메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 29, Issue 2, 2007, Pages 151-169

The aesthetic value of animals

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords

ANIMALIA;

EID: 34250822831     PISSN: 01634275     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.5840/enviroethics200729218     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (22)

References (75)
  • 3
    • 34250842133 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This attention is reflected in interest in ontologically bizarre artworks, such as some conceptual works, and in discussion of traditional forms of art, such as painting and music, which, some have argued, are not as ontologically simple as has been thought. For an overview of ontological issues in current aesthetic theory, see Stephen Davies, Ontology of Art, in The Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics, ed. J. Levinson Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003, pp. 155-80
    • This attention is reflected in interest in ontologically bizarre artworks, such as some conceptual works, and in discussion of traditional forms of art, such as painting and music, which, some have argued, are not as ontologically simple as has been thought. For an overview of ontological issues in current aesthetic theory, see Stephen Davies, "Ontology of Art," in The Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics, ed. J. Levinson (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), pp. 155-80.
  • 4
    • 34250807503 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Introduction: The Aesthetics of Nature
    • For an overview of work on nature in environmental aesthetics, see, Peterborough, Ontario: Broadview Press
    • For an overview of work on nature in environmental aesthetics, see Allen Carlson and Arnold Berleant, "Introduction: The Aesthetics of Nature," in The Aesthetics of Natural Environments (Peterborough, Ontario: Broadview Press, 2004).
    • (2004) The Aesthetics of Natural Environments
    • Carlson, A.1    Berleant, A.2
  • 5
    • 34250819650 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Other natural entities, such as swamps, forests, and mountains have been considered by environmental aestheticians in some depth, but discussion of animals is scant and unsystematic in comparison. I describe what some environmental aestheticians have said about animals in section three, below
    • Other natural entities, such as swamps, forests, and mountains have been considered by environmental aestheticians in some depth, but discussion of animals is scant and unsystematic in comparison. I describe what some environmental aestheticians have said about animals in section three, below.
  • 6
    • 34250812855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What is Aesthetic Pleasure?
    • See, e.g, Ithaca: Cornell University Press
    • See, e.g., Jerrold Levinson, "What is Aesthetic Pleasure?" in The Pleasures of Aesthetics: Philosophical Essays (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1996), pp. 1-10.
    • (1996) The Pleasures of Aesthetics: Philosophical Essays , pp. 1-10
    • Levinson, J.1
  • 7
    • 0041833980 scopus 로고
    • On the Origins of 'Aesthetic Disinterestedness
    • On the conception of disinterestedness and its historical development, see
    • On the conception of disinterestedness and its historical development, see Jerome Stolnitz, "On the Origins of 'Aesthetic Disinterestedness, '" Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism (1961): 131-43.
    • (1961) Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , pp. 131-143
    • Stolnitz, J.1
  • 8
    • 34250900719 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an overview of this issue, see chapters two and three of Nicholas Hammond's Twentieth Century Wildlife Artists (Woodstock, N.Y.: Overlook Press, 1986).
    • For an overview of this issue, see chapters two and three of Nicholas Hammond's Twentieth Century Wildlife Artists (Woodstock, N.Y.: Overlook Press, 1986).
  • 10
    • 34250812313 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Ruskin, Modern Painters (London: J. M. Dent and Co., 1907), 2, chap. 12, p. 240.
    • John Ruskin, Modern Painters (London: J. M. Dent and Co., 1907), vol. 2, chap. 12, p. 240.
  • 12
    • 34250820876 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Andrew Fisher notes this tendency in E. O. Wilson's Biophilia hypothesis and related sociobiological analyses of our relationship with nature: see Fisher's Aesthetics, in A Companion to Environmental Philosophy, ed. Dale Jameison (Maiden, Mass.: Blackwell, 2001), pp. 267-68.
    • John Andrew Fisher notes this tendency in E. O. Wilson's "Biophilia hypothesis" and related sociobiological analyses of our relationship with nature: see Fisher's "Aesthetics," in A Companion to Environmental Philosophy, ed. Dale Jameison (Maiden, Mass.: Blackwell, 2001), pp. 267-68.
