-
1
-
-
84861383787
-
-
note
-
Montreal, Que., By-Law RCG 10-016 §§ 7, 14 (Aug. 26, 2010).
-
-
-
-
4
-
-
0347343263
-
-
note
-
As I explain later, similar language is used with, and similar consequences are See Dan B. Dobbs, Law of Remedies 12 (2d ed. 1993). Second, unlike Oman I argue that an important objection to the idea of an ordinary duty to pay damages is that wrongdoers cannot reasonably be expected to know how much they should pay by way of damages or, in some cases, whether they ought to pay damages at all.
-
(1993)
Law of Remedies
, pp. 12
-
-
Dobbs, D.B.1
-
5
-
-
0347343263
-
-
note
-
As I explain later, similar language is used with, and similar consequences are See Dan B. Dobbs, Law of Remedies 12 (2d ed. 1993). Second, unlike Oman I argue that an important objection to the idea of an ordinary duty to pay damages is that wrongdoers cannot reasonably be expected to know how much they should pay by way of damages or, in some cases, whether they ought to pay damages at all.
-
(1993)
Law of Remedies
, pp. 12
-
-
Dobbs, D.B.1
-
6
-
-
0347343263
-
-
note
-
As I explain later, similar language is used with, and similar consequences are See Dan B. Dobbs, Law of Remedies 12 (2d ed. 1993). Second, unlike Oman I argue that an important objection to the idea of an ordinary duty to pay damages is that wrongdoers cannot reasonably be expected to know how much they should pay by way of damages or, in some cases, whether they ought to pay damages at all.
-
(1993)
Law of Remedies
, pp. 12
-
-
Dobbs, D.B.1
-
9
-
-
84861389852
-
-
note
-
As understood here, a judicial "award" is the operational part of a legal decision. Common examples include orders or judgments that require the performance of a contract, the payment of money, or the cessation of an activity.
-
-
-
-
10
-
-
84937334675
-
Rights, Wrongs, and Remedies
-
See, e.g., Peter Birks, Rights, Wrongs, and Remedies, 20 O.J.L.S. 1, 28 (2000).
-
(2000)
O.J.L.S.
, vol.20
-
-
Birks, P.1
-
15
-
-
74849096289
-
A Consent Theory of Contract
-
Randy E. Barnett, A Consent Theory of Contract, 86 Colum. L. Rev. 269 (1986).
-
(1986)
Colum. L. Rev.
, vol.86
, pp. 269
-
-
Barnett, R.E.1
-
16
-
-
66749122160
-
The Unity of Contract Law
-
note
-
Peter Benson, The Unity of Contract Law, in TheTheory of Contract Law 118 (Peter Benson ed., 2001).
-
(2001)
TheTheory of Contract Law
, pp. 118
-
-
Benson, P.1
-
17
-
-
21144478652
-
The Moral Foundations of Tort Law
-
Stephen R. Perry, The Moral Foundations of Tort Law, 77 Iowa L. Rev. 449 (1992). Rights-based theories are sometimes described as corrective justice theories.
-
(1992)
Iowa L. Rev.
, vol.77
, pp. 449
-
-
Perry, S.R.1
-
18
-
-
47049123771
-
Philosophy of Private Law
-
note
-
For an overview, see Benjamin C. Zipursky, Philosophy of Private Law, in The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law 623, 627-31 (Jules Coleman & Scott Shapiro eds., 2002). The label is problematic because the concept of corrective justice is understood in radically different ways.
-
(2002)
The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law
-
-
Zipursky, B.C.1
-
20
-
-
0004106103
-
-
note
-
See Ernest J. Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law 3 (1995) (emphasizing the longstanding suspicion of the idea of private law in American legal scholarship). I happily acknowledge that there are overlaps between, on the one hand, my diagnosis of the state of private law theory and my account of some of the tenets of the New Private Law and, on the other hand, Weinrib's critique of functionalist accounts of private law and his defense of an internal approach. Nonetheless, important differences remain. Most obviously-and most saliently for mainstream legal scholars in the United States-I am claiming for private law the mantle of pragmatism, rather than what Weinrib describes as "formalism, "
-
(1995)
The Idea of Private Law
, pp. 3
-
-
Weinrib, E.J.1
-
21
-
-
80052483641
-
Two Conceptions of Remedies
-
note
-
Ernest J. Weinrib, Two Conceptions of Remedies, in JustifyingPrivate Law Remedies 3, 31-32 (Charles E.F. Rickett ed., 2008) [hereinafter Weinrib, Two Conceptions]. The just-mentioned theories are, however, alike in that they all explain damage awards on the basis that victims have rights to the payment of damages.
