JOHN FINNIS, NATURAL LAW AND NATURAL RIGHTS 217 (1980); see GEORGE, supranote 91, at 95-96, 155-57; accord U.S. CATHOLIC CONFERENCE, CATECHISM OF THE CATHOLIC CHURCH §§2351-57, at 564-66 (1994) (specifying moral offenses against chastity).
    • JOHN FINNIS, NATURAL LAW AND NATURAL RIGHTS 217 (1980); see GEORGE, supranote 91, at 95-96, 155-57; accord U.S. CATHOLIC CONFERENCE, CATECHISM OF THE CATHOLIC CHURCH §§2351-57, at 564-66 (1994) (specifying moral offenses against chastity).
  • 158
    • 84869694867 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See U.S. CATHOLIC CONFERENCE, supra note 158, §2284, at 550.
    • See U.S. CATHOLIC CONFERENCE, supra note 158, §2284, at 550.
  • 159
    • 68949132383 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [T]he existence of somedtng called 'obscenity' is still a long and painful step from agreement on a workable definition of the term. Paris Adult Theatre I v. Slaton, 413 U.S. 49, 79 (1973) (Brennan, J., dissenting).
    • "[T]he existence of somedtng called 'obscenity' is still a long and painful step from agreement on a workable definition of the term." Paris Adult Theatre I v. Slaton, 413 U.S. 49, 79 (1973) (Brennan, J., dissenting).
  • 160
    • 68949144463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Katrina M. Wyman describes this view without embracing it herself in her Response in this Issue, Katrina M. Wyman, Should Property Scholars Embrace Virtue Ethics? A Skeptical Comment, 94 CORNELL L. REV. 991, 1002-04 (2009).
    • Katrina M. Wyman describes this view without embracing it herself in her Response in this Issue, Katrina M. Wyman, Should Property Scholars Embrace Virtue Ethics? A Skeptical Comment, 94 CORNELL L. REV. 991, 1002-04 (2009).
  • 161
    • 68949139842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GEORGE, supra note 91, at 25-26. For an excellent analysis of Aristotle's analysis of this issue, see Buckle, supra note 14.
    • GEORGE, supra note 91, at 25-26. For an excellent analysis of Aristotle's analysis of this issue, see Buckle, supra note 14.
  • 162
    • 68949139878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Alexander, supra note 147, at 1068
    • See Alexander, supra note 147, at 1068.
  • 163
    • 68949095553 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. MACINTYRE, supra note 80, at 205 ([A] virtue is not a disposition that makes for success only in some one particular type of situation. What are spoken of as the virtues of a good committee man or of a good administrator or of a gambler or a pool husder are professional skills professionally deployed in ttose situations where they can be effective, not virtues.).
    • Cf. MACINTYRE, supra note 80, at 205 ("[A] virtue is not a disposition that makes for success only in some one particular type of situation. What are spoken of as the virtues of a good committee man or of a good administrator or of a gambler or a pool husder are professional skills professionally deployed in ttose situations where they can be effective, not virtues.").
  • 164
    • 68949153278 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Alexander, supra note 4, at 747 (citing Duncan Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, 89 HARV. L. REV. 1685, 1737 (1976)).
    • See Alexander, supra note 4, at 747 (citing Duncan Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, 89 HARV. L. REV. 1685, 1737 (1976)).
  • 165
    • 84886336150 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • notes 110-16 and accompanying text
    • See supra notes 110-16 and accompanying text.
    • See supra
  • 166
    • 68949138370 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This section and the next will explain the basic issues in the political-theory terms in which virtue-friendly early Enlightenment political philosophers portrayed ttose terms. To appreciate the issues fully, one would also need a sound appreciation of the history of the same period, and specifically the full range of historical forces that caused metheval law, which applied natural-law principles, to evolve into modern law, which drew on natural rights. For two excellent starts into that topic, see BRIAN TIERNEY, THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS (1997, Benjamin Straumann, Is Modern Liberty Ancient? Roman Remethes and Natural Rights in Hugo Grotius's Early Works on Natural Law, 27 LAW & HIST. REV. 55 2009
    • This section and the next will explain the basic issues in the political-theory terms in which virtue-friendly early Enlightenment political philosophers portrayed ttose terms. To appreciate the issues fully, one would also need a sound appreciation of the history of the same period, and specifically the full range of historical forces that caused metheval law, which applied natural-law principles, to evolve into modern law, which drew on natural rights. For two excellent starts into that topic, see BRIAN TIERNEY, THE IDEA OF NATURAL RIGHTS (1997); Benjamin Straumann, Is Modern Liberty Ancient? Roman Remethes and Natural Rights in Hugo Grotius's Early Works on Natural Law, 27 LAW & HIST. REV. 55 (2009).
  • 167
    • 68949095606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed, Professor Alexander deserves pride of place in this project. See GREGORY S. ALEXANDER, COMMODITY & PROPRIETY: COMPETING VISIONS OF PROPERTY IN AMERICAN LEGAL THOUGHT, 1776-1970 (1997); James W. EIy, Jr., Book Review, 43 AM. J. JURIS. 227 (1998) (reviewing ALEXANDER, supra).
    • Indeed, Professor Alexander deserves pride of place in this project. See GREGORY S. ALEXANDER, COMMODITY & PROPRIETY: COMPETING VISIONS OF PROPERTY IN AMERICAN LEGAL THOUGHT, 1776-1970 (1997); James W. EIy, Jr., Book Review, 43 AM. J. JURIS. 227 (1998) (reviewing ALEXANDER, supra).
  • 168
    • 84869707038 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Alexander, supra note 4, at 748. 170 See Peñalver, supra note 5, at 877-86.
    • See Alexander, supra note 4, at 748. 170 See Peñalver, supra note 5, at 877-86.
  • 169
    • 68949138581 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra notes 35-36 and accompanying text.
    • See supra notes 35-36 and accompanying text.
  • 170
    • 68949153496 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Christopher J. Berry, Adam Smith and the Virtues of Commerce, in NOMOS XXXIV: VIRTUE 69, 69 (1992); see CHRISTOPHER J. BERRY, THE IDEA OF A DEMOCRATIC COMMUNITY (1989).
