메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 125, Issue 7, 2012, Pages 1727-1756

Duties, liabilities, and damages

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84861375683     PISSN: 0017811X     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Note
Times cited : (52)

References (137)
  • 1
    • 84861383787 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Montreal, Que., By-Law RCG 10-016 §§ 7, 14 (Aug. 26, 2010).
  • 4
    • 0347343263 scopus 로고
    • note
    • As I explain later, similar language is used with, and similar consequences are See Dan B. Dobbs, Law of Remedies 12 (2d ed. 1993). Second, unlike Oman I argue that an important objection to the idea of an ordinary duty to pay damages is that wrongdoers cannot reasonably be expected to know how much they should pay by way of damages or, in some cases, whether they ought to pay damages at all.
    • (1993) Law of Remedies , pp. 12
    • Dobbs, D.B.1
  • 5
    • 0347343263 scopus 로고
    • note
    • As I explain later, similar language is used with, and similar consequences are See Dan B. Dobbs, Law of Remedies 12 (2d ed. 1993). Second, unlike Oman I argue that an important objection to the idea of an ordinary duty to pay damages is that wrongdoers cannot reasonably be expected to know how much they should pay by way of damages or, in some cases, whether they ought to pay damages at all.
    • (1993) Law of Remedies , pp. 12
    • Dobbs, D.B.1
  • 6
    • 0347343263 scopus 로고
    • note
    • As I explain later, similar language is used with, and similar consequences are See Dan B. Dobbs, Law of Remedies 12 (2d ed. 1993). Second, unlike Oman I argue that an important objection to the idea of an ordinary duty to pay damages is that wrongdoers cannot reasonably be expected to know how much they should pay by way of damages or, in some cases, whether they ought to pay damages at all.
    • (1993) Law of Remedies , pp. 12
    • Dobbs, D.B.1
  • 9
    • 84861389852 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • As understood here, a judicial "award" is the operational part of a legal decision. Common examples include orders or judgments that require the performance of a contract, the payment of money, or the cessation of an activity.
  • 10
    • 84937334675 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rights, Wrongs, and Remedies
    • See, e.g., Peter Birks, Rights, Wrongs, and Remedies, 20 O.J.L.S. 1, 28 (2000).
    • (2000) O.J.L.S. , vol.20
    • Birks, P.1
  • 15
    • 74849096289 scopus 로고
    • A Consent Theory of Contract
    • Randy E. Barnett, A Consent Theory of Contract, 86 Colum. L. Rev. 269 (1986).
    • (1986) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.86 , pp. 269
    • Barnett, R.E.1
  • 16
    • 66749122160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Unity of Contract Law
    • note
    • Peter Benson, The Unity of Contract Law, in TheTheory of Contract Law 118 (Peter Benson ed., 2001).
    • (2001) TheTheory of Contract Law , pp. 118
    • Benson, P.1
  • 17
    • 21144478652 scopus 로고
    • The Moral Foundations of Tort Law
    • Stephen R. Perry, The Moral Foundations of Tort Law, 77 Iowa L. Rev. 449 (1992). Rights-based theories are sometimes described as corrective justice theories.
    • (1992) Iowa L. Rev. , vol.77 , pp. 449
    • Perry, S.R.1
  • 18
    • 47049123771 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Philosophy of Private Law
    • note
    • For an overview, see Benjamin C. Zipursky, Philosophy of Private Law, in The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law 623, 627-31 (Jules Coleman & Scott Shapiro eds., 2002). The label is problematic because the concept of corrective justice is understood in radically different ways.
