메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 11, Issue 2-3, 2012, Pages 135-158

Probability, anti-resilience, and the weight of expectation

Author keywords

Evidence; Inference; Probability; Resilience; Standard of proof; Weight

Indexed keywords


EID: 84866414503     PISSN: 14708396     EISSN: 1470840X     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1093/lpr/mgs004     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (12)

References (85)
  • 1
    • 84866400897 scopus 로고
    • At one point in time the expression 'probabilistic certainty'may have appeared an oxymoron, like 'relatively unique'. Many medieval philosophers viewed probability as the absence of certainty; the two were 'opposed categories' like true and false: Lorraine Daston, Classical Probability in the Enlightenment (Princeton University Press, Princeton, However, Bernoulli and his successors put the two on the same scale. '[S]eventeenth century mathematicians [came] to view the relationship of probability to certainty as that of parts to the whole
    • At one point in time the expression 'probabilistic certainty'may have appeared an oxymoron, like 'relatively unique'. Many medieval philosophers viewed probability as the absence of certainty; the two were 'opposed categories' like true and false: Lorraine Daston, Classical Probability in the Enlightenment (Princeton University Press, Princeton, However, Bernoulli and his successors put the two on the same scale. '[S]eventeenth century mathematicians [came] to view the relationship of probability to certainty as that of parts to the whole1988) 37.
    • (1988) , pp. 37
  • 2
    • 0000823710 scopus 로고
    • Trial byMathematics: Precision and Ritual in the Legal Process
    • 1346-50. Another often discussed hypothetical is the Gatecrasher Case: LJ Cohen, The Probable and the Provable (Clarendon Press, Oxford 1977) 75
    • Laurence H Tribe, 'Trial byMathematics: Precision and Ritual in the Legal Process' (1971) 84 Harvard Law Review 1340-41, 1346-50. Another often discussed hypothetical is the Gatecrasher Case: LJ Cohen, The Probable and the Provable (Clarendon Press, Oxford 1977) 75.
    • (1971) Harvard Law Review , vol.84 , pp. 1340-41
    • Tribe, L.H.1
  • 3
    • 84866372551 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Eg Grogan v Garner 498 US 279 (1991).
  • 4
    • 84866374939 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Eg Davies v Taylor AC 207, 219 (Lord Simon).1974
  • 5
    • 1542570085 scopus 로고
    • The Use of Statistical Evidence of Identification in Civil Litigation:Well-worn Hypotheticals, Real Cases, and Controversy
    • But see James Brook 'The Use of Statistical Evidence of Identification in Civil Litigation:Well-worn Hypotheticals, Real Cases, and Controversy' (1985) St Louis University Law Journal 293-299.
    • (1985) St Louis University Law Journal , pp. 293-299
    • Brook, J.1
  • 6
    • 0004281082 scopus 로고
    • A Treatise on Probability
    • MacMillan and Co, London
    • JM Keynes, A Treatise on Probability (MacMillan and Co, London 1921) 71
    • (1921) , pp. 71
    • Keynes, J.M.1
  • 8
    • 34250122774 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Barbara Davidson and Robert Pargetter, 'Weight' (1986) 49 Philosophical Studies
    • Barbara Davidson and Robert Pargetter, 'Weight' (1986) 49 Philosophical Studies 219
  • 9
    • 85010635736 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Weights of Evidence
    • Dale Nance, 'The Weights of Evidence' [2008] Episteme 267-268
    • (2008) Episteme , pp. 267-268
    • Nance, D.1
  • 10
    • 33750015574 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Foundations of Evidence Law
    • OUP, Oxford
    • Alex Stein, Foundations of Evidence Law (OUP, Oxford 2005) 47-48.
    • (2005) , pp. 47-48
    • Stein, A.1
  • 11
    • 0347825115 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Assessing Evidence
    • Richard Friedman, 'Assessing Evidence' (1996) 94 Michigan Law Review 1810-1819
    • (1996) Michigan Law Review , vol.94 , pp. 1810-1819
    • Friedman, R.1
  • 12
    • 77950416760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Philosophy of Evidence Law - Justice in the Search for Truth (OUP, Oxford)
    • Hock Lai Ho, A Philosophy of Evidence Law - Justice in the Search for Truth (OUP, Oxford 2008) 166.
