메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 5, Issue 4, 1999, Pages 415-434

Incorporationism and the objectivity of moral norms

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 85022395247     PISSN: 13523252     EISSN: 14698048     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S1352325299054038     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (6)

References (27)
  • 2
    • 0347613405 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • consistency with morality is necessary but not sufficient, for membership in the legal system…. (2) A rule or standard could be law simply because it was part of (either critical or conventional) morality-i.e., the moral content of the rule or standard is sufficient to make it a member of the legal system.” Brian Bix, Patrolling the Boundaries: Inclusive Legal Positivism and the Nature of Jurisprudential Debate, 12 CAN. J.L. & JURIS.
    • As Brian Bix points out, there are two ways in which moral norms might figure into a legal system's criteria of validity: “(1) A rule or standard that would otherwise be part of the legal system would be excluded should it be inconsistent with a moral rule or standard-i.e., consistency with morality is necessary but not sufficient, for membership in the legal system…. (2) A rule or standard could be law simply because it was part of (either critical or conventional) morality-i.e., the moral content of the rule or standard is sufficient to make it a member of the legal system.” Brian Bix, Patrolling the Boundaries: Inclusive Legal Positivism and the Nature of Jurisprudential Debate, 12 CAN. J.L. & JURIS. 17, 21 (1999).
    • (1999) As Brian Bix points out, there are two ways in which moral norms might figure into a legal system's criteria of validity: “(1) A rule or standard that would otherwise be part of the legal system would be excluded should it be inconsistent with a moral rule or standard-i.e. , vol.17 , pp. 21
  • 3
    • 85022395035 scopus 로고
    • Law, and Morality, 68 MONIST
    • Joseph Raz, Authority, Law, and Morality, 68 MONIST 295 (1985).
    • (1985) Authority , pp. 295
    • Raz, J.1
  • 4
    • 33749474011 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in ANALYZING LAW: NEW ESSAYS IN LEGAL THEORY 33 (Brian Bix ed., ).
    • Scott Shapiro, The Difference that Rules Make, in ANALYZING LAW: NEW ESSAYS IN LEGAL THEORY 33 (Brian Bix ed., 1998).
    • (1998) The Difference that Rules Make
    • Shapiro, S.1
  • 5
    • 85022376493 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Guyora Binder, Critical Legal Studies, in A COMPANION TO PHILOSOPHY OF LAW AND LEGAL THEORY 280 (Dennis Patterson ed., ).
    • Critical legal theorists, however, dispute this claim. See, e.g., Guyora Binder, Critical Legal Studies, in A COMPANION TO PHILOSOPHY OF LAW AND LEGAL THEORY 280 (Dennis Patterson ed., 1996).
    • (1996) Critical legal theorists, however, dispute this claim.
  • 8
    • 85016697222 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Conventionality, and the Practical Difference Thesis, 4 LEGAL THEORY
    • Jules L. Coleman, Incorporationism, Conventionality, and the Practical Difference Thesis, 4 LEGAL THEORY 381 (1998).
    • (1998) Incorporationism , pp. 381
    • Coleman, J.L.1
  • 9
    • 85022422331 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • L.A. Hart… that unless a realm of metaphysically independent moral facts exists, the incorporation of moral criteria into a Rule of Recognition will mean that any norms validated by reference to those criteria are not preexisting laws” (CGL, 190-92, emphasis added).
    • For this reason, Kramer believes it is necessary to “rectify an unduly sweeping concession made by H.L.A. Hart… that unless a realm of metaphysically independent moral facts exists, the incorporation of moral criteria into a Rule of Recognition will mean that any norms validated by reference to those criteria are not preexisting laws” (CGL, 190-92, emphasis added).
    • For this reason, Kramer believes it is necessary to “rectify an unduly sweeping concession made
  • 12
    • 85022394987 scopus 로고
    • Jules Coleman and Brian Leiter describe metaphysical realism as follows: First, the existence and character of the world is not simply the extension of human mind…. Secondly, the existence and character of the world does not depend on the evidentiary tools available to us for gaining access to it.” Jules L. Coleman & Brian Leiter, Determinacy, Objectivity, and Authority, in LAW AND INTERPRETATION 203 (Andrei Marmor ed., ) [hereinafter DOA].
    • Jules Coleman and Brian Leiter describe metaphysical realism as follows: “Metaphysical realism is the view that what there is-the world-is independent of human minds in two senses. First, the existence and character of the world is not simply the extension of human mind…. Secondly, the existence and character of the world does not depend on the evidentiary tools available to us for gaining access to it.” Jules L. Coleman & Brian Leiter, Determinacy, Objectivity, and Authority, in LAW AND INTERPRETATION 203 (Andrei Marmor ed., 1995) [hereinafter DOA].
    • (1995) “Metaphysical realism is the view that what there is-the world-is independent of human minds in two senses.
  • 14
    • 0040272524 scopus 로고
    • in ESSAYS ON MORAL REALISM 22 (Geoffrey Sayre-McCord ed., ) [herein after MMR].
    • Geoffrey Sayre-McCord, The Many Moral Realisms, in ESSAYS ON MORAL REALISM 22 (Geoffrey Sayre-McCord ed., 1988) [herein after MMR].