    • (2002) The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law
    • Zipursky, B.C.1
  • 20
    • 0004106103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Ernest J. Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law 3 (1995) (emphasizing the longstanding suspicion of the idea of private law in American legal scholarship). I happily acknowledge that there are overlaps between, on the one hand, my diagnosis of the state of private law theory and my account of some of the tenets of the New Private Law and, on the other hand, Weinrib's critique of functionalist accounts of private law and his defense of an internal approach. Nonetheless, important differences remain. Most obviously-and most saliently for mainstream legal scholars in the United States-I am claiming for private law the mantle of pragmatism, rather than what Weinrib describes as "formalism, "
    • (1995) The Idea of Private Law , pp. 3
    • Weinrib, E.J.1
  • 21
    • 80052483641 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Two Conceptions of Remedies
    • note
    • Ernest J. Weinrib, Two Conceptions of Remedies, in JustifyingPrivate Law Remedies 3, 31-32 (Charles E.F. Rickett ed., 2008) [hereinafter Weinrib, Two Conceptions]. The just-mentioned theories are, however, alike in that they all explain damage awards on the basis that victims have rights to the payment of damages.
    • (2008) JustifyingPrivate Law Remedies
    • Weinrib, E.J.1
  • 22
    • 84861381084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Primary legal duties arise from "not-wrongs, " such as entering an agreement, being born, or attaining the age of majority. Secondary duties, by contrast, arise from legal wrongs, such as a breach of contract or a tort. Writers who use this terminology typically suppose that the main example of a secondary duty is a duty to pay damages. See, e.g., Rafal Zakrzewski, RemediesReclassified 165-77 (2005).
    • (2005) RemediesReclassified , pp. 165-177
    • Zakrzewski, R.1
  • 23
    • 0004106103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In The Idea of Private Law, Weinrib describes the law of damages as imposing liabilities.
    • The Idea of Private Law
  • 26
    • 78649903198 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As if It Had Never Happened
    • See, e.g., Arthur Ripstein, As if It Had Never Happened, 48 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 1957, 1979-82 (2007).
    • (2007) Wm. & Mary L. Rev. , vol.48
    • Ripstein, A.1
  • 27
    • 0004106103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Ernest J. Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law 3 (1995) (emphasizing the longstanding suspicion of the idea of private law in American legal scholarship). I happily acknowledge that there are overlaps between, on the one hand, my diagnosis of the state of private law theory and my account of some of the tenets of the New Private Law and, on the other hand, Weinrib's critique of functionalist accounts of private law and his defense of an internal approach. Nonetheless, important differences remain. Most obviously-and most saliently for mainstream legal scholars in the United States-I am claiming for private law the mantle of pragmatism, rather than what Weinrib describes as "formalism, "
    • (1995) The Idea of Private Law , pp. 3
    • Weinrib, E.J.1
  • 28
    • 0004106103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Ernest J. Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law 3 (1995) (emphasizing the longstanding suspicion of the idea of private law in American legal scholarship). I happily acknowledge that there are overlaps between, on the one hand, my diagnosis of the state of private law theory and my account of some of the tenets of the New Private Law and, on the other hand, Weinrib's critique of functionalist accounts of private law and his defense of an internal approach. Nonetheless, important differences remain. Most obviously-and most saliently for mainstream legal scholars in the United States-I am claiming for private law the mantle of pragmatism, rather than what Weinrib describes as "formalism, "
    • (1995) The Idea of Private Law , pp. 3
    • Weinrib, E.J.1
  • 30
    • 21144478652 scopus 로고
    • The Moral Foundations of Tort Law
    • Stephen R. Perry, The Moral Foundations of Tort Law, 77 Iowa L. Rev. 449, 478-79 (1992).
    • (1992) Iowa L. Rev. , vol.77
    • Perry, S.R.1
  • 31
    • 21144478652 scopus 로고
    • The Moral Foundations of Tort Law
    • Stephen R. Perry, The Moral Foundations of Tort Law, 77 Iowa L. Rev. 449, 478-79 (1992).
    • (1992) Iowa L. Rev. , vol.77
    • Perry, S.R.1
  • 32
    • 84861392675 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I say "in principle" to allow for the possibility that the duty to pay damages is inchoate until fixed by the court. I explore this possibility in Part II.
  • 34
    • 0347343263 scopus 로고
    • note
    • As I explain later, similar language is used with, and similar consequences are See Dan B. Dobbs, Law of Remedies 12 (2d ed. 1993). Second, unlike Oman I argue that an important objection to the idea of an ordinary duty to pay damages is that wrongdoers cannot reasonably be expected to know how much they should pay by way of damages or, in some cases, whether they ought to pay damages at all.
