메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 36, Issue 4, 2010, Pages 1057-1077

Actor, structure, process: Transcending the state personhood debate by means of a pragmatist ontological model for International Relations theory

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 79953027364     PISSN: 02602105     EISSN: 14699044     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0260210510000203     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (29)

References (81)
  • 1
    • 84974183553 scopus 로고
    • The agent-structure problem in international relations theory
    • On the agent-structure problem see, for example
    • On the agent-structure problem see, for example, Alexander E. Wendt, 'The agent-structure problem in international relations theory', International Organization, 41 (1987), pp. 335-70;
    • (1987) International Organization , vol.41 , pp. 335-370
    • Wendt, A.E.1
  • 2
    • 84975994571 scopus 로고
    • What's at stake in the agent-structure debate
    • David Dessler, 'What's at Stake in the Agent-Structure Debate', International Organization, 43 (1989), pp. 441-73;
    • (1989) International Organization , vol.43 , pp. 441-473
    • Dessler, D.1
  • 3
    • 84922925093 scopus 로고
    • The agent-structure problem in foreign policy analysis
    • Walter Carlsnaes, 'The Agent-Structure Problem in Foreign Policy Analysis', International Studies Quarterly, 36 (1992), pp. 245-70;
    • (1992) International Studies Quarterly , vol.36 , pp. 245-270
    • Carlsnaes, W.1
  • 4
    • 0033095970 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • They shoot dead horses, don't they? Locating agency in the agent-structure problematique
    • and Colin Wight, 'They Shoot Dead Horses, Don't They? Locating Agency in the Agent-Structure Problematique', in: European Journal of International Relations, 5 (1999), pp. 109-42.
    • (1999) European Journal of International Relations , vol.5 , pp. 109-142
    • Wight, C.1
  • 5
    • 79953027773 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Since we adopt a pragmatist position, ontology is not to be understood in its older metaphysical sense of describing the social world as it really or truly is. For us, ontology denotes a view of the world as we believe it to be; a view, to be clear, that hopefully will be superseded by a better truth and a better view of reality
    • Since we adopt a pragmatist position, ontology is not to be understood in its older metaphysical sense of describing the social world as it really or truly is. For us, ontology denotes a view of the world as we believe it to be; a view, to be clear, that (hopefully) will be superseded by a better truth and a better view of reality.
  • 6
    • 79953024775 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Our understanding of abduction follows Charles Sanders Peirce, who himself was drawing on Aristotle to develop an explanation for the emergence of new hypotheses which is impossible for both deduction and induction: 'Abduction is the process of forming an explanatory hypothesis. It is the only logical operation which introduces any new idea; for induction does nothing but determine a value, and deduction merely evolves the necessary consequences of a pure hypothesis. Deduction proves that something must be; Induction shows that something is actually operative; Abduction merely suggests that something may be. Its only justification is that from its suggestion deduction can draw a prediction which can be tested by induction, and that, if we are ever to learn anything or to understand phenomena at all, it must be by abduction that this is to be brought about.'
    • Our understanding of abduction follows Charles Sanders Peirce, who himself was drawing on Aristotle to develop an explanation for the emergence of new hypotheses (which is impossible for both deduction and induction): 'Abduction is the process of forming an explanatory hypothesis. It is the only logical operation which introduces any new idea; for induction does nothing but determine a value, and deduction merely evolves the necessary consequences of a pure hypothesis. Deduction proves that something must be; Induction shows that something is actually operative; Abduction merely suggests that something may be. Its only justification is that from its suggestion deduction can draw a prediction which can be tested by induction, and that, if we are ever to learn anything or to understand phenomena at all, it must be by abduction that this is to be brought about.'
  • 7
    • 79953029816 scopus 로고
    • Cf, edited by Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 5.171
    • Cf. Charles Sanders Peirce, Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, edited by Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1965), p. 106 (5.171).
    • (1965) Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce , pp. 106
    • Peirce, C.S.1
  • 9
    • 0003565595 scopus 로고
    • as well as, Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp
    • as well as Hans Joas, Die Kreativität des Handelns (Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp, 1992), p. 198.
    • (1992) Die Kreativität des Handelns , pp. 198
    • Joas, H.1
  • 11
    • 79953030042 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and 31 2005, pp. 349-60
    • and 31 (2005), pp. 349-60.
  • 12
    • 11144357816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The state as person in international theory
    • See
    • See Alexander Wendt, 'The state as person in international theory', Review of International Studies, 30 (2004), p. 289.
