메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 125, Issue 7, 2012, Pages 1640-1663

Introduction: Pragmatism and private law

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84861357418     PISSN: 0017811X     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Note
Times cited : (78)

References (152)
  • 1
    • 11244319559 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The New Private Law: An Introduction
    • note
    • This capsule definition is rough, in part because private law also governs the rights and duties of public entities insofar as they act in a private capacity-for example, as owners of property. As used here, the phrase "the New Private Law" refers to emerging perspectives on (or approaches to) private law, not to new developments in substantive law. It is shorthand for new thinking in private law. Cf. Julie A. Nice, The New Private Law: An Introduction, 73 Denv. U. L. Rev. 993, 993-95 (1996) (using the phrase to refer to the privatization of functions traditionally performed by governments, such as the provision of benefit payments or environmental protection).
    • (1996) Denv. U. L. Rev. , vol.73 , pp. 993-995
    • Nice, J.A.1
  • 2
    • 66849142353 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Law for States: International Law, Constitutional Law, Public Law
    • See Jack Goldsmith & Daryl Levinson, Law for States: International Law, Constitutional Law, Public Law, 122 Harv. L. Rev. 1791, 1795 (2009).
    • (2009) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.122
    • Goldsmith, J.1    Levinson, D.2
  • 3
    • 0040294741 scopus 로고
    • In the Shadow of the Legislature: The Common Law in the Age of the New Public Law
    • note
    • See Daniel A. Farber & Philip P. Frickey, In the Shadow of the Legislature: The Common Law in the Age of the New Public Law, 89 Mich. L. Rev. 875, 884-87 (1991) (reviewing-in a contribution to a symposium on "the new public law"-sources of skepticism about distinctions between private and public law).
    • (1991) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.89
    • Farber, D.A.1    Frickey, P.P.2
  • 4
    • 0036997292 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Remembering Gary-and Tort Theory
    • note
    • George P. Fletcher, Remembering Gary-and Tort Theory, 50 UCLA L. Rev. 279, 289 (2002) (internal quotation marks omitted) (invoking the "all law is public law" slogan and lamenting that, in the United States, it reflects the dominant academic view).
    • (2002) UCLA L. Rev. , vol.50
    • Fletcher, G.P.1
  • 5
    • 38349072833 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legal Realism as Theory of Law
    • note
    • Michael Steven Green, Legal Realism as Theory of Law, 46 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 1915, 1917 (2005) (emphasis omitted) (observing that the phrase "we are all realists now" is so familiar that it "has become a cliché to call it a 'cliché'" (quoting Laura Kalman, Legal Realism atYale, 1927-1960, at 229 (1986).
    • (2005) Wm. & Mary L. Rev. , vol.46
    • Green, M.S.1
  • 6
    • 0001417422 scopus 로고
    • The Path of the Law
    • O.W. Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457 (1897).
    • (1897) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.10 , pp. 457
    • Holmes, O.W.1
  • 7
    • 0040404476 scopus 로고
    • Some Realism About Realism-Responding to Dean Pound
    • Karl N. Llewellyn, Some Realism About Realism-Responding to Dean Pound, 44 Harv. L. Rev. 1222 (1931).
    • (1931) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.44 , pp. 1222
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 8
    • 0001272681 scopus 로고
    • Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication
    • Duncan Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, 89 Harv. L. Rev. 1685 (1976).
    • (1976) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.89 , pp. 1685
    • Kennedy, D.1
  • 9
    • 84861410311 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The origins of the phrase are uncertain. See John Ciardi, A Browser's Dictionary and Native's Guide to the Unknown American Language 41 (1980) (suggesting that it might derive from the use of concealed brass tacks to hold together upholstery, or from dry goods stores' use of brass tacks embedded in their counters to provide precise measures of fabric lengths).
  • 10
    • 84861367540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Brass-tacks pragmatism bears some resemblance to what William James once described as the "tough-minded" temperament. William James, Pragmatism: A New Name for SomeOld Ways of Thinking 12 (1907). On James's view, however, tough-minded thinking, along with its "tender-minded" counterpart, was unpragmatic-hence he offered pragmatism as a way of reconciling the two, at 32-33. Moreover, certain attributes that he assigned to toughminded thinking (for example, pessimism), at 12, are not ones that I attribute to brass-tacks pragmatism. Likewise, the alternative form of pragmatism mentioned here-"inclusive" pragmatism-does not partake of several of the qualities that James assigned to the tender-minded disposition.
  • 11
    • 0031503279 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Holmes's Path
    • See David J. Seipp, Holmes's Path, 77 B.U. L. Rev. 515, 530 (1997).
    • (1997) B.U. L. Rev. , vol.77
    • Seipp, D.J.1
  • 12
    • 0001417422 scopus 로고
    • The Path of the Law
    • O.W. Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457 (1897).
    • (1897) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.10 , pp. 457
    • Holmes, O.W.1
  • 13
    • 0001417422 scopus 로고
    • The Path of the Law
    • O.W. Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457 (1897).
    • (1897) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.10 , pp. 457
    • Holmes, O.W.1
  • 14
    • 0001417422 scopus 로고
    • The Path of the Law
    • O.W. Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457 (1897).
    • (1897) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.10 , pp. 457
    • Holmes, O.W.1
  • 15
    • 0001417422 scopus 로고
    • The Path of the Law
    • O.W. Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457 (1897).
    • (1897) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.10 , pp. 457
    • Holmes, O.W.1
  • 16
    • 0001417422 scopus 로고
    • The Path of the Law
    • O.W. Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457 (1897).
