메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 64, Issue 3, 2006, Pages 367-377

A naturalist definition of art

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 61049441097     PISSN: 00218529     EISSN: 15406245     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1540-594X.2006.00217.x     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (55)

References (25)
  • 3
    • 84925919126 scopus 로고
    • Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall
    • published in response to Morris Weitz, this is a pioneering article. Richard L. Anderson, Art in Primitive Societies (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1979)
    • (1979) Art in Primitive Societies
    • Anderson, R.L.1
  • 4
    • 79954178413 scopus 로고
    • Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall
    • and Calliope's Sisters: A Comparative Study of Philosophies of Art (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1990); while these books do not present an explicit list, they bring together most of the items included here
    • (1990) A Comparative Study of Philosophies of Art
    • Calliope1
  • 5
    • 61049301502 scopus 로고
    • Why Philosophy of Art in a Cross-Cultural Perspective?
    • Julius Moravcsik, "Why Philosophy of Art in a Cross-Cultural Perspective?" The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 51 (1993): 425-436
    • (1993) The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.51 , pp. 425-436
    • Moravcsik, J.1
  • 7
    • 60949892256 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Art' as a Cluster Concept
    • ed. Noël Carroll University of Wisconsin Press
    • Berys Gaut, "'Art' as a Cluster Concept," in Theories of Art Today, ed. Noël Carroll (University of Wisconsin Press, 2000), pp. 25-44
    • (2000) Theories of Art Today , pp. 25-44
    • Gaut, B.1
  • 8
    • 1642391119 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But They Don't Have Our Concept of Art
    • ed. Noël Carroll University of Wisconsin Press
    • Denis Dutton, "But They Don't Have Our Concept of Art," in Theories of Art Today, ed. Noël Carroll (University of Wisconsin Press, 2000), pp. 217-240
    • (2000) Theories of Art Today , pp. 217-240
    • Dutton, D.1
  • 9
    • 12744250962 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aesthetic Universals
    • London: Routledge
    • "Aesthetic Universals," in The Routledge Companion to Aesthetics, ed. Berys Gaut and Dominic McIver Lopes (London: Routledge, 2001), pp. 203-214. These two somewhat different lists of characteristic criteria for art across cultures differ somewhat from my present list, which is now explicitly refined to include only recognition criteria for art
    • (2001) The Routledge Companion to Aesthetics , pp. 203-214
    • Gaut, B.1    Lopes, D.M.2
  • 11
  • 12
    • 0007436899 scopus 로고
    • New York: Free Press
    • and Homo Aestheticus (New York: Free Press, 1992)
    • (1992) Homo Aestheticus
  • 13
    • 0347541060 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Henry Holt
    • Paul Ekman, Emotions Revealed (New York: Henry Holt, 2003), is a good introduction to "generic" emotions. The distinction I make here is perhaps parallel to the Sanskrit distinction between bhava, the basic emotions of life, and rasa, the peculiar emotions, something like unique flavor, expressed in works of art
    • (2003) Emotions Revealed
    • Ekman, P.1
  • 14
    • 79953375522 scopus 로고
    • Defining Art Historically
    • Cornell University Press
    • Jerrold Levinson, "Defining Art Historically," in his Music, Art, and Metaphysics (Cornell University Press, 1990)
    • (1990) Music, Art, and Metaphysics
    • Levinson, J.1
  • 15
  • 16
    • 84877935740 scopus 로고
    • The Republic of Art
    • New York: Peter Lang
    • and many books and articles following; Terry Diffey, "The Republic of Art," in his The Republic of Art and Other Essays (New York: Peter Lang, 1991)
    • (1991) The Republic of Art and Other Essays
    • Diffey, T.1
  • 19
    • 79954239749 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brian Boyd has urged me in a personal communication to expand my list of recognition criteria to include separate items for (a) artifactuality and (b) having been made for an audience. I resist for the reasons given, but his may be the wiser view
    • Brian Boyd has urged me in a personal communication to expand my list of recognition criteria to include separate items for (a) artifactuality and (b) having been made for an audience. I resist for the reasons given, but his may be the wiser view
  • 20
    • 34249432769 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Cluster Account of Art Defended
    • Berys Gaut, "The Cluster Account of Art Defended," The British Journal of Aesthetics 45 (2005): 273-288
    • (2005) The British Journal of Aesthetics , vol.45 , pp. 273-288
    • Gaut, B.1
  • 21
    • 0000951796 scopus 로고
    • Proper Names
    • John Searle originated the notion of cluster descriptions in his 1958 paper, "Proper Names," Mind 67 (1958): 166-173
    • (1958) Mind , vol.67 , pp. 166-173
    • Searle, J.1
  • 22
    • 85047698992 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Cluster Theory of Art
    • Stephen Davies, "The Cluster Theory of Art," The British Journal of Aesthetics 44 (2004): 297-300. All quotations in this paragraph are from this source
    • (2004) The British Journal of Aesthetics , vol.44 , pp. 297-300
    • Davies, S.1
  • 25
    • 61049213071 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In urging me to include artifactuality and audience in the list, Brian Boyd pointed out the usefulness of these criteria to the soccer example: If you view a work of art as an intentional object (and something done for an audience) then you have a very good criterion for dismissing the soccer match: the two sides are not cooperating to achieve something together that will move an audience (that would be a Harlem Globetrotters display, not an actual match) but are competing: the various 'performers' are at counter-purposes, whereas even in collective works of art with competing interests, like a studio film, all involved are striving to create the work of art, although perhaps according to different values; or a jazz combo, where all spontaneously react to one another's play but for the sake of the work and the audience, not for the sake of a victory and the support of part of the audience
    • In urging me to include artifactuality and audience in the list, Brian Boyd pointed out the usefulness of these criteria to the soccer example: "If you view a work of art as an intentional object (and something done for an audience) then you have a very good criterion for dismissing the soccer match: the two sides are not cooperating to achieve something together that will move an audience (that would be a Harlem Globetrotters display, not an actual match) but are competing: the various 'performers' are at counter-purposes, whereas even in collective works of art with competing interests, like a studio film, all involved are striving to create the work of art, although perhaps according to different values; or a jazz combo, where all spontaneously react to one another's play but for the sake of the work and the audience, not for the sake of a victory and the support of part of the audience."


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.