    • (2008) , pp. 166
    • Ho, H.L.1
  • 13
    • 80855157275 scopus 로고
    • The Paradox of the Gatecrasher and Other Stories
    • Eg David Kaye, 'The Paradox of the Gatecrasher and Other Stories' [1979] Ariz State LJ 101.
    • (1979) Ariz State LJ , pp. 101
    • Kaye, D.1
  • 14
    • 84866433053 scopus 로고
    • The Civil Standard of Proof Uncertainty: Probability, Belief and Justice
    • David Hamer, 'The Civil Standard of Proof Uncertainty: Probability, Belief and Justice' (1994) 16 Sydney Law Review 506-516.
    • (1994) Sydney Law Review , vol.16 , pp. 506-516
    • Hamer, D.1
  • 15
    • 84866358877 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • [2011] UKSC 10 (9 March 2011).
  • 16
    • 84866358876 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • As the Court noted, this question has been considered elsewhere, eg Sienkiewicz (n 11) [85] (Lord Phillips), discussing Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals Inc v Havner 953 SW 2d 706 (1997).
  • 17
    • 84866400901 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • In addition to this theoretical concern, the court raised practical concerns about the significance and reliability of the statistics, the availability and reliability of evidence of the plaintiff's situation, and whether the statistics cover the plaintiff's situation: eg [98] (Lord Phillips).
  • 18
    • 84866367829 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Sienkiewicz (n 11) [154], [163] (Lord Rodger); [170] (Lady Hale); [190] (Lord Mance); [205] (Lord Kerr).
  • 19
    • 84928447007 scopus 로고
    • Liability and Individualized Evidence
    • Eg JJ Thomson, 'Liability and Individualized Evidence' (1986) 49 Lawand Contemporary Problems 199
    • (1986) Lawand Contemporary Problems , vol.49
    • Thomson, J.1
  • 20
    • 26444532558 scopus 로고
    • The Morality of Statistical Proof and the Risk of Mistaken Liability
    • D TWasserman, 'The Morality of Statistical Proof and the Risk of Mistaken Liability' (1991) 13 Cardozo Law Review 935
    • (1991) Cardozo Law Review , vol.13 , pp. 935
    • Twasserman, T.W.D.1
  • 21
    • 84866367830 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Statistical Evidence and Individual Litigants: A Reconsideration of Wasserman's Argument from Autonomy
    • Amit Pundik, 'Statistical Evidence and Individual Litigants: A Reconsideration of Wasserman's Argument from Autonomy' (2008) International Journal of Evidence and Proof 303.
    • (2008) International Journal of Evidence and Proof , pp. 303
    • Pundik, A.1
  • 22
    • 84866358881 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Above (n 11) [163] (emphasis added).
  • 23
    • 84866367828 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Above (n 11) [95] (Lord Phillips); [171] (Lady Hale); [217] (Lord Dyson); drawing on earlier discussions in Herskovits v Group Health Cooperative of Puget Sound 664 P 2d 474 491 (Brachtenbach J) and Hotson v East Berkshire Area Health Authority [1987] AC 750, 789 (Lord Mackay).1983
  • 24
    • 84866389848 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Above (n 11) [95]-[96] (Lord Phillips).
  • 25
    • 84866358879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Ultimately Sienkiewicz was decided in favour of the plaintiffs by the application of a principle from Fairchild v Glenhaven Funeral Services Ltd 1 AC 32 which, in mesothelioma cases, deems contribution to risk to be causal contribution, even where the risk is insufficient to establish causation on the balance of probabilities. The Sienkiewicz court, however, also expressed misgivings about this departure from orthodoxy: Above (n 11) [186] (Lord Brown); see also at [167] (Lady Hale).2003
  • 26
    • 84866358880 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Historically, the complainant's delay did call into question his or her credibility: Eg R v DD
    • Historically, the complainant's delay did call into question his or her credibility: Eg R v DD [2000] 2 275 [60
    • (2000) , vol.2 , Issue.275 , pp. 60
  • 27
  • 28
    • 77956947485 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The credibility issue can be clearly separated from the weight/forensic disadvantage issue: David Hamer, 'Trying Delays: Forensic Disadvantage in Child Sexual Assault Trials
    • The credibility issue can be clearly separated from the weight/forensic disadvantage issue: David Hamer, 'Trying Delays: Forensic Disadvantage in Child Sexual Assault Trials' [2010] Criminal Law Review 671-672.