  • 13
    • 34250814856 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Not all forms of environmental thought lean in this direction, of course: see, for instance, Peter Singer's withering repudiation of the term animal lover in Animal Liberation, 2d ed. (New York: Avon Books, 1990), pp. ii-iii.
    • Not all forms of environmental thought lean in this direction, of course: see, for instance, Peter Singer's withering repudiation of the term "animal lover" in Animal Liberation, 2d ed. (New York: Avon Books, 1990), pp. ii-iii.
  • 14
    • 34249433339 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Discussion of this issue remains rare, but is increasing: see especially Carol Gould, Glamour as an Aesthetic Property of Persons, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 63 (2005): 237-47.
    • Discussion of this issue remains rare, but is increasing: see especially Carol Gould, "Glamour as an Aesthetic Property of Persons," Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 63 (2005): 237-47.
  • 15
    • 34250881898 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is a brief consideration of the aesthetics of persons in Nick Zangwill, Beauty, in Levinson, ed., Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics, pp. 325-43, pp. 336-39;
    • There is a brief consideration of the aesthetics of persons in Nick Zangwill, "Beauty," in Levinson, ed., Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics, pp. 325-43, pp. 336-39;
  • 18
    • 0004254707 scopus 로고
    • Perhaps the best-known development of this line of thought is Naomi Wolf's, New York: Doubleday
    • Perhaps the best-known development of this line of thought is Naomi Wolf's The Beauty Myth (New York: Doubleday, 1992).
    • (1992) The Beauty Myth
  • 19
    • 34250845334 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the moral agent/moral patient distinction, see Tom Regan. The Case for Animal Rights (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1983), pp. 151-56.
    • On the moral agent/moral patient distinction, see Tom Regan. The Case for Animal Rights (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1983), pp. 151-56.
  • 20
    • 34250898927 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To my knowledge, there exists no systematic review of aesthetic practices concerning animals. In fact, the only philosophical work focusing specifically on the topic, of which I am aware, is Holmes Rolston, III's essay Beauty and the Beast: Aesthetic Experience of Wildlife, in Daniel J. Decker and Gary R. Goff, eds., Valuing Wildlife: Economic and Social Perspectives (Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press, 1987), pp. 187-96.
    • To my knowledge, there exists no systematic review of aesthetic practices concerning animals. In fact, the only philosophical work focusing specifically on the topic, of which I am aware, is Holmes Rolston, III's essay "Beauty and the Beast: Aesthetic Experience of Wildlife," in Daniel J. Decker and Gary R. Goff, eds., Valuing Wildlife: Economic and Social Perspectives (Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press, 1987), pp. 187-96.
  • 21
    • 34250828819 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ruskin, Modern Painters, 2, p. 246. Ruskin qualifies this claim, however, because animals can also possess typical beauty, which is independent of their vital beauty.
    • Ruskin, Modern Painters, vol. 2, p. 246. Ruskin qualifies this claim, however, because animals can also possess "typical" beauty, which is independent of their vital beauty.
  • 22
  • 24
    • 0003433302 scopus 로고
    • On this topic, see, London: The Tantivy Press
    • On this topic, see George Speaight, A History of the Circus (London: The Tantivy Press, 1980), pp. 125-28,
    • (1980) A History of the Circus , pp. 125-128
    • Speaight, G.1
  • 26
    • 0141478726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Diane Michelfelder, Valuing Wildlife Populations in Urban Environments, Journal of Social Philosophy 34 (2003): 85. Michelfelder's essay is not concerned with the aesthetics of wildlife per se, but with the broader issue of our moral relations with urban wildlife.
    • Diane Michelfelder, "Valuing Wildlife Populations in Urban Environments," Journal of Social Philosophy 34 (2003): 85. Michelfelder's essay is not concerned with the aesthetics of wildlife per se, but with the broader issue of our moral relations with urban wildlife.
  • 27
    • 0010655556 scopus 로고
    • Part and Parcel in Animal and Human Societies
    • Cambridge, Mass, Harvard University Press
    • Konrad Lorenz, "Part and Parcel in Animal and Human Societies," in Studies in Animal and Human Behaviour, vol. 2. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 115-95.
