-
1
-
-
79953124087
-
-
The best-known example in legal theory is that of Gustav Radbruch, whose apparent conversion from positivism after World War II became the occasion for speculation about its implications in the classic exchange between Hart and Fuller. See H.LA Hart, Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals, 71 HARV. L. REV. 593 (1958); Lon Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to Lauf-a Reply to Professor Hart, 71
-
The best-known example in legal theory is that of Gustav Radbruch, whose apparent conversion from positivism after World War II became the occasion for speculation about its implications in the classic exchange between Hart and Fuller. See H.LA Hart, Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals, 71 HARV. L. REV. 593 (1958); Lon Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to Lauf-a Reply to Professor Hart, 71 HARV. L. REV. 630 (1958).
-
(1958)
HARV. L. REV.
, pp. 630
-
-
-
2
-
-
84984061568
-
-
Herbert LA. Hart: In Memoriam, 6
-
N. MacCormick, Herbert LA. Hart: In Memoriam, 6 RATIO JURIS 337 (1993).
-
(1993)
RATIO JURIS
, pp. 337
-
-
MacCormick, N.1
-
3
-
-
0004220262
-
-
All page references in the text are to H.LA. Hart, (2d ed. ) (with Postscript).
-
All page references in the text are to H.LA. Hart, THE CONCEPT OF LAW (2d ed. 1994) (with Postscript).
-
(1994)
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
-
-
-
5
-
-
0042534394
-
-
“Soft positivism” is the term Hart uses to describe this position. For a book-length defense of this view, see WJ. Waluchow
-
“Soft positivism” is the term Hart uses to describe this position. For a book-length defense of this view, see WJ. Waluchow, INCLUSIVE LEGAL POSITIVISM (1994).
-
(1994)
INCLUSIVE LEGAL POSITIVISM
-
-
-
10
-
-
84868616862
-
-
Law's Normative Claims, (R. Geortre ).
-
See P. Soper, Law's Normative Claims, in THE AUTONOMY OF LAW 215, 218-20 (R. Geortre 1996).
-
(1996)
THE AUTONOMY OF LAW
, vol.215
, pp. 218-220
-
-
Soper, P.1
-
12
-
-
85022745693
-
-
94 MICH. L. REV. 1739, 1741-44 (reviewing W.J. Waluchow, INCLUSIVE LEGAL POSITIVISM, PRACTICAL REASON AND NORMS note 5); id, PRACTICAL REASON AND NORMS note 6
-
See P. Soper, Searching for Positivism, 94 MICH. L. REV. 1739, 1741-44 (1996) (reviewing W.J. Waluchow, INCLUSIVE LEGAL POSITIVISM, PRACTICAL REASON AND NORMS note 5); id, PRACTICAL REASON AND NORMS note 6, at 101-109.
-
(1996)
Searching for Positivism
, pp. 101-109
-
-
Soper, P.1
-
13
-
-
84922952188
-
-
75 MICH. L. REV. 473 (1977); D. Lyons, Principles, Positivism, and Legal Theory, 87 YALE L. J. 415 (reviewing Ronald Dworkin, TAKING RIGHTS SERIOUSLY); J. Coleman, Negative and Positive Positivism.
-
See P. Soper, Legal Theory and the Obligation of a Judge: The Hart/Dwbrkin Dispute, 75 MICH. L. REV. 473 (1977); D. Lyons, Principles, Positivism, and Legal Theory, 87 YALE L. J. 415 (1977) (reviewing Ronald Dworkin, TAKING RIGHTS SERIOUSLY); J. Coleman, Negative and Positive Positivism.
-
(1977)
Legal Theory and the Obligation of a Judge: The Hart/Dwbrkin Dispute
-
-
Soper, P.1
-
14
-
-
85022889137
-
-
LEGAL STUD. 139 (1982).
-
(1982)
LEGAL STUD.
, pp. 139
-
-
-
15
-
-
0008200920
-
-
in NATURAL LAW THEORY 188 (R. Georee ed ).
-
See, e.g., M. Moore, Law as a Functional Kind, in NATURAL LAW THEORY 188 (R. Georee ed 1992).