    • (2004) Review of International Studies , vol.30 , pp. 289
    • Wendt, A.1
  • 13
    • 11144357816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The state as person in international theory
    • See, Ibid
    • See Alexander Wendt, 'The state as person in international theory', Review of International Studies, 30 (2004), p. 291.
    • (2004) Review of International Studies , vol.30 , pp. 291
    • Wendt, A.1
  • 14
    • 11144355442 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • State agency: Social action without human activity?
    • Colin Wight, 'State agency: social action without human activity?', Review of International Studies, 30 (2004), p. 270.
    • (2004) Review of International Studies , vol.30 , pp. 270
    • Wight, C.1
  • 15
    • 11144355442 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • State agency: Social action without human activity?
    • Ibid
    • Colin Wight, 'State agency: social action without human activity?', Review of International Studies, 30 (2004), p. 271.
    • (2004) Review of International Studies , vol.30 , pp. 271
    • Wight, C.1
  • 17
  • 29
    • 2142739577 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid, In his response, Wendt describes Wight's position as an interesting hybrid. While arguing against the reducibility of states to their members, he was approving the reducibility of their intentions
    • Wight, 'State agency', p. 279. In his response, Wendt describes Wight's position as an interesting hybrid. While arguing against the reducibility of states to their members, he was approving the reducibility of their intentions (
    • State Agency , pp. 279
    • Wight1
  • 30
    • 17444381001 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see, The demarcation line that separates Wendt's response to the as if-approach from Wight's runs along this point indeed. While the former asserts that state persons have own intentions irreducible to human beings, the latter assumes that states cannot have any intentions, since they are no persons at all
    • see Wendt, 'The state as person', p. 298). The demarcation line that separates Wendt's response to the as if-approach from Wight's runs along this point indeed. While the former asserts that state persons have own intentions irreducible to human beings, the latter assumes that states cannot have any intentions, since they are no persons at all.
    • The State as Person , pp. 298
    • Wendt1
  • 31
    • 17444424944 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • How not to argue against state personhood: A reply to lomas
    • See
    • See Alexander Wendt, 'How not to argue against state personhood: a reply to Lomas', Review of International Studies, 31 (2005), p. 358.
    • (2005) Review of International Studies , vol.31 , pp. 358
    • Wendt, A.1
  • 33
    • 79953027170 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Despite we share unease in the dual framing of the state-personhood debate, this stance marks a rather strong contrast to the position of another contributor, who treats non-humans as responsible actors as well
    • Despite we share unease in the dual framing of the state-personhood debate, this stance marks a rather strong contrast to the position of another contributor, who treats non-humans as responsible actors as well.
  • 34
    • 42949128601 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Real"? As if! critical reflections on state personhood
    • See
    • See Jacob Schiff, '"Real"? As if! Critical reflections on state personhood', Review of International Studies, 34 (2008), pp. 363-77.
    • (2008) Review of International Studies , vol.34 , pp. 363-377
    • Schiff, J.1
  • 35
    • 68749118304 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On acting and knowing. How pragmatism can advance international relations research and methodology
    • See, for example
    • See, for example, Jörg Friedrichs and Friedrich Kratochwil, 'On Acting and Knowing. How Pragmatism can advance International Relations Research and Methodology', International Organization, 63 (2009), pp. 701-31;
    • (2009) International Organization , vol.63 , pp. 701-731
    • Jörg Friedrichs1    Kratochwil, F.2
  • 36
    • 70249090046 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pragmatism and international relations
    • Gunther Hellmann, 'Pragmatism and International Relations', International Studies Review, 11 (2009), pp. 638-62
    • (2009) International Studies Review , vol.11 , pp. 638-662
    • Hellmann, G.1
  • 38
    • 33947719971 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of false promises and good bets: A plea for a pragmatic approach to theory building (the Tartu lecture)
    • DOI 10.1057/palgrave.jird.1800111, PII 1800111
    • Friedrich Kratochwil, 'Of false promises and good bets: a plea for a pragmatic approach to theory building (the Tartu lecture) ', Journal of International Relations and Development, 10 (2007), pp. 1-15; (Pubitemid 46505772)
    • (2007) Journal of International Relations and Development , vol.10 , Issue.1 , pp. 1-15
    • Kratochwil, F.1
  • 39