    • (1993) Law of Remedies , pp. 12
    • Dobbs, D.B.1
  • 39
    • 4544375290 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Steven Shavell, Foundations of EconomicAnalysis of Law 9-32 (2004) [hereinafter Shavell, Foundations]. Utilitarian theories are often described as "economic" theories because contemporary writers who regard the law as a vehicle for promoting utility usually adopt economic tools and techniques in their arguments.
    • (2004) Foundations of EconomicAnalysis of Law , pp. 9-32
    • Shavell, S.1
  • 40
    • 17244370822 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See, e.g., Thomas J. Miceli, The Economic Approach to Law 1 (2004) ("The economic approach to law assumes that rational individuals view legal sanctions (monetary damages, prison) as implicit prices for certain kinds of behavior, and that these prices can be set to guide these behaviors in a socially desirable direction. ").
    • (2004) The Economic Approach to Law , pp. 1
    • Miceli, T.J.1
  • 41
    • 84861389856 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Richard A. Posner, The Economics ofJustice 75 (1981) ("The basic function of law in an economic or wealth-maximization perspective is to alter incentives. ").
    • (1981) The Economics ofJustice , vol.75
    • Posner, R.A.1
  • 42
    • 35448950482 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Contract Remedies: General
    • note
    • Paul G. Mahoney, Contract Remedies: General, in 3 Encyclopedia of Law & Economics 117, 118 (Boudewijn Bouckaert & Gerrit De Geest eds., 2000) ("The economic function of contract remedies... is to alter the incentives facing the party who regrets entering into the contract.... ").
    • (2000) Encyclopedia of Law & Economics , vol.3
    • Mahoney, P.G.1
  • 43
    • 0001609162 scopus 로고
    • Property Rules, Liability Rules, and Inalienability: One View of the Cathedral
    • Guido Calabresi & A. Douglas Melamed, Property Rules, Liability Rules, and Inalienability: One View of the Cathedral, 85 Harv. L. Rev. 1089, 1092 (1972).
    • (1972) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.85
    • Calabresi, G.1    Melamed, A.D.2
  • 44
    • 80052616759 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Normativity of Private Law
    • I explain the argument that follows in more detail in Stephen A. Smith, The Normativity of Private Law, 31 O.J.L.S. 215 (2011).
    • (2011) O.J.L.S. , vol.31 , pp. 215
    • Smith, S.A.1
  • 45
    • 84861389858 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Authorities that are not viewed in this way may try to encourage compliance by attaching sanctions to their rules, but in this case the rules qua rules are superfluous: the same result could be achieved by making it clear that citizens who engage in a given behavior will be penalized.
  • 46
    • 0001417422 scopus 로고
    • The Path of the Law
    • O.W. Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457, 459 (1897).
    • (1897) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.10
    • Holmes, O.W.1
  • 47
    • 58149384112 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Social Norms and the Law: Why Peoples Obey the Law
    • See Amir N. Licht, Social Norms and the Law: Why Peoples Obey the Law, 4 Rev. L. & Econ. 715, 715-17 (2008).
    • (2008) Rev. L. & Econ. , vol.4
    • Licht, A.N.1
  • 49
    • 67649365633 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Norms and the Law
    • note
    • For an overview, see Richard H. McAdams & Eric B. Rasmusen, Norms and the Law, in 2 Handbook of Law & Economics 1573, 1573-1610 (A. Mitchell Polinsky & Steven Shavell eds., 2007).
    • (2007) Handbook of Law & Economics , vol.2
    • McAdams, R.H.1    Rasmusen, E.B.2
  • 50
    • 0347053819 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Do Good Laws Make Good Citizens? An Economic Analysis of Internalized Norms
    • See, e.g., Robert Cooter, Do Good Laws Make Good Citizens? An Economic Analysis of Internalized Norms, 86 Va. L. Rev. 1577, 1598-1600 (2000).