    • (1897) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.10 , pp. 457
    • Holmes, O.W.1
  • 17
    • 0001417422 scopus 로고
    • The Path of the Law
    • O.W. Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457 (1897).
    • (1897) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.10 , pp. 457
    • Holmes, O.W.1
  • 18
    • 0001417422 scopus 로고
    • The Path of the Law
    • O.W. Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457 (1897).
    • (1897) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.10 , pp. 457
    • Holmes, O.W.1
  • 19
    • 0001417422 scopus 로고
    • The Path of the Law
    • O.W. Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457 (1897).
    • (1897) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.10 , pp. 457
    • Holmes, O.W.1
  • 20
    • 0001417422 scopus 로고
    • The Path of the Law
    • O.W. Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457 (1897).
    • (1897) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.10 , pp. 457
    • Holmes, O.W.1
  • 21
    • 0001417422 scopus 로고
    • The Path of the Law
    • O.W. Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457 (1897).
    • (1897) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.10 , pp. 457
    • Holmes, O.W.1
  • 22
    • 0001417422 scopus 로고
    • The Path of the Law
    • O.W. Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457 (1897).
    • (1897) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.10 , pp. 457
    • Holmes, O.W.1
  • 23
    • 0040404476 scopus 로고
    • Some Realism About Realism-Responding to Dean Pound
    • Karl N. Llewellyn, Some Realism About Realism-Responding to Dean Pound, 44 Harv. L. Rev. 1222 (1931).
    • (1931) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.44 , pp. 1222
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 24
    • 84861350858 scopus 로고
    • Holmes
    • note
    • K.N. Llewellyn, Holmes, 35 Colum. L. Rev. 485, 487-89 (1935) (crediting Holmes with having pointed the way to a realistic understanding of law while also noting ways in which he partook of antirealism).
    • (1935) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.35
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 25
    • 0040404476 scopus 로고
    • Some Realism About Realism-Responding to Dean Pound
    • Karl N. Llewellyn, Some Realism About Realism-Responding to Dean Pound, 44 Harv. L. Rev. 1222 (1931).
    • (1931) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.44 , pp. 1222
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 26
    • 0040404476 scopus 로고
    • Some Realism About Realism-Responding to Dean Pound
    • Karl N. Llewellyn, Some Realism About Realism-Responding to Dean Pound, 44 Harv. L. Rev. 1222 (1931).
    • (1931) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.44 , pp. 1222
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 27
    • 0040404476 scopus 로고
    • Some Realism About Realism-Responding to Dean Pound
    • Karl N. Llewellyn, Some Realism About Realism-Responding to Dean Pound, 44 Harv. L. Rev. 1222 (1931).
    • (1931) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.44 , pp. 1222
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 28
    • 0001417422 scopus 로고
    • The Path of the Law
    • O.W. Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457 (1897).
    • (1897) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.10 , pp. 457
    • Holmes, O.W.1
  • 29
    • 0040404476 scopus 로고
    • Some Realism About Realism-Responding to Dean Pound
    • Karl N. Llewellyn, Some Realism About Realism-Responding to Dean Pound, 44 Harv. L. Rev. 1222 (1931).
    • (1931) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.44 , pp. 1222
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 30
    • 0001417422 scopus 로고
    • The Path of the Law
    • O.W. Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457 (1897).
    • (1897) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.10 , pp. 457
    • Holmes, O.W.1
  • 31
    • 0001272681 scopus 로고
    • Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication
    • Duncan Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, 89 Harv. L. Rev. 1685 (1976).
    • (1976) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.89 , pp. 1685
    • Kennedy, D.1
  • 32
    • 0001272681 scopus 로고
    • Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication
    • Duncan Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, 89 Harv. L. Rev. 1685 (1976).
    • (1976) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.89 , pp. 1685
    • Kennedy, D.1
  • 38
    • 0001272681 scopus 로고
    • Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication
    • Duncan Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, 89 Harv. L. Rev. 1685 (1976).
    • (1976) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.89 , pp. 1685
    • Kennedy, D.1
  • 39
    • 0001272681 scopus 로고
    • Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication
    • Duncan Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, 89 Harv. L. Rev. 1685 (1976).
    • (1976) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.89 , pp. 1685
    • Kennedy, D.1
  • 41
    • 0001272681 scopus 로고
    • Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication
    • Duncan Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, 89 Harv. L. Rev. 1685 (1976).
    • (1976) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.89 , pp. 1685
    • Kennedy, D.1
  • 42
    • 0001272681 scopus 로고
    • Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication
    • Duncan Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, 89 Harv. L. Rev. 1685 (1976).
    • (1976) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.89 , pp. 1685
    • Kennedy, D.1
  • 43
    • 0004106103 scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Ernest J. Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law 3 (1995) (emphasizing the longstanding suspicion of the idea of private law in American legal scholarship). I happily acknowledge that there are overlaps between, on the one hand, my diagnosis of the state of private law theory and my account of some of the tenets of the New Private Law and, on the other hand, Weinrib's critique of functionalist accounts of private law and his defense of an internal approach. Nonetheless, important differences remain. Most obviously-and most saliently for mainstream legal scholars in the United States-I am claiming for private law the mantle of pragmatism, rather than what Weinrib describes as "formalism, "
    • (1995) The Idea of Private Law , pp. 3
    • Weinrib, E.J.1
  • 44
    • 0004106103 scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Ernest J. Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law 3 (1995) (emphasizing the longstanding suspicion of the idea of private law in American legal scholarship). I happily acknowledge that there are overlaps between, on the one hand, my diagnosis of the state of private law theory and my account of some of the tenets of the New Private Law and, on the other hand, Weinrib's critique of functionalist accounts of private law and his defense of an internal approach. Nonetheless, important differences remain. Most obviously-and most saliently for mainstream legal scholars in the United States-I am claiming for private law the mantle of pragmatism, rather than what Weinrib describes as "formalism, "
    • (1995) The Idea of Private Law , pp. 3
    • Weinrib, E.J.1
  • 45
    • 0001417422 scopus 로고
    • The Path of the Law
    • O.W. Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457 (1897).