-
(2008)
JustifyingPrivate Law Remedies
-
-
Weinrib, E.J.1
-
22
-
-
84861381084
-
-
note
-
Primary legal duties arise from "not-wrongs, " such as entering an agreement, being born, or attaining the age of majority. Secondary duties, by contrast, arise from legal wrongs, such as a breach of contract or a tort. Writers who use this terminology typically suppose that the main example of a secondary duty is a duty to pay damages. See, e.g., Rafal Zakrzewski, RemediesReclassified 165-77 (2005).
-
(2005)
RemediesReclassified
, pp. 165-177
-
-
Zakrzewski, R.1
-
23
-
-
0004106103
-
-
note
-
In The Idea of Private Law, Weinrib describes the law of damages as imposing liabilities.
-
The Idea of Private Law
-
-
-
26
-
-
78649903198
-
As if It Had Never Happened
-
See, e.g., Arthur Ripstein, As if It Had Never Happened, 48 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 1957, 1979-82 (2007).
-
(2007)
Wm. & Mary L. Rev.
, vol.48
-
-
Ripstein, A.1
-
27
-
-
0004106103
-
-
note
-
See Ernest J. Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law 3 (1995) (emphasizing the longstanding suspicion of the idea of private law in American legal scholarship). I happily acknowledge that there are overlaps between, on the one hand, my diagnosis of the state of private law theory and my account of some of the tenets of the New Private Law and, on the other hand, Weinrib's critique of functionalist accounts of private law and his defense of an internal approach. Nonetheless, important differences remain. Most obviously-and most saliently for mainstream legal scholars in the United States-I am claiming for private law the mantle of pragmatism, rather than what Weinrib describes as "formalism, "
-
(1995)
The Idea of Private Law
, pp. 3
-
-
Weinrib, E.J.1
-
28
-
-
0004106103
-
-
note
-
See Ernest J. Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law 3 (1995) (emphasizing the longstanding suspicion of the idea of private law in American legal scholarship). I happily acknowledge that there are overlaps between, on the one hand, my diagnosis of the state of private law theory and my account of some of the tenets of the New Private Law and, on the other hand, Weinrib's critique of functionalist accounts of private law and his defense of an internal approach. Nonetheless, important differences remain. Most obviously-and most saliently for mainstream legal scholars in the United States-I am claiming for private law the mantle of pragmatism, rather than what Weinrib describes as "formalism, "
-
(1995)
The Idea of Private Law
, pp. 3
-
-
Weinrib, E.J.1
-
30
-
-
21144478652
-
The Moral Foundations of Tort Law
-
Stephen R. Perry, The Moral Foundations of Tort Law, 77 Iowa L. Rev. 449, 478-79 (1992).
-
(1992)
Iowa L. Rev.
, vol.77
-
-
Perry, S.R.1
-
31
-
-
21144478652
-
The Moral Foundations of Tort Law
-
Stephen R. Perry, The Moral Foundations of Tort Law, 77 Iowa L. Rev. 449, 478-79 (1992).
-
(1992)
Iowa L. Rev.
, vol.77
-
-
Perry, S.R.1
-
32
-
-
84861392675
-
-
note
-
I say "in principle" to allow for the possibility that the duty to pay damages is inchoate until fixed by the court. I explore this possibility in Part II.
-
-
-
-
34
-
-
0347343263
-
-
note
-
As I explain later, similar language is used with, and similar consequences are See Dan B. Dobbs, Law of Remedies 12 (2d ed. 1993). Second, unlike Oman I argue that an important objection to the idea of an ordinary duty to pay damages is that wrongdoers cannot reasonably be expected to know how much they should pay by way of damages or, in some cases, whether they ought to pay damages at all.