    • (2000) Va. L. Rev. , vol.86
    • Cooter, R.1
  • 51
    • 33846577294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Intrinsic Value of Obeying a Law: Economic Analysis of the Internal Viewpoint
    • Robert Cooter, The Intrinsic Value of Obeying a Law: Economic Analysis of the Internal Viewpoint, 75 Fordham L. Rev. 1275, 1276-77 (2006).
    • (2006) Fordham L. Rev. , vol.75
    • Cooter, R.1
  • 52
    • 0037678329 scopus 로고
    • Enforcing Promises: An Examination of the Basis of Contract
    • See Charles J. Goetz & Robert E. Scott, Enforcing Promises: An Examination of the Basis of Contract, 89 Yale L.J. 1261, 1263-64, 1279-80 (1980).
    • (1980) Yale L.J. , vol.89
    • Goetz, C.J.1    Scott, R.E.2
  • 53
    • 0042895545 scopus 로고
    • The Mitigation Principle: Toward a General Theory of Contractual Obligation
    • See Charles J. Goetz & Robert E. Scott, The Mitigation Principle: Toward a General Theory of Contractual Obligation, 69 Va. L. Rev. 967, 971 (1983) and accompanying text.
    • (1983) Va. L. Rev. , vol.69
    • Goetz, C.J.1    Scott, R.E.2
  • 56
    • 4544375290 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Steven Shavell, Foundations of EconomicAnalysis of Law 9-32 (2004) [hereinafter Shavell, Foundations]. Utilitarian theories are often described as "economic" theories because contemporary writers who regard the law as a vehicle for promoting utility usually adopt economic tools and techniques in their arguments.
    • (2004) Foundations of EconomicAnalysis of Law , pp. 9-32
    • Shavell, S.1
  • 57
    • 0003774434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • As I discuss in more detail below, see Richard A. Posner, Economic Analysis of Law 29-34 (8th ed. 2011) pp. 1738-40, some writers have explained contract damages on the basis that they give contracting parties incentives to breach whenever the cost of performance is greater than the value of performance-the so-called "efficient breach" theory.
    • (2011) Economic Analysis of Law , pp. 1738-1740
    • Posner, R.A.1
  • 59
    • 0347539474 scopus 로고
    • Breach of Contract, Damage Measures, and Economic Efficiency
    • Robert L. Birmingham, Breach of Contract, Damage Measures, and Economic Efficiency, 24 Rutgers L. Rev. 273, 292 (1970).
    • (1970) Rutgers L. Rev. , vol.24
    • Birmingham, R.L.1
  • 60
    • 78649909352 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What Is Tort Law For? Part 1: The Place of Corrective Justice
    • See John Gardner, What Is Tort Law For? Part 1: The Place of Corrective Justice, 30 Law& Phil. 1, (2011) pp. 1738-40.
    • (2011) Law& Phil. , vol.30 , pp. 1738-1740
    • Gardner, J.1
  • 61
    • 78649909352 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What Is Tort Law For? Part 1: The Place of Corrective Justice
    • See John Gardner, What Is Tort Law For? Part 1: The Place of Corrective Justice, 30 Law& Phil. 1, 33-35 (2011).
    • (2011) Law& Phil. , vol.30
    • Gardner, J.1
  • 62
    • 84927012473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Personal Practical Conflicts
    • note
    • Professor John Gardner's explanation draws on Joseph Raz, Personal Practical Conflicts, in Practical Conflicts 172, 189-93 (Peter Baumann & Monika Betzler eds., 2004).
    • (2004) Practical Conflicts
    • Raz, J.1
  • 63
    • 78649909352 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What Is Tort Law For? Part 1: The Place of Corrective Justice
    • John Gardner, Obligations and Outcomes in the Law of Torts, in Relating to Responsibility111, 134 (Peter Cane & John Gardner eds., 2001).
    • (2011) Law& Phil. , vol.30
    • Gardner, J.1
  • 64
    • 78649909352 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What Is Tort Law For? Part 1: The Place of Corrective Justice
    • John Gardner, Obligations and Outcomes in the Law of Torts, in Relating to Responsibility111, 134 (Peter Cane & John Gardner eds., 2001).