    • (1897) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.10 , pp. 457
    • Holmes, O.W.1
  • 46
    • 0001417422 scopus 로고
    • The Path of the Law
    • O.W. Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457 (1897).
    • (1897) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.10 , pp. 457
    • Holmes, O.W.1
  • 47
    • 0040404476 scopus 로고
    • Some Realism About Realism-Responding to Dean Pound
    • Karl N. Llewellyn, Some Realism About Realism-Responding to Dean Pound, 44 Harv. L. Rev. 1222 (1931).
    • (1931) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.44 , pp. 1222
    • Llewellyn, K.N.1
  • 48
    • 0348194818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Moral of MacPherson
    • note
    • See John C.P. Goldberg & Benjamin C. Zipursky, The Moral of MacPherson, 146 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1733, 1777-98 (1998). As this observation implies, the same brass-tacks disposition that has fueled skepticism toward private law might well distort modern understandings of public law. I defer to scholars of public law on the extent to which it has done so and on whether there might be need of a new public law.
    • (1998) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.146
    • Goldberg, J.C.P.1    Zipursky, B.C.2
  • 49
    • 0348194818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Moral of MacPherson
    • note
    • See John C.P. Goldberg & Benjamin C. Zipursky, The Moral of MacPherson, 146 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1733, 1777-98 (1998). As this observation implies, the same brass-tacks disposition that has fueled skepticism toward private law might well distort modern understandings of public law. I defer to scholars of public law on the extent to which it has done so and on whether there might be need of a new public law.
    • (1998) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.146
    • Goldberg, J.C.P.1    Zipursky, B.C.2
  • 50
    • 0001272681 scopus 로고
    • Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication
    • Duncan Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, 89 Harv. L. Rev. 1685 (1976).
    • (1976) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.89 , pp. 1685
    • Kennedy, D.1
  • 52
    • 0040294747 scopus 로고
    • Tort Law Public Law in Disguise II
    • note
    • Leon Green, Tort Law Public Law in Disguise II, 38 Tex. L. Rev. 257, 267 (1960) (arguing that appellate courts are relatively well situated to implement new policies through their decisions in tort cases).
    • (1960) Tex. L. Rev. , vol.38
    • Green, L.1
  • 53
    • 0004082608 scopus 로고
    • note
    • For Judge Posner, judges, by virtue of their relative political insulation, are well situated to pursue the primary (social) good of efficient resource allocation. See William M. Landes & Richard A. Posner, The Economic Structure of Tort Law 18-19 (1987).
    • (1987) The Economic Structure of Tort Law , pp. 18-19
    • Landes, W.M.1    Posner, R.A.2
  • 54
    • 0043011224 scopus 로고
    • note
    • For Judge Weinstein, judges can, and must, harness the power conferred by tort law to provide assistance to individuals whose needs the political branches have unjustly neglected. See Jack B. Weinstein, Individual Justice in Mass Tort Litigation 5 (1995).
    • (1995) Individual Justice in Mass Tort Litigation , pp. 5
    • Weinstein, J.B.1
  • 55
    • 0043011224 scopus 로고
    • note
    • For Judge Weinstein, judges can, and must, harness the power conferred by tort law to provide assistance to individuals whose needs the political branches have unjustly neglected. See Jack B. Weinstein, Individual Justice in Mass Tort Litigation 5 (1995).
    • (1995) Individual Justice in Mass Tort Litigation , pp. 5
    • Weinstein, J.B.1
  • 56
    • 0003666422 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Guido Calabresi, The Costs of Accidents 244-85 (1970) (arguing that negligence law is ill suited to minimize the costs of accidents).
    • (1970) The Costs of Accidents , pp. 244-285
    • Calabresi, G.1
  • 57
    • 0003666422 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Guido Calabresi, The Costs of Accidents 244-85 (1970) (arguing that negligence law is ill suited to minimize the costs of accidents).
    • (1970) The Costs of Accidents , pp. 244-285
    • Calabresi, G.1
  • 58
    • 0003666422 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Guido Calabresi, The Costs of Accidents 244-85 (1970) (arguing that negligence law is ill suited to minimize the costs of accidents).
    • (1970) The Costs of Accidents , pp. 244-285
    • Calabresi, G.1
  • 59
    • 0003666422 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Guido Calabresi, The Costs of Accidents 244-85 (1970) (arguing that negligence law is ill suited to minimize the costs of accidents).
    • (1970) The Costs of Accidents , pp. 244-285
    • Calabresi, G.1
  • 60
    • 0003666422 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Guido Calabresi, The Costs of Accidents 244-85 (1970) (arguing that negligence law is ill suited to minimize the costs of accidents).