-
(1993)
Law of Remedies
, pp. 12
-
-
Dobbs, D.B.1
-
39
-
-
4544375290
-
-
note
-
Steven Shavell, Foundations of EconomicAnalysis of Law 9-32 (2004) [hereinafter Shavell, Foundations]. Utilitarian theories are often described as "economic" theories because contemporary writers who regard the law as a vehicle for promoting utility usually adopt economic tools and techniques in their arguments.
-
(2004)
Foundations of EconomicAnalysis of Law
, pp. 9-32
-
-
Shavell, S.1
-
40
-
-
17244370822
-
-
note
-
See, e.g., Thomas J. Miceli, The Economic Approach to Law 1 (2004) ("The economic approach to law assumes that rational individuals view legal sanctions (monetary damages, prison) as implicit prices for certain kinds of behavior, and that these prices can be set to guide these behaviors in a socially desirable direction. ").
-
(2004)
The Economic Approach to Law
, pp. 1
-
-
Miceli, T.J.1
-
41
-
-
84861389856
-
-
note
-
Richard A. Posner, The Economics ofJustice 75 (1981) ("The basic function of law in an economic or wealth-maximization perspective is to alter incentives. ").
-
(1981)
The Economics ofJustice
, vol.75
-
-
Posner, R.A.1
-
42
-
-
35448950482
-
Contract Remedies: General
-
note
-
Paul G. Mahoney, Contract Remedies: General, in 3 Encyclopedia of Law & Economics 117, 118 (Boudewijn Bouckaert & Gerrit De Geest eds., 2000) ("The economic function of contract remedies... is to alter the incentives facing the party who regrets entering into the contract.... ").
-
(2000)
Encyclopedia of Law & Economics
, vol.3
-
-
Mahoney, P.G.1
-
43
-
-
0001609162
-
Property Rules, Liability Rules, and Inalienability: One View of the Cathedral
-
Guido Calabresi & A. Douglas Melamed, Property Rules, Liability Rules, and Inalienability: One View of the Cathedral, 85 Harv. L. Rev. 1089, 1092 (1972).
-
(1972)
Harv. L. Rev.
, vol.85
-
-
Calabresi, G.1
Melamed, A.D.2
-
44
-
-
80052616759
-
The Normativity of Private Law
-
I explain the argument that follows in more detail in Stephen A. Smith, The Normativity of Private Law, 31 O.J.L.S. 215 (2011).
-
(2011)
O.J.L.S.
, vol.31
, pp. 215
-
-
Smith, S.A.1
-
45
-
-
84861389858
-
-
note
-
Authorities that are not viewed in this way may try to encourage compliance by attaching sanctions to their rules, but in this case the rules qua rules are superfluous: the same result could be achieved by making it clear that citizens who engage in a given behavior will be penalized.
-
-
-
-
46
-
-
0001417422
-
The Path of the Law
-
O.W. Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457, 459 (1897).
-
(1897)
Harv. L. Rev.
, vol.10
-
-
Holmes, O.W.1
-
47
-
-
58149384112
-
Social Norms and the Law: Why Peoples Obey the Law
-
See Amir N. Licht, Social Norms and the Law: Why Peoples Obey the Law, 4 Rev. L. & Econ. 715, 715-17 (2008).
-
(2008)
Rev. L. & Econ.
, vol.4
-
-
Licht, A.N.1
-
49
-
-
67649365633
-
Norms and the Law
-
note
-
For an overview, see Richard H. McAdams & Eric B. Rasmusen, Norms and the Law, in 2 Handbook of Law & Economics 1573, 1573-1610 (A. Mitchell Polinsky & Steven Shavell eds., 2007).
-
(2007)
Handbook of Law & Economics
, vol.2
-
-
McAdams, R.H.1
Rasmusen, E.B.2
-
50
-
-
0347053819
-
Do Good Laws Make Good Citizens? An Economic Analysis of Internalized Norms
-
See, e.g., Robert Cooter, Do Good Laws Make Good Citizens? An Economic Analysis of Internalized Norms, 86 Va. L. Rev. 1577, 1598-1600 (2000).
-
(2000)
Va. L. Rev.