    • Christopher J. Berry, Adam Smith and the Virtues of Commerce, in NOMOS XXXIV: VIRTUE 69, 69 (1992); see CHRISTOPHER J. BERRY, THE IDEA OF A DEMOCRATIC COMMUNITY (1989).
  • 171
    • 68949095511 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DAVID HUME, AN ENQUIRY CONCERNING THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS III.t, at 25-26 (Open Court Publishing Co. 1966) (1777).
    • DAVID HUME, AN ENQUIRY CONCERNING THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS III.t, at 25-26 (Open Court Publishing Co. 1966) (1777).
  • 172
    • 68949095512 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Charles Larmore, 7'Ae Limits of Aristotelian Ethics, in NOMOS XXXIV: VIRTUE, supra note 172, at 185, 192; see CHARLES E. LARMORE, PATTERNS OF MORAL COMPLEXITY (1987).
    • Charles Larmore, 7'Ae Limits of Aristotelian Ethics, in NOMOS XXXIV: VIRTUE, supra note 172, at 185, 192; see CHARLES E. LARMORE, PATTERNS OF MORAL COMPLEXITY (1987).
  • 173
    • 68949153381 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MACINTYRE, supra note 80, at 195
    • MACINTYRE, supra note 80, at 195.
  • 174
    • 68949095558 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GEORGE, supra note 91, at 38
    • GEORGE, supra note 91, at 38.
  • 175
    • 84869694864 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Peñalver, supra note 5, at 887 n.260 (citing MACINTYRE, supra note 80); id. at 873-74 & n.207 (citing GEORGE, supra note 91).
    • See Peñalver, supra note 5, at 887 n.260 (citing MACINTYRE, supra note 80); id. at 873-74 & n.207 (citing GEORGE, supra note 91).
  • 176
    • 68949095510 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Within the context of a polis and an ethical theory intended to accompany it, the strategy of pointing to a phronimos makes a certain sense. However, to divorce this strategy from its social and economic roots and to then apply it to a very different sort of community-one where people really do not know each othet all that well, and where there is wide disagreement on values-does not [make sense]. Louden, supra note 66, at 213.
    • Within the context of a polis and an ethical theory intended to accompany it, the strategy of pointing to a phronimos makes a certain sense. However, to divorce this strategy from its social and economic roots and to then apply it to a very different sort of community-one where people really do not know each othet all that well, and where there is wide disagreement on values-does not [make sense]. Louden, supra note 66, at 213.
  • 177
    • 68949138463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See POLITICS, supra note 40, VII.4, at 1326a25-27; POLITICS (Lord trans.), supranote 40, at 204.
    • See POLITICS, supra note 40, VII.4, at 1326a25-27; POLITICS (Lord trans.), supranote 40, at 204.
  • 178
    • 68949139886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See POLITICS, supra note 40, 1.2, at 1252a24-53a39; POLITICS (Lord trans.), supra note 40, at 35-38.
    • See POLITICS, supra note 40, 1.2, at 1252a24-53a39; POLITICS (Lord trans.), supra note 40, at 35-38.
  • 179
    • 68949139642 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See POLITICS, supra note 40, 1.2, at 1252a24-1253a39; POLITICS (Lord trans.), supra note 40, at 35-38.
    • See POLITICS, supra note 40, 1.2, at 1252a24-1253a39; POLITICS (Lord trans.), supra note 40, at 35-38.
  • 180
    • 68949138410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See POLITICS, supra note 40, VII.8, at 1328bll-13; POLITICS (Lord trans.), supra note 40, at 210 (proposing to make the priesdy offices simultaneously fifth and first in priority in the well-ordered city).
    • See POLITICS, supra note 40, VII.8, at 1328bll-13; POLITICS (Lord trans.), supra note 40, at 210 (proposing to make the priesdy offices simultaneously fifth and first in priority in the well-ordered city).
  • 181
    • 68949138638 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thomas G. West, Introduction to FOUR TEXTS ON SOCRATES 9,15 (Thomas G. West & Grace Starry West trans., rev. ed. 1998) (commenting on Plato's dialogue Euthyphro).
    • Thomas G. West, Introduction to FOUR TEXTS ON SOCRATES 9,15 (Thomas G. West & Grace Starry West trans., rev. ed. 1998) (commenting on Plato's dialogue Euthyphro).
  • 182
    • 68949139887 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Matthew 28:18-20. The same can be said of the othet major monotteistic revealed religions; it just so happens that Christianity has been the most influential of these religions in the Western world.
    • See, e.g., Matthew 28:18-20. The same can be said of the othet major monotteistic revealed religions; it just so happens that Christianity has been the most influential of these religions in the Western world.
  • 183
    • 68949095446 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See POLITICS, supra note 40, 1.2, at 1253a35-36; POLITICS (Lord trans.), supra note 40, at 38.
    • See POLITICS, supra note 40, 1.2, at 1253a35-36; POLITICS (Lord trans.), supra note 40, at 38.
  • 184
    • 85089741981 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Development Ideology, the Peasantry, and Genocide: Rwanda Repesented in Habyarimana's Speeches, 2
    • Philip Verwimp, Development Ideology, the Peasantry, and Genocide: Rwanda Repesented in Habyarimana's Speeches, 2 J. GENOCIDE RES. 325, 326 (2000).
    • (2000) J. GENOCIDE RES , vol.325 , pp. 326
    • Verwimp, P.1
  • 185
    • 68949153301 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 325 (quoting Major-General Juvenal Habyarimana, Message of the Head of State (May 1, 1974)).
    • Id. at 325 (quoting Major-General Juvenal Habyarimana, Message of the Head of State (May 1, 1974)).
  • 186
    • 68949153279 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 147 and accompanying text.
    • See supra note 147 and accompanying text.
  • 187
    • 68949136431 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Harry V. Jaffa, Aristotle, in HISTORY OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 64, 65-67 (Leo Strauss & Joseph Cropsey eds., 2d ed. 1972). But see Miller, supra note 144 reading Aris-
    • See Harry V. Jaffa, Aristotle, in HISTORY OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 64, 65-67 (Leo Strauss & Joseph Cropsey eds., 2d ed. 1972). But see Miller, supra note 144 (reading Aris-
  • 188
    • 68949132361 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • tode's political theory to be at least somewhat compatible with some theories of rights; supra notes 165-66 and accompanying text.