    • (1970) The Costs of Accidents , pp. 244-285
    • Calabresi, G.1
  • 61
    • 0003666422 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Guido Calabresi, The Costs of Accidents 244-85 (1970) (arguing that negligence law is ill suited to minimize the costs of accidents).
    • (1970) The Costs of Accidents , pp. 244-285
    • Calabresi, G.1
  • 62
    • 0004106103 scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Ernest J. Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law 3 (1995) (emphasizing the longstanding suspicion of the idea of private law in American legal scholarship). I happily acknowledge that there are overlaps between, on the one hand, my diagnosis of the state of private law theory and my account of some of the tenets of the New Private Law and, on the other hand, Weinrib's critique of functionalist accounts of private law and his defense of an internal approach. Nonetheless, important differences remain. Most obviously-and most saliently for mainstream legal scholars in the United States-I am claiming for private law the mantle of pragmatism, rather than what Weinrib describes as "formalism, "
    • (1995) The Idea of Private Law , pp. 3
    • Weinrib, E.J.1
  • 63
    • 0348093327 scopus 로고
    • Reason and Fiat in Case Law
    • note
    • Lon L. Fuller, Reason and Fiat in Case Law, 59 Harv. L. Rev. 376, 392 (1946) (criticizing as deficient Holmes's conception of private law as merely "state fiat").
    • (1946) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.59
    • Fuller, L.L.1
  • 64
    • 79959313410 scopus 로고
    • Holmes' Positivism-An Addendum
    • note
    • Henry M. Hart, Jr., Holmes' Positivism-An Addendum, 64 Harv. L. Rev. 929, 932 (1951) (criticizing parts of Holmes's thought for its "behaviorism").
    • (1951) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.64
    • Hart Jr., H.M.1
  • 65
    • 0000580092 scopus 로고
    • Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals
    • note
    • H.L.A. Hart, Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals, 71 Harv. L. Rev. 593, 606-15 (1958) (defending legal positivism against realist-inspired skepticism).
    • (1958) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.71
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 66
    • 0348129429 scopus 로고
    • Book Review
    • note
    • Charles Fried, Book Review, 93 Harv. L. Rev. 1858, 1860, 1867 (1980) (reviewing P.S. Atiyah, The Rise and Fall of Freedom of Contract (1979) (defending a traditional concept of contract law against the skeptical critiques of Kennedy, Atiyah, and others).
    • (1980) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.93
    • Fried, C.1
  • 67
    • 33746957440 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Natural Law: The Classical Tradition
    • note
    • Some of these criticisms have carried intellectual baggage of a sort that members of the U.S. legal academy are understandably reluctant to take on. Natural law theory, for example, has long stood in opposition to brass-tacks pragmatism. And although it comes in many variants, natural law theory is usually tied to acceptance of a demanding set of claims about human nature and human flourishing. See, e.g., John Finnis, Natural Law: The Classical Tradition, in The OxfordHandbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law 1, 28-29 (Jules Coleman & Scott Shapiro eds., 2002). Likewise, rights-based views inspired by Kant and Locke have long been fertile sources of arguments against brass-tacks pragmatism, but they have also required embracing controversial foundational assumptions about the rights individuals have qua individuals.
    • (2002) The OxfordHandbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law
    • Finnis, J.1
  • 68
    • 0004106103 scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Ernest J. Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law 3 (1995) (emphasizing the longstanding suspicion of the idea of private law in American legal scholarship). I happily acknowledge that there are overlaps between, on the one hand, my diagnosis of the state of private law theory and my account of some of the tenets of the New Private Law and, on the other hand, Weinrib's critique of functionalist accounts of private law and his defense of an internal approach. Nonetheless, important differences remain. Most obviously-and most saliently for mainstream legal scholars in the United States-I am claiming for private law the mantle of pragmatism, rather than what Weinrib describes as "formalism, "
    • (1995) The Idea of Private Law , pp. 3
    • Weinrib, E.J.1
  • 69
    • 84861359147 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Of course, my impressionistic intellectual-historical romp concluded with an article published thirty-five years ago. I think it is fair to say that Kennedy's particular rendition of the bottom line in law has not gained widespread acceptance. Indeed, he later abandoned some of its (1984) (recanting "the whole idea of individualism and altruism"). I mean this last observation not as criticism, but as evidence against the supposition that legal thought "hit brass" in 1976. I likewise see little evidence that, in the ensuing years, a theory has emerged that is immune from being second-guessed on the same metric of hardheadedness that Kennedy invoked against Llewellyn, and that Llewellyn invoked against Holmes.
  • 70
    • 0003726851 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Contract law seems alive and well notwithstanding Gilmore's obituary. See Grant Gilmore, The Death of Contract 3 (1974). The deficiencies of efforts simply to reduce tort law to a system of efficient accident deterrence are profound.
    • (1974) The Death of Contract , pp. 3
    • Gilmore, G.1
  • 71
    • 78650383241 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Harry Potter and the Trouble with Tort Theory
    • note
    • See, e.g., Scott Hershovitz, Harry Potter and the Trouble with Tort Theory, 63 Stan. L. Rev. 67, 69-75 (2010) (arguing that accounts of tort as a scheme of efficient deterrence arbitrarily exclude consideration of a wide range of potential costs and benefits). In noting the deficiencies of this sort of effort at large-scale reductionism, I do not mean to denigrate the capacity of microeconomic analysis to illuminate private law. As noted below, one of the distinctive features of the New Private Law is its methodological catholicism.