, vol.86
-
-
Cooter, R.1
-
51
-
-
33846577294
-
The Intrinsic Value of Obeying a Law: Economic Analysis of the Internal Viewpoint
-
Robert Cooter, The Intrinsic Value of Obeying a Law: Economic Analysis of the Internal Viewpoint, 75 Fordham L. Rev. 1275, 1276-77 (2006).
-
(2006)
Fordham L. Rev.
, vol.75
-
-
Cooter, R.1
-
52
-
-
0037678329
-
Enforcing Promises: An Examination of the Basis of Contract
-
See Charles J. Goetz & Robert E. Scott, Enforcing Promises: An Examination of the Basis of Contract, 89 Yale L.J. 1261, 1263-64, 1279-80 (1980).
-
(1980)
Yale L.J.
, vol.89
-
-
Goetz, C.J.1
Scott, R.E.2
-
53
-
-
0042895545
-
The Mitigation Principle: Toward a General Theory of Contractual Obligation
-
See Charles J. Goetz & Robert E. Scott, The Mitigation Principle: Toward a General Theory of Contractual Obligation, 69 Va. L. Rev. 967, 971 (1983) and accompanying text.
-
(1983)
Va. L. Rev.
, vol.69
-
-
Goetz, C.J.1
Scott, R.E.2
-
56
-
-
4544375290
-
-
note
-
Steven Shavell, Foundations of EconomicAnalysis of Law 9-32 (2004) [hereinafter Shavell, Foundations]. Utilitarian theories are often described as "economic" theories because contemporary writers who regard the law as a vehicle for promoting utility usually adopt economic tools and techniques in their arguments.
-
(2004)
Foundations of EconomicAnalysis of Law
, pp. 9-32
-
-
Shavell, S.1
-
57
-
-
0003774434
-
-
note
-
As I discuss in more detail below, see Richard A. Posner, Economic Analysis of Law 29-34 (8th ed. 2011) pp. 1738-40, some writers have explained contract damages on the basis that they give contracting parties incentives to breach whenever the cost of performance is greater than the value of performance-the so-called "efficient breach" theory.
-
(2011)
Economic Analysis of Law
, pp. 1738-1740
-
-
Posner, R.A.1
-
59
-
-
0347539474
-
Breach of Contract, Damage Measures, and Economic Efficiency
-
Robert L. Birmingham, Breach of Contract, Damage Measures, and Economic Efficiency, 24 Rutgers L. Rev. 273, 292 (1970).
-
(1970)
Rutgers L. Rev.
, vol.24
-
-
Birmingham, R.L.1
-
60
-
-
78649909352
-
What Is Tort Law For? Part 1: The Place of Corrective Justice
-
See John Gardner, What Is Tort Law For? Part 1: The Place of Corrective Justice, 30 Law& Phil. 1, (2011) pp. 1738-40.
-
(2011)
Law& Phil.
, vol.30
, pp. 1738-1740
-
-
Gardner, J.1
-
61
-
-
78649909352
-
What Is Tort Law For? Part 1: The Place of Corrective Justice
-
See John Gardner, What Is Tort Law For? Part 1: The Place of Corrective Justice, 30 Law& Phil. 1, 33-35 (2011).
-
(2011)
Law& Phil.
, vol.30
-
-
Gardner, J.1
-
62
-
-
84927012473
-
Personal Practical Conflicts
-
note
-
Professor John Gardner's explanation draws on Joseph Raz, Personal Practical Conflicts, in Practical Conflicts 172, 189-93 (Peter Baumann & Monika Betzler eds., 2004).
-
(2004)
Practical Conflicts
-
-
Raz, J.1
-
63
-
-
78649909352
-
What Is Tort Law For? Part 1: The Place of Corrective Justice
-
John Gardner, Obligations and Outcomes in the Law of Torts, in Relating to Responsibility111, 134 (Peter Cane & John Gardner eds., 2001).
-
(2011)
Law& Phil.
, vol.30
-
-
Gardner, J.1
-
64
-
-
78649909352
-
What Is Tort Law For? Part 1: The Place of Corrective Justice
-
John Gardner, Obligations and Outcomes in the Law of Torts, in Relating to Responsibility111, 134 (Peter Cane & John Gardner eds., 2001).
-
(2011)
Law& Phil.