    • 30444447976 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Forget post-positivist' IR!: The legacy of IR theory as the locus for a pragmatist turn
    • DOI 10.1177/0010836705052240
    • Helena Rytövuori-Apunen, 'Forget 'Post-Positivist IR'! The Legacy of IR Theory as the Locus for a Pragmatist Turn', Cooperation and Conflict, 40 (2005), pp. 147-77; (Pubitemid 43074569)
    • (2005) Cooperation and Conflict , vol.40 , Issue.2 , pp. 147-177
    • Rytovuori-Apunen, H.1
  • 40
    • 12944276485 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deweyan pragmatism and post-positivist social science in IR
    • DOI 10.1177/03058298020310030801
    • Molly Cochran, 'Deweyan Pragmatism and Post-Positivst Social Science in IR', Millennium. Journal of International Studies, 31 (2002), pp. 525-48; (Pubitemid 44775814)
    • (2002) Millennium: Journal of International Studies , vol.31 , Issue.3 , pp. 525-548
    • Cochran, M.1
  • 41
    • 12944263165 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Re-orienting international relations: On pragmatism, pluralism and practical reasoning
    • DOI 10.1177/03058298020310030201
    • David Owen, 'Re-orienting International Relations: On Pragmatism, Pluralism and Practical Reasoning', Millennium. Journal of International Studies, 31 (2002), pp. 653-73; (Pubitemid 44775819)
    • (2002) Millennium: Journal of International Studies , vol.31 , Issue.3 , pp. 653-673
    • Owen, D.1
  • 42
    • 0031161681 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Exorcismus theoriae': Pragmatism, metaphors and the return of the medieval in IR theory
    • and Ronald J. Deibert, "Exorcismus Theoriae': Pragmatism, Metaphors and the Return of the Medieval in IR Theory', European Journal of International Relations, 3 (1997), pp. 167-92. (Pubitemid 127176457)
    • (1997) European Journal of International Relations , vol.3 , Issue.2 , pp. 167-192
    • Deibert, R.J.1
  • 47
    • 11144353783 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beware of organicism: The narrative self of the state
    • see
    • (see Iver B. Neumann, 'Beware of organicism: the narrative self of the state', Review of International Studies, 30 (2004), pp. 260-1)
    • (2004) Review of International Studies , vol.30 , pp. 260-261
    • Neumann, I.B.1
  • 48
    • 79953027725 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As social structures, corporate actors such as the state have interfaces which also harbour such possibilities as division, growth, merger, interlocking and specialisation
    • ibid.. Here again, the problem of the relationship between actors and states tends to be negated by equating both sides with each other
    • 'As social structures, corporate actors such as the state have interfaces which also harbour such possibilities as division, growth, merger, interlocking and specialisation' (Review of International Studies, 30 (2004), pp. 265). Here again, the problem of the relationship between actors and states tends to be negated by equating both sides with each other.
    • (2004) Review of International Studies , vol.30 , pp. 265
  • 49
    • 0002479337 scopus 로고
    • Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes
    • See, in Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave eds, London: Cambridge University Press
    • See Imre Lakatos, 'Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes', in Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave (eds), Criticism and the growth of knowledge (London: Cambridge University Press, 1970), p. 118.
    • (1970) Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge , pp. 118
    • Lakatos, I.1
  • 50
    • 0348207828 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why a world state is inevitable
    • In particular, this concern is fed by
    • In particular, this concern is fed by Alexander Wendt, 'Why a world state is inevitable', European Journal of International Relations, 9 (2003), pp. 491-542.
    • (2003) European Journal of International Relations , vol.9 , pp. 491-542
    • Wendt, A.1
  • 51
    • 0004205937 scopus 로고
    • See, New York et al.: McGraw-Hill, as still the most prominent example. To our surprise and in contrast to his piece on anarchy
    • See Kenneth N. Waltz, Theory of International Politics (New York et al.: McGraw-Hill, 1979) as still the most prominent example. To our surprise and in contrast to his piece on anarchy (
    • (1979) Theory of International Politics
    • Waltz, K.N.1
  • 52
    • 84972442822 scopus 로고
    • Anarchy is what states make of it: The social construction of power politics
    • see, this increasingly applies to Wendt as well
    • see Alexander Wendt, 'Anarchy is what states make of it: the social construction of power politics', International Organization, 46 (1992), pp. 391-425) this increasingly applies to Wendt as well.
    • (1992) International Organization , vol.46 , pp. 391-425
    • Wendt, A.1
  • 53
    • 0035634512 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Let us now praise great men. Bringing the statesmen back in
    • See, for example
    • See, for example, Daniel L. Byman and Kenneth M. Pollack, 'Let us now praise great men. Bringing the statesmen back in', International Security, 25 (2001), pp. 107-46.