-
(1992)
Law as a Functional Kind
-
-
Moore, M.1
-
17
-
-
85022828600
-
-
Thus, Fuller himself could imagine justifying occasional retroactive laws, even though they too violated one of his eight constraints. See at 39
-
Thus, Fuller himself could imagine justifying occasional retroactive laws, even though they too violated one of his eight constraints. See id. at 39, 44, 51-62.
-
id.
, vol.44
, pp. 51-62
-
-
-
18
-
-
85022860515
-
-
In his famous Speluncean Explorers piece, Fuller imagines one judge “discovering” for the first time a dustyjudicial precedent that would completely reverse what judges had thought he law was, at least in some respects, arguably requiring a different result in the case before & h. See L. Fuller, 62 HARV. L. REV.
-
In his famous Speluncean Explorers piece, Fuller imagines one judge “discovering” for the first time a dustyjudicial precedent that would completely reverse what judges had thought he law was, at least in some respects, arguably requiring a different result in the case before & h. See L. Fuller, The Case of the Speluncean Explorers, 62 HARV. L. REV. 616, 628 (1949).
-
(1949)
The Case of the Speluncean Explorers
, vol.616
, pp. 628
-
-
-
20
-
-
85022783372
-
-
13, at 141,145-48 (on the distinction between a semantic and epistemic Rule of Recognition).
-
See. Coleman, INVENTING RIGHT AND WRONG note 13, at 141,145-48 (on the distinction between a semantic and epistemic Rule of Recognition).
-
INVENTING RIGHT AND WRONG note
-
-
Coleman1
-
21
-
-
85022789219
-
formal
-
At times, Hart suggests that his soft positivism only extends to this idea of rather than substantive incorporation. See, e.g., Hart, INVENTING RIGHT AND WRONG note note 3, at 258-59 (suggesting that his practice theory of rules explains howjudges may be agreed on “the relevance” of incorporated moral tests for law, even though they disagree as to what the tests require in particular cases). For the reasons suggested in the text, I have ignored the possibility that Hart thinks of soft positivism as involving only “formal” incorporation of moral standards, with all subsequent attempts to apply such standards constituting judicial legislation.
-
At times, Hart suggests that his soft positivism only extends to this idea of “formal” rather than substantive incorporation. See, e.g., Hart, INVENTING RIGHT AND WRONG note note 3, at 258-59 (suggesting that his practice theory of rules explains howjudges may be agreed on “the relevance” of incorporated moral tests for law, even though they disagree as to what the tests require in particular cases). For the reasons suggested in the text, I have ignored the possibility that Hart thinks of soft positivism as involving only “formal” incorporation of moral standards, with all subsequent attempts to apply such standards constituting judicial legislation.
-
-
-
-
24
-
-
85022839211
-
-
ch. 5, at 86-87, with id, ch. 8 at 172-80 and ch 9
-
Cf. THE CONCEPT OF UW, ch. 5, at 86-87, with id, ch. 8 at 172-80 and ch 9 at 202-203.
-
THE CONCEPT OF UW
, pp. 202-203
-
-
-
25
-
-
0004294163
-
-
H.L.A. Hart
-
See H.L.A. Hart, ESSAYS ON BENTHAM 156-57 (1982).
-
(1982)
ESSAYS ON BENTHAM
, pp. 156-157
-
-
-
26
-
-
85022807959
-
-
10, at 218, 241
-
See P. Soper, supranolc 10, at 218, 241 n.10.
-
supranolc
, Issue.10
-
-
Soper, P.1
-
27
-
-
85022904272
-
-
28, at 160; see also id.
-
H.L.A. Hart, supranolc note 28, at 160; see also id. at 264-67.
-
supranolc note
, pp. 264-267
-
-
Hart, H.L.A.1
-
29
-
-
85022750315
-
-
7 NAT. L. F. 177
-
See. Noonan, 7 NAT. L. F. 177 (1962) (book review).
-
(1962)
book review
-
-
Noonan1
-
33
-
-
0142222771
-
-
THE AUTHORITY OF THE STATE note note note 14
-
See Dworkin, LAWS EMPIRE, THE AUTHORITY OF THE STATE note note note 14, at 191.
-
LAWS EMPIRE
, pp. 191
-
-
Dworkin1
|