메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 24, Issue 4, 1998, Pages 101-114

On constitution and causation in international relations

(1)  Wendt, Alexander a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0032285704     PISSN: 02602105     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/s0260210598001028     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (308)

References (52)
  • 1
    • 0039110037 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • These labels are far from ideal, since in the strict 'logical', sense 'positivism' has been dead in the philosophy of science for decades, and as such all contemporary epistemologies are 'post'-positivist. However, they are the terms in which the current debate in International Relations about the epistemological status of social science is being carried out and as such I reluctantly adopt them here.
  • 2
    • 0000001307 scopus 로고
    • The third debate: On the prospects of international theory in a post-positivist era
    • For a good overview of the Third Debate, see Yosef Lapid, 'The Third Debate: On the Prospects of International Theory in a Post-positivist Era', International Studies Quarterly, 33 (1989), pp. 235-54, and the subsequent commentaries in the same journal. On the Second Debate see, for example, Hedley Bull, 'International theory: The Case for a Classical Approach', in K. Knorr and J. Rosenau (eds.), Contending Approaches to International Politics (Princeton, NJ: 1969), and Morton Kaplan, 'The New Great Debate: Traditionalism vs. Science in International Relations', Ibid.
    • (1989) International Studies Quarterly , vol.33 , pp. 235-254
    • Lapid, Y.1
  • 3
    • 0003117897 scopus 로고
    • International theory: The case for a classical approach
    • K. Knorr and J. Rosenau (eds.), Princeton, NJ
    • For a good overview of the Third Debate, see Yosef Lapid, 'The Third Debate: On the Prospects of International Theory in a Post-positivist Era', International Studies Quarterly, 33 (1989), pp. 235-54, and the subsequent commentaries in the same journal. On the Second Debate see, for example, Hedley Bull, 'International theory: The Case for a Classical Approach', in K. Knorr and J. Rosenau (eds.), Contending Approaches to International Politics (Princeton, NJ: 1969), and Morton Kaplan, 'The New Great Debate: Traditionalism vs. Science in International Relations', Ibid.
    • (1969) Contending Approaches to International Politics
    • Bull, H.1
  • 4
    • 84878870873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The new great debate: Traditionalism vs. science in international relations
    • Princeton, NJ
    • For a good overview of the Third Debate, see Yosef Lapid, 'The Third Debate: On the Prospects of International Theory in a Post-positivist Era', International Studies Quarterly, 33 (1989), pp. 235-54, and the subsequent commentaries in the same journal. On the Second Debate see, for example, Hedley Bull, 'International theory: The Case for a Classical Approach', in K. Knorr and J. Rosenau (eds.), Contending Approaches to International Politics (Princeton, NJ: 1969), and Morton Kaplan, 'The New Great Debate: Traditionalism vs. Science in International Relations', Ibid.
    • Contending Approaches to International Politics
    • Kaplan, M.1
  • 5
    • 0040294118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scientific realism and social kinds
    • ch. 2 Cambridge
    • For a broader exploration, see 'Scientific Realism and Social Kinds', ch. 2 in Wendt, Social Theory of International Politics (Cambridge, 1999).
    • (1999) Social Theory of International Politics
    • Wendt1
  • 7
    • 84974040512 scopus 로고
    • Bridging the theory/metatheory gap in international relations
    • The author addressed the ontological aspects of this book in 'Bridging the Theory/Metatheory Gap in International Relations', Review of International Studies, 17 (1991), pp. 383-92, which was followed by a reply from Hollis and Smith, 'Beware of Gurus: Structure and Action in International Relations', Ibid., pp. 393-410, and a further exchange in 1992. Here I take up its epistemological aspects, which I had set aside in my 1991 review.