    • tode's political theory to be at least somewhat compatible with some theories of rights); supra notes 165-66 and accompanying text.
  • 189
    • 68949138637 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Larmore, supra note 174, at 195
    • Larmore, supra note 174, at 195.
  • 190
    • 68949136432 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I have explained why the claims made about Locke in the following paragraphs interpret Locke faittfully in Eric R. Claeys, TAe Private Society and the Liberal Public Good in John Locke's Thought, 25 Soc. PHIL. & POL'Y 201 2008
    • I have explained why the claims made about Locke in the following paragraphs interpret Locke faittfully in Eric R. Claeys, TAe Private Society
  • 191
    • 68949138636 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See JOHN LOCKE, ESSAY CONCERNING HUMAN UNDERSTANDING 11.21.55, at 269 (Peter H. Nidditch ed, 1979, criticizing the [p]hilosophers of old for in vain enquiring, whether Summum bonum consisted in Riches, or bodily Delights, or Virtue, or Contemplation: And they might have as reasonably disputed, whether the best Relish were to be found in Apples, Plumbs, or Nuts; and have divided themselves into Sects upon it, PETER C. MYERS, OUR ONLY STAR AND COMPASS: LOCKE AND THE STRUGGLE FOR POLITICAL RATIONALITY 123 1998, Locke] does not see in [natural human sociality] a natural inclination toward lawfulness or virtue
    • See JOHN LOCKE, ESSAY CONCERNING HUMAN UNDERSTANDING 11.21.55, at 269 (Peter H. Nidditch ed., 1979) (criticizing "the [p]hilosophers of old" for "in vain enquiring], whether Summum bonum consisted in Riches, or bodily Delights, or Virtue, or Contemplation: And they might have as reasonably disputed, whether the best Relish were to be found in Apples, Plumbs, or Nuts; and have divided themselves into Sects upon it"); PETER C. MYERS, OUR ONLY STAR AND COMPASS: LOCKE AND THE STRUGGLE FOR POLITICAL RATIONALITY 123 (1998) ("[Locke] does not see in [natural human sociality] a natural inclination toward lawfulness or virtue.").
  • 192
    • 68949095556 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, JOHN COLMAN, JOHN LOCKE'S MORAL PHILOSOPHY 195-96 (1983, both describing Locke's political philosophy as having hedonistic foundations, MYERS, supra note 192, at 137-72; Nomi M. Stolzenberg & Gideon Yaffe, Waldron's Locke and Locke's WaIdron: A Review offeremy Waldron's God, Locke, and Equality, 49 INQUIRY 186,197-202 (2006, reviewing WALDRON, infra, and reading Locke to be a utilitarian, Thomas G. West, Nature and Happiness in Locke (Unabridged, 2004, http://www.claremont.org/publications/ pubid.659/pub-detail.asp (book review, arguing that Locke is a eudaimonistic consequentialist, Contra JEREMY WALDRON, GOD, LOCKE, AND EQUALITY: CHRISTIAN FOUNDATIONS OF JOHN LOCKE'S POLITICAL THOUGHT 82,102, 225 2002, reading Locke to be a deontologist an
    • See, e.g., JOHN COLMAN, JOHN LOCKE'S MORAL PHILOSOPHY 195-96 (1983) (both describing Locke's political philosophy as having hedonistic foundations); MYERS, supra note 192, at 137-72; Nomi M. Stolzenberg & Gideon Yaffe, Waldron's Locke and Locke's WaIdron: A Review offeremy Waldron's God, Locke, and Equality, 49 INQUIRY 186,197-202 (2006) (reviewing WALDRON, infra, and reading Locke to be a utilitarian) ; Thomas G. West, Nature and Happiness in Locke (Unabridged) (2004), http://www.claremont.org/publications/ pubid.659/pub-detail.asp (book review) (arguing that Locke is a eudaimonistic consequentialist) . Contra JEREMY WALDRON, GOD, LOCKE, AND EQUALITY: CHRISTIAN FOUNDATIONS OF JOHN LOCKE'S POLITICAL THOUGHT 82,102, 225 (2002) (reading Locke to be a deontologist and a divine-command theorist) ; Peter Laslett, Introduction to LOCKE, TWO TREATISES OF GOVERNMENT 3, 81-82 (Peter Laslett ed., Cambridge Univ. Press 1988) (1690) [hereinafter "Two TREATISES"] ("Locke's ethical statements . . . point in many directions at the same time.").
  • 193
    • 84963456897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • notes 105-06 and accompanying text
    • See supra notes 105-06 and accompanying text.
    • See supra
  • 194
    • 68949139840 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, Robert A. Goldwin, John Locke, in HISTORY OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 476, 476-510 Leo Strauss & Joseph Cropsey eds, 3d ed. 1987, Locke considers the possibility that some one good and excellent Man, having got a Preheminency amongst the rest, had this Deference paid to his Goodness and Vertue, that the chief Rule, by a tacit Consent devolved into absolute monarchy. Two TREATISES, supra note 193,11.94, at 329. In context, however, this example confirms Locke's overall reserve toward virtue understood as an open-ended goal of political life. Virtue is part of the monarchical political system Locke seeks to displace. Similarly, Locke acknowledges that Age or Virtue may give men a just Precedency over their peers-but not to the point that the former may claim the power to rule the latter wittout their consent. Id. 11.54, at 304
    • See, e.g., Robert A. Goldwin, John Locke, in HISTORY OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 476, 476-510 (Leo Strauss & Joseph Cropsey eds., 3d ed. 1987). Locke considers the possibility that "some one good and excellent Man, having got a Preheminency amongst the rest, had this Deference paid to his Goodness and Vertue . . . that the chief Rule ... by a tacit Consent devolved" into absolute monarchy. Two TREATISES, supra note 193,11.94, at 329. In context, however, this example confirms Locke's overall reserve toward virtue understood as an open-ended goal of political life. Virtue is part of the monarchical political system Locke seeks to displace. Similarly, Locke acknowledges that "Age or Virtue may give men a just Precedency" over their peers-but not to the point that the former may claim the power to rule the latter wittout their consent. Id. 11.54, at 304.