    • (2001) International Security , vol.25 , pp. 107-146
    • Byman, D.L.1    Pollack, K.M.2
  • 55
    • 11144357994 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hegel's house, or "people are states too"
    • At least on the level of the signifier, Jackson see
    • At least on the level of the signifier, Jackson (see Patrick T. Jackson, 'Hegel's House, or "People are states too"', Review of International Studies, 30 (2004), pp. 281-87)
    • (2004) Review of International Studies , vol.30 , pp. 281-287
    • Jackson, P.T.1
  • 56
    • 11144357994 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hegel's house, or "people are states too"
    • seems to strongly emphasise processes as well. But to our minds, his focus on the social processes which create and sustain entities, ibid. does not leave sufficient space for both structures and actors. Due to a different ontology, his idea of process rather resembles something that we try to grasp by means of the category of structure
    • seems to strongly emphasise processes as well. But to our minds, his focus on the social processes which create and sustain entities (Patrick T. Jackson, 'Hegel's House, or "People are states too"', Review of International Studies, 30 (2004), pp. 284) does not leave sufficient space for both structures and actors. Due to a different ontology, his idea of process rather resembles something that we try to grasp by means of the category of structure.
    • (2004) Review of International Studies , vol.30 , pp. 284
    • Jackson, P.T.1
  • 58
    • 33744777532 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Causes of a divided discipline: Rethinking the concept of cause in International Relations theory
    • DOI 10.1017/S026021050600698X, PII S026021050600698X
    • In this context, we will be drawing on Aristotle's differentiation between four types of causes that were only recently restated in a brilliant manner by Kurki. See Milja Kurki, 'Causes of a divided discipline: rethinking the concept of cause in International Relations theory', Review of International Studies, 32 (2006), pp. 189-216. (Pubitemid 43823182)
    • (2006) Review of International Studies , vol.32 , Issue.2 , pp. 189-216
    • Kurki, M.1
  • 59
    • 79953029016 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • According to our understanding, state structures show no 'active causal' effects in the sense of Aristotle and Kurki. However, although we hold that structures of corporate practice do not have causal effects, we do not state that there are no causal powers in the social world at all. But as driving forces of social processes, causal powers, due to the temporal differentiation between 'I' and 'me' established by G. H. Mead, always emanate from human beings see also the characterisation of the process-part of our model below
    • According to our understanding, state structures show no 'active causal' effects in the sense of Aristotle and Kurki. However, although we hold that structures of corporate practice do not have causal effects, we do not state that there are no causal powers in the social world at all. But as driving forces of social processes, causal powers, due to the temporal differentiation between 'I' and 'me' established by G. H. Mead, always emanate from human beings (see also the characterisation of the process-part of our model below).
  • 60
  • 62
    • 33751160126 scopus 로고
    • See, edited by Philip P. Wiener New York: Dover Publications, 'Consider what effects that might conceivably have practical bearing you conceive the object of your conception to have. Then your conception of those effects is the WHOLE of your conception of the object; emphasis in original
    • See Charles Sanders Peirce, Selected Writings: values in a universe of chance, edited by Philip P. Wiener (New York: Dover Publications, 1966 [1958]), p. 192: 'Consider what effects that might conceivably have practical bearing you conceive the object of your conception to have. Then your conception of those effects is the WHOLE of your conception of the object; (emphasis in original).
    • (1958) Selected Writings: Values in a Universe of Chance , pp. 192
    • Peirce, C.S.1
  • 64
    • 0003348607 scopus 로고
    • The public and its problems
    • See, in John Dewey ed., Edited by Jo Ann Boydston Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press
    • See John Dewey, 'The Public and Its Problems', in John Dewey (ed.), The Later Works, 1925-53, Vol. 2:1925-1927. Edited by Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1984 [1927]).
    • (1927) The Later Works, 1925-53 , vol.2 , pp. 1925-1927
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 65
    • 79953025509 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What we call an 'actor' here is often referred to as 'agent' or 'person' in the literature. Since it is not always clear what each concept exactly stands for, we are going to use the same term for the same analytical object throughout the whole article
    • What we call an 'actor' here is often referred to as 'agent' or 'person' in the literature. Since it is not always clear what each concept exactly stands for, we are going to use the same term for the same analytical object throughout the whole article.