    • (1991) Review of International Studies , vol.17 , pp. 383-392
  • 8
    • 84974047650 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beware of gurus: Structure and action in international relations
    • The author addressed the ontological aspects of this book in 'Bridging the Theory/Metatheory Gap in International Relations', Review of International Studies, 17 (1991), pp. 383-92, which was followed by a reply from Hollis and Smith, 'Beware of Gurus: Structure and Action in International Relations', Ibid., pp. 393-410, and a further exchange in 1992. Here I take up its epistemological aspects, which I had set aside in my 1991 review.
    • Review of International Studies , pp. 393-410
    • Hollis1    Smith2
  • 11
    • 0040294108 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • First as a student of his in graduate school and then through several unpublished manuscripts on the logic of constitutive inquiry which he co-authored with Stephen Majeski, most recently 'Modeling Theories of Constitutive Relations in Polities' (1998); for an earlier approach, see David Sylvan and Barry Glassner, A Rationalist Methodology for the Social Sciences (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985). Two other key sources for thinking about constitutive theory are Friedrich Kratochwil, Rules, Norms and Decisions (Cambridge, 1989) and Nicholas Onuf, World of Our Making (Columbia, SC, 1989). And although using other terminology, much the same kind of argument has long been advanced by Hayward Alker; see Rediscoveries and Reformulations (Cambridge, 1996). Use of the term 'constitutive' to describe this kind of theory seems to be gaining ground, as evidenced by Steve Smith's 'The Self-images of a Discipline: A Genealogy of International Relations Theory', in K. Booth and S. Smith (eds.), International Relations Theory Today (Cambridge, 1995), pp. 26-8.
    • (1998) Modeling Theories of Constitutive Relations in Polities
    • Majeski, S.1
  • 12
    • 84934922288 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • First as a student of his in graduate school and then through several unpublished manuscripts on the logic of constitutive inquiry which he co-authored with Stephen Majeski, most recently 'Modeling Theories of Constitutive Relations in Polities' (1998); for an earlier approach, see David Sylvan and Barry Glassner, A Rationalist Methodology for the Social Sciences (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985). Two other key sources for thinking about constitutive theory are Friedrich Kratochwil, Rules, Norms and Decisions (Cambridge, 1989) and Nicholas Onuf, World of Our Making (Columbia, SC, 1989). And although using other terminology, much the same kind of argument has long been advanced by Hayward Alker; see Rediscoveries and Reformulations (Cambridge, 1996). Use of the term 'constitutive' to describe this kind of theory seems to be gaining ground, as evidenced by Steve Smith's 'The Self-images of a Discipline: A Genealogy of International Relations Theory', in K. Booth and S. Smith (eds.), International Relations Theory Today (Cambridge, 1995), pp. 26-8.
    • (1985) A Rationalist Methodology for the Social Sciences
    • Sylvan, D.1    Glassner, B.2
  • 13
    • 0004142397 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • First as a student of his in graduate school and then through several unpublished manuscripts on the logic of constitutive inquiry which he co-authored with Stephen Majeski, most recently 'Modeling Theories of Constitutive Relations in Polities' (1998); for an earlier approach, see David Sylvan and Barry Glassner, A Rationalist Methodology for the Social Sciences (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985). Two other key sources for thinking about constitutive theory are Friedrich Kratochwil, Rules, Norms and Decisions (Cambridge, 1989) and Nicholas Onuf, World of Our Making (Columbia, SC, 1989). And although using other terminology, much the same kind of argument has long been advanced by Hayward Alker; see Rediscoveries and Reformulations (Cambridge, 1996). Use of the term 'constitutive' to describe this kind of theory seems to be gaining ground, as evidenced by Steve Smith's 'The Self-images of a Discipline: A Genealogy of International Relations Theory', in K. Booth and S. Smith (eds.), International Relations Theory Today (Cambridge, 1995), pp. 26-8.