    • (2011) Law& Phil. , vol.30
    • Gardner, J.1
  • 66
    • 0347539474 scopus 로고
    • Breach of Contract, Damage Measures, and Economic Efficiency
    • Robert L. Birmingham, Breach of Contract, Damage Measures, and Economic Efficiency, 24 Rutgers L. Rev. 273, 292 (1970).
    • (1970) Rutgers L. Rev. , vol.24
    • Birmingham, R.L.1
  • 67
    • 22544435816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Economic Analysis of Contract Law After Three Decades: Success or Failure?
    • See, e.g., Eric A. Posner, Economic Analysis of Contract Law After Three Decades: Success or Failure?, 112 Yale L.J. 829, 834-39 (2003).
    • (2003) Yale L.J. , vol.112
    • Posner, E.A.1
  • 68
    • 0040746598 scopus 로고
    • The Case for Specific Performance
    • Alan Schwartz, The Case for Specific Performance, 89 Yale L.J. 271, 278-96 (1979).
    • (1979) Yale L.J. , vol.89
    • Schwartz, A.1
  • 69
    • 84861389854 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This qualification is necessary because contractual duties cannot plausibly be described as disjunctive in cases in which courts are willing to order specific performance of those duties.
  • 70
    • 0001417422 scopus 로고
    • The Path of the Law
    • O.W. Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457 (1897).
    • (1897) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.10 , pp. 457
    • Holmes, O.W.1
  • 71
    • 84861383790 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For Holmes, to say there is a legal duty to pay a sum of money is not to say that legally the money should be paid; the duty may mean no more than that the law will force you to pay the money.
  • 72
    • 84855887848 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Myth of Efficient Breach: New Defenses of the Expectation Interest
    • See, e.g., Daniel Markovits & Alan Schwartz, The Myth of Efficient Breach: New Defenses of the Expectation Interest, 97 Va. L. Rev. 1939, 2006 (2011). The authors limit their argument to commercial parties.
    • (2011) Va. L. Rev. , vol.97
    • Markovits, D.1    Schwartz, A.2
  • 73
    • 84855887848 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Myth of Efficient Breach: New Defenses of the Expectation Interest
    • See, e.g., Daniel Markovits & Alan Schwartz, The Myth of Efficient Breach: New Defenses of the Expectation Interest, 97 Va. L. Rev. 1939, 2006 (2011). The authors limit their argument to commercial parties.
    • (2011) Va. L. Rev. , vol.97
    • Markovits, D.1    Schwartz, A.2
  • 74
    • 0042895545 scopus 로고
    • The Mitigation Principle: Toward a General Theory of Contractual Obligation
    • note
    • For an argument describing the general utility of implying terms that the parties would have wanted, see Charles J. Goetz & Robert E. Scott, The Mitigation Principle: Toward a General Theory of Contractual Obligation, 69 Va. L. Rev. 967, 971 (1983), which notes that "[i]deally, the preformulated rules supplied by the state should mimic the agreements contracting parties would reach were they costlessly to bargain out each detail of the transaction, "
    • (1983) Va. L. Rev. , vol.69
    • Goetz, C.J.1    Scott, R.E.2
  • 75
    • 0002692296 scopus 로고
    • Filling Gaps in Incomplete Contracts: An Economic Theory of Default Rules
    • This version of the disjunctive duty thesis is therefore similar to the idea, defended by some utilitarian writers, that the damages rules for breach of contract should be understood as default terms implied into all contracts. See, e.g., Ian Ayres & Robert Gertner, Filling Gaps in Incomplete Contracts: An Economic Theory of Default Rules, 99 Yale L.J. 87, 88, 101-04, 121-22 (1989).
    • (1989) Yale L.J. , vol.99
    • Ayres, I.1    Gertner, R.2
  • 76
    • 84930561365 scopus 로고
    • Strategic Bargaining and the Economic Theory of Contract Default Rules
    • Jason Scott Johnston, Strategic Bargaining and the Economic Theory of Contract Default Rules, 100 Yale L.J. 615, 615-18 (1990).