  • 195
    • 68949139884 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LOCKE, supra note 192, 11.21.51, at 266.
    • LOCKE, supra note 192, 11.21.51, at 266.
  • 196
    • 84869694862 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JOHN LOCKE, Some Thoughts Concerning Education, in SOME THOUGHTS CONCERNING EDUCATION AND OF THE CONDUCT OF THE UNDERSTANDING §33, at 25 (Ruth W. Grant & Nathan Tarcov eds., 1996) (1693).
    • JOHN LOCKE, Some Thoughts Concerning Education, in SOME THOUGHTS CONCERNING EDUCATION AND OF THE CONDUCT OF THE UNDERSTANDING §33, at 25 (Ruth W. Grant & Nathan Tarcov eds., 1996) (1693).
  • 197
    • 68949138366 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See JOHN LOCKE, THE REASONABLENESS OF CHRISTIANITY 55 241-45, at 169-85 (George W. Ewing ed., 1965) (1695).
    • See JOHN LOCKE, THE REASONABLENESS OF CHRISTIANITY 55 241-45, at 169-85 (George W. Ewing ed., 1965) (1695).
  • 198
    • 68949095415 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JOHN LOCKE, A LETTER CONCERNING TOLERATION 18 (London, Awnsham Churchill 1689).
    • JOHN LOCKE, A LETTER CONCERNING TOLERATION 18 (London, Awnsham Churchill 1689).
  • 199
    • 68949138367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JOHN LOCKE, Epistola de Tolerantia: A Letter Concerning Toleration 122 (Raymond Klibanskyed.,J.W. Gough trans., 1968) (1689).
    • JOHN LOCKE, Epistola de Tolerantia: A Letter Concerning Toleration 122 (Raymond Klibanskyed.,J.W. Gough trans., 1968) (1689).
  • 200
    • 68949139799 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LOCKE, supra note 199, at 40-41
    • LOCKE, supra note 199, at 40-41.
  • 201
    • 68949139802 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See LOCKE, supra note 193, 11.34, at 291.
    • See LOCKE, supra note 193, 11.34, at 291.
  • 202
    • 68949095705 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra notes 158-60 and accompanying text; see also Claeys, supra note 191, at 223-24.
    • See supra notes 158-60 and accompanying text; see also Claeys, supra note 191, at 223-24.
  • 204
    • 84868079593 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 193, II.5, at
    • LOCKE, supra note 193, II.5, at 303-320.
    • supra , pp. 303-320
    • LOCKE1
  • 205
    • 68949126717 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I BLACKSTONE, supra note 12, at *123.
    • I BLACKSTONE, supra note 12, at *123.
  • 206
    • 68949132378 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at *124
    • id. at *124.
  • 207
    • 68949095660 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 208
    • 68949122243 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at *8
    • id. at *8.
  • 209
    • 68949138363 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., MARK WARREN BAILEY, GUARDIANS OF THE MORAL ORDER: THE LEGAL PHILOSOPHY OF THE SUPREME COURT, 1860-1910, at 24-84 (2004) (describing the standard catechism of law, ethics, politics, and theology learned by college students in the second quarter of the nineteenth century at leading liberal arts colleges).
    • See, e.g., MARK WARREN BAILEY, GUARDIANS OF THE MORAL ORDER: THE LEGAL PHILOSOPHY OF THE SUPREME COURT, 1860-1910, at 24-84 (2004) (describing the standard catechism of law, ethics, politics, and theology learned by college students in the second quarter of the nineteenth century at leading liberal arts colleges).
  • 210
    • 68949136429 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., THE FEDERALIST NO. 10, at 77, 79 (James Madison) (Clinton Rossiter ed., 1961) (suggesting that the latent causes of faction are .. . sown in the nature of man and include zeal for different opinions concerning religion, concerning government, and many other points, as well of speculation as of practice, an attachment to different leaders, and the verious [sic] and unequal distribution of property).
    • See, e.g., THE FEDERALIST NO. 10, at 77, 79 (James Madison) (Clinton Rossiter ed., 1961) (suggesting that "the latent causes of faction are .. . sown in the nature of man" and include "zeal for different opinions concerning religion, concerning government, and many other points, as well of speculation as of practice," "an attachment to different leaders," and "the verious [sic] and unequal distribution of property").
  • 211
    • 68949132360 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • THE FEDERALIST NO. 51 (James Madison), supra note 211, at 320, 324 (explaining how the American political order secures civil rights widi the multiplicity of interests and religious rights with the multiplicity of sects).
    • THE FEDERALIST NO. 51 (James Madison), supra note 211, at 320, 324 (explaining how the American political order secures civil rights widi "the multiplicity of interests" and religious rights with "the multiplicity of sects").
  • 213
    • 68949095706 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. art. XV (June 12, 1776).
    • Id. art. XV (June 12, 1776).
  • 214
    • 68949132377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., MASS. CONST, of 1780, Declaration of Rights, art. 3 (stating that the happiness of a people, and the good order and preservation of civil government, essentially depend upon piety, religion and morality); Northwest Ordinance art. 3 (1787) (assuming [r]eligion, morality, and knowledge [to be] necessary to good government and the happiness of mankind).
    • See, e.g., MASS. CONST, of 1780, Declaration of Rights, art. 3 (stating that "the happiness of a people, and the good order and preservation of civil government, essentially depend upon piety, religion and morality"); Northwest Ordinance art. 3 (1787) (assuming "[r]eligion, morality, and knowledge [to be] necessary to good government and the happiness of mankind").
  • 215
    • 21344464214 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Property as the Keystone Right?, 71
    • See generally
    • See generally Carol M. Rose, Property as the Keystone Right?, 71 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 329 (1996).
    • (1996) NOTRE DAME L. REV , vol.329
    • Rose, C.M.1
  • 216
    • 68949153303 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • THE FEDERALIST NO. 10, supra note 211, at 78. But see The FEDERALIST NO. 3 (John Jay), supra note 211, at 44, 45 (describing public safety as the first object of government).
    • THE FEDERALIST NO. 10, supra note 211, at 78. But see The FEDERALIST NO. 3 (John Jay), supra note 211, at 44, 45 (describing public safety as the first object of government).