    • (1989) Rules, Norms and Decisions
    • Kratochwil, F.1
  • 14
    • 0003579955 scopus 로고
    • Columbia, SC
    • First as a student of his in graduate school and then through several unpublished manuscripts on the logic of constitutive inquiry which he co-authored with Stephen Majeski, most recently 'Modeling Theories of Constitutive Relations in Polities' (1998); for an earlier approach, see David Sylvan and Barry Glassner, A Rationalist Methodology for the Social Sciences (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985). Two other key sources for thinking about constitutive theory are Friedrich Kratochwil, Rules, Norms and Decisions (Cambridge, 1989) and Nicholas Onuf, World of Our Making (Columbia, SC, 1989). And although using other terminology, much the same kind of argument has long been advanced by Hayward Alker; see Rediscoveries and Reformulations (Cambridge, 1996). Use of the term 'constitutive' to describe this kind of theory seems to be gaining ground, as evidenced by Steve Smith's 'The Self-images of a Discipline: A Genealogy of International Relations Theory', in K. Booth and S. Smith (eds.), International Relations Theory Today (Cambridge, 1995), pp. 26-8.
    • (1989) World of Our Making
    • Onuf, N.1
  • 15
    • 0009260427 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • First as a student of his in graduate school and then through several unpublished manuscripts on the logic of constitutive inquiry which he co-authored with Stephen Majeski, most recently 'Modeling Theories of Constitutive Relations in Polities' (1998); for an earlier approach, see David Sylvan and Barry Glassner, A Rationalist Methodology for the Social Sciences (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985). Two other key sources for thinking about constitutive theory are Friedrich Kratochwil, Rules, Norms and Decisions (Cambridge, 1989) and Nicholas Onuf, World of Our Making (Columbia, SC, 1989). And although using other terminology, much the same kind of argument has long been advanced by Hayward Alker; see Rediscoveries and Reformulations (Cambridge, 1996). Use of the term 'constitutive' to describe this kind of theory seems to be gaining ground, as evidenced by Steve Smith's 'The Self-images of a Discipline: A Genealogy of International Relations Theory', in K. Booth and S. Smith (eds.), International Relations Theory Today (Cambridge, 1995), pp. 26-8.
    • (1996) Rediscoveries and Reformulations
    • Alker, H.1
  • 16
    • 0003112133 scopus 로고
    • The self-images of a discipline: A genealogy of international relations theory
    • K. Booth and S. Smith (eds.), Cambridge
    • First as a student of his in graduate school and then through several unpublished manuscripts on the logic of constitutive inquiry which he co-authored with Stephen Majeski, most recently 'Modeling Theories of Constitutive Relations in Polities' (1998); for an earlier approach, see David Sylvan and Barry Glassner, A Rationalist Methodology for the Social Sciences (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985). Two other key sources for thinking about constitutive theory are Friedrich Kratochwil, Rules, Norms and Decisions (Cambridge, 1989) and Nicholas Onuf, World of Our Making (Columbia, SC, 1989). And although using other terminology, much the same kind of argument has long been advanced by Hayward Alker; see Rediscoveries and Reformulations (Cambridge, 1996). Use of the term 'constitutive' to describe this kind of theory seems to be gaining ground, as evidenced by Steve Smith's 'The Self-images of a Discipline: A Genealogy of International Relations Theory', in K. Booth and S. Smith (eds.), International Relations Theory Today (Cambridge, 1995), pp. 26-8.
    • (1995) International Relations Theory Today , pp. 26-28
    • Smith, S.1
  • 19
    • 0040294103 scopus 로고
    • Explanation and the theory of questions
    • See, for example, Charles Cross, 'Explanation and the Theory of Questions', Erkenntnis, 34 (1991), pp. 237-60.
    • (1991) Erkenntnis , vol.34 , pp. 237-260
    • Cross, C.1
  • 20
    • 0003472528 scopus 로고
    • London
    • For discussion of these competing views of causal explanation, see Russell Keat and John Urry, Social Theory as Science, 2nd edn (London, 1982), and Ernan McMullin, 'Two Ideals of Explanation in Natural Science', in P. French, et al. (eds.), Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. 9 (Minneapolis, MN, 1984), pp. 205-20.
