메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 25, Issue 2, 1996, Pages 87-139

Objectivity and truth: You'd better believe it

(1)  Dworkin, Ronald a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0010915611     PISSN: 00483915     EISSN: 10884963     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1088-4963.1996.tb00036.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (468)

References (23)
  • 1
    • 53349149428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • "Skepticism" is used in different ways. I use it in the sense not of agnosticism but of rejection. I emphasize that different skeptics, even about morality, have different targets. The skeptics I mainly discuss claim to reject not morality but only certain philosophical opinions about it.
  • 2
    • 53349084123 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Whether a form of skepticism is properly understood as internal or selectively external to the domain it criticizes is often a complex interpretive question. Science-based skepticism about religion is internal, for example, if religion is understood to be itself part of the domain of science, as it should be if it includes causal claims about the origin of the universe that are competitive with other cosmological theories.
  • 3
    • 0004166519 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • I have discussed this distinction before. See my Law's Empire (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1986), pp. 78-86.
    • (1986) Law's Empire , pp. 78-86
  • 5
    • 0007187880 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Does Academic Freedom Have Philosophical Presuppositions?
    • ed. Louis Menand Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Richard Rorty, "Does Academic Freedom Have Philosophical Presuppositions?," in The Future of Academic Freedom, ed. Louis Menand (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996), pp. 29-30.
    • (1996) The Future of Academic Freedom , pp. 29-30
    • Rorty, R.1
  • 6
    • 53349139954 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Not, that is, if they are sensible. I am not considering here the patently false view that it is part of the very meaning of "correct" that right actions are those that maximize happiness. If that were right, only utilitarians could avoid linguistic error.
  • 8
    • 0007214911 scopus 로고
    • Two Notions of Necessity
    • Compare the discussion of "subjective naturalism" in M. Davies and L. Humberstone, "Two Notions of Necessity," Philosophical Studies 38, no. 1 (1980): 22-25. The subjectivism discussed there is personal - something being wrong is taken to be a matter of the speaker disliking it. The argument in the text, which addresses the less implausible example of intersubjective subjectivism, would of course also apply to the personal version.
    • (1980) Philosophical Studies , vol.38 , Issue.1 , pp. 22-25
    • Davies, M.1    Humberstone, L.2
  • 9
    • 0003678815 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • That is the sense of "represents" that Crispin Wright uses in exploring the question whether moral beliefs can represent reality. See Wright, Truth and Objectivity (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1992). I return to Wright's discussion later.
    • (1992) Truth and Objectivity
    • Wright1
  • 12
    • 0003925356 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Simon Blackburn, Essays in Quasi-Realism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992), pp. 172-73.
    • (1992) Essays in Quasi-Realism , pp. 172-173
    • Blackburn, S.1
  • 15
    • 0003438275 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • That is a crude statement of a prominent and influential account of interpretation. See Donald Davidson, Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984).
    • (1984) Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation
    • Davidson, D.1
  • 16
    • 0004269702 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • See Gilbert Harman, The Nature of Morality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1977).
    • (1977) The Nature of Morality
    • Harman, G.1
  • 17
    • 0004052131 scopus 로고
    • New York: Pantheon Books
    • See, for example, the literature described in Robert Wright, The Moral Animal (New York: Pantheon Books, 1994).
    • (1994) The Moral Animal
    • Wright, R.1
  • 18
    • 0003740191 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984), p. 431.
    • (1984) Reasons and Persons , pp. 431
    • Parfit, D.1
  • 19
    • 53349126095 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I say "all" sides to include the possibility that I see no good reason for thinking the issue indeterminate either
    • I say "all" sides to include the possibility that I see no good reason for thinking the issue indeterminate either.
  • 20
    • 0002494274 scopus 로고
    • Foundations of Liberal Equality
    • ed. Grethe Peterson Salt Lake City: University of Utah
    • I defend a different but in some ways similar view about ethics in "Foundations of Liberal Equality," in Tanner Lectures on Human Values, Volume XI, ed. Grethe Peterson (Salt Lake City: University of Utah, 1990).
    • (1990) Tanner Lectures on Human Values , vol.11
  • 21
    • 53349139953 scopus 로고
    • No Right Answer?
    • my book, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • For a fuller exposition of the argument of this paragraph, see "No Right Answer?" in my book, A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985).
    • (1985) A Matter of Principle
  • 22
    • 84925906459 scopus 로고
    • The Third Theory of Law
    • Fall
    • John Mackie argued that a legal theory that made moral argument relevant would characteristically produce indeterminacy. See his "The Third Theory of Law," Philosophy & Public Affairs 7, no. 1 (Fall 1977): 3-16.
    • (1977) Philosophy & Public Affairs , vol.7 , Issue.1 , pp. 3-16
  • 23
    • 53349158719 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Critical Legal Studies
    • See the discussion of "Critical Legal Studies" in my Law's Empire, pp. 271-74.
    • Law's Empire , pp. 271-274


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.