-
1
-
-
79251602945
-
Counterattack and counterpoint
-
(August 13, )
-
"Counterattack and Counterpoint," Time (August 13, 1973).
-
(1973)
Time
-
-
-
2
-
-
79251643757
-
-
Here is what the transcript of the March 21, 1973, tape says: "president: How much money do you need? dean: I would say these people are going to cost, uh, a million dollars over the next, uh,-two years. (Pause) president: We could get that. dean: Uh, huh. president: You, on the money, if you need the money, I mean, uh, you could get the money. Let's say- dean: Well, I think that we're going- president: What I mean is, you could, you could get a million dollars. And you could get it in cash. I, I know where it could be gotten. dean: Uh, huh." (Watergate Trial Conversations, Nixon Presidential Library and Museum, )
-
Here is what the transcript of the March 21, 1973, tape says: "president: How much money do you need? dean: I would say these people are going to cost, uh, a million dollars over the next, uh,-two years. (Pause) president: We could get that. dean: Uh, huh. president: You, on the money, if you need the money, I mean, uh, you could get the money. Let's say- dean: Well, I think that we're going- president: What I mean is, you could, you could get a million dollars. And you could get it in cash. I, I know where it could be gotten. dean: Uh, huh." (Watergate Trial Conversations, Nixon Presidential Library and Museum, http://nixon.archives.gov/forresearchers/find/tapes/ watergate/ trial/transcripts.php.)
-
-
-
-
3
-
-
0003867020
-
-
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, )
-
See T. M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998), 11;
-
(1998)
What We Owe to Each Other
, pp. 11
-
-
Scanlon, T.M.1
-
4
-
-
4544315326
-
Should we pass the buck?
-
ed. Anthony O'Hear, supp. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, )
-
Jonathan Dancy, "Should We Pass the Buck?" in Philosophy, the Good, the True, and the Beautiful, ed. Anthony O'Hear, supp. vol. 47 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000): 159-73;
-
(2000)
Philosophy, the Good, the True, and the Beautiful
, vol.47
, pp. 159-173
-
-
Dancy, J.1
-
5
-
-
58749090441
-
Scanlon's contractualism and the redundancy objection
-
Philip Stratton-Lake, "Scanlon's Contractualism and the Redundancy Objection," Analysis 63, no. 1 (2003): 70-76;
-
(2003)
Analysis
, vol.63
, Issue.1
, pp. 70-76
-
-
Stratton-Lake, P.1
-
6
-
-
77952288413
-
The good and the right
-
Michael J. Zimmerman, "The Good and the Right," Utilitas 19, no. 3 (2007): 326-53;
-
(2007)
Utilitas
, vol.19
, Issue.3
, pp. 326-353
-
-
Zimmerman, M.J.1
-
7
-
-
77953343018
-
Wrongness and reasons: A re-examination
-
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, )
-
T. M. Scanlon, "Wrongness and Reasons: A Re-examination," Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol. 2 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 5-20.
-
(2007)
Oxford Studies in Metaethics
, vol.2
, pp. 5-20
-
-
Scanlon, T.M.1
-
8
-
-
79251601684
-
-
These include Dancy, Stratton-Lake, and Zimmerman (see previous note)
-
These include Dancy, Stratton-Lake, and Zimmerman (see previous note).
-
-
-
-
9
-
-
79251623647
-
-
The latter term derives from Dancy, "Should We Pass the Buck?" When I speak of "good-making" or "right-" or "wrong-making" properties in what follows, I will have this sense in mind, namely, grounds or normative reasons for something's value, rightness, or wrongness. We might call this a normative sense, as opposed to a metaphysical sense of good-making or right- or wrong-making features (i.e., the features in which something's being good, right, or wrong consists metaphysically)
-
The latter term derives from Dancy, "Should We Pass the Buck?" When I speak of "good-making" or "right-" or "wrong-making" properties in what follows, I will have this sense in mind, namely, grounds or normative reasons for something's value, rightness, or wrongness. We might call this a normative sense, as opposed to a metaphysical sense of good-making or right- or wrong-making features (i.e., the features in which something's being good, right, or wrong consists metaphysically).
-
-
-
-
10
-
-
79251639432
-
-
I shall be arguing that an act's wrongmaking features in the normative sense (i.e., the grounds of or normative reasons for something's being wrong) do not exhaust the reasons not to perform the wrongful act-that the fact that the act is wrong is itself a reason not to perform it. I should not be understood as claiming that if there is some complex fact or facts in which this latter fact consists metaphysically, the fact that an act is wrong is a reason that is additional to these facts, since, on the hypothesis in question, that is what the fact of an act's being wrong would itself consist in. I have been helped here by discussion with, among others, Janice Dowell and Peter Schulte
-
I shall be arguing that an act's wrongmaking features in the normative sense (i.e., the grounds of or normative reasons for something's being wrong) do not exhaust the reasons not to perform the wrongful act-that the fact that the act is wrong is itself a reason not to perform it. I should not be understood as claiming that if there is some complex fact or facts in which this latter fact consists metaphysically, the fact that an act is wrong is a reason that is additional to these facts, since, on the hypothesis in question, that is what the fact of an act's being wrong would itself consist in. I have been helped here by discussion with, among others, Janice Dowell and Peter Schulte.