    • (1990) Yale L.J. , vol.100
    • Johnston, J.S.1
  • 77
    • 84861379208 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Relationship Between Rights and Remedies in Private Law: A Comparison Between the Common and the Civil Law Tradition
    • note
    • I discuss the civil law position briefly Helge Dedek, The Relationship Between Rights and Remedies in Private Law: A Comparison Between the Common and the Civil Law Tradition, in Taking Remedies Seriously 63 (Robert J. Sharpe & Kent Roach eds., 2010) and accompanying text.
    • (2010) Taking Remedies Seriously , pp. 63
    • Dedek, H.1
  • 78
    • 69849102311 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Institutions and Indirectness in Intellectual Property
    • Henry E. Smith, Institutions and Indirectness in Intellectual Property, 157 U. Pa. L. Rev. 2083, 2090-2103 (2009).
    • (2009) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.157
    • Smith, H.E.1
  • 79
    • 84861381084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Primary legal duties arise from "not-wrongs, " such as entering an agreement, being born, or attaining the age of majority. Secondary duties, by contrast, arise from legal wrongs, such as a breach of contract or a tort. Writers who use this terminology typically suppose that the main example of a secondary duty is a duty to pay damages. See, e.g., Rafal Zakrzewski, RemediesReclassified 165-77 (2005).
    • (2005) RemediesReclassified , pp. 165-177
    • Zakrzewski, R.1
  • 80
    • 84861378589 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Definition and Division: A Meditation on Institutes 3.13
    • note
    • Peter Birks, Definition and Division: A Meditation on Institutes 3.13, in The Classification of Obligations 1, 24 (Peter Birks ed., 1997).
    • (1997) The Classification of Obligations
    • Birks, P.1
  • 81
    • 69849102311 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Institutions and Indirectness in Intellectual Property
    • Henry E. Smith, Institutions and Indirectness in Intellectual Property, 157 U. Pa. L. Rev. 2083, 2090-2103 (2009).
    • (2009) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.157
    • Smith, H.E.1
  • 90
    • 84861383792 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This discretion is qualitatively different from the weak discretion that courts necessarily exercise whenever they apply general rules to specific facts. Courts openly acknowledge that the quantification of, for example, damages for pain and suffering involves a large subjective element. See, e.g., Wise v. Kaye, [1962] 1 Q.B. 638 at 669 (Eng.).
  • 91
    • 84861379208 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Relationship Between Rights and Remedies in Private Law: A Comparison Between the Common and the Civil Law Tradition
    • note
    • See Helge Dedek, The Relationship Between Rights and Remedies in Private Law: A Comparison Between the Common and the Civil Law Tradition, in Taking Remedies Seriously 63 (Robert J. Sharpe & Kent Roach eds., 2010).
    • (2010) Taking Remedies Seriously , pp. 63
    • Dedek, H.1
  • 98
    • 0347343263 scopus 로고
    • note
    • As I explain later, similar language is used with, and similar consequences are See Dan B. Dobbs, Law of Remedies 12 (2d ed. 1993). Second, unlike Oman I argue that an important objection to the idea of an ordinary duty to pay damages is that wrongdoers cannot reasonably be expected to know how much they should pay by way of damages or, in some cases, whether they ought to pay damages at all.
    • (1993) Law of Remedies , pp. 12
    • Dobbs, D.B.1
  • 99
    • 0347343263 scopus 로고
    • note
    • As I explain later, similar language is used with, and similar consequences are See Dan B. Dobbs, Law of Remedies 12 (2d ed. 1993). Second, unlike Oman I argue that an important objection to the idea of an ordinary duty to pay damages is that wrongdoers cannot reasonably be expected to know how much they should pay by way of damages or, in some cases, whether they ought to pay damages at all.
    • (1993) Law of Remedies , pp. 12
    • Dobbs, D.B.1
  • 100
    • 84861381082 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This language is often explicit in civilian codes. See, e.g., Civil Code of Québec, S.Q. 1991, c. 64, art. 1458 (Can.) ("Every person has a duty to honour his contractual undertakings. ").