    • (1971) Studies in Animal and Human Behaviour , vol.2 , pp. 115-195
    • Lorenz, K.1
  • 28
    • 34250799462 scopus 로고
    • Cuteness
    • For further discussion of this response, see
    • For further discussion of this response, see John Morreall, "Cuteness," British Journal of Aesthetics 31 (1991): 39-47.
    • (1991) British Journal of Aesthetics , vol.31 , pp. 39-47
    • Morreall, J.1
  • 30
    • 1542511547 scopus 로고
    • Neoteny in American Perceptions of Animals
    • See also, ed. R. J. Hoage Washington, D.C, Smithsonian Institution Press
    • See also Elizabeth A. Lawrence, "Neoteny in American Perceptions of Animals," in Perceptions of Animals in American Culture, ed. R. J. Hoage (Washington, D.C.: Smithsonian Institution Press, 1989), pp. 57-76.
    • (1989) Perceptions of Animals in American Culture , pp. 57-76
    • Lawrence, E.A.1
  • 31
    • 34250831878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In his empirical study of attitudes toward wildlife, Stephen Kellert defines the aesthetic attitude as one that primarily emphasizes the attractiveness of symbolic significance of animals. The major concern is with the artistic merit and beauty of animals, or their allegorical appeal as bearers of some special message. Stephen Kellert, Perceptions of Animals in America, in Hoage, Perceptions of Animals in American Culture, p. 8.
    • In his empirical study of attitudes toward wildlife, Stephen Kellert defines the "aesthetic attitude" as one that "primarily emphasizes the attractiveness of symbolic significance of animals. The major concern is with the artistic merit and beauty of animals, or their allegorical appeal as bearers of some special message." Stephen Kellert, "Perceptions of Animals in America," in Hoage, Perceptions of Animals in American Culture, p. 8.
  • 32
    • 2942561396 scopus 로고
    • On Preserving the Natural Environment
    • Mark Sagoff, "On Preserving the Natural Environment," Yale Law Journal 84 (1974): 228.
    • (1974) Yale Law Journal , vol.84 , pp. 228
    • Sagoff, M.1
  • 36
    • 34250886657 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • reprinted in Nick Zangwill, The Metaphysics of Beauty (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2001), p. 116.
    • reprinted in Nick Zangwill, The Metaphysics of Beauty (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2001), p. 116.
  • 38
    • 0012221951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Eaton argues that the representation of deer in Bambi affected deer management policies for the worse, through its effect on public opinion, See her Fact and Fiction in the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature
    • As morality tales for children, anthropomorphic representations seem unobjectionable enough, though the broader implications of this practice may be problematic
    • As morality tales for children, anthropomorphic representations seem unobjectionable enough, though the broader implications of this practice may be problematic. Marcia Eaton argues that the representation of deer in Bambi affected deer management policies for the worse, through its effect on public opinion, See her "Fact and Fiction in the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature," Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 56 (1998): 149-56.
    • (1998) Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.56 , pp. 149-156
    • Marcia1
  • 39
    • 34250844756 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. Ronald Paulson New Haven: Yale University Press
    • William Hogarth, The Analysis of Beauty, ed. Ronald Paulson (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1997), p. 15.
    • (1997) The Analysis of Beauty , pp. 15
    • Hogarth, W.1
  • 40
    • 20144364036 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beauty and Utility in Eighteenth-Century Aesthetics
    • For an overview of the relation between beauty and function along with related concepts, see
    • For an overview of the relation between beauty and function (along with related concepts), see Paul Guyer, "Beauty and Utility in Eighteenth-Century Aesthetics," Eighteenth-Century Studies 35 (2002): 439-53.
    • (2002) Eighteenth-Century Studies , vol.35 , pp. 439-453
    • Guyer, P.1
  • 41
    • 79952468152 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is a large literature on the application of function, in this sense, to the traits of animals. Two representative treatments are Karen Neander, The Teleological Notion of 'Function,' Australasian Journal of Philosophy 69 (1991): 454-68:
    • There is a large literature on the application of "function," in this sense, to the traits of animals. Two representative treatments are Karen Neander, "The Teleological Notion of 'Function,'" Australasian Journal of Philosophy 69 (1991): 454-68:
  • 42
    • 0000103250 scopus 로고
    • A Modern History Theory of Functions
    • and Peter Godfrey-Smith, "A Modern History Theory of Functions," Noûs 28 (1994): 344-62.