, vol.30
-
-
Gardner, J.1
-
66
-
-
0347539474
-
Breach of Contract, Damage Measures, and Economic Efficiency
-
Robert L. Birmingham, Breach of Contract, Damage Measures, and Economic Efficiency, 24 Rutgers L. Rev. 273, 292 (1970).
-
(1970)
Rutgers L. Rev.
, vol.24
-
-
Birmingham, R.L.1
-
67
-
-
22544435816
-
Economic Analysis of Contract Law After Three Decades: Success or Failure?
-
See, e.g., Eric A. Posner, Economic Analysis of Contract Law After Three Decades: Success or Failure?, 112 Yale L.J. 829, 834-39 (2003).
-
(2003)
Yale L.J.
, vol.112
-
-
Posner, E.A.1
-
68
-
-
0040746598
-
The Case for Specific Performance
-
Alan Schwartz, The Case for Specific Performance, 89 Yale L.J. 271, 278-96 (1979).
-
(1979)
Yale L.J.
, vol.89
-
-
Schwartz, A.1
-
69
-
-
84861389854
-
-
note
-
This qualification is necessary because contractual duties cannot plausibly be described as disjunctive in cases in which courts are willing to order specific performance of those duties.
-
-
-
-
70
-
-
0001417422
-
The Path of the Law
-
O.W. Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457 (1897).
-
(1897)
Harv. L. Rev.
, vol.10
, pp. 457
-
-
Holmes, O.W.1
-
71
-
-
84861383790
-
-
note
-
For Holmes, to say there is a legal duty to pay a sum of money is not to say that legally the money should be paid; the duty may mean no more than that the law will force you to pay the money.
-
-
-
-
72
-
-
84855887848
-
The Myth of Efficient Breach: New Defenses of the Expectation Interest
-
See, e.g., Daniel Markovits & Alan Schwartz, The Myth of Efficient Breach: New Defenses of the Expectation Interest, 97 Va. L. Rev. 1939, 2006 (2011). The authors limit their argument to commercial parties.
-
(2011)
Va. L. Rev.
, vol.97
-
-
Markovits, D.1
Schwartz, A.2
-
73
-
-
84855887848
-
The Myth of Efficient Breach: New Defenses of the Expectation Interest
-
See, e.g., Daniel Markovits & Alan Schwartz, The Myth of Efficient Breach: New Defenses of the Expectation Interest, 97 Va. L. Rev. 1939, 2006 (2011). The authors limit their argument to commercial parties.
-
(2011)
Va. L. Rev.
, vol.97
-
-
Markovits, D.1
Schwartz, A.2
-
74
-
-
0042895545
-
The Mitigation Principle: Toward a General Theory of Contractual Obligation
-
note
-
For an argument describing the general utility of implying terms that the parties would have wanted, see Charles J. Goetz & Robert E. Scott, The Mitigation Principle: Toward a General Theory of Contractual Obligation, 69 Va. L. Rev. 967, 971 (1983), which notes that "[i]deally, the preformulated rules supplied by the state should mimic the agreements contracting parties would reach were they costlessly to bargain out each detail of the transaction, "
-
(1983)
Va. L. Rev.
, vol.69
-
-
Goetz, C.J.1
Scott, R.E.2
-
75
-
-
0002692296
-
Filling Gaps in Incomplete Contracts: An Economic Theory of Default Rules
-
This version of the disjunctive duty thesis is therefore similar to the idea, defended by some utilitarian writers, that the damages rules for breach of contract should be understood as default terms implied into all contracts. See, e.g., Ian Ayres & Robert Gertner, Filling Gaps in Incomplete Contracts: An Economic Theory of Default Rules, 99 Yale L.J. 87, 88, 101-04, 121-22 (1989).
-
(1989)
Yale L.J.
, vol.99
-
-
Ayres, I.1
Gertner, R.2
-
76
-
-
84930561365
-
Strategic Bargaining and the Economic Theory of Contract Default Rules
-
Jason Scott Johnston, Strategic Bargaining and the Economic Theory of Contract Default Rules, 100 Yale L.J. 615, 615-18 (1990).
-
(1990)
Yale L.J.