  • 102
    • 0043240610 scopus 로고
    • Voluntary Obligations and Normative Powers II
    • note
    • Joseph Raz, Voluntary Obligations and Normative Powers II, 46 Proc. AristotelianSoc'y 79, 81 (1972) (emphasis added).
    • (1972) Proc. AristotelianSoc'y , vol.46
    • Raz, J.1
  • 103
    • 69849102311 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Institutions and Indirectness in Intellectual Property
    • Henry E. Smith, Institutions and Indirectness in Intellectual Property, 157 U. Pa. L. Rev. 2083, 2090-2103 (2009).
    • (2009) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.157
    • Smith, H.E.1
  • 104
    • 84861389855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Thus, a statute that attempted to impose a duty to pay a fine (for example, "anyone who litters has a legal duty to pay the state $1000") would be interpreted as imposing a tax. Only the latter interpretation makes sense of the fact that, because it is directed at citizens generally, the statute purports to declare a moral duty.
  • 106
    • 0347343263 scopus 로고
    • note
    • As I explain later, similar language is used with, and similar consequences are See Dan B. Dobbs, Law of Remedies 12 (2d ed. 1993). Second, unlike Oman I argue that an important objection to the idea of an ordinary duty to pay damages is that wrongdoers cannot reasonably be expected to know how much they should pay by way of damages or, in some cases, whether they ought to pay damages at all.
    • (1993) Law of Remedies , pp. 12
    • Dobbs, D.B.1
  • 107
    • 84861383791 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • There are also practical reasons for announcing legal duties in advance of ordering them or authorizing their execution. To the extent that paying damages is presented as a legal duty, citizens who are disposed to view their legal duties in the way the law wants them viewed-namely as moral duties-will approach such actions differently than they would if they were merely ordered to perform them.
  • 108
    • 84861381085 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For law-respecting citizens, settlements made in advance of litigation will not be regarded as akin to plea-bargaining deals, but rather as attempts to determine, so far as practical, their moral duties. Similarly, post-litigation payments will be regarded as fulfilling a moral obligation, not merely as something that one has been forced to do.
  • 109
    • 84861381088 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For these citizens, there will be a stigma attached to attempts to avoid payment (for instance, by hiding assets) that would not exist if the only reason for making the payment were that the law commanded such payment. Thus, if the law did indeed regard paying damages as a moral obligation, it would be in the law's interest to make this fact clear by clarifying that payment is a legal duty.
  • 111
    • 29044449535 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Constitutional Status of Tort Law: Due Process and the Right to a Law for the Redress of Wrongs
    • John C.P. Goldberg, The Constitutional Status of Tort Law: Due Process and the Right to a Law for the Redress of Wrongs, 115 Yale L.J. 524 (2005).
    • (2005) Yale L.J. , vol.115 , pp. 524
    • Goldberg, J.C.P.1
  • 112
    • 0142138821 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Civil Recourse, Not Corrective Justice
    • Benjamin C. Zipursky, Civil Recourse, Not Corrective Justice, 91 Geo. L.J. 695 (2003).
    • (2003) Geo. L.J. , vol.91 , pp. 695
    • Zipursky, B.C.1
  • 113
    • 0348194818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Moral of MacPherson
    • note
    • See John C.P. Goldberg & Benjamin C. Zipursky, The Moral of MacPherson, 146 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1733, 1777-98 (1998). As this observation implies, the same brass-tacks disposition that has fueled skepticism toward private law might well distort modern understandings of public law. I defer to scholars of public law on the extent to which it has done so and on whether there might be need of a new public law.
    • (1998) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.146
    • Goldberg, J.C.P.1    Zipursky, B.C.2
  • 114
    • 69849102311 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Institutions and Indirectness in Intellectual Property
    • Henry E. Smith, Institutions and Indirectness in Intellectual Property, 157 U. Pa. L. Rev. 2083, 2090-2103 (2009).
