메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 64, Issue 4, 2006, Pages 439-450

Interpreting words, interpreting worlds

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 61049094035     PISSN: 00218529     EISSN: 15406245     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1540-594X.2006.00222.x     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (10)

References (29)
  • 1
    • 0042364682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reading Fiction and Conceptual Knowledge: Philosophical Thought in Literary Context
    • quote from p. 331
    • The work of Eileen John can be read as an implicit exception to this claim. Her work is marked by an interest in showing that of those works of fiction that put on offer a form of philosophical or conceptual knowledge, the moment of cognitive acquisition "is apt to occur primarily in our responses to the work - such works call for the reader or audience to be philosophers." Eileen John, "Reading Fiction and Conceptual Knowledge: Philosophical Thought in Literary Context," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 56 (1998): 331-348; quote from p. 331. I take it that locating the mechanism of cognitive acquisition in our responses to a work of fiction - rather than in some feature of the text itself - is tantamount to situating it in our interpretive activities. In a few respects, this article can be read as an attempt to explore how we might develop John's claim explicitly in terms of a theory of interpretation.
    • (1998) The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.56 , pp. 331-348
    • John, E.1
  • 2
    • 34347309262 scopus 로고
    • On the Cognitive Triviality of Art
    • For some of the more influential recitals of the arguments canvassed here, see Jerome Stolnitz, "On the Cognitive Triviality of Art," The British Journal of Aesthetics 32 (1992): 191-200;
    • (1992) The British Journal of Aesthetics , vol.32 , pp. 191-200
    • Stolnitz, J.1
  • 6
    • 61149177198 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Between Truth and Triviality
    • I developed a more sustained account of the problem than I offer here in "Between Truth and Triviality," The British Journal of Aesthetics 43 (2003): 224-237
    • (2003) The British Journal of Aesthetics , vol.43 , pp. 224-237
  • 7
    • 79954385587 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford University Press, forthcoming
    • and in Fiction and the Weave of Life (Oxford University Press, forthcoming).
    • Fiction and the Weave of Life
  • 9
    • 79954140086 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Interpretation
    • London: Routledge
    • For a clear and helpful overview of conventionalism and intentionalism in the theory of interpretation, see Robert Stecker, "Interpretation," in The Routledge Companion to Aesthetics, ed. Berys Gaut and Dominic McIver Lopes (London: Routledge, 1999).
    • (1999) The Routledge Companion to Aesthetics
    • Stecker, R.1    B. Gaut2    D.M. Lopes3
  • 10
    • 61049451826 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Art, Meaning, and Artist's Meaning
    • ed. Matthew Kieran New York: Blackwell
    • For an excellent critical discussion of intentionalism, see Daniel O. Nathan, "Art, Meaning, and Artist's Meaning," in Contemporary Debates in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art, ed. Matthew Kieran (New York: Blackwell, 2006).
    • (2006) Contemporary Debates in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art
    • Nathan, D.O.1
  • 11
    • 34547713943 scopus 로고
    • Intentions and Interpretation: A Last Look
    • ed. Gary Iseminger Temple University Press
    • For a popular account of a version of hypothetical intentionalism that gives a central role to the notion of an audience in imputing intentions that are in turn determinative of literary meaning, see Jerrold Levinson's "Intentions and Interpretation: A Last Look," in Intention and Interpretation, ed. Gary Iseminger (Temple University Press, 1992),
    • (1992) Intention and Interpretation
    • Levinson, J.1
  • 12
    • 77949517039 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hypothetical Intentionalism: Statement, Objections, and Replies
    • Penn State University Press
    • and his "Hypothetical Intentionalism: Statement, Objections, and Replies," in Is There a Single Right Interpretation? ed. Michael Krausz (Penn State University Press, 2002).
    • (2002) Is There a Single Right Interpretation?
    • Krausz, M.1
  • 14
    • 84929769107 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wittgensteinian Intentions
    • ed. Iseminger
    • For the classic statement of this, see Colin Lyas, "Wittgensteinian Intentions," in Intention and Interpretation, ed. Iseminger.
    • Intention and Interpretation
    • Lyas, C.1
  • 15
    • 79953912361 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Imagined Worlds and the Real One
    • ed. John Gibson and Wolfgang Huemer (London: Routledge)
    • Bernard Harrison, "Imagined Worlds and the Real One," in The Literary Wittgenstein, ed. John Gibson and Wolfgang Huemer (London: Routledge, 2004), p. 93.
    • (2004) The Literary Wittgenstein , pp. 93
    • Harrison, B.1
  • 16
    • 0003476974 scopus 로고
    • Harvard University Press
    • The phrase "fictional world" is used here in a generic sense. There are many accounts of the nature of fictional worlds currently on offer, and I would like to keep my account broad enough so that it can sit comfortably with many of them. For a helpful discussion of various ways philosophers give sense to the idea of a fictional world, see Kendall Walton, Mimesis as Make-Believe (Harvard University Press, 1990), pp. 57-69.
    • (1990) Mimesis as Make-Believe , pp. 57-69
    • Walton, K.1
  • 18
    • 79954379031 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Sun Also Rises: Incompatible Interpretations
    • whose influence on my thinking here I take this opportunity to acknowledge
    • I offer as evidence of this claim that in two of the most prominent anthologies on interpretation in analytic aesthetics - Iseminger, ed., Intention and Interpretation and Krausz, ed., Is There a Single Right Interpretation? - none of the contributors concern themselves with the fictionality (what I call the world-generating capacity) of literary works and the implications this has for our interpretive encounters with them, with one exception. The exception is Alan Goldman's "The Sun Also Rises: Incompatible Interpretations," in Krausz, whose influence on my thinking here I take this opportunity to acknowledge.
    • Krausz
    • Goldman, A.1
  • 21
    • 79954171153 scopus 로고
    • Man, Time, and Eternity
    • (New York: W. W. Norton & Company)
    • Cleanth Brooks, "Man, Time, and Eternity," reprinted in the Norton Critical Edition of The Sound and the Fury (New York: W. W. Norton & Company, 1994), p. 292.
    • (1994) Norton Critical Edition of The Sound and the Fury , pp. 292
    • Brooks, C.1
  • 22
    • 0004109730 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Harvard University Press
    • John McDowell, Mind and World (Harvard University Press, 1998), p. 11.
    • (1998) Mind and World , pp. 11
    • McDowell, J.1
  • 25
    • 0008271110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Penguin Classics
    • Charles Dickens, Oliver Twist (New York: Penguin Classics, 2003), p. 22.
    • (2003) Oliver Twist , pp. 22
    • Dickens, C.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.