  • 217
    • 12344277664 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BUCKLE, supra note 58, at 124; Paul A. Rahe, TAe Political Needs of a Toolmaking Animal: Madison, Hamilton, Locke, and the Question of Property, 22 Soc. PHIL. & POL'Y 1 (2005).
    • See BUCKLE, supra note 58, at 124; Paul A. Rahe, TAe Political Needs of a Toolmaking Animal: Madison, Hamilton, Locke, and the Question of Property, 22 Soc. PHIL. & POL'Y 1 (2005).
  • 218
    • 68949139623 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, MACINTYRE, supra note 80
    • See, e.g., MACINTYRE, supra note 80.
  • 219
    • 68949139624 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., ANDREW KOPPELMAN, ANTIDISCRIMINATION LAW AND SOCIAL EQUALITY (1996) (examining racism and stigmatization in both governmental and nongovernmental contexts).
    • See, e.g., ANDREW KOPPELMAN, ANTIDISCRIMINATION LAW AND SOCIAL EQUALITY (1996) (examining racism and stigmatization in both governmental and nongovernmental contexts).
  • 220
    • 68949095419 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Claeys, supra note 191, at 224-30
    • See Claeys, supra note 191, at 224-30.
  • 221
    • 68949138407 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See POLITICS, supra note 40, II.8, at 1268b22-1269a28; POLITICS (Lord trans.), supra note 40, at 72-73.
    • See POLITICS, supra note 40, II.8, at 1268b22-1269a28; POLITICS (Lord trans.), supra note 40, at 72-73.
  • 222
    • 68949132242 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 3 BLACKSTONE, note 12, at, Blackstone justified these laws on the ground that they inculcated charity, specifically as understood in the Mosaical law
    • See 3 BLACKSTONE, supra note 12, at *212-13. Blackstone justified these laws on the ground that they inculcated charity, specifically as understood in the Mosaical law.
    • supra
  • 223
    • 68949139618 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at *213; accord Leviticus 23:22; Ruth 2:2.
    • See id. at *213; accord Leviticus 23:22; Ruth 2:2.
  • 224
    • 68949095708 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Bennis v. Michigan, 516 U.S. 442 (1996) (rejecting a due process challenge by a wife to block a forfeiture proceeding against a car, co-owned widi her husband and used by the husband to solicit a prostitute, even though the wife did not audiorize or even know how her husband was using the car).
    • See, e.g., Bennis v. Michigan, 516 U.S. 442 (1996) (rejecting a due process challenge by a wife to block a forfeiture proceeding against a car, co-owned widi her husband and used by the husband to solicit a prostitute, even though the wife did not audiorize or even know how her husband was using the car).
  • 225
    • 84963456897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • notes 163-64 and accompanying text
    • See supra notes 163-64 and accompanying text.
    • See supra
  • 226
    • 68949095662 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alexander, supra note 4, at 746
    • Alexander, supra note 4, at 746.
  • 227
    • 68949095710 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 747.
    • See id. at 747.
  • 228
    • 68949095603 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Alexander, supra note 147, at 754-55
    • See Alexander, supra note 147, at 754-55.
  • 229
    • 68949139881 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alexander, supra note 4, at 774
    • Alexander, supra note 4, at 774.
  • 230
    • 68949095507 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 231
    • 68949138457 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 779-82
    • Id. at 779-82.
  • 232
    • 68949138580 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Estancias Dallas Corp. v. Schulte, 500 S.W.2d 217, 219 (Tex. App. 1973).
    • See, e.g., Estancias Dallas Corp. v. Schulte, 500 S.W.2d 217, 219 (Tex. App. 1973).
  • 233
    • 68949122245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 221-22 (suggesting that the court would deny the injunction only if the polluter could satisfy a 'stern rule of necessity rather than on the right of the [polluter] to work a hurt, or injury to his neighbor' (quoting Storey v. Cent. Hide & Rendering Co., 226 S.W.2d 615, 619 (Tex. 1950))); Quinn v. Am. Spiral Spring & Mfg. Co., 141 A. 855, 857, 858 (Pa. 1928) (holding that the defendant must move equipment in its iron and steel plant in order to minimize damage to a neighbor's house and providing for an injunction if the defendant could not comply).
    • See id. at 221-22 (suggesting that the court would deny the injunction only if the polluter could satisfy a " 'stern rule of necessity rather than on the right of the [polluter] to work a hurt, or injury to his neighbor'" (quoting Storey v. Cent. Hide & Rendering Co., 226 S.W.2d 615, 619 (Tex. 1950))); Quinn v. Am. Spiral Spring & Mfg. Co., 141 A. 855, 857, 858 (Pa. 1928) (holding that the defendant must move equipment in its iron and steel plant in order to minimize damage to a neighbor's house and providing for an injunction if the defendant could not comply).
  • 234
    • 68949095661 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Boomer v. Ad. Cement Co., 257 N.E.2d 870, 873, n.* (NY. 1970) (noting the number of employees and the amount invested in a cement plant before declining to permanendy enjoin the plant as a nuisance); Madison v. Ducktown Sulphur, Copper & Iron Co., 83 S.W. 658, 661, 666-67 (Tenn. 1904) (declining to permanendy enjoin mining and manufacturing operations, but granting damages after comparing the value of the industry to the surrounding property).
    • See, e.g., Boomer v. Ad. Cement Co., 257 N.E.2d 870, 873, n.* (NY. 1970) (noting the number of employees and the amount invested in a cement plant before declining to permanendy enjoin the plant as a nuisance); Madison v. Ducktown Sulphur, Copper & Iron Co., 83 S.W. 658, 661, 666-67 (Tenn. 1904) (declining to permanendy enjoin mining and manufacturing operations, but granting damages after comparing the value of the industry to the surrounding property).
  • 235
    • 0001609162 scopus 로고
    • Property Rules, Liability Rules, and Inalienability: One View of the Cathedral, 85
    • See generally
    • See generally Guido Calabresi & A. Douglas Melamed, Property Rules, Liability Rules, and Inalienability: One View of the Cathedral, 85 HARV. L. REV. 1089 (1972).
    • (1972) HARV. L. REV , vol.1089
    • Calabresi, G.1    Douglas Melamed, A.2
  • 236
    • 68949138373 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Alexander, supra note 4, at 762-64
    • See Alexander, supra note 4, at 762-64.