    • (2009) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.157
    • Smith, H.E.1
  • 119
    • 84861381087 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Deterrence is one-but only one-possible explanation for the practice of punishing criminals.
  • 120
    • 84861392680 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For an overview of theories of punishment, see A Reader on Punishment (R.A. Duff & David Garland eds., 1994). As we saw earlier, with the exception of punitive damages, damage awards cannot be explained, even in principle, by deterrence (because the defendant's gain can exceed the award). This conclusion does not preclude the possibility that having to pay damages may influence citizens' behavior. It merely reflects the fact that if damage awards were designed to deter rights infringements, then we would expect them to be set much higher than they are.
  • 121
    • 84861381089 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I am not suggesting that all moral duties have or should have legal counterparts. I am merely reiterating the point made earlier that, from the law's perspective, legal duties are meant to reflect or give effect to moral reasons that already apply to the duties' subjects.
  • 122
    • 84861381086 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I am not suggesting that all moral duties have or should have legal counterparts. I am merely reiterating the point made earlier that, from the law's perspective, legal duties are meant to reflect or give effect to moral reasons that already apply to the duties' subjects.
  • 123
    • 84937334675 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rights, Wrongs, and Remedies
    • See Peter Birks, Rights, Wrongs, and Remedies, 20 O.J.L.S. 1, 27 (2000).
    • (2000) O.J.L.S. , vol.20
    • Birks, P.1
  • 124
    • 78649909352 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What Is Tort Law For? Part 1: The Place of Corrective Justice
    • See John Gardner, What Is Tort Law For? Part 1: The Place of Corrective Justice, 30 Law& Phil. 1, 33-35 (2011).
    • (2011) Law& Phil. , vol.30
    • Gardner, J.1
  • 127
    • 84861392679 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The term "vindication" is preferable because, while related to acknowledgment (and recognition), it is stronger and appropriately conveys the fact (as explained above) that the law actually requires an action as opposed to merely making a pronouncement.
  • 132
    • 84861379208 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Relationship Between Rights and Remedies in Private Law: A Comparison Between the Common and the Civil Law Tradition
    • note
    • See, e.g., Code civil [C. civ.] art. 1382 (Fr.) ("Every action of man whatsoever which occasions injury to another, binds him through whose fault it happened to reparation thereof. "). For an overview of the civil law position, see Helge Dedek, The Relationship Between Rights and Remedies in Private Law: A Comparison Between the Common and the Civil Law Tradition, in Taking Remedies Seriously 63 (Robert J. Sharpe & Kent Roach eds., 2010).
    • (2010) Taking Remedies Seriously , pp. 63
    • Dedek, H.1
  • 133
    • 69749104752 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The distinctiveness, importance, and ubiquity of such awards is a theme discussed in Robert Stevens, Torts and Rights 59-91 (2007).
    • (2007) Torts and Rights , pp. 59-91
    • Stevens, R.1
  • 134
    • 84861377497 scopus 로고
    • Huckle v. Money
    • note
    • See, e.g., Huckle v. Money, (1763) 95 Eng. Rep. 768 (K.B.).
    • (1763) Eng. Rep. , vol.95 , pp. 768
  • 135
    • 69749104752 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The distinctiveness, importance, and ubiquity of such awards is a theme discussed in Robert Stevens, Torts and Rights 59-91 (2007).
    • (2007) Torts and Rights , pp. 59-91
    • Stevens, R.1
  • 136
    • 84861389857 scopus 로고
    • note
    • In the United Kingdom, a purchaser of defective goods is entitled to the difference in market value between the promised goods and the goods he received-even where he suffers no loss because the goods are satisfactory for his purpose. See, e.g., Rodocanachi, Sons & Co. v. Milburn Bros., [1886] Q.B.D. 67 at 76-77.
    • (1886) Rodocanachi, Sons & Co. v. Milburn Bros. , pp. 76-77
  • 137
    • 69749104752 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The distinctiveness, importance, and ubiquity of such awards is a theme discussed in Robert Stevens, Torts and Rights 59-91 (2007).
    • (2007) Torts and Rights , pp. 59-91
    • Stevens, R.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.