    • (2010) Criminal Law Review , pp. 671-672
  • 29
    • 84866400903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Delayed Complaint, Lost Evidence and Fair Trial: Epistemic and Non-epistemic Concerns' in Paul Roberts and Jill Hunter (eds), Criminal Evidence and Human Rights, Ch. 9, p. 215 (Hart, Oxford
    • DavidHamer, 'Delayed Complaint, Lost Evidence and Fair Trial: Epistemic and Non-epistemic Concerns' in Paul Roberts and Jill Hunter (eds), Criminal Evidence and Human Rights, Ch. 9, p. 215 (Hart, Oxford, 2012
    • (2012)
    • Hamer, D.1
  • 30
    • 77956971099 scopus 로고
    • (1989) 168 CLR 79.
    • (1989) CLR , vol.168 , pp. 79
  • 31
    • 84920713528 scopus 로고
    • In many US jurisdictions: eg Brian L Porto, 'New Hampshire's New Statute of Limitations for Child Sexual Assault: Is It Constitutional and Is It Good Public Policy?
    • In many US jurisdictions: eg Brian L Porto, 'New Hampshire's New Statute of Limitations for Child Sexual Assault: Is It Constitutional and Is It Good Public Policy?' (1991) 26 New England Law Review 141.
    • (1991) New England Law Review , vol.26 , pp. 141
  • 32
    • 84866382101 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Ireland: PL v DPP
    • In Ireland: PL v DPP [2004] 4 IR 494.
    • (2004) IR , vol.4 , pp. 494
  • 33
    • 84866385123 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • EWCA Crim 3049; R v Littler.
    • Eg Joynson [2008] EWCA Crim 3049; R v Littler .[2001] NSWCCA 173
    • (2008) NSWCCA , pp. 173
    • Joynson1
  • 34
    • 84866372550 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Longman (1989) 168 CLR 79, 91 (Brennan, Dawson and Toohey JJ). For the recommended English direction see: Judicial Studies Board, Crown Court Bench Book: Directing the Jury (March 2010), 34.
  • 35
    • 84866374936 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • 54 NSWLR 241 [35] (Wood CJ at CL); see also at [118] (Sully J). The direction has recently been toned down by legislation (eg Evidence Act 1995 (NSW) s 165B(4)), but remains strongly pro-defendant.(2002)
  • 36
    • 0347825115 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Assessing Evidence
    • Richard Friedman 'Assessing Evidence' (1996) 94 Michigan Law Review 1810-1819
    • (1996) Michigan Law Review , vol.94 , pp. 1810-1819
    • Friedman, R.1
  • 37
    • 84866365612 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Stein (n 6) 120; see also at 97-100, 228; Ho (n 8) 278.
  • 38
    • 84866385591 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • unreported, EWCA Crim Div, 27 March
    • Turner (unreported, EWCA Crim Div, 27 March 2000) [19].
    • (2000) , pp. 19
    • Turner1
  • 39
    • 84866365611 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Crampton v R (2000) 206 CLR 161 [45] (Gaudron, Gummow and Callinan JJ); [140] (Hayne J).
  • 40
    • 84866365610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • BWT (n 29) [23] (Wood CJ at CL); see also R v Inston (2009) 103 SASR 265 [112] (Vanstone J).
  • 41
    • 84866372552 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Wood CJ at CL recognised that his views were unorthodox: BWT (n 29) [13]; see also Percival EWCA Crim Div, 97/6746/ X4, June 19, 1998. Other possible explanations such as the presumption of innocence and the defendant's right to present a defence are examined and found wanting in Hamer (n 20) and Hamer (n 21).
