메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 64, Issue 4, 2006, Pages 429-438

Moderate actual intentionalism defended

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 61049106933     PISSN: 00218529     EISSN: 15406245     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1540-594X.2006.00221.x     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (30)

References (29)
  • 1
    • 84920586763 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Blackwell
    • Gregory Currie, Arts and Minds (Oxford: Blackwell, 2004), p. 132.
    • (2004) Arts and Minds , pp. 132
    • Currie, G.1
  • 2
    • 63149113868 scopus 로고
    • Art Interpretation
    • I have developed this view in a series of books and papers: "Art Interpretation," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 52 (1994): 193-206;
    • (1994) The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.52 , pp. 193-206
  • 5
    • 48349092630 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield)
    • Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art: An Introduction (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 2005), pp. 127-142. These works also consider a variety of objections to both the unified view in particular and moderate intentionalism in general. Some of these are reconsidered here; others are not.
    • (2005) Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art: An Introduction , pp. 127-142
  • 6
    • 34249433536 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Intentional Model of Interpretation
    • Alex Kiefer misconstrues my view when he asserts that "Stecker's goal is to support a version of actual intentionalism, according to which an artist's work means just what the artist intended it to mean." In fact, without noticing it, he attributes to me a pair of inconsistent claims, since he immediately goes on to say: "His view is, roughly, that the meaning of a work should be understood along the lines of utterance meaning in ordinary conversation." This entails the inconsistency since utterance meanings can diverge from intended meanings, as Kiefer goes on to explain. Hence no one should have the goal mentioned in the first of the two quoted sentences, while holding the view stated in the second. See Alex Kiefer, "The Intentional Model of Interpretation," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 63 (2005): 271-281.
    • (2005) The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.63 , pp. 271-281
    • Kiefer, A.1
  • 7
    • 80054450407 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • David Davies argues that utterance meaning, as I set it out, can be reduced to "contextualized conventional meaning" in his review of Interpretation and Construction in The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 62 (2004): 291-293.
    • (2004) The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.62 , pp. 291-293
  • 8
    • 60950562583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Interpretation and Intention
    • example on p. 80
    • Noël Carroll, "Interpretation and Intention," Metaphilosophy 31 (2000): 75-95, example on p. 80.
    • (2000) Metaphilosophy , vol.31 , pp. 75-95
    • Carroll, N.1
  • 9
    • 80054644275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Art, Meaning and Artist's Meaning
    • (Oxford: Blackwell)
    • Daniel Nathan suggests that a disambiguating intention cannot make an ambiguous "text" unambiguous. "Art, Meaning and Artist's Meaning," in Contemporary Debates in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art, ed. Matthew Kieran (Oxford: Blackwell, 2005), p. 291.
    • (2005) Contemporary Debates in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art , pp. 291
    • Kieran, M.1
  • 10
    • 84920586763 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is true, but the object of interpretation is not a sentence or a text, but an utterance or work. See Currie, Arts and Minds, pp. 9-27. I doubt that anyone believes that an utterance of "Mary doesn't have a heart" means all the possible senses of the quoted sentence. For the intention to disambiguate, there must be the possibility of uptake.
    • Arts and Minds , pp. 9-27
    • Currie1
  • 11
    • 61049305358 scopus 로고
    • The Dead
    • ed. D. R. Schwarz New York: St. Martins Press
    • James Joyce, "The Dead," in The Dead, ed. D. R. Schwarz (New York: St. Martins Press, 1994), p. 48.
    • (1994) The Dead , pp. 48
    • Joyce, J.1
  • 12
    • 80054326756 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • My point about Blake is found in Interpretation and Construction, p. 47. Kiefer's response is found in "The Intentional Model of Interpretation," p. 272.
    • The Intentional Model of Interpretation , pp. 272
  • 14
    • 63149095563 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An Epistemic Dilemma for Actual Intentionalism
    • This version of the objection is found in Saam Trivedi, "An Epistemic Dilemma for Actual Intentionalism," The British Journal of Aesthetics 41 (2001): 192-206.
    • (2001) The British Journal of Aesthetics , vol.41 , pp. 192-206
    • Trivedi, S.1
  • 16
    • 34547713950 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Appreciation and Literary Interpretation
    • ed. Michael Krausz Penn State University Press
    • Peter Lamarque, "Appreciation and Literary Interpretation," in Is There a Single Right Interpretation? ed. Michael Krausz (Penn State University Press, 2002), pp. 285-306,
    • (2002) Is There a Single Right Interpretation , pp. 285-306
    • Lamarque, P.1
  • 17
    • 60950238430 scopus 로고
    • The Meaning of a Literary Work
    • make similar points
    • and Stein Haugom Olsen, "The Meaning of a Literary Work" New Literary History 14 (1982): 13-32, make similar points.
    • (1982) New Literary History , vol.14 , pp. 13-32
    • Haugom Olsen, S.1
  • 22
    • 80054481275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For further discussion of the epistemic problem of identifying intentions in and out of literary works, see my Artworks, p. 179
    • Artworks , pp. 179
  • 24
    • 77949525607 scopus 로고
    • The Relevance of Painters and Writers Intentions
    • Value maximizers about art interpretation include Stephen Davies, "The Relevance of Painters and Writers Intentions," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 41 (1982): 65-76;
    • (1982) The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.41 , pp. 65-76
    • Davies, S.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.