    • (1982) Social Theory as Science, 2nd Edn
    • Keat, R.1    Urry, J.2
  • 21
    • 84985346435 scopus 로고
    • Two ideals of explanation in natural science
    • P. French, et al. (eds.), Minneapolis, MN
    • For discussion of these competing views of causal explanation, see Russell Keat and John Urry, Social Theory as Science, 2nd edn (London, 1982), and Ernan McMullin, 'Two Ideals of Explanation in Natural Science', in P. French, et al. (eds.), Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. 9 (Minneapolis, MN, 1984), pp. 205-20.
    • (1984) Midwest Studies in Philosophy , vol.9 , pp. 205-220
    • McMullin, E.1
  • 26
    • 0040294106 scopus 로고
    • Is statistical inference appropriate to structuralism?
    • For a good discussion of how behavioural methods and language relate to constitutive theorizing, see David Sylvan and Barry Glassner, 'Is Statistical Inference Appropriate to Structuralism?', Quality and Quantity, 17 (1983), pp. 69-86.
    • (1983) Quality and Quantity , vol.17 , pp. 69-86
    • Sylvan, D.1    Glassner, B.2
  • 27
    • 0001576897 scopus 로고
    • Realism and antirealism in social science
    • The phrase 'tacit realism' is Mario Bunge's in 'Realism and Antirealism in Social Science', Theory and Decision, 35 (1993). pp. 207-35. A similar argument is made by Linda Alcoff about Foucault's work in 'Foucault as Epistemologist', The Philosophical Forum, 25 (1993), pp. 95-124.
    • (1993) Theory and Decision , vol.35 , pp. 207-235
    • Bunge, M.1
  • 28
    • 0001576897 scopus 로고
    • Foucault as epistemologist
    • The phrase 'tacit realism' is Mario Bunge's in 'Realism and Antirealism in Social Science', Theory and Decision, 35 (1993). pp. 207-35. A similar argument is made by Linda Alcoff about Foucault's work in 'Foucault as Epistemologist', The Philosophical Forum, 25 (1993), pp. 95-124.
    • (1993) The Philosophical Forum , vol.25 , pp. 95-124
    • Alcoff, L.1
  • 29
    • 0000824398 scopus 로고
    • Actions, reasons, and causes
    • For perhaps the definitive statement of how ideas, in the form of reasons, can have causal effects on behaviour see Donald Davidson, 'Actions, Reasons, and Causes', Journal of Philosophy, 60 (1963), pp. 685-700. In saying that reasons can be causes I am taking one side in a debate about what remains a controversial issue; for an opposing, Wittgensteinian, view see David Rubenstein, 'The Concept of Action in the Social Sciences', Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 7 (1977), pp. 209-36. On the causal role of ideas in international politics, see especially Judith Goldstein and Robert Keohane (eds.), Ideas and Foreign Policy (Ithaca, NY, 1993).
    • (1963) Journal of Philosophy , vol.60 , pp. 685-700
    • Davidson, D.1
  • 30
    • 84981477797 scopus 로고
    • The concept of action in the social sciences
    • For perhaps the definitive statement of how ideas, in the form of reasons, can have causal effects on behaviour see Donald Davidson, 'Actions, Reasons, and Causes', Journal of Philosophy, 60 (1963), pp. 685-700. In saying that reasons can be causes I am taking one side in a debate about what remains a controversial issue; for an opposing, Wittgensteinian, view see David Rubenstein, 'The Concept of Action in the Social Sciences', Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 7 (1977), pp. 209-36. On the causal role of ideas in international politics, see especially Judith Goldstein and Robert Keohane (eds.), Ideas and Foreign Policy (Ithaca, NY, 1993).