  • 42
    • 0003460554 scopus 로고
    • Decision Theory and the Factfinding Process
    • J Kaplan, 'Decision Theory and the Factfinding Process' (1968) 20 Stanford Law Review 1065
    • (1968) Stanford Law Review , vol.20 , pp. 1065
    • Kaplan, J.1
  • 43
    • 80052997088 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Probabilistic Standards of Proof, Their Complements, and the Errors That are Expected to Flow from Them
    • David Hamer 'Probabilistic Standards of Proof, Their Complements, and the Errors That are Expected to Flow from Them' (2004) 1 University of New England Law Journal 71
    • (2004) University of New England Law Journal , vol.1 , pp. 71
    • Hamer, D.1
  • 44
    • 84866358885 scopus 로고
    • University of Pennsylvania Law Review 1031, 1033, 1055. As I have previously noted (Hamer (n 38) 71 fn 1) the goal of factual accuracy has also been described as 'foremost' (Adrian S Zuckerman, Principles of Criminal Evidence (OUP, Oxford 1989) 7), 'fundamental' (Vern RWalker, 'Preponderance, Probability and Warranted Factfinding' (1996) 62 Brooklyn Law Review 1075, 1081), 'principal' (Jonathan Koehler and Daniel N Shaviro, 'Veridical Verdicts: Increasing Verdict Accuracy through the use of Overtly Probabilistic Evidence and Methods' (1990) 75 Cornell Law Review 247, 250), 'overriding' (William Twining, Theories of Evidence: BenthamandWigmore (1985) 117), 'necessary' (William Twining, 'Rationality and scepticism in judicial proof: some signposts' (1989) II International Journal for the Semiotics of Law 69, 72), 'primary' (ibid 70) and 'central' (Jack Weinstein, 'Some difficulties in devising rules for determining truth in judicial trials' (1966) 66 Columbia Law Review 223-243)
    • Marvin E Frankel, 'The Search for Truth: An Umpireal View' (1975) 123 University of Pennsylvania Law Review 1031, 1033, 1055. As I have previously noted (Hamer (n 38) 71 fn 1) the goal of factual accuracy has also been described as 'foremost' (Adrian S Zuckerman, Principles of Criminal Evidence (OUP, Oxford 1989) 7), 'fundamental' (Vern RWalker, 'Preponderance, Probability and Warranted Factfinding' (1996) 62 Brooklyn Law Review 1075, 1081), 'principal' (Jonathan Koehler and Daniel N Shaviro, 'Veridical Verdicts: Increasing Verdict Accuracy through the use of Overtly Probabilistic Evidence and Methods' (1990) 75 Cornell Law Review 247, 250), 'overriding' (William Twining, Theories of Evidence: BenthamandWigmore (1985) 117), 'necessary' (William Twining, 'Rationality and scepticism in judicial proof: some signposts' (1989) II International Journal for the Semiotics of Law 69, 72), 'primary' (ibid 70) and 'central' (Jack Weinstein, 'Some difficulties in devising rules for determining truth in judicial trials' (1966) 66 Columbia Law Review 223-243).
    • (1966) Columbia Law Review , vol.66
    • Frankel, M.E.1
  • 45
    • 84866374940 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Standards of proof may be set at levels of probability tominimise the expected error costs: Kaplan (n 38); Hamer (n 38). Of course, there may be a range of objections to this explicitly probabilistic approach to proof. I put these to one side in order to focus on the weight issue.
  • 46
    • 84866400902 scopus 로고
    • Good Thinking: The Foundations of Probability and Its Applications (University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis
    • Eg IJ Good, Good Thinking: The Foundations of Probability and Its Applications (University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1983) 178
    • (1983) , pp. 178
    • Good, I.1
  • 47
    • 34047273943 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Problematic Value of MathematicalModels of Evidence
    • Ronald J Allen and Michael S Pardo, 'The Problematic Value of MathematicalModels of Evidence' (2007) 36 Journal of Legal Studies 107-134.
    • (2007) Journal of Legal Studies , vol.36 , pp. 107-134
    • Allen, R.J.1    Pardo, M.S.2
  • 48
    • 84866367831 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Stein (n 6) 90.
  • 50
    • 84866389849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Allen and Pardo (42), 134.
    • , Issue.42 , pp. 134
    • Allen1    Pardo2
  • 51
    • 84866400905 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stein (6) 122-3
    • , Issue.6 , pp. 122-3
    • Stein1
  • 54
    • 84866358882 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • [2005] 2 AC 176 [14].
  • 55
    • 84866400907 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • (1990) 169 CLR 638, 642-3 (Deane, Gaudron and McHugh JJ).