-
-
-
-
11
-
-
0003742241
-
-
Cf. Michael Smith on the de dicto desire to avoid wrongdoing as opposed to de re desires to avoid actions of wrong-making kinds, (Oxford: Blackwell, )
-
Cf. Michael Smith on the de dicto desire to avoid wrongdoing as opposed to de re desires to avoid actions of wrong-making kinds: Michael Smith, The Moral Problem (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), 75-76.
-
(1994)
The Moral Problem
, pp. 75-76
-
-
Smith, M.1
-
13
-
-
79251635998
-
-
I take this to be a more pointed version of the first line of thought mentioned above
-
I take this to be a more pointed version of the first line of thought mentioned above.
-
-
-
-
15
-
-
79251634758
-
-
That is, why not think that moral wrongness passes the buck to features that are wrong-making in the sense of providing normative grounds of an act's wrongness? This differs from any features that might be wrong-making in the sense of being what an action's being wrong consists in metaphysically
-
That is, why not think that moral wrongness passes the buck to features that are wrong-making in the sense of providing normative grounds of an act's wrongness? This differs from any features that might be wrong-making in the sense of being what an action's being wrong consists in metaphysically.
-
-
-
-
17
-
-
77953343018
-
Wrongness and reasons: A re-examination
-
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, )
-
T. M. Scanlon, "Wrongness and Reasons: A Re-examination," Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol. 2 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 5-20.
-
(2007)
Oxford Studies in Metaethics
, vol.2
, pp. 5-20
-
-
Scanlon, T.M.1
-
18
-
-
79251642528
-
-
See note 5 above
-
See note 5 above.
-
-
-
-
21
-
-
35148879560
-
-
I defend this analysis in greater detail in, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, )
-
I defend this analysis in greater detail in The Second-Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2006).
-
(2006)
The Second-Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability
-
-
-
22
-
-
79251620988
-
-
In my view, the warranted-attitude theory (or, more specifically, the fitting-attitude theory, which I shall discuss presently) is the most plausible approach to analyzing normative concepts. It is not necessary to the argument of this essay, however, that it actually succeeds. We shall simply assume that it does succeed as the most plausible line of thought leading to the view that wrongness is not itself a reason for acting
-
In my view, the warranted-attitude theory (or, more specifically, the fitting-attitude theory, which I shall discuss presently) is the most plausible approach to analyzing normative concepts. It is not necessary to the argument of this essay, however, that it actually succeeds. We shall simply assume that it does succeed as the most plausible line of thought leading to the view that wrongness is not itself a reason for acting.
-
-
-
-
23
-
-
79251640934
-
-
My point will be that accepting a fitting-attitude theory of wrongness would not commit us to this. To the contrary, on the fitting-attitude theory of wrongness that I shall propose, wrongness is indeed itself a practical reason
-
My point will be that accepting a fitting-attitude theory of wrongness would not commit us to this. To the contrary, on the fitting-attitude theory of wrongness that I shall propose, wrongness is indeed itself a practical reason.
-
-
-
-
24
-
-
60949180215
-
Knowing what to do, seeing what to do
-
ed. Philip Stratton-Lake (Oxford: Oxford University Press, )
-
Allan Gibbard, "Knowing What to Do, Seeing What to Do," in Ethical Intuitionism: Re-evaluations, ed. Philip Stratton-Lake (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), 212.
-
(2003)
Ethical Intuitionism: Re-evaluations
, pp. 212
-
-
Gibbard, A.1
-
25
-
-
32644490266
-
Suggested non-naturalistic analysis of good
-
A. C. Ewing, "Suggested Non-Naturalistic Analysis of Good," Mind 48 (1939): 1-22;
-
(1939)
Mind
, vol.48
, pp. 1-22
-
-
Ewing, A.C.1
-
28
-
-
0003541293
-
-
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, )
-
Allan Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990), 7.
-
(1990)
Wise Choices, Apt Feelings
, pp. 7
-
-
Gibbard, A.1
-
29
-
-
48449094357
-
Just plain 'ought'
-
See also
-
See also Owen McLeod, "Just Plain 'Ought'," The Journal of Ethics 5 (2001): 269-91.
