메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 67, Issue 1, 2009, Pages 37-47

Counterfactual narrative explanation

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 61949271944     PISSN: 00218529     EISSN: 15406245     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1540-6245.2008.01333.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (7)

References (28)
  • 2
    • 61049094035 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Interpreting Words, Interpreting Worlds
    • see pp. 439-440
    • John Gibson, "Interpreting Words, Interpreting Worlds," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 64 (2006): 439-450, see pp. 439-440.
    • (2006) The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.64 , pp. 439-450
    • Gibson, J.1
  • 3
    • 20644441869 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Who Is Afraid of Ceteris-Paribus Laws? Or: How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love Them
    • Compare Marc Lange, "Who Is Afraid of Ceteris-Paribus Laws? Or: How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love Them," Erkenntnis 57 (2002): 407-423.
    • (2002) Erkenntnis , vol.57 , pp. 407-423
    • Marc Lange, C.1
  • 4
    • 79955186502 scopus 로고
    • Emotions are species of determinate patterns of salience among objects of attention, lines of inquiry, and inferential strategies
    • MIT Press
    • Ronald de Sousa "Emotions are species of determinate patterns of salience among objects of attention, lines of inquiry, and inferential strategies." The Rationality of Emotion (MIT Press, 1987), p. 196.
    • (1987) The Rationality of Emotion , pp. 196
    • De Sousa, R.1
  • 5
    • 0003799915 scopus 로고
    • Word and Object
    • MIT Press
    • Willard van Orman Quine, Word and Object (MIT Press, 1960), p. 19;
    • (1960) , pp. 19
    • Van Orman Quine, W.1
  • 6
    • 60949203402 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Affective States and Epistemic Immediacy
    • see p. 81
    • Christopher Hookway, "Affective States and Epistemic Immediacy," Metaphilosophy 34 (2003): 78-96, see p. 81.
    • (2003) , vol.34 , pp. 78-96
    • Hookway, C.1
  • 10
    • 61049441097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Works of art tend to be designed to utilize a combined variety of human perceptual and intellectual capacities to a full extent
    • quote from p. 372
    • Denis Dutton "Works of art tend to be designed to utilize a combined variety of human perceptual and intellectual capacities to a full extent," in "A Naturalist Definition of Art," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 64 (2006): 367-377, quote from p. 372.
    • (2006) The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.64 , pp. 367-377
    • Dutton, D.1
  • 11
    • 79955353525 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • critical interpretationmarks a process of articulating patterns of salience, value, and significance in the worlds literary works bring to view
    • Gibson "critical interpretationmarks a process of articulating patterns of salience, value, and significance in the worlds literary works bring to view," in "Interpreting Words, InterpretingWorlds," p. 444.
    • Interpreting Words, InterpretingWorlds , pp. 444
    • Gibson, J.1
  • 12
    • 11144270760 scopus 로고
    • Kritik der Urtheilskraft
    • Berlin: Reimer
    • Immanuel Kant, Kritik der Urtheilskraft; Kants Gesammelte Schriften 5 (Berlin: Reimer, 1908), p. 190.
    • (1908) Kants Gesammelte Schriften , vol.5 , pp. 190
    • Kant, I.1
  • 15
    • 34948814174 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Armchair Philosophy, Metaphysical Modality, and Counterfactual Thinking
    • quotes from pp. 10, 15, respectively
    • Timothy Williamson, "Armchair Philosophy, Metaphysical Modality, and Counterfactual Thinking," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 105 (2005): 1-23, quotes from pp. 10, 15, respectively.
    • (2005) Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , vol.105 , pp. 1-23
    • Williamson, T.1
  • 16
    • 0002189157 scopus 로고
    • Truth in Fiction
    • Oxford University Press, quote from pp. 278-279
    • David Lewis, "Truth in Fiction," Philosophical Papers, Vol. 1 (Oxford University Press, 1983), pp. 261-280, quote from pp. 278-279.
    • (1983) Philosophical Papers , vol.1 , pp. 261-280
    • Lewis, D.1
  • 17
    • 34047122873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Introduction: Conceivability and Possibility
    • ed. Tamar Gendler and John Hawthorne Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • Tamar Gendler and John Hawthorne, "Introduction: Conceivability and Possibility," in Conceivability and Possibility, ed. Tamar Gendler and John Hawthorne (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2002), pp. 1-70.
    • (2002) Conceivability and Possibility , pp. 1-70
    • Gendler1    J. Hawthorne, T.2
  • 18
    • 79955226989 scopus 로고
    • deductive argumentswhose conclusion is the explanandum sentence; ⋯ and whose premiss-set, the explanans, consists of general laws ⋯ and of other statements ⋯ which make assertions about particular facts
    • Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall
    • Carl Hempel "deductive argumentswhose conclusion is the explanandum sentence; ⋯ and whose premiss-set, the explanans, consists of general laws ⋯ and of other statements ⋯ which make assertions about particular facts." Philosophy of Natural Science (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1966), p. 51.
    • (1966) Philosophy of Natural Science , pp. 51
    • Hempel, C.1
  • 21
    • 79955234169 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intentional heuristic: in determining what is true in a given fiction, the reader ⋯ should adapt the thoughts and premises that the author(s) of that fiction settled on in creating the work, yet only insofar as these assumptions mesh sufficiently with the features of the utterance
    • Paisley Livingston's "Intentional heuristic: in determining what is true in a given fiction, the reader ⋯ should adapt the thoughts and premises that the author(s) of that fiction settled on in creating the work, yet only insofar as these assumptions mesh sufficiently with the features of the utterance," in Livingston, Art and Intention, p. 207.
    • Livingston, Art and Intention , pp. 207
    • Livingston, P.1
  • 23
    • 0001995839 scopus 로고
    • Historical Narratives and the Philosophy of Art
    • see p. 321
    • Nöel Carroll, "Historical Narratives and the Philosophy of Art," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 51 (1993): 313-326, see p. 321.
    • (1993) The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.51 , pp. 313-326
    • Carroll, N.1
  • 24
    • 61949278921 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a thorough elaboration of the notion of a historical narrative, compare, p
    • For a thorough elaboration of the notion of a historical narrative, compare Nöel Carroll, "Historical Narratives and the Philosophy of Art," p. 321.
    • Historical Narratives and the Philosophy of Art , pp. 321
    • Carroll, N.1
  • 25
    • 61049106933 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moderate Actual Intentionalism Defended
    • see p. 431
    • Robert Stecker, "Moderate Actual Intentionalism Defended," The Journal ofAesthetics and Art Criticism 64 (2006): 429-438, see p. 431.
    • (2006) The Journal ofAesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.64 , pp. 429-438
    • Stecker, R.1
  • 27
    • 61149248798 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Family Resemblances, Relationalism, and the Meaning of Art
    • quote from p. 297
    • Daniel Kaufman: "There is a purely contemplative dimension to our experience of artworks; that one of our primary interests in art is in the states of mind and, especially, the distinctive pleasures that are engendered by its contemplation," in "Family Resemblances, Relationalism, and the Meaning of Art," The British Journal of Aesthetics 47 (2007): 280-297, quote from p. 297.
    • (2007) The British Journal of Aesthetics , vol.47 , pp. 280-297
    • Kaufman, D.1
  • 28
    • 60950157853 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aesthetic Experience Revisited
    • see p. 152
    • Nöel Carroll, "Aesthetic Experience Revisited," The British Journal of Aesthetics 42 (2002): 145-168, see p. 152.
    • (2002) The British Journal of Aesthetics , vol.42 , pp. 145-168
    • Carroll, N.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.