    • (1994) Noûs , vol.28 , pp. 344-362
    • Godfrey-Smith, P.1
  • 43
    • 28644450851 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Modern Philosophical Resurrection of Teleology
    • For a more general overview of philosophical analysis of function, see
    • For a more general overview of philosophical analysis of function, see Mark Perlman, "The Modern Philosophical Resurrection of Teleology," The Monist 87 (2004): 3-51.
    • (2004) The Monist , vol.87 , pp. 3-51
    • Perlman, M.1
  • 44
    • 0004118035 scopus 로고
    • trans. James Creed Meredith Oxford: Oxford University Press, sec. 16
    • Immanuel Kant, The Critique of Judgement, trans. James Creed Meredith (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1952 [1928]), p. 73, sec. 16.
    • (1928) The Critique of Judgement , pp. 73
    • Kant, I.1
  • 45
    • 34250819648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paul Guyer, Kant and the Claims of Taste, 2d ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), p. 215. Note that other leading interpretations share Guyer's view that, for Kant, function or purpose is not internal to the pleasure of the beautiful (for a concise overview of these influential interpretations, see Guyer, Free and Adherent Beauty: A Modest Proposal, British Journal of Aesthetics 42 [2002]: 357-66).
    • Paul Guyer, Kant and the Claims of Taste, 2d ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), p. 215. Note that other leading interpretations share Guyer's view that, for Kant, function or purpose is not "internal" to the pleasure of the beautiful (for a concise overview of these influential interpretations, see Guyer, "Free and Adherent Beauty: A Modest Proposal," British Journal of Aesthetics 42 [2002]: 357-66).
  • 46
    • 34250802424 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dependent Beauty as the Appreciation of Teleological Style
    • Some interpretations of Kant, however, have more in common with the strong sense of functional beauty: see, e.g
    • Some interpretations of Kant, however, have more in common with the strong sense of "functional beauty": see, e.g., Robert Wicks, "Dependent Beauty as the Appreciation of Teleological Style," Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 55 (1997): 387-400;
    • (1997) Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.55 , pp. 387-400
    • Wicks, R.1
  • 47
    • 34250837790 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Understanding Kant's Distinction Between Free and Dependent Beauty
    • and Philip Mallaband, "Understanding Kant's Distinction Between Free and Dependent Beauty," Philosophical Quarterly 52 (2002): 66-81.
    • (2002) Philosophical Quarterly , vol.52 , pp. 66-81
    • Mallaband, P.1
  • 49
    • 60949294309 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aesthetic Judgments, Artworks and Functional Beauty
    • Stephen Davies, "Aesthetic Judgments, Artworks and Functional Beauty," Philosophical Quarterly 56 (2006): 237.
    • (2006) Philosophical Quarterly , vol.56 , pp. 237
    • Davies, S.1
  • 50
    • 34250834751 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Malcolm Budd seems to have something like the strong sense in mind when he discusses aesthetic judgments concerning the pleasing qualitative perfection of an organism as being an instance of kind K. The aesthetic qualities involved in such judgments, Budd explains, depend on the character of the natural functions of a certain natural kind and the ways in which they are realized in the appearance of something of that kind. These ways include fitness of the parts to perform their natural function and the manifest suitability of the bodily parts to the creature's ability to flourish in its natural environment. Budd, The Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature, p. 42
    • Malcolm Budd seems to have something like the strong sense in mind when he discusses aesthetic judgments concerning the pleasing qualitative perfection of an organism "as being an instance of kind K." The aesthetic qualities involved in such judgments, Budd explains, "depend on the character of the natural functions of a certain natural kind and the ways in which they are realized in the appearance of something of that kind." These ways include "fitness of the parts to perform their natural function" and the "manifest suitability of the bodily parts to the creature's ability to flourish in its natural environment." Budd, The Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature, p. 42.
  • 52
    • 0008438277 scopus 로고
    • Categories of Art
    • and Kendall Wallon, "Categories of Art," Philosophical Review 79 (1970): 334-67.