  • 66
    • 0032354630 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What is agency?
    • It is exactly this competence to act that termed as 'agency' can be found in a growing part of the literature, occasionally making things more complicate than they were by equating agency with actor. For a comprehensive discussion of the term agency and its history of effects, however, see
    • It is exactly this competence to act that termed as 'agency' can be found in a growing part of the literature, occasionally making things more complicate than they were by equating agency with actor. For a comprehensive discussion of the term agency and its history (of effects), however, see Mustafa Emirbayer and Ann Mische, 'What is agency?', American Journal of Sociology, 103 (1998), pp. 962-1023.
    • (1998) American Journal of Sociology , vol.103 , pp. 962-1023
    • Emirbayer, M.1    Mische, A.2
  • 68
    • 79953024887 scopus 로고
    • unpublished work of George Herbert Mead, edited with an introduction by David L. Miller London, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press
    • and George Herbert Mead, The individual and the social self: unpublished work of George Herbert Mead, edited with an introduction by David L. Miller (London, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1982), p. 177.
    • (1982) The Individual and the Social Self , pp. 177
    • Mead, G.H.1
  • 70
    • 79953028102 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See
    • See Kurki, 'Causes', p. 206.
    • Causes , pp. 206
    • Kurki1
  • 72
    • 0032285704 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On constitution and causation in international relations
    • See
    • See Alexander Wendt, 'On constitution and causation in International Relations', Review of International Studies, 24 (1998), p. 105.
    • (1998) Review of International Studies , vol.24 , pp. 105
    • Wendt, A.1
  • 73
    • 79953026946 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In this context, it might of course also be useful to study varying rules for action on the level of a certain SCP's leading personnel
    • In this context, it might of course also be useful to study varying rules for action on the level of a certain SCP's leading personnel.
  • 74
    • 85055303535 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Die via media als konstitutionstheoretische einbahnstraße. Zur entwicklung des akteur-struktur-problems bei alexander wendt
    • Just as in the context of rejecting the state personhood concept, it is important to note that we do not claim to be the first to present a process model of international relations. While believing that Wendt's model does not leave enough room for open processes but provides a closed system with pre-determined outcomes instead, we are aware of certain parallels between our model and the proposals by Herborth, Jackson and Nexon, as well Patomäki. See
    • Just as in the context of rejecting the state personhood concept, it is important to note that we do not claim to be the first to present a process model of international relations. While believing that Wendt's model does not leave enough room for open processes but provides a closed system with pre-determined outcomes instead, we are aware of certain parallels between our model and the proposals by Herborth, Jackson and Nexon, as well Patomäki. See Benjamin Herborth, 'Die via media als konstitutionstheoretische Einbahnstraße. Zur Entwicklung des Akteur-Struktur-Problems bei Alexander Wendt', Zeitschrift für Internationale Beziehungen, 11 (2004), pp. 61-88;
    • (2004) Zeitschrift für Internationale Beziehungen , vol.11 , pp. 61-88
    • Herborth, B.1
  • 75
    • 0033196158 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Relations before states: Substance, process, and the study of world politics
    • Patrick T. Jackson and Daniel Nexon, 'Relations Before States: Substance, Process, and the Study of World Politics', European Journal of International Relations, 5 (1999), pp. 291-332;
    • (1999) European Journal of International Relations , vol.5 , pp. 291-332
    • Jackson, P.T.1    Nexon, D.2
  • 76
  • 77
    • 33748418823 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The continuity of change, or a change in continuity?
    • Concerning the record of theoretical explanations, we side with Wight who states: 'There is a real need for the development of theoretical accounts able to locate the continuity of change and the change in continuity.' See
    • Concerning the record of theoretical explanations, we side with Wight who states: 'There is a real need for the development of theoretical accounts able to locate the continuity of change and the change in continuity.' See Colin Wight, 'The Continuity of Change, or a Change in Continuity?', International Studies Review, 3 (2001), pp. 81-90.
    • (2001) International Studies Review , vol.3 , pp. 81-90
    • Wight, C.1
  • 78
    • 79953025850 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Even though all of these forms of continuity and change were stated in the mode of transformation and change, continuity is not precluded from this scheme. Due to the dialectical relationship between the two phenomena, not to discover a change in any of these forms always means continuity
    • Even though all of these forms of continuity and change were stated in the mode of transformation and change, continuity is not precluded from this scheme. Due to the dialectical relationship between the two phenomena, not to discover a change in any of these forms always means continuity.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.