    • (2010) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.63
    • Hershovitz, S.1
  • 74
    • 0004106103 scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Ernest J. Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law 3 (1995) (emphasizing the longstanding suspicion of the idea of private law in American legal scholarship). I happily acknowledge that there are overlaps between, on the one hand, my diagnosis of the state of private law theory and my account of some of the tenets of the New Private Law and, on the other hand, Weinrib's critique of functionalist accounts of private law and his defense of an internal approach. Nonetheless, important differences remain. Most obviously-and most saliently for mainstream legal scholars in the United States-I am claiming for private law the mantle of pragmatism, rather than what Weinrib describes as "formalism, "
    • (1995) The Idea of Private Law , pp. 3
    • Weinrib, E.J.1
  • 75
    • 0002953848 scopus 로고
    • Some Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning
    • See Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld, Some Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning, 23 Yale L.J. 16 (1913).
    • (1913) Yale L.J. , vol.23 , pp. 16
    • Hohfeld, W.N.1
  • 77
    • 70350756132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Obligations and Outcomes in the Law of Torts
    • note
    • John Gardner, Obligations and Outcomes in the Law of Torts, in Relating to Responsibility111, 134 (Peter Cane & John Gardner eds., 2001).
    • (2001) Relating to Responsibility
    • Gardner, J.1
  • 78
    • 70350756132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Obligations and Outcomes in the Law of Torts
    • note
    • John Gardner, Obligations and Outcomes in the Law of Torts, in Relating to Responsibility111, 134 (Peter Cane & John Gardner eds., 2001).
    • (2001) Relating to Responsibility
    • Gardner, J.1
  • 79
    • 0348194818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Moral of MacPherson
    • note
    • See John C.P. Goldberg & Benjamin C. Zipursky, The Moral of MacPherson, 146 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1733, 1777-98 (1998). As this observation implies, the same brass-tacks disposition that has fueled skepticism toward private law might well distort modern understandings of public law. I defer to scholars of public law on the extent to which it has done so and on whether there might be need of a new public law.
    • (1998) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.146
    • Goldberg, J.C.P.1    Zipursky, B.C.2
  • 82
    • 84861360023 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The idea that pragmatism in thinking about law (and morality) comes in a more inclusive, less hardheaded guise is hardly new.
  • 83
    • 0038751705 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For recent thoughtful articulations, see Jules L. Coleman, The Practice of Principle 6 (2001) (outlining a pragmatist approach to legal theory).
    • (2001) The Practice of Principle , pp. 6
    • Coleman, J.L.1
  • 84
    • 78651368981 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Don Herzog, Cunning 12 (2006) (identifying a pragmatist sensibility with an antireductionist approach to practical reason)
    • (2006) Cunning , pp. 12
    • Herzog, D.1
  • 85
    • 85009446942 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pragmatic Conceptualism
    • note
    • Benjamin C. Zipursky, Pragmatic Conceptualism, 6 Legal Theory 457, 474-78 (2000) (arguing that conceptual analysis can figure centrally in pragmatist legal analysis).
    • (2000) Legal Theory , vol.6
    • Zipursky, B.C.1
  • 86
    • 84861359140 scopus 로고
    • note
    • It thus carries with it the same deflationary spirit one finds in coherentist approaches to political theory and practical reason. See, e.g., Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice xiv (1983). See generally J.J.C. Smart & Bernard Williams, Utilitarianism: For andAgainst 77-150 (1973).
    • (1983) Spheres of Justice xiv
    • Walzer, M.1
  • 88
    • 84861409796 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The ensuing discussion is somewhat tort centric, which reflects both my limitations and the extent to which tort, even more so than contracts and property, has been the victim of private law skepticism.
  • 89
    • 0002953848 scopus 로고
    • Some Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning
    • See Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld, Some Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning, 23 Yale L.J. 16 (1913).
    • (1913) Yale L.J. , vol.23 , pp. 16
    • Hohfeld, W.N.1
  • 91
    • 84861409795 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In principle, this openness to criticism and revision includes an openness to the rejection of private law as a distinct category. Of course the upshot of this Introduction and this Symposium is that the reinvigoration of this category will help lawyers to better understand bodies of law such as contracts, property, and torts, and better understand the institutional environment in which they operate.
  • 92
    • 84861375683 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Duties, Liabilities, and Damages
    • Stephen A. Smith, Duties, Liabilities, and Damages, 125 Harv. L. Rev. 1727 (2012).
    • (2012) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.125 , pp. 1727
    • Smith, S.A.1
  • 93
    • 0142138821 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Civil Recourse, Not Corrective Justice
    • For related arguments rejecting the idea that civil liability as imposed in U.S. courts amounts to the recognition of a genuine duty of repair, see Benjamin C. Zipursky, Civil Recourse, Not Corrective Justice, 91 Geo. L.J. 695 (2003).
    • (2003) Geo. L.J. , vol.91 , pp. 695
    • Zipursky, B.C.1
  • 98
    • 84861355002 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • They did some of each. The loss of consortium action was retained, Dan B. Dobbs, TheLaw of Torts § 310, at 841-42 (2000), whereas the heart-balm torts have largely been eliminated, Id. § 442, at 1247.
    • (2000) TheLaw of Torts , pp. 841-842
    • Dobbs, D.B.1
  • 99
    • 84861355002 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • They did some of each. The loss of consortium action was retained, Dan B. Dobbs, TheLaw of Torts § 310, at 841-42 (2000), whereas the heart-balm torts have largely been eliminated, Id. § 442, at 1247.