    • (1988) The Many Moral Realisms
    • Sayre-McCord, G.1
  • 16
    • 85022359621 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in ANALYZING LAW: NEW ESSAYS IN LEGAL THEORY 11 (Brian Bix ed., ).
    • Andrei Marmor, An Essay on the Objectivity of Law, in ANALYZING LAW: NEW ESSAYS IN LEGAL THEORY 11 (Brian Bix ed., 1998).
    • (1998) An Essay on the Objectivity of Law
    • Marmor, A.1
  • 17
    • 85022349052 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On their view, conventionalism is a form of minimal objectivity that does not imply realism (DOA, 253).
    • Coleman and Leiter side with Marmor on this issue. On their view, conventionalism is a form of minimal objectivity that does not imply realism (DOA, 253).
    • Coleman and Leiter side with Marmor on this issue.
  • 19
    • 78650447024 scopus 로고
    • 11 J. LEGAL STUD. 139. For an interesting, though sometimes problematic, discussion of the various ways in which the Separability Thesis can be interpreted, see Klaus Füßer, Farewell to ‘Legal Positivism': The Separation Thesis Unravelling, in THE AUTONOMY OF LAW: ESSAYS ON LEGAL POSITIVISM 119 (Robert P. George ed., 1996).
    • See Jules L. Coleman, Negative and Positive Positivism, 11 J. LEGAL STUD. 139 (1982). For an interesting, though sometimes problematic, discussion of the various ways in which the Separability Thesis can be interpreted, see Klaus Füßer, Farewell to ‘Legal Positivism': The Separation Thesis Unravelling, in THE AUTONOMY OF LAW: ESSAYS ON LEGAL POSITIVISM 119 (Robert P. George ed., 1996).
    • (1982) Negative and Positive Positivism
    • Coleman, J.L.1
  • 21
    • 85022407509 scopus 로고
    • Austin expresses this intuition as follows: The most pernicious laws, and therefore those which are most opposed to the will of God, have been and are continually enforced as laws by judicial tribunals.” John Austin, THE PROVINCE OF JURISPRUDENCE DETERMINED 158. The intuition here is that a system of rules can be a legal system even if those rules do not comport with moral principles.
    • Austin expresses this intuition as follows: “Now, to say that human laws which conflict with the Divine Law are not binding, that is to say, are not laws, is to talk sheer nonsense. The most pernicious laws, and therefore those which are most opposed to the will of God, have been and are continually enforced as laws by judicial tribunals.” John Austin, THE PROVINCE OF JURISPRUDENCE DETERMINED 158 (1995). The intuition here is that a system of rules can be a legal system even if those rules do not comport with moral principles.
    • (1995) “Now, to say that human laws which conflict with the Divine Law are not binding, that is to say, are not laws, is to talk sheer nonsense.
  • 22
    • 85022386121 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Jules L. Coleman, Second Thoughts and Other First Impressions, in ANALYZING LAW: NEW ESSAYS IN LEGAL THEORY, “Now, to say that human laws which conflict with the Divine Law are not binding, that is to say, are not laws, is to talk sheer nonsense. note 21, at
    • For an opposing view, see Jules L. Coleman, Second Thoughts and Other First Impressions, in ANALYZING LAW: NEW ESSAYS IN LEGAL THEORY, “Now, to say that human laws which conflict with the Divine Law are not binding, that is to say, are not laws, is to talk sheer nonsense. note 21, at 264-66.
    • For an opposing view , pp. 264-266
  • 23
    • 85022419111 scopus 로고
    • Hereinafter referred to as AL. Raz believes the Source Thesis is implied by the view, which he takes to be conceptually true, that law claims legitimate authority. See Raz, For an opposing view note
    • Joseph Raz, THE AUTHORITY OF LAW 46 (1979). Hereinafter referred to as AL. Raz believes the Source Thesis is implied by the view, which he takes to be conceptually true, that law claims legitimate authority. See Raz, For an opposing view note 3.
    • (1979) THE AUTHORITY OF LAW 46 , pp. 3
    • Raz, J.1
  • 25
  • 27
    • 85022417201 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • While Dworkin acknowledges the existence of difficult cases that do not fall clearly under a rule, he believes they are not resolved by an exercise of judicial discretion. On Dworkin's view, there is always a right answer to such cases implicit in the preexisting law. Of course, it sometimes takes a judge of Herculean intellectual ability to discern what the right answer is, but it is always there to be found in preexisting law. Since the right answer to even hard legal disputes is always part of preexisting law, Dworkin believes that a judge can take property from a defendant in a hard case without unfairness (TRS, 87-130).
    • The same is true of Dworkin's view of judicial lawmaking. While Dworkin acknowledges the existence of difficult cases that do not fall clearly under a rule, he believes they are not resolved by an exercise of judicial discretion. On Dworkin's view, there is always a right answer to such cases implicit in the preexisting law. Of course, it sometimes takes a judge of Herculean intellectual ability to discern what the right answer is, but it is always there to be found in preexisting law. Since the right answer to even hard legal disputes is always part of preexisting law, Dworkin believes that a judge can take property from a defendant in a hard case without unfairness (TRS, 87-130).
    • The same is true of Dworkin's view of judicial lawmaking.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.