  • 56
    • 84866358886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Above (n 53) [13]
  • 57
    • 19644397277 scopus 로고
    • Causation, Responsibility, Probability, Naked Statistics and Proof: Pruning the Bramble Bush by Clarifying the Concepts
    • See also Richard Wright, 'Causation, Responsibility, Probability, Naked Statistics and Proof: Pruning the Bramble Bush by Clarifying the Concepts', (1988) 73 Iowa Law Review 1001-1041
    • (1988) Iowa Law Review , vol.73 , pp. 1001-1041
    • Wright, R.1
  • 58
    • 0004052654 scopus 로고
    • The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science
    • Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass
    • J Dupre, The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass 1995) 184-5.
    • (1995) , pp. 184-5
    • Dupre, J.1
  • 59
    • 84866400909 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Above (n 53) [82].
  • 60
    • 84866400906 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The exception grows still larger considering the potential for humans to interact with, and introduce uncertainty into, what would otherwise be deterministic segments of the world: Dupre
    • The exception grows still larger considering the potential for humans to interact with, and introduce uncertainty into, what would otherwise be deterministic segments of the world: Dupre (n 59) 190.
    • , Issue.59 , pp. 190
  • 61
    • 84866389850 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stein (6) 48
    • , Issue.6 , pp. 48
    • Stein1
  • 62
    • 61149217230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Resiliency, Robustness and Rationality of Probability Judgments
    • James Logue, 'Resiliency, Robustness and Rationality of Probability Judgments' (1997) 11 International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 21.
    • (1997) International Studies in the Philosophy of Science , vol.11 , pp. 21
    • Logue, J.1
  • 63
    • 84866358884 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Ho (n 8) 278.
  • 64
    • 84866358883 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Stein (n 6) 88. See alsoNeil Cohen, 'Confidence in Probability: Burdens of Persuasion in aWorld of ImperfectKnowledge' (1985) 60 New York University L Rev 385. See also Barbara Davidson and Robert Pargetter, 'Weight' 49 Philosophical Studies 219, who define 'weight' in terms of the probability assessment's resistance to further change rather than by reference to the quantity of evidence that has been considered.1986
  • 65
    • 84866389851 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Cohen (n 64); Logue (n 62) 91; Stein (n 6) 48 fn 51.
  • 66
    • 84866389854 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • With replacement, unless the number is very large.
  • 67
    • 84866374931 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The 95% confidence interval is most commonly used. Briefly, this can be roughly calculated as p±2 The symbol represents the standard deviation, which can be estimated by?(pq/n), where n is the number of samples, p is the frequency of 'successes' (eg red balls) and q the frequency of 'failures' (eg non-red balls): W Mendenhall, Introduction to Probability and Statistics (Duxbury Press, Mass 1979) 239-40
  • 68
    • 84866374930 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • This formula is based upon themathematics of the normal function which can be taken as an approximation of the binomial probability distribution. The normal approximation is better for larger sample sizes, however, Mendenhall suggests that where the frequency is centred, as it is in the present case with p1/40.5, the normal approximation of a binomial distribution of only 10 samples is still 'reasonably good': at 203.
  • 69
    • 0346894804 scopus 로고
    • Apples and Oranges: Confidence Coefficients and the Burden of Persuasion
    • See also David Kaye, 'Apples and Oranges: Confidence Coefficients and the Burden of Persuasion' (1987) 73 Cornell Law Review 54
    • (1987) Cornell Law Review , vol.73 , pp. 54
    • Kaye, D.1
  • 70
    • 84866365608 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • n 10
    • Hamer (n 10) 518-20.
    • Hamer1
  • 71
    • 0003466767 scopus 로고
    • An Introduction to the Philosophy of Induction and Probability
    • Clarendon Press, Oxford
    • See also LJ Cohen, An Introduction to the Philosophy of Induction and Probability (Clarendon Press, Oxford 1989) 99-108.
    • (1989) , pp. 99-108
    • Cohen, L.1
  • 72
    • 84866358891 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Good (n 41) 178; see also B Skyrms, Choice and Chance (Belmont: Wadsworth, 4th ed, 2000) 155.
  • 73
    • 84866385587 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The relationship between probabilistic certainty and the risk of error ismediated by the standard of proof. If the standard of proof is 50%, the relationship is direct-the apparent risk of error is the complement of the degree of certainty. With a higher standard of proof, the relationship is less straightforward. Eg, in a criminal case, a fact-finder's certainty may increase from50 to 90%while still not eliminating a reasonable doubt. Certainty has increased, but this has only brought an increase in the apparent risk of amistaken acquittal. But while the asymmetric standard of proof is a complicating factor, it remains true that, at the limits, the risk of error is reduced by increasing certainty. Note also that fresh evidence offers the expectation of making a decision with greater utility: see (n 73).