, vol.100
-
-
Johnston, J.S.1
-
77
-
-
84861379208
-
The Relationship Between Rights and Remedies in Private Law: A Comparison Between the Common and the Civil Law Tradition
-
note
-
I discuss the civil law position briefly Helge Dedek, The Relationship Between Rights and Remedies in Private Law: A Comparison Between the Common and the Civil Law Tradition, in Taking Remedies Seriously 63 (Robert J. Sharpe & Kent Roach eds., 2010) and accompanying text.
-
(2010)
Taking Remedies Seriously
, pp. 63
-
-
Dedek, H.1
-
78
-
-
69849102311
-
Institutions and Indirectness in Intellectual Property
-
Henry E. Smith, Institutions and Indirectness in Intellectual Property, 157 U. Pa. L. Rev. 2083, 2090-2103 (2009).
-
(2009)
U. Pa. L. Rev.
, vol.157
-
-
Smith, H.E.1
-
79
-
-
84861381084
-
-
note
-
Primary legal duties arise from "not-wrongs, " such as entering an agreement, being born, or attaining the age of majority. Secondary duties, by contrast, arise from legal wrongs, such as a breach of contract or a tort. Writers who use this terminology typically suppose that the main example of a secondary duty is a duty to pay damages. See, e.g., Rafal Zakrzewski, RemediesReclassified 165-77 (2005).
-
(2005)
RemediesReclassified
, pp. 165-177
-
-
Zakrzewski, R.1
-
80
-
-
84861378589
-
Definition and Division: A Meditation on Institutes 3.13
-
note
-
Peter Birks, Definition and Division: A Meditation on Institutes 3.13, in The Classification of Obligations 1, 24 (Peter Birks ed., 1997).
-
(1997)
The Classification of Obligations
-
-
Birks, P.1
-
81
-
-
69849102311
-
Institutions and Indirectness in Intellectual Property
-
Henry E. Smith, Institutions and Indirectness in Intellectual Property, 157 U. Pa. L. Rev. 2083, 2090-2103 (2009).
-
(2009)
U. Pa. L. Rev.
, vol.157
-
-
Smith, H.E.1
-
90
-
-
84861383792
-
-
note
-
This discretion is qualitatively different from the weak discretion that courts necessarily exercise whenever they apply general rules to specific facts. Courts openly acknowledge that the quantification of, for example, damages for pain and suffering involves a large subjective element. See, e.g., Wise v. Kaye, [1962] 1 Q.B. 638 at 669 (Eng.).
-
-
-
-
91
-
-
84861379208
-
The Relationship Between Rights and Remedies in Private Law: A Comparison Between the Common and the Civil Law Tradition
-
note
-
See Helge Dedek, The Relationship Between Rights and Remedies in Private Law: A Comparison Between the Common and the Civil Law Tradition, in Taking Remedies Seriously 63 (Robert J. Sharpe & Kent Roach eds., 2010).
-
(2010)
Taking Remedies Seriously
, pp. 63
-
-
Dedek, H.1
-
98
-
-
0347343263
-
-
note
-
As I explain later, similar language is used with, and similar consequences are See Dan B. Dobbs, Law of Remedies 12 (2d ed. 1993). Second, unlike Oman I argue that an important objection to the idea of an ordinary duty to pay damages is that wrongdoers cannot reasonably be expected to know how much they should pay by way of damages or, in some cases, whether they ought to pay damages at all.
-
(1993)
Law of Remedies
, pp. 12
-
-
Dobbs, D.B.1
-
99
-
-
0347343263
-
-
note
-
As I explain later, similar language is used with, and similar consequences are See Dan B. Dobbs, Law of Remedies 12 (2d ed. 1993). Second, unlike Oman I argue that an important objection to the idea of an ordinary duty to pay damages is that wrongdoers cannot reasonably be expected to know how much they should pay by way of damages or, in some cases, whether they ought to pay damages at all.
-
(1993)
Law of Remedies
, pp. 12
-
-
Dobbs, D.B.1
-
100
-
-
84861381082
-
-
note
-
This language is often explicit in civilian codes. See, e.g., Civil Code of Québec, S.Q. 1991, c. 64, art. 1458 (Can.) ("Every person has a duty to honour his contractual undertakings. ").
-
-
-
-
102
-
-
0043240610
-
Voluntary Obligations and Normative Powers II
-
note
-
Joseph Raz, Voluntary Obligations and Normative Powers II, 46 Proc. AristotelianSoc'y 79, 81 (1972) (emphasis added).