    • (2000) TheLaw of Torts , pp. 841-842
    • Dobbs, D.B.1
  • 100
    • 84864749339 scopus 로고
    • note
    • See generally Tunkl v. Regents of the Univ. of Cal., 383 P.2d 441 (Cal. 1963) (articulating public policy limits on the enforceability of otherwise valid waivers of liability).
    • (1963) Tunkl v. Regents of the Univ. of Cal. , vol.383 , pp. 441
  • 101
    • 84861370985 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Property as the Law of Things
    • Henry E. Smith, Property as the Law of Things, 125 Harv. L. Rev. 1691 (2012).
    • (2012) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.125 , pp. 1691
    • Smith, H.E.1
  • 102
    • 84861370985 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Property as the Law of Things
    • Henry E. Smith, Property as the Law of Things, 125 Harv. L. Rev. 1691 (2012).
    • (2012) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.125 , pp. 1691
    • Smith, H.E.1
  • 103
    • 58149401035 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Community and Custom in Property
    • See generally, e.g., Henry E. Smith, Community and Custom in Property, 10 TheoreticalInquiries L. 5 (2009).
    • (2009) TheoreticalInquiries L. , vol.10 , pp. 5
    • Smith, H.E.1
  • 104
    • 34250678122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intellectual Property as Property: Delineating Entitlements in Information
    • Henry E. Smith, Intellectual Property as Property: Delineating Entitlements in Information, 116 Yale L.J. 1742 (2007).
    • (2007) Yale L.J. , vol.116 , pp. 1742
    • Smith, H.E.1
  • 105
    • 0142231834 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Language of Property: Form, Context, and Audience
    • Henry E. Smith, The Language of Property: Form, Context, and Audience, 55 Stan. L. Rev. 1105 (2003).
    • (2003) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.55 , pp. 1105
    • Smith, H.E.1
  • 108
    • 84861355006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The High Bench vs. the Ivory Tower
    • note
    • See, e.g., Richard Brust, The High Bench vs. the Ivory Tower, A.B.A. J., Feb. 1, 2012, http://www.abajournal.com/magazine/article/the_high_bench_vs._the_ivory_tower/(quoting and discussing the Chief Justice's remarks: "Pick up a copy of any law review that you see... and the first article is likely to be, you know, the influence of Immanuel Kant on evidentiary approaches in 18th century Bulgaria.... I'm sure [it] was of great interest to the academic that wrote it, but it isn't of much use to the bar" (alteration in original) (internal quotation marks omitted). Judge Edwards previously expressed similar sentiments in a published article. Harry T. Edwards, The Growing Disjunction Between Legal Education and the Legal Profession, 91 Mich. L. Rev. 34 (1992).
    • (2012) A.B.A. J.
    • Brust, R.1
  • 109
    • 84861359143 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It is too broad because there is plenty of relevant legal scholarship being published. It is too narrow insofar as it suggests that immediate relevance to practice should be the exclusive criterion against which to measure the worth of legal scholarship.
  • 110
    • 0004264409 scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., The Common Law 108 (45th prtg. 1923) (suggesting that legal fault is defined in a way that permits liability to attach even to individuals who lack the capacity to consistently act with sufficient care to avoid being deemed legally at fault).
    • (1923) The Common Law , pp. 108
    • Holmes Jr., O.W.1
  • 112
    • 67649365633 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Norms and the Law
    • note
    • Richard H. McAdams & Eric B. Rasmusen, Norms and the Law, in 2 Handbook of Law and Economics 1573 (A. Mitchell Polinsky & Steven Shavell eds., 2007). The sketch of law's interaction with social norms offered in this Introduction is artificially unilateral in focusing on ways in which private law's rules track social norms. A fuller account would need to consider the reciprocal impact of law on social norms.
    • (2007) Handbook of Law and Economics , vol.2 , pp. 1573
    • McAdams, R.H.1    Rasmusen, E.B.2
  • 113
    • 84861375683 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Duties, Liabilities, and Damages
    • Stephen A. Smith, Duties, Liabilities, and Damages, 125 Harv. L. Rev. 1727 (2012).
    • (2012) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.125 , pp. 1727
    • Smith, S.A.1
  • 114
    • 84861355005 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Of course, civil jury trials are a rarity relative to the number of civil complaints filed.
  • 115
    • 84861355010 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See E. Allan Farnsworth, Contracts § 7.14, at 476-79 (4th ed. 2004) (discussing circumstances in which questions of contract interpretation are left to the court or to jurors).
  • 116
    • 84861355008 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Restatement (Second) of Torts § 285(d) (1965).
  • 117
    • 84861386261 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pain and Suffering and Beyond: Some Thoughts on Recovery for Intangible Loss
    • note
    • See, e.g., Robert L. Rabin, Pain and Suffering and Beyond: Some Thoughts on Recovery for Intangible Loss, 55 DePaul L. Rev. 359, 373 (2006) (noting jurors' "relatively unlimited discretion" to determine reasonable compensation for any given tort victim's intangible losses).
    • (2006) DePaul L. Rev. , vol.55
    • Rabin, R.L.1
  • 121
    • 78649662552 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sleight of Hand
    • note
    • See Benjamin C. Zipursky, Sleight of Hand, 48 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 1999, 2033-40 (2007) (outlining a competency-based conception of ordinary prudence).
    • (2007) Wm. & Mary L. Rev. , vol.48
    • Zipursky, B.C.1
  • 123
    • 84861355011 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Charles Fried, Contract as Promise 85-91 (1981) (citing approvingly courts' application of the doctrine of good faith to avoid rewarding opportunistic behavior).