  • 237
    • 68949134270 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., J.E. PENNER, THE IDEA OF PROPERTY IN LAW 49 (1997) (If we believe in any fairly robust interest in autonomy, then the interest in determining the use of things is in part an interest in trying to achieve different goals.).
    • See, e.g., J.E. PENNER, THE IDEA OF PROPERTY IN LAW 49 (1997) ("If we believe in any fairly robust interest in autonomy, then the interest in determining the use of things is in part an interest in trying to achieve different goals.").
  • 238
    • 68949095664 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part I.E.
    • See supra Part I.E.
  • 239
    • 68949095505 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2 BLACKSTONE, supra note 12, at *2.
    • 2 BLACKSTONE, supra note 12, at *2.
  • 240
    • 68949139620 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at *14
    • Id. at *14.
  • 241
    • 68949138634 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Madison v. Ducktown Sulphur, Copper & Iron Co., 83 S.W. 658, 667 (Tenn. 1904);
    • Madison v. Ducktown Sulphur, Copper & Iron Co., 83 S.W. 658, 667 (Tenn. 1904);
  • 242
    • 68949139937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see JAMES W. ELY, JR., RAILROADS AND AMERICAN LAW 200-05 (2001);
    • see JAMES W. ELY, JR., RAILROADS AND AMERICAN LAW 200-05 (2001);
  • 243
    • 84869696011 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paul M. Kurtz, MreeíeenťA Century Anti-Entrepeneurial Nuisance Injunctions-Avoiding the Chancellor, 17 WM. & MARY L. REV. 621, 647-48, 656-63 (1976).
    • Paul M. Kurtz, MreeíeenťA Century Anti-Entrepeneurial Nuisance Injunctions-Avoiding the Chancellor, 17 WM. & MARY L. REV. 621, 647-48, 656-63 (1976).
  • 244
    • 68949138368 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some of the confusion here stems also from a tendency in the cases to describe property in terms of the lay conception of the right to exclude. As Alexander correcdy notes, exclude focuses on the right without the correlative duty. If property refers to a domain of [e]xclusivity, exclusive use accentuates the fact that boundaries steer parallel discretion to many different owners simultaneously. See supra note 133 and accompanying text.
    • Some of the confusion here stems also from a tendency in the cases to describe property in terms of the lay conception of the "right to exclude." As Alexander correcdy notes, "exclude" focuses on the right without the correlative duty. If property refers to a domain of "[e]xclusivity," "exclusive use" accentuates the fact that boundaries steer parallel discretion to many different owners simultaneously. See supra note 133 and accompanying text.
  • 245
    • 68949095663 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Calabresi &: Melamed, supra note 235, at 1116
    • See Calabresi &: Melamed, supra note 235, at 1116.
  • 246
    • 68949144467 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alexander, supra note 4, at 780
    • Alexander, supra note 4, at 780.
  • 247
    • 68949139933 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 257 N.E.2d 870 (N.Y. 1970). In fairness, even after Boomer, many modern cases continue to weigh the equities more skeptically than Boomer encourages.
    • 257 N.E.2d 870 (N.Y. 1970). In fairness, even after Boomer, many modern cases continue to weigh the equities more skeptically than Boomer encourages.
  • 248
    • 68949139619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Estancias Dallas Corp. v. Schultz, 500 S.W.2d 217 (Tex. App. 1973). Even in Boomer, on remand, the trial court awarded the plaintiffs quadruple the actual damages it had determined they had suffered before appeal.
    • See, e.g., Estancias Dallas Corp. v. Schultz, 500 S.W.2d 217 (Tex. App. 1973). Even in Boomer, on remand, the trial court awarded the plaintiffs quadruple the actual damages it had determined they had suffered before appeal.
  • 249
    • 68949095605 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Daniel A. Farber, Reassessing Boomer: Justice, Efficiency, and Nuisance Law, in PROPERTY LAW AND LEGAL EDUCATION: ESSAYS IN HONOR OF JOHN E. CRIBBET 7, 8-11 (Peter Hay & Michael H. Heoflich eds., 1988). For a skeptical account of Boomer, consider Roger Meiners & Bruce Yandle, Common Law and the Conceit of Modem Environmental Policy, 7 GEO. MASON L. REV. 923 (1999).
    • See Daniel A. Farber, Reassessing Boomer: Justice, Efficiency, and Nuisance Law, in PROPERTY LAW AND LEGAL EDUCATION: ESSAYS IN HONOR OF JOHN E. CRIBBET 7, 8-11 (Peter Hay & Michael H. Heoflich eds., 1988). For a skeptical account of Boomer, consider Roger Meiners & Bruce Yandle, Common Law and the Conceit of Modem Environmental Policy, 7 GEO. MASON L. REV. 923 (1999).
  • 250
    • 84869707035 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS §§826-28 (1979). I might use a theory of justice to interpret an instrumentalist opinion if the opinion's instrumentalist arguments are so question-begging they seem likely to be recasting instrumentally latent and unarticulated claims of justice. Posner's economic analysis of adverse possession reads this way to me. See supra notes 124-25 and accompanying text. That possibility might apply to economic analysis of nuisance remethes, but whether it does or not is a question too complicated and tangential to explore here.
    • RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS §§826-28 (1979). I might use a theory of justice to interpret an instrumentalist opinion if the opinion's instrumentalist arguments are so question-begging they seem likely to be recasting instrumentally latent and unarticulated claims of justice. Posner's economic analysis of adverse possession reads this way to me. See supra notes 124-25 and accompanying text. That possibility might apply to economic analysis of nuisance remethes, but whether it does or not is a question too complicated and tangential to explore here.