-
(1972)
Proc. AristotelianSoc'y
, vol.46
-
-
Raz, J.1
-
103
-
-
69849102311
-
Institutions and Indirectness in Intellectual Property
-
Henry E. Smith, Institutions and Indirectness in Intellectual Property, 157 U. Pa. L. Rev. 2083, 2090-2103 (2009).
-
(2009)
U. Pa. L. Rev.
, vol.157
-
-
Smith, H.E.1
-
104
-
-
84861389855
-
-
note
-
Thus, a statute that attempted to impose a duty to pay a fine (for example, "anyone who litters has a legal duty to pay the state $1000") would be interpreted as imposing a tax. Only the latter interpretation makes sense of the fact that, because it is directed at citizens generally, the statute purports to declare a moral duty.
-
-
-
-
106
-
-
0347343263
-
-
note
-
As I explain later, similar language is used with, and similar consequences are See Dan B. Dobbs, Law of Remedies 12 (2d ed. 1993). Second, unlike Oman I argue that an important objection to the idea of an ordinary duty to pay damages is that wrongdoers cannot reasonably be expected to know how much they should pay by way of damages or, in some cases, whether they ought to pay damages at all.
-
(1993)
Law of Remedies
, pp. 12
-
-
Dobbs, D.B.1
-
107
-
-
84861383791
-
-
note
-
There are also practical reasons for announcing legal duties in advance of ordering them or authorizing their execution. To the extent that paying damages is presented as a legal duty, citizens who are disposed to view their legal duties in the way the law wants them viewed-namely as moral duties-will approach such actions differently than they would if they were merely ordered to perform them.
-
-
-
-
108
-
-
84861381085
-
-
note
-
For law-respecting citizens, settlements made in advance of litigation will not be regarded as akin to plea-bargaining deals, but rather as attempts to determine, so far as practical, their moral duties. Similarly, post-litigation payments will be regarded as fulfilling a moral obligation, not merely as something that one has been forced to do.
-
-
-
-
109
-
-
84861381088
-
-
note
-
For these citizens, there will be a stigma attached to attempts to avoid payment (for instance, by hiding assets) that would not exist if the only reason for making the payment were that the law commanded such payment. Thus, if the law did indeed regard paying damages as a moral obligation, it would be in the law's interest to make this fact clear by clarifying that payment is a legal duty.
-
-
-
-
111
-
-
29044449535
-
The Constitutional Status of Tort Law: Due Process and the Right to a Law for the Redress of Wrongs
-
John C.P. Goldberg, The Constitutional Status of Tort Law: Due Process and the Right to a Law for the Redress of Wrongs, 115 Yale L.J. 524 (2005).
-
(2005)
Yale L.J.
, vol.115
, pp. 524
-
-
Goldberg, J.C.P.1
-
112
-
-
0142138821
-
Civil Recourse, Not Corrective Justice
-
Benjamin C. Zipursky, Civil Recourse, Not Corrective Justice, 91 Geo. L.J. 695 (2003).
-
(2003)
Geo. L.J.
, vol.91
, pp. 695
-
-
Zipursky, B.C.1
-
113
-
-
0348194818
-
The Moral of MacPherson
-
note
-
See John C.P. Goldberg & Benjamin C. Zipursky, The Moral of MacPherson, 146 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1733, 1777-98 (1998). As this observation implies, the same brass-tacks disposition that has fueled skepticism toward private law might well distort modern understandings of public law. I defer to scholars of public law on the extent to which it has done so and on whether there might be need of a new public law.
-
(1998)
U. Pa. L. Rev.
, vol.146
-
-
Goldberg, J.C.P.1
Zipursky, B.C.2
-
114
-
-
69849102311
-
Institutions and Indirectness in Intellectual Property
-
Henry E. Smith, Institutions and Indirectness in Intellectual Property, 157 U. Pa. L. Rev. 2083, 2090-2103 (2009).
-
(2009)
U. Pa. L. Rev.
, vol.157
-
-
Smith, H.E.1
-
119
-
-
84861381087
-
-
note
-
Deterrence is one-but only one-possible explanation for the practice of punishing criminals.