  • 124
    • 84859551033 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Neglected Defense of Undue Hardship (and the Doctrinal Train Wreck in Boomer v. Atlantic Cement)
    • note
    • See Restatement (Second) of Torts § 164. The law does, however, ameliorate some of the potential harshness of such torts through its standards for issuing injunctions. See Douglas Laycock, The Neglected Defense of Undue Hardship (and the Doctrinal Train Wreck in Boomer v. Atlantic Cement), J. Tort L., Dec. 2011, art. 3 (reviewing decisions declining to issue injunctions that inflict undue hardship on the defendant).
    • (2011) J. Tort L., Dec.
    • Laycock, D.1
  • 125
    • 84861409798 scopus 로고
    • note
    • See, e.g., Empro Mfg. Co. v. Ball-Co Mfg., Inc., 870 F.2d 423, 424-26 (7th Cir. 1989) (rejecting a prospective buyer's request for a temporary restraining order against a seller that would have rendered a letter of intent an enforceable contract in light of the parties' purported intent to be bound).
    • (1989) Empro Mfg. Co. v. Ball-Co Mfg., Inc. , vol.870
  • 126
    • 84861392647 scopus 로고
    • note
    • See, e.g., Shelley v. Kraemer, 334 U.S. 1, 20-21 (1948) (deeming judicial enforcement of racially restrictive covenants to violate principles of equal protection and thus denying to state and federal courts the power to enforce such covenants).
    • (1948) Shelley v. Kraemer , vol.334
  • 127
    • 84861375683 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Duties, Liabilities, and Damages
    • Stephen A. Smith, Duties, Liabilities, and Damages, 125 Harv. L. Rev. 1727 (2012).
    • (2012) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.125 , pp. 1727
    • Smith, S.A.1
  • 128
    • 84861407349 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Palsgraf, Punitive Damages, and Preemption
    • Benjamin C. Zipursky, Palsgraf, Punitive Damages, and Preemption, 125 Harv. L. Rev. 1757 (2012).
    • (2012) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.125 , pp. 1757
    • Zipursky, B.C.1
  • 129
    • 84861407349 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Palsgraf, Punitive Damages, and Preemption
    • Benjamin C. Zipursky, Palsgraf, Punitive Damages, and Preemption, 125 Harv. L. Rev. 1757 (2012).
    • (2012) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.125 , pp. 1757
    • Zipursky, B.C.1
  • 130
    • 84861407349 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Palsgraf, Punitive Damages, and Preemption
    • Benjamin C. Zipursky, Palsgraf, Punitive Damages, and Preemption, 125 Harv. L. Rev. 1757 (2012).
    • (2012) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.125 , pp. 1757
    • Zipursky, B.C.1
  • 131
    • 79952159315 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See, e.g., BMW of N. Am., Inc. v. Gore, 517 U.S. 559, 572 n.17 (1996).
    • (1996) BMW of N. Am., Inc. v. Gore , vol.517 , Issue.17
  • 133
    • 0348194818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Moral of MacPherson
    • note
    • See John C.P. Goldberg & Benjamin C. Zipursky, The Moral of MacPherson, 146 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1733, 1777-98 (1998). As this observation implies, the same brass-tacks disposition that has fueled skepticism toward private law might well distort modern understandings of public law. I defer to scholars of public law on the extent to which it has done so and on whether there might be need of a new public law.
    • (1998) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.146
    • Goldberg, J.C.P.1    Zipursky, B.C.2
  • 134
    • 0013541976 scopus 로고
    • Judicial Review of Manufacturers' Conscious Design Choices: The Limits of Adjudication
    • note
    • See James A. Henderson, Jr., Judicial Review of Manufacturers' Conscious Design Choices: The Limits of Adjudication, 73 Colum. L. Rev. 1531, 1537-38 (1973) (discussing how doctrine reflects judicial concerns for justiciability).
    • (1973) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.73
    • Henderson Jr., J.A.1
  • 135
    • 84861360031 scopus 로고
    • note
    • See, e.g., Riss v. City of New York, 240 N.E.2d 860, 860-61 (N.Y. 1968). The court in Riss cited deference to departmental decisionmaking as a ground for exempting a police department from liability for negligence in failing to take steps to protect the victim of a third party's attack, even though the victim had presented credible evidence to the police of being at risk of imminent attack by the eventual attacker.
    • (1968) Riss v. City of New York , vol.240 , pp. 860-861
  • 136
    • 84861360031 scopus 로고
    • note
    • See, e.g., Riss v. City of New York, 240 N.E.2d 860, 860-61 (N.Y. 1968). The court in Riss cited deference to departmental decisionmaking as a ground for exempting a police department from liability for negligence in failing to take steps to protect the victim of a third party's attack, even though the victim had presented credible evidence to the police of being at risk of imminent attack by the eventual attacker.
    • (1968) Riss v. City of New York , vol.240 , pp. 860-861
  • 137
    • 84861409800 scopus 로고
    • note
    • See, e.g., Strauss v. Belle Realty Co., 482 N.E.2d 34, 36 (N.Y. 1985) (citing public policy considerations as reasons to impose a "privity" limitation on liability for injuries caused by a utility's carelessness).