  • 74
    • 84866372544 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • At the end of Section 4, and see proof in Appendix A.
  • 75
    • 84866365606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Good's analysis (n 41) focused on the expected utility of a decision based on a probability assessment. Expected certainty behaves in essentially the same way as expected utility-both are V-shaped linear functions of probability. Certainty has the advantage of being a purely epistemic measure. '[W]eight.. is undoubtedly an epistemic concept, and attempts to account for it or measure it in terms of non-epistemic criteria must be suspect': James Logue, Projective Probability (OUP, Oxford 1995) 84.
  • 76
    • 84866365607 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • This model was implemented on an Excel spreadsheet with programming in Visual Basic. My thanks to Joshua Klose for the programming.
  • 77
    • 84866365609 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Because the numbers in the table were generated randomly, the ' and "marks do not signify whether the evidence is favourable or unfavourable to the conclusion, G.
  • 78
    • 84866374934 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Cell entries in the original table were randomly selected numbers between 0 and 100. Because each number has an equal chance of being selected, as the size of the table increases, the prior probability (the ratio of the sum of half the table divided by the sum of the whole table) tends towards 1/2 as table size increases. (This is related to the anti-resilience effect discussed in Section 10.) The cell entries in this notional frequency table were again randomly generated but, to generate a higher prior probability, the G entries were skewed up and the NG entries skewed down.
  • 79
    • 84866372548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • At least this is true on the probabilistic unit interval. The odds and log-odds measures are a different matter. There is insufficient space here to explore the implications of the different measures.
  • 80
    • 84866372547 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Above (nn 45-46).
  • 81
    • 84906882712 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Presumption of Innocence as a Human Right
    • In Roberts and Hunter, Ch 11,
    • Eg, Hock Lai Ho, 'The Presumption of Innocence as a Human Right', In Roberts and Hunter, Ch 11, p. 259 (201
    • , vol.201 , pp. 259
    • Ho, H.L.1
  • 82
    • 84866385590 scopus 로고
    • Significance should not be attached to the fact that the police have laid charges and the prosecution service has brought the matter to trial. Whatever incriminating evidence influenced them, if admissible, can be presented to the court in due course: Bell v Wolfish 441 US
    • Significance should not be attached to the fact that the police have laid charges and the prosecution service has brought the matter to trial. Whatever incriminating evidence influenced them, if admissible, can be presented to the court in due course: Bell v Wolfish 441 US 520 (1979), 533.
    • (1979) , vol.520 , pp. 533
  • 83
    • 84866372546 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Just as crime rates are relatively low in probabilistic terms. Eg among serious crimes, sexual assault has the one of the highest crime rates. The victimization rate for 2010 for Australia was 79.5 per 100 000 (as against 1 in 100 000 for murder): Australian Bureau of Statistics, 4510.0 Recorded Crime - Victims (Commonwealth of Australia, Canberra 2001) 9. This relatively high crime rate is less than 1/10 of 1%.
  • 84
    • 84866374935 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Above (nn 62-64).
  • 85
    • 84866400908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The standard deviation provides a measure of the variation of sample data around a mean. The probability calculation for the frequency table is not a simple calculation of amean, but instead involves the ratio of means. The probability-the sumof the first column divided by the sumof both columns-is equal to themean of the first column divided by two times the mean of both columns. The standard deviation of functions of means such as this, like the standard deviation of a simple mean, is inversely proportional to the square root of the sample size. See eg, US Commerce Department, NIST/SEMATECH e-Handbook of Statistical Methods
    • The standard deviation provides a measure of the variation of sample data around a mean. The probability calculation for the frequency table is not a simple calculation of amean, but instead involves the ratio of means. The probability-the sumof the first column divided by the sumof both columns-is equal to themean of the first column divided by two times the mean of both columns. The standard deviation of functions of means such as this, like the standard deviation of a simple mean, is inversely proportional to the square root of the sample size. See eg, US Commerce Department, NIST/SEMATECH e-Handbook of Statistical Methods, http://www.itl.nist.gov/div898/handbook


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.