    • (1970) Philosophical Review , vol.79 , pp. 334-367
    • Wallon, K.1
  • 53
    • 34250836161 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Feasible Aesthetic Formalism
    • Note that even formalists concede that at least some of aesthetic qualities of art are shaped, in part, by knowledge of art history and genre: see, e.g
    • Note that even formalists concede that at least some of aesthetic qualities of art are shaped, in part, by knowledge of art history and genre: see, e.g., Nick Zangwill's "Feasible Aesthetic Formalism," Noûs 33 (1999): 610-29.
    • (1999) Noûs , vol.33 , pp. 610-629
    • Zangwill's, N.1
  • 54
    • 34250903344 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The general view that scientific knowledge can alter our aesthetic responses to natural things is developed by Allen Carlson in Aesthetics and the Environment: The Appreciation of Nature, Art and Architecture London: Routledge, 2000
    • The general view that scientific knowledge can alter our aesthetic responses to natural things is developed by Allen Carlson in Aesthetics and the Environment: The Appreciation of Nature, Art and Architecture (London: Routledge, 2000).
  • 55
    • 33644699813 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nature Appreciation, Science and Positive Aesthetics
    • I defend and develop this view in, 42 2002
    • I defend and develop this view in "Nature Appreciation, Science and Positive Aesthetics," British Journal of Aesthetics 42 (2002): 279-95,
    • British Journal of Aesthetics , pp. 279-295
  • 56
    • 35648938500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and in Theory, Observation, and the Role of Scientific Understanding in the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 36 (2006): 165-86.
    • and in "Theory, Observation, and the Role of Scientific Understanding in the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature," Canadian Journal of Philosophy 36 (2006): 165-86.
  • 57
    • 60949600883 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Natural Functions and the Aesthetic Appreciation of Inorganic Nature
    • I discuss the role played in aesthetic appreciation by knowledge of function specifically in, 44 2004
    • I discuss the role played in aesthetic appreciation by knowledge of function specifically in "Natural Functions and the Aesthetic Appreciation of Inorganic Nature," British Journal of Aesthetics 44 (2004): 44-56.
    • British Journal of Aesthetics , pp. 44-56
  • 59
    • 34250820875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note that Burke often speaks of utility, rather than fitness. These are distinct concepts, but Burke seems to use the terms interchangeably: It is said that the idea of utility, or of a part's being well adapted to answer its end, is the cause of beauty. . . (ibid., p. 104).
    • Note that Burke often speaks of "utility," rather than "fitness." These are distinct concepts, but Burke seems to use the terms interchangeably: "It is said that the idea of utility, or of a part's being well adapted to answer its end, is the cause of beauty. . ." (ibid., p. 104).
  • 60
    • 34250865354 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Burke's rejection of beauty as fitness was unorthodox in eighteenth-century British thought, but not unique. As Paul Guyer points out, Francis Hutcheson mounted a similar argument against Berkeley, though employing artefacts rather than animals in his examples (Beauty and Utility, p. 441); Hutcheson's argument occurs in the fourth edition of his Inquiry into Beauty and Virtue, and is reprinted in George Berkeley - Alciphron in Focus, ed. D. Berman (London: Routledge, 1993), pp. 169-70.
    • Burke's rejection of beauty as fitness was unorthodox in eighteenth-century British thought, but not unique. As Paul Guyer points out, Francis Hutcheson mounted a similar argument against Berkeley, though employing artefacts rather than animals in his examples ("Beauty and Utility," p. 441); Hutcheson's argument occurs in the fourth edition of his Inquiry into Beauty and Virtue, and is reprinted in George Berkeley - Alciphron in Focus, ed. D. Berman (London: Routledge, 1993), pp. 169-70.
  • 61
    • 34250867767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Burke's examples have classical antecedents: the pig snout, discussed below, clearly echoes the dung-basket of Xenophon's Memorabilia, reprinted in Philosophies of Beauty from Socrates to Robert Bridges: Being the Sources of Aesthetic Theory, ed. E. F. Carritt (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1931), p. 1.