    • (1985) Strauss v. Belle Realty Co. , vol.482
  • 139
    • 0040593231 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constitutional Cases
    • note
    • See, e.g., Ronald Dworkin, Constitutional Cases, in Taking Rights Seriously, at 131, 149 (arguing for a "fusion of constitutional law and moral theory" and suggesting that Rawls's work points the way forward for that endeavor).
    • Taking Rights Seriously
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 140
    • 0006500960 scopus 로고
    • The Supreme Court, 1968 Term-Foreword: On Protecting the Poor Through the Fourteenth Amendment
    • note
    • Frank I. Michelman, The Supreme Court, 1968 Term-Foreword: On Protecting the Poor Through the Fourteenth Amendment, 83 Harv. L. Rev. 7, 14-15 (1969) (invoking Rawls's concept of justice as fairness in support of judicial recognition of a constitutional right to governmental assistance to protect against deprivations associated with poverty).
    • (1969) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.83
    • Michelman, F.I.1
  • 141
    • 84936068266 scopus 로고
    • note
    • See, e.g., Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire 301-09 (1986) (identifying a moral foundation for a cost-benefit conception of negligence and nuisance in the distributive-justice principle of equality of resources).
    • (1986) Law's Empire , pp. 301-309
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 142
    • 84903230387 scopus 로고
    • Lochner's Legacy
    • note
    • Cass R. Sunstein, Lochner's Legacy, 87 Colum. L. Rev. 873, 875 (1987) (arguing for the inversion of a claimed historical tendency among courts to treat common law distributions of entitlements as setting a neutral baseline against which to measure the constitutionality of legislation).
    • (1987) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.87
    • Sunstein, C.R.1
  • 143
    • 84861355003 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • To be clear, I am not arguing that private law norms or principles should have lexical priority over public law norms or principles. As between them, there is an accommodation to be worked out that will at times be effortless and at other times be difficult.
  • 144
    • 84861366541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Obligatory Structure of Copyright Law: Unbundling the Wrong of Copying
    • note
    • Shyamkrishna Balganesh, The Obligatory Structure of Copyright Law: Unbundling the Wrong of Copying, 125 Harv. L. Rev. 1664 (2012). Tort law also attends to basic social virtues that do not reduce down to questions of distributive justice. One of its main points is to identify, articulate, and reinforce certain responsibilities that we owe to one another, responsibilities that are sensitive to distinct social roles and relationships and to the myriad ways in which persons interact with one another. In doing so, it helps achieve various goods, including the good of holding people accountable to one another.
    • (2012) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.125 , pp. 1664
    • Balganesh, S.1
  • 145
    • 33750196544 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Accidents of the Great Society
    • See John C.P. Goldberg & Benjamin C. Zipursky, Accidents of the Great Society, 64 Md. L. Rev. 364, 388-92, 404-07 (2005).
    • (2005) Md. L. Rev. , vol.64
    • Goldberg, J.C.P.1    Zipursky, B.C.2
  • 146
    • 76849108842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Equal Accountability Through Tort Law
    • Jason M. Solomon, Equal Accountability Through Tort Law, 103 Nw. U. L. Rev. 1765, 1794-97 (2009).
    • (2009) Nw. U. L. Rev. , vol.103
    • Solomon, J.M.1
  • 147
    • 85009446942 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pragmatic Conceptualism
    • note
    • Benjamin C. Zipursky, Pragmatic Conceptualism, 6 Legal Theory 457, 474-78 (2000) (arguing that conceptual analysis can figure centrally in pragmatist legal analysis).
    • (2000) Legal Theory , vol.6
    • Zipursky, B.C.1
  • 148
    • 84861616009 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See, e.g., Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell, Fairness Versus Welfare 3 (2002) (positing a fundamental conflict between welfarist and fairness-based approaches to legal analysis, and arguing for the superiority of the former).
    • (2002) Fairness Versus Welfare , pp. 3
    • Kaplow, L.1    Shavell, S.2
  • 150
    • 84861366541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Obligatory Structure of Copyright Law: Unbundling the Wrong of Copying
    • note
    • Shyamkrishna Balganesh, The Obligatory Structure of Copyright Law: Unbundling the Wrong of Copying, 125 Harv. L. Rev. 1664 (2012). Tort law also attends to basic social virtues that do not reduce down to questions of distributive justice. One of its main points is to identify, articulate, and reinforce certain responsibilities that we owe to one another, responsibilities that are sensitive to distinct social roles and relationships and to the myriad ways in which persons interact with one another. In doing so, it helps achieve various goods, including the good of holding people accountable to one another.
    • (2012) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.125 , pp. 1664
    • Balganesh, S.1
  • 151
    • 84861366541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Obligatory Structure of Copyright Law: Unbundling the Wrong of Copying
    • note
    • Shyamkrishna Balganesh, The Obligatory Structure of Copyright Law: Unbundling the Wrong of Copying, 125 Harv. L. Rev. 1664 (2012). Tort law also attends to basic social virtues that do not reduce down to questions of distributive justice. One of its main points is to identify, articulate, and reinforce certain responsibilities that we owe to one another, responsibilities that are sensitive to distinct social roles and relationships and to the myriad ways in which persons interact with one another. In doing so, it helps achieve various goods, including the good of holding people accountable to one another.
    • (2012) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.125 , pp. 1664
    • Balganesh, S.1
  • 152
    • 84861375683 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Duties, Liabilities, and Damages
    • Stephen A. Smith, Duties, Liabilities, and Damages, 125 Harv. L. Rev. 1727 (2012).
    • (2012) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.125 , pp. 1727
    • Smith, S.A.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.