    • (1977) Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour , vol.7 , pp. 209-236
    • Rubenstein, D.1
  • 31
    • 0003463272 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, NY
    • For perhaps the definitive statement of how ideas, in the form of reasons, can have causal effects on behaviour see Donald Davidson, 'Actions, Reasons, and Causes', Journal of Philosophy, 60 (1963), pp. 685-700. In saying that reasons can be causes I am taking one side in a debate about what remains a controversial issue; for an opposing, Wittgensteinian, view see David Rubenstein, 'The Concept of Action in the Social Sciences', Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 7 (1977), pp. 209-36. On the causal role of ideas in international politics, see especially Judith Goldstein and Robert Keohane (eds.), Ideas and Foreign Policy (Ithaca, NY, 1993).
    • (1993) Ideas and Foreign Policy
    • Goldstein, J.1    Keohane, R.2
  • 32
    • 0018050318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The nature and plausibility of cognitivism
    • See John Haugeland, 'The Nature and Plausibility of Cognitivism', The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 2 (1978), p. 216, and Cummins, 1983, p. 15.
    • (1978) The Behavioral and Brain Sciences , vol.2 , pp. 216
    • Haugeland, J.1
  • 33
    • 0018050318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cummins, 1983, p. 15
    • See John Haugeland, 'The Nature and Plausibility of Cognitivism', The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 2 (1978), p. 216, and Cummins, 1983, p. 15.
  • 34
    • 84925920743 scopus 로고
    • On the reification of social structure
    • S. McNall and G. Howe (eds.), Greenwich, CT
    • On this conception of reification, see Douglas Maynard and Thomas Wilson, 'On the Reification of Social Structure', in S. McNall and G. Howe (eds.), Current Perspectives in Social Theory, vol. 1 (Greenwich, CT, 1980), pp. 287-322, and also Peter Berger and Thomas Luckmann, The Social Construction of Reality (New York, 1966), p. 89.
    • (1980) Current Perspectives in Social Theory , vol.1 , pp. 287-322
    • Maynard, D.1    Wilson, T.2
  • 35
    • 0003458607 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • On this conception of reification, see Douglas Maynard and Thomas Wilson, 'On the Reification of Social Structure', in S. McNall and G. Howe (eds.), Current Perspectives in Social Theory, vol. 1 (Greenwich, CT, 1980), pp. 287-322, and also Peter Berger and Thomas Luckmann, The Social Construction of Reality (New York, 1966), p. 89.
    • (1966) The Social Construction of Reality , pp. 89
    • Berger, P.1    Luckmann, T.2
  • 36
    • 0039110025 scopus 로고
    • "Explaining what" in history'
    • P. Gardiner (ed.), Glencoe, IL
    • William Dray, '"Explaining what" in history', in P. Gardiner (ed.), Theories of History (Glencoe, IL, 1959), and Philosophy of History (Englewood Cliffs, NJ, 1964). For a contemporary critique of Dray's position, see Richard Reiner, 'Necessary conditions and explaining how-possibly', The Philosophical Quarterly, 43 (1993), pp. 58-69.
    • (1959) Theories of History
    • Dray, W.1
  • 37
    • 0007041254 scopus 로고
    • Englewood Cliffs, NJ
    • William Dray, '"Explaining what" in history', in P. Gardiner (ed.), Theories of History (Glencoe, IL, 1959), and Philosophy of History (Englewood Cliffs, NJ, 1964). For a contemporary critique of Dray's position, see Richard Reiner, 'Necessary conditions and explaining how-possibly', The Philosophical Quarterly, 43 (1993), pp. 58-69.
    • (1964) Philosophy of History
  • 38
    • 84963024041 scopus 로고
    • Necessary conditions and explaining how-possibly
    • William Dray, '"Explaining what" in history', in P. Gardiner (ed.), Theories of History (Glencoe, IL, 1959), and Philosophy of History (Englewood Cliffs, NJ, 1964). For a contemporary critique of Dray's position, see Richard Reiner, 'Necessary conditions and explaining how-possibly', The Philosophical Quarterly, 43 (1993), pp. 58-69.
