메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 4, Issue 3, 1998, Pages 359-380

Two puzzles from the postscript

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 85022852144     PISSN: 13523252     EISSN: 14698048     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S1352325200001063     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (4)

References (34)
  • 1
    • 79953124087 scopus 로고
    • The best-known example in legal theory is that of Gustav Radbruch, whose apparent conversion from positivism after World War II became the occasion for speculation about its implications in the classic exchange between Hart and Fuller. See H.LA Hart, Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals, 71 HARV. L. REV. 593 (1958); Lon Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to Lauf-a Reply to Professor Hart, 71
    • The best-known example in legal theory is that of Gustav Radbruch, whose apparent conversion from positivism after World War II became the occasion for speculation about its implications in the classic exchange between Hart and Fuller. See H.LA Hart, Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals, 71 HARV. L. REV. 593 (1958); Lon Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to Lauf-a Reply to Professor Hart, 71 HARV. L. REV. 630 (1958).
    • (1958) HARV. L. REV. , pp. 630
  • 2
    • 84984061568 scopus 로고
    • Herbert LA. Hart: In Memoriam, 6
    • N. MacCormick, Herbert LA. Hart: In Memoriam, 6 RATIO JURIS 337 (1993).
    • (1993) RATIO JURIS , pp. 337
    • MacCormick, N.1
  • 3
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • All page references in the text are to H.LA. Hart, (2d ed. ) (with Postscript).
    • All page references in the text are to H.LA. Hart, THE CONCEPT OF LAW (2d ed. 1994) (with Postscript).
    • (1994) THE CONCEPT OF LAW
  • 5
    • 0042534394 scopus 로고
    • “Soft positivism” is the term Hart uses to describe this position. For a book-length defense of this view, see WJ. Waluchow
    • “Soft positivism” is the term Hart uses to describe this position. For a book-length defense of this view, see WJ. Waluchow, INCLUSIVE LEGAL POSITIVISM (1994).
    • (1994) INCLUSIVE LEGAL POSITIVISM
  • 10
    • 84868616862 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Law's Normative Claims, (R. Geortre ).
    • See P. Soper, Law's Normative Claims, in THE AUTONOMY OF LAW 215, 218-20 (R. Geortre 1996).
    • (1996) THE AUTONOMY OF LAW , vol.215 , pp. 218-220
    • Soper, P.1
  • 12
    • 85022745693 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 94 MICH. L. REV. 1739, 1741-44 (reviewing W.J. Waluchow, INCLUSIVE LEGAL POSITIVISM, PRACTICAL REASON AND NORMS note 5); id, PRACTICAL REASON AND NORMS note 6
    • See P. Soper, Searching for Positivism, 94 MICH. L. REV. 1739, 1741-44 (1996) (reviewing W.J. Waluchow, INCLUSIVE LEGAL POSITIVISM, PRACTICAL REASON AND NORMS note 5); id, PRACTICAL REASON AND NORMS note 6, at 101-109.
    • (1996) Searching for Positivism , pp. 101-109
    • Soper, P.1
  • 13
    • 84922952188 scopus 로고
    • 75 MICH. L. REV. 473 (1977); D. Lyons, Principles, Positivism, and Legal Theory, 87 YALE L. J. 415 (reviewing Ronald Dworkin, TAKING RIGHTS SERIOUSLY); J. Coleman, Negative and Positive Positivism.
    • See P. Soper, Legal Theory and the Obligation of a Judge: The Hart/Dwbrkin Dispute, 75 MICH. L. REV. 473 (1977); D. Lyons, Principles, Positivism, and Legal Theory, 87 YALE L. J. 415 (1977) (reviewing Ronald Dworkin, TAKING RIGHTS SERIOUSLY); J. Coleman, Negative and Positive Positivism.
    • (1977) Legal Theory and the Obligation of a Judge: The Hart/Dwbrkin Dispute
    • Soper, P.1
  • 14
    • 85022889137 scopus 로고
    • LEGAL STUD. 139 (1982).
    • (1982) LEGAL STUD. , pp. 139
  • 15
    • 0008200920 scopus 로고
    • in NATURAL LAW THEORY 188 (R. Georee ed ).
    • See, e.g., M. Moore, Law as a Functional Kind, in NATURAL LAW THEORY 188 (R. Georee ed 1992).
    • (1992) Law as a Functional Kind
    • Moore, M.1
  • 17
    • 85022828600 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thus, Fuller himself could imagine justifying occasional retroactive laws, even though they too violated one of his eight constraints. See at 39