    • Burke's examples have classical antecedents: the pig snout, discussed below, clearly echoes the dung-basket of Xenophon's Memorabilia, reprinted in Philosophies of Beauty from Socrates to Robert Bridges: Being the Sources of Aesthetic Theory, ed. E. F. Carritt (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1931), p. 1.
  • 63
    • 34250837791 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 107.
    • Burke1
  • 64
    • 34250819649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 105.
    • Burke1
  • 65
    • 34250849402 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 107.
    • Burke1
  • 66
    • 34250793686 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Guyer suggests that the Burke/Hutcheson counterexamples were not answered by eighteenth-century defenders of the view that fitness is a sufficient condition for beauty, and that the relationship of beauty to fitness was ultimately resolved in a different way (see above) by Kant (Beauty and Utility, p. 445, George Landow expresses a similar view in his study of John Ruskin's aesthetics, writing that whatever way Hume and others intended the notion of utility to be taken, in these terms the swine would have been beautiful. And swine are not beautiful. George Landow, The Aesthetic and Critical Theories of John Ruskin Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1971, p. 98
    • Guyer suggests that the Burke/Hutcheson counterexamples were not answered by eighteenth-century defenders of the view that fitness is a sufficient condition for beauty, and that the relationship of beauty to fitness was ultimately resolved in a different way (see above) by Kant ("Beauty and Utility," p. 445). George Landow expresses a similar view in his study of John Ruskin's aesthetics, writing that "whatever way Hume and others intended the notion of utility to be taken, in these terms the swine would have been beautiful. And swine are not beautiful." George Landow, The Aesthetic and Critical Theories of John Ruskin (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1971), p. 98.
  • 67
    • 34250822059 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is worth noting that Burke offers other examples of such cases, viz.: How well fitted is the wolf for running and leaping! how admirably is the lion armed for battle! but will any one therefore call the elephant, the wolf, and the lion, beautiful animals? (A Philosophical Enquiry, pp. 105-06). Since some of these animals are for us, if not for Burke, generally viewed as paradigms of the beautiful, they are not even putative counterexamples to the claim that looking fit is sufficient for being beautiful.
    • It is worth noting that Burke offers other examples of such cases, viz.: "How well fitted is the wolf for running and leaping! how admirably is the lion armed for battle! but will any one therefore call the elephant, the wolf, and the lion, beautiful animals?" (A Philosophical Enquiry, pp. 105-06). Since some of these animals are for us, if not for Burke, generally viewed as paradigms of the beautiful, they are not even putative counterexamples to the claim that looking fit is sufficient for being beautiful.
  • 72
    • 0344769335 scopus 로고
    • Beauty: Some Stages in the History of an Idea
    • On this shift, see
    • On this shift, see Jerome Stolnitz, "Beauty: Some Stages in the History of an Idea," Journal of the History of Ideas 22 (1961): 185-204.
    • (1961) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.22 , pp. 185-204
    • Stolnitz, J.1
  • 73
    • 34250871043 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Peter Kivy, The Seventh Sense: Francis Hutcheson and Eighteenth-Century British Aesthetics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1976), p. 94. On Hutcheson's criticisms of the identification of beauty with fitness, see n. 42 above.
    • See Peter Kivy, The Seventh Sense: Francis Hutcheson and Eighteenth-Century British Aesthetics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1976), p. 94. On Hutcheson's criticisms of the identification of beauty with fitness, see n. 42 above.
  • 74
    • 34250857205 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Along similar lines, Tom Leddy has recently argued that some aesthetic terms, such as looking neat and looking clean have been neglected because they are unusual or absent in art. See Leddy, Everyday Surface Aesthetic Qualities: 'Neat,' 'Messy,' 'Clean,' 'Dirty,' Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53 (1995): 259-68;
    • Along similar lines, Tom Leddy has recently argued that some aesthetic terms, such as "looking neat" and "looking clean" have been neglected because they are unusual or absent in art. See Leddy, "Everyday Surface Aesthetic Qualities: 'Neat,' 'Messy,' 'Clean,' 'Dirty,'" Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53 (1995): 259-68;
  • 75
    • 78649715029 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sparkle and Shine
    • 37 1997
    • "Sparkle and Shine," British Journal of Aesthetics 37 (1997): 259-73.
    • British Journal of Aesthetics , pp. 259-273


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.