    • (1993) The Philosophical Quarterly , vol.43 , pp. 58-69
    • Reiner, R.1
  • 39
    • 84970761759 scopus 로고
    • Economic models and historical explanation
    • Steven Rappaport, 'Economic Models and Historical Explanation', Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 25 (1995), pp. 421-41. For a good overview of the role of unification in scientific explanation more generally see Philip Kitcher, 'Explanatory Unification and the Causal Structure of the World', in P. Kitcher and W. Salmon (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 13 (Minneapolis, MN, 1989), pp. 410-505.
    • (1995) Philosophy of the Social Sciences , vol.25 , pp. 421-441
    • Rappaport, S.1
  • 40
    • 84970761759 scopus 로고
    • Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world
    • P. Kitcher and W. Salmon (eds.), Minneapolis, MN
    • Steven Rappaport, 'Economic Models and Historical Explanation', Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 25 (1995), pp. 421-41. For a good overview of the role of unification in scientific explanation more generally see Philip Kitcher, 'Explanatory Unification and the Causal Structure of the World', in P. Kitcher and W. Salmon (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 13 (Minneapolis, MN, 1989), pp. 410-505.
    • (1989) Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science , vol.13 , pp. 410-505
    • Kitcher, P.1
  • 42
    • 0040888349 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cummins, p. 18
    • Cummins, p. 18.
  • 45
    • 0004794834 scopus 로고
    • Structural explanation
    • This usage is different to Kenneth Waltz's in Theory of International Politics, but compatible with the idea of 'structural' explanation. See Ernan McMullin, 'Structural Explanation', American Philosophical Quarterly, 15 (1978), pp. 139-47.
    • (1978) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.15 , pp. 139-147
    • McMullin, E.1
  • 46
    • 0039702240 scopus 로고
    • Is essentialism unscientific?
    • See Jarrett Leplin, 'Is Essentialism Unscientific?', Philosophy of Science, 55 (1988), pp. 493-510. For doubts about the claim that an essentialist strategy is necessary in the natural sciences see Paul Teller, 'Relational Holism and Quantum Mechanics', British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 37 (1986), pp. 71-81, and for a thoughtful discussion of essentialism in the social sciences, see Andrew Sayer, 'Essentialism, Social Constructionism, and Beyond', Sociological Review, 45 (1997), 453-87.
    • (1988) Philosophy of Science , vol.55 , pp. 493-510
    • Leplin, J.1
  • 47
    • 84936153873 scopus 로고
    • Relational holism and quantum mechanics
    • See Jarrett Leplin, 'Is Essentialism Unscientific?', Philosophy of Science, 55 (1988), pp. 493-510. For doubts about the claim that an essentialist strategy is necessary in the natural sciences see Paul Teller, 'Relational Holism and Quantum Mechanics', British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 37 (1986), pp. 71-81, and for a thoughtful discussion of essentialism in the social sciences, see Andrew Sayer, 'Essentialism, Social Constructionism, and Beyond', Sociological Review, 45 (1997), 453-87.
    • (1986) British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , vol.37 , pp. 71-81
    • Teller, P.1
  • 48
    • 0005858020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Essentialism, social constructionism, and beyond
    • See Jarrett Leplin, 'Is Essentialism Unscientific?', Philosophy of Science, 55 (1988), pp. 493-510. For doubts about the claim that an essentialist strategy is necessary in the natural sciences see Paul Teller, 'Relational Holism and Quantum Mechanics', British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 37 (1986), pp. 71-81, and for a thoughtful discussion of essentialism in the social sciences, see Andrew Sayer, 'Essentialism, Social Constructionism, and Beyond', Sociological Review, 45 (1997), 453-87.
    • (1997) Sociological Review , vol.45 , pp. 453-487
    • Sayer, A.1
  • 50
    • 0004032873 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • For a systematic development of this idea, see Bertell Ollman, Alienation (Cambridge, 1971).
    • (1971) Alienation
    • Ollman, B.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.