    • Thus, Fuller himself could imagine justifying occasional retroactive laws, even though they too violated one of his eight constraints. See id. at 39, 44, 51-62.
    • id. , vol.44 , pp. 51-62
  • 18
    • 85022860515 scopus 로고
    • In his famous Speluncean Explorers piece, Fuller imagines one judge “discovering” for the first time a dustyjudicial precedent that would completely reverse what judges had thought he law was, at least in some respects, arguably requiring a different result in the case before & h. See L. Fuller, 62 HARV. L. REV.
    • In his famous Speluncean Explorers piece, Fuller imagines one judge “discovering” for the first time a dustyjudicial precedent that would completely reverse what judges had thought he law was, at least in some respects, arguably requiring a different result in the case before & h. See L. Fuller, The Case of the Speluncean Explorers, 62 HARV. L. REV. 616, 628 (1949).
    • (1949) The Case of the Speluncean Explorers , vol.616 , pp. 628
  • 20
    • 85022783372 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 13, at 141,145-48 (on the distinction between a semantic and epistemic Rule of Recognition).
    • See. Coleman, INVENTING RIGHT AND WRONG note 13, at 141,145-48 (on the distinction between a semantic and epistemic Rule of Recognition).
    • INVENTING RIGHT AND WRONG note
    • Coleman1
  • 21
    • 85022789219 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • formal
    • At times, Hart suggests that his soft positivism only extends to this idea of rather than substantive incorporation. See, e.g., Hart, INVENTING RIGHT AND WRONG note note 3, at 258-59 (suggesting that his practice theory of rules explains howjudges may be agreed on “the relevance” of incorporated moral tests for law, even though they disagree as to what the tests require in particular cases). For the reasons suggested in the text, I have ignored the possibility that Hart thinks of soft positivism as involving only “formal” incorporation of moral standards, with all subsequent attempts to apply such standards constituting judicial legislation.
    • At times, Hart suggests that his soft positivism only extends to this idea of “formal” rather than substantive incorporation. See, e.g., Hart, INVENTING RIGHT AND WRONG note note 3, at 258-59 (suggesting that his practice theory of rules explains howjudges may be agreed on “the relevance” of incorporated moral tests for law, even though they disagree as to what the tests require in particular cases). For the reasons suggested in the text, I have ignored the possibility that Hart thinks of soft positivism as involving only “formal” incorporation of moral standards, with all subsequent attempts to apply such standards constituting judicial legislation.
  • 24
    • 85022839211 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ch. 5, at 86-87, with id, ch. 8 at 172-80 and ch 9
    • Cf. THE CONCEPT OF UW, ch. 5, at 86-87, with id, ch. 8 at 172-80 and ch 9 at 202-203.
    • THE CONCEPT OF UW , pp. 202-203
  • 25
    • 0004294163 scopus 로고
    • H.L.A. Hart
    • See H.L.A. Hart, ESSAYS ON BENTHAM 156-57 (1982).
    • (1982) ESSAYS ON BENTHAM , pp. 156-157
  • 26
    • 85022807959 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 10, at 218, 241
    • See P. Soper, supranolc 10, at 218, 241 n.10.
    • supranolc , Issue.10
    • Soper, P.1
  • 27
    • 85022904272 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 28, at 160; see also id.
    • H.L.A. Hart, supranolc note 28, at 160; see also id. at 264-67.
    • supranolc note , pp. 264-267
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 29
    • 85022750315 scopus 로고
    • 7 NAT. L. F. 177
    • See. Noonan, 7 NAT. L. F. 177 (1962) (book review).
    • (1962) book review
    • Noonan1
  • 33
    • 0142222771 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • THE AUTHORITY OF THE STATE note note note 14
    • See Dworkin, LAWS EMPIRE, THE AUTHORITY OF THE STATE note note note 14, at 191.
    • LAWS EMPIRE , pp. 191
    • Dworkin1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.