  • 251
    • 84869694861 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • King v. Columbian Carbon Co., 152 F.2d 636, 638 (5th Cir. 1945); see Pendoley v. Ferreira, 187 N.E.2d 142, 146 (Mass. 1963) (giving [d]ue consideration ... to the [defendants'] economic interest in an orderly, rather dian a hurried, liquidation of their [polluting business]); Gilbert v. Showérman, 23 Mich. 448 at *4 (1871) (denying injunctive relief where the business of the defendants is . . . lawful in itself and necessary to the community); Storey v. Cent. Hide & Rendering Co, 226 S.W.2d 615, 617 (Tex. 1950) (focusing on whether the defendant engaged in a lawful activity);
    • King v. Columbian Carbon Co., 152 F.2d 636, 638 (5th Cir. 1945); see Pendoley v. Ferreira, 187 N.E.2d 142, 146 (Mass. 1963) (giving "[d]ue consideration ... to the [defendants'] economic interest in an orderly, rather dian a hurried, liquidation of their [polluting business]"); Gilbert v. Showérman, 23 Mich. 448 at *4 (1871) (denying injunctive relief where "the business of the defendants is . . . lawful in itself and necessary to the community"); Storey v. Cent. Hide & Rendering Co, 226 S.W.2d 615, 617 (Tex. 1950) (focusing on whether the defendant engaged in a "lawful" activity);
  • 252
    • 68949144466 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also H.G. WOOD, A PRACTICAL TREATISE ON THE LAW OF NUISANCES IN THEIR VARIOUS FORMS: INCLUDING REMEDIES THEREFOR AT LAW AND IN EQUITY 1182 (3d ed. 1893) ([T]he effect upon the defendant's business and interests will be considered.).
    • see also H.G. WOOD, A PRACTICAL TREATISE ON THE LAW OF NUISANCES IN THEIR VARIOUS FORMS: INCLUDING REMEDIES THEREFOR AT LAW AND IN EQUITY 1182 (3d ed. 1893) ("[T]he effect upon the defendant's business and interests will be considered.").
  • 253
    • 68949153380 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alexander, supra note 4, at 781
    • Alexander, supra note 4, at 781.
  • 254
    • 68949138409 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Provided the law recognizes that the plaintiff has suffered some invasion of rights and holds the plaintiff harmless for the taking with proper damages.
    • Provided the law recognizes that the plaintiff has suffered some invasion of rights and holds the plaintiff harmless for the taking with proper damages.
  • 255
    • 68949122247 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Carpenter v. Double R Catde Co., 701 P.2d 222, 227 (Idaho 1985), takes this approach, but the case is regarded as an outher. See, e.g., RICHARD A. EPSTEIN, TORTS 361 (2001) (praising the strong dissent for righdy denouncing] the majority's approach).
    • Carpenter v. Double R Catde Co., 701 P.2d 222, 227 (Idaho 1985), takes this approach, but the case is regarded as an outher. See, e.g., RICHARD A. EPSTEIN, TORTS 361 (2001) (praising the "strong dissent" for "righdy denouncing]" the majority's approach).
  • 256
    • 68949153307 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Smith, supra note 124, at 985-86
    • See Smith, supra note 124, at 985-86.
  • 257
    • 68949138458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 277 A.2d 369 (N.J. 1971).
    • 277 A.2d 369 (N.J. 1971).
  • 258
    • 68949153306 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, Pruneyard Shopping Ctr. v. Robbins, 447 U.S. 74, 77, 88 (1980) (holding that a state law did not violate property rights when it prevented a private shopping center from excluding individuals seeking signatures for a petition).
    • See, e.g, Pruneyard Shopping Ctr. v. Robbins, 447 U.S. 74, 77, 88 (1980) (holding that a state law did not violate property rights when it prevented a private shopping center from excluding individuals seeking signatures for a petition).
  • 259
    • 68949138462 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Shack, 277 A.2d at 370.
    • See Shack, 277 A.2d at 370.
  • 260
    • 68949095509 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 370-71.
    • See id. at 370-71.
  • 261
    • 68949132357 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 373-75.
    • See id. at 373-75.
  • 262
    • 84869707033 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Peñalver, supra note 5, at 883-84
    • Peñalver, supra note 5, at 883-84.
  • 263
    • 68949139936 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Alexander, supra note 4, at 808
    • See Alexander, supra note 4, at 808.
  • 264
    • 68949138374 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • w. PAGE KEETON ET AL., PROSSER AND KEETON ON THE LAW OF TORTS 70 (5tt ed. 1984).
    • w. PAGE KEETON ET AL., PROSSER AND KEETON ON THE LAW OF TORTS 70 (5tt ed. 1984).
  • 265
    • 68949138461 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BLACKSTONE, supra note 12, at *209.
    • BLACKSTONE, supra note 12, at *209.
  • 266
    • 68949138372 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Vincent v. Lake Erie Transp. Co., 124 N.W. 221 (Minn. 1910); Ploof v. Putnam, 71 A. 188 (Vt. 1908).
    • See, e.g., Vincent v. Lake Erie Transp. Co., 124 N.W. 221 (Minn. 1910); Ploof v. Putnam, 71 A. 188 (Vt. 1908).
  • 267
    • 68949138371 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Smith v. New England Aircraft Co., 170 N.E. 385 (Mass. 1930).
    • See, e.g., Smith v. New England Aircraft Co., 170 N.E. 385 (Mass. 1930).
  • 268
    • 68949139801 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Andrew P. Morriss, Review of Jesse Dukeminier and James E. Krier, Property (4th Edition 1998), 22 SEATTLE U. L. REV. 997, 1005 (1999) (calling Shack virtually meaningless outside its historical and economic context and questioning whether the case accurately expresses even a significant minority view of limits on the right to exclude).
    • See Andrew P. Morriss, Review of Jesse Dukeminier and James E. Krier, Property (4th Edition 1998), 22 SEATTLE U. L. REV. 997, 1005 (1999) (calling Shack "virtually meaningless outside its historical and economic context" and questioning "whether the case accurately expresses even a significant minority view of limits on the right to exclude").
  • 269
    • 68949139883 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see State v. Shack, 277 A.2d 369, 370 (N.J. 1971).
    • see State v. Shack, 277 A.2d 369, 370 (N.J. 1971).
  • 270
    • 68949138579 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id
    • id.
  • 271
    • 68949122249 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Morriss, supra note 262, at 1005-06.
    • See Morriss, supra note 262, at 1005-06.
  • 272
    • 68949139639 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an academic exposition of the case for protecting migrant workers, see MARC LINDER, MIGRANT WORKERS & MINIMUM WAGES: REGULATING THE EXPLOITATION OF AGRICULTURAL LABOR IN THE UNITED STATES (1992).