-
-
-
-
120
-
-
84861392680
-
-
note
-
For an overview of theories of punishment, see A Reader on Punishment (R.A. Duff & David Garland eds., 1994). As we saw earlier, with the exception of punitive damages, damage awards cannot be explained, even in principle, by deterrence (because the defendant's gain can exceed the award). This conclusion does not preclude the possibility that having to pay damages may influence citizens' behavior. It merely reflects the fact that if damage awards were designed to deter rights infringements, then we would expect them to be set much higher than they are.
-
-
-
-
121
-
-
84861381089
-
-
note
-
I am not suggesting that all moral duties have or should have legal counterparts. I am merely reiterating the point made earlier that, from the law's perspective, legal duties are meant to reflect or give effect to moral reasons that already apply to the duties' subjects.
-
-
-
-
122
-
-
84861381086
-
-
note
-
I am not suggesting that all moral duties have or should have legal counterparts. I am merely reiterating the point made earlier that, from the law's perspective, legal duties are meant to reflect or give effect to moral reasons that already apply to the duties' subjects.
-
-
-
-
123
-
-
84937334675
-
Rights, Wrongs, and Remedies
-
See Peter Birks, Rights, Wrongs, and Remedies, 20 O.J.L.S. 1, 27 (2000).
-
(2000)
O.J.L.S.
, vol.20
-
-
Birks, P.1
-
124
-
-
78649909352
-
What Is Tort Law For? Part 1: The Place of Corrective Justice
-
See John Gardner, What Is Tort Law For? Part 1: The Place of Corrective Justice, 30 Law& Phil. 1, 33-35 (2011).
-
(2011)
Law& Phil.
, vol.30
-
-
Gardner, J.1
-
127
-
-
84861392679
-
-
note
-
The term "vindication" is preferable because, while related to acknowledgment (and recognition), it is stronger and appropriately conveys the fact (as explained above) that the law actually requires an action as opposed to merely making a pronouncement.
-
-
-
-
132
-
-
84861379208
-
The Relationship Between Rights and Remedies in Private Law: A Comparison Between the Common and the Civil Law Tradition
-
note
-
See, e.g., Code civil [C. civ.] art. 1382 (Fr.) ("Every action of man whatsoever which occasions injury to another, binds him through whose fault it happened to reparation thereof. "). For an overview of the civil law position, see Helge Dedek, The Relationship Between Rights and Remedies in Private Law: A Comparison Between the Common and the Civil Law Tradition, in Taking Remedies Seriously 63 (Robert J. Sharpe & Kent Roach eds., 2010).
-
(2010)
Taking Remedies Seriously
, pp. 63
-
-
Dedek, H.1
-
133
-
-
69749104752
-
-
note
-
The distinctiveness, importance, and ubiquity of such awards is a theme discussed in Robert Stevens, Torts and Rights 59-91 (2007).
-
(2007)
Torts and Rights
, pp. 59-91
-
-
Stevens, R.1
-
134
-
-
84861377497
-
Huckle v. Money
-
note
-
See, e.g., Huckle v. Money, (1763) 95 Eng. Rep. 768 (K.B.).
-
(1763)
Eng. Rep.
, vol.95
, pp. 768
-
-
-
135
-
-
69749104752
-
-
The distinctiveness, importance, and ubiquity of such awards is a theme discussed in Robert Stevens, Torts and Rights 59-91 (2007).
-
(2007)
Torts and Rights
, pp. 59-91
-
-
Stevens, R.1
-
136
-
-
84861389857
-
-
note
-
In the United Kingdom, a purchaser of defective goods is entitled to the difference in market value between the promised goods and the goods he received-even where he suffers no loss because the goods are satisfactory for his purpose. See, e.g., Rodocanachi, Sons & Co. v. Milburn Bros., [1886] Q.B.D. 67 at 76-77.
-
(1886)
Rodocanachi, Sons & Co. v. Milburn Bros.
, pp. 76-77
-
-
-
137
-
-
69749104752
-
-
The distinctiveness, importance, and ubiquity of such awards is a theme discussed in Robert Stevens, Torts and Rights 59-91 (2007).
-
(2007)
Torts and Rights
, pp. 59-91
-
-
Stevens, R.1
|