    • For an academic exposition of the case for protecting migrant workers, see MARC LINDER, MIGRANT WORKERS & MINIMUM WAGES: REGULATING THE EXPLOITATION OF AGRICULTURAL LABOR IN THE UNITED STATES (1992).
  • 273
    • 68949139621 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See WENDELL BERRY, THE GIFT OF GOOD LAND: FURTHER ESSAYS CULTURAL AND AGRICULTURAL (1981) (exploring how farmers enjoy closeness to land and the practice of farming independent from their monetary benefits).
    • See WENDELL BERRY, THE GIFT OF GOOD LAND: FURTHER ESSAYS CULTURAL AND AGRICULTURAL (1981) (exploring how farmers enjoy closeness to land and the practice of farming independent from their monetary benefits).
  • 274
    • 68949138369 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. ROBERT C. ELLICKSON, ORDER WITHOUT LAW: HOW NEIGHBORS SETTLE DISPUTES 40-120 (1991) (finding that ranchers and farmers internalize strong social norms to respect one another's boundaries, even when local trespass rules sanction such invasions).
    • Cf. ROBERT C. ELLICKSON, ORDER WITHOUT LAW: HOW NEIGHBORS SETTLE DISPUTES 40-120 (1991) (finding that ranchers and farmers internalize strong social norms to respect one another's boundaries, even when local trespass rules sanction such invasions).
  • 275
    • 68949138635 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Howard Gault Co. v. Tex. Rural Legal Aid, Inc., 615 F. Supp. 916, 922-26 (N.D. Tex. 1985).
    • See Howard Gault Co. v. Tex. Rural Legal Aid, Inc., 615 F. Supp. 916, 922-26 (N.D. Tex. 1985).
  • 276
    • 68949095508 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, Lloyd Corp. v. Tanner, 407 U.S. 551 (1972) ([T]his Court has never held that a trespasser or an uninvited guest may exercise general rights of free speech on property privately owned and used nondiscriminatorily for private purposes only.).
    • See, e.g, Lloyd Corp. v. Tanner, 407 U.S. 551 (1972) ("[T]his Court has never held that a trespasser or an uninvited guest may exercise general rights of free speech on property privately owned and used nondiscriminatorily for private purposes only.").
  • 277
    • 68949144468 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BARRY GREEVER, TRAIN INSTITUTE, STRATEGIC AND TACTICAL RESEARCH POWER STRUCTURE ANALYSIS 14, 16 (1981);
    • BARRY GREEVER, TRAIN INSTITUTE, STRATEGIC AND TACTICAL RESEARCH POWER STRUCTURE ANALYSIS 14, 16 (1981);
  • 278
    • 68949095602 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see id. at 58
    • see id. at 58.
  • 279
    • 68949153308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Smith, supra note 124, at 982-84
    • See Smith, supra note 124, at 982-84.
  • 280
    • 68949139882 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 962-63.
    • See id. at 962-63.
  • 281
    • 68949139935 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MACINTYRE, supra note 80, at 186
    • MACINTYRE, supra note 80, at 186.
  • 282
    • 84869711080 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Peñalver, supra note 5, at 884
    • See Peñalver, supra note 5, at 884.
  • 283
    • 68949139934 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, supranote 14, V.3, at 1131a24-bl2;
    • See NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, supranote 14, V.3, at 1131a24-bl2;
  • 284
    • 68949132359 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NICOMACHEAN ETHICS Sachs trans, supra note 14, at 84
    • NICOMACHEAN ETHICS (Sachs trans.), supra note 14, at 84.
  • 285
    • 68949111589 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GEORGE, supra note 91, at 44; accord POLITICS, supra note 40, II.5, at 1263M1-14;
    • GEORGE, supra note 91, at 44; accord POLITICS, supra note 40, II.5, at 1263M1-14;
  • 286
    • 68949132358 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • POLITICS (Lord trans.), supra note 40, at 61.
    • POLITICS (Lord trans.), supra note 40, at 61.
  • 287
    • 68949136430 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See PENNER, supra note 237, at 74-75
    • See PENNER, supra note 237, at 74-75.
  • 288
    • 84866252860 scopus 로고
    • Reliance Interest in Property, 40
    • arguing that, when individuals rely on relations organized around property assets, their reliance can grow into property interests in ttose assets, See
    • See Joseph William Singer, TAe Reliance Interest in Property, 40 STAN.-L. REV. 611 (1988) (arguing that, when individuals rely on relations organized around property assets, their reliance can grow into property interests in ttose assets).
    • (1988) STAN.-L. REV , vol.611
    • Joseph William Singer, T.A.1
  • 289
    • 68949138460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Rael Jean Isaac, WAo Funds the Left? The GOP, WALL ST. J., June 23, 1995, at Al4, Lexis Nexis Academic.
    • See Rael Jean Isaac, WAo Funds the Left? The GOP, WALL ST. J., June 23, 1995, at Al4, Lexis Nexis Academic.
  • 290
    • 68949134271 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1 XENOPHON, CYROPAEDIA 1.3.16-17, at 40-43 (G.P. Goold ed., 1994) (1914).
    • 1 XENOPHON, CYROPAEDIA 1.3.16-17, at 40-43 (G.P. Goold ed., 1994) (1914).
  • 291
    • 68949144469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see id. at 1.3.17-18, at 42-43.
    • see id. at 1.3.17-18, at 42-43.
  • 292
    • 68949095604 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ROBERT FAULKNER, THE CASE FOR GREATNESS: HONORABLE AMBITION AND ITS CRITICS 144 (2007);
    • See ROBERT FAULKNER, THE CASE FOR GREATNESS: HONORABLE AMBITION AND ITS CRITICS 144 (2007);
  • 293
    • 68949095557 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see id. at 140-44.
    • see id. at 140-44.
  • 294
    • 68949095411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I diank Peter Byrne for encouraging me to consider this possibility
    • I diank Peter Byrne for encouraging me to consider this possibility.
  • 295
    • 68949153379 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, supra note 14, X.9, at 1180a22-24;
    • See NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, supra note 14, X.9, at 1180a22-24;
  • 296
    • 68949139622 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NICOMACHEAN ETHICS Sachs trans, supra note 14, at 198
    • NICOMACHEAN ETHICS (Sachs trans.), supra note 14, at 198.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.