-
(2001)
The Journal of Ethics
, vol.5
, pp. 269-291
-
-
McLeod, O.1
-
30
-
-
0040350680
-
The moralistic fallacy: On the 'appropriateness' of emotions
-
Justin D'Arms and Daniel Jacobson, "The Moralistic Fallacy: On the 'Appropriateness' of Emotions," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61 (2000): 65-90;
-
(2000)
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
, vol.61
, pp. 65-90
-
-
D'Arms, J.1
Jacobson, D.2
-
31
-
-
0039592585
-
Sentiment and value
-
Justin D'Arms and Daniel Jacobson, "Sentiment and Value," Ethics 110 (2000): 722-48;
-
(2000)
Ethics
, vol.110
, pp. 722-748
-
-
D'Arms, J.1
Jacobson, D.2
-
32
-
-
4444324344
-
The strike of the demon: On fitting pro-attitudes and value
-
Wlodek Rabinowicz and Toni Ronnøw-Rasmussen, "The Strike of the Demon: On Fitting Pro-Attitudes and Value," Ethics 114 (2004): 391-423.
-
(2004)
Ethics
, vol.114
, pp. 391-423
-
-
Rabinowicz, W.1
Ronnøw-Rasmussen, T.2
-
33
-
-
79251602700
-
-
The "toxin puzzle" refers to a situation Kavka described in which there is an instrumental reason to form an intention to drink a toxin (e.g., that one would be rewarded if one did), but in which this apparently gives one no reason to act on the intention
-
The "toxin puzzle" refers to a situation Kavka described in which there is an instrumental reason to form an intention to drink a toxin (e.g., that one would be rewarded if one did), but in which this apparently gives one no reason to act on the intention.
-
-
-
-
34
-
-
84959761254
-
The toxin puzzle
-
See Gregory S. Kavka, "The Toxin Puzzle," Analysis 43 (1983): 33-36.
-
(1983)
Analysis
, vol.43
, pp. 33-36
-
-
Kavka, G.S.1
-
36
-
-
79251645202
-
-
For example, it might be a reason not just for a desire to eat an apple, but for a desire to eat an apple on account of its taste
-
For example, it might be a reason not just for a desire to eat an apple, but for a desire to eat an apple on account of its taste. (Rabinowicz and Ronnøw-Rasmussen, "The Strike of the Demon," 414.)
-
The Strike of the Demon
, pp. 414
-
-
Rabinowicz1
Ronnøw-Rasmussen2
-
38
-
-
52549091387
-
-
(Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, )
-
W. D. Falk, Ought, Reasons, and Morality (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1986), 117.
-
(1986)
Ought, Reasons, and Morality
, pp. 117
-
-
Falk, W.D.1
-
39
-
-
34547150589
-
The wrong kind of reason
-
Pamela Hieronymi, "The Wrong Kind of Reason," The Journal of Philosophy 102, no. 9 (2005): 437-57.
-
(2005)
The Journal of Philosophy
, vol.102
, Issue.9
, pp. 437-457
-
-
Hieronymi, P.1
-
42
-
-
0004113926
-
-
For a defense of such a view, see, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, )
-
For a defense of such a view, see Elizabeth Anderson, Value in Ethics and Economics (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990).
-
(1990)
Value in Ethics and Economics
-
-
Anderson, E.1
-
43
-
-
79954857355
-
-
for a parallel argument against holding that wrongness creates an additional reason
-
See Zimmerman, "The Good and the Right," for a parallel argument against holding that wrongness creates an additional reason.
-
The Good and the Right
-
-
Zimmerman1
-
44
-
-
79251649686
-
-
For our purposes, we do not strictly need to suppose that a fitting-attitude theory actually does entail buck-passing about value. The argument of this essay is that even if it were to support buck-passing about the relevant valuing attitudes in this way, a fittingattitude account of wrongness of the sort I will propose would not entail buck-passing about wrongness with respect to reasons for action
-
For our purposes, we do not strictly need to suppose that a fitting-attitude theory actually does entail buck-passing about value. The argument of this essay is that even if it were to support buck-passing about the relevant valuing attitudes in this way, a fittingattitude account of wrongness of the sort I will propose would not entail buck-passing about wrongness with respect to reasons for action.
-
-
-
-
45
-
-
79251602203
-
-
Here again, then, we can just assume that a fitting-attitude theory of value of the sort Scanlon gestures to entails buck-passing about value with respect to the relevant valuing attitudes. I am indebted here to discussion with Ruth Chang
-
Here again, then, we can just assume that a fitting-attitude theory of value of the sort Scanlon gestures to entails buck-passing about value with respect to the relevant valuing attitudes. I am indebted here to discussion with Ruth Chang.
-
-
-
-
47
-
-
79251637582
-
-
There I define a set of secondpersonal concepts, which conceptually involve the idea of claims and demands that can be addressed (to an addressee, second-personally), and I argue that these include the concepts of moral obligation, wrong, rights, the dignity of persons, and the very concept of a moral person (as a subject of obligations)
-
There I define a set of secondpersonal concepts, which conceptually involve the idea of claims and demands that can be addressed (to an addressee, second-personally), and I argue that these include the concepts of moral obligation, wrong, rights, the dignity of persons, and the very concept of a moral person (as a subject of obligations).
-
-
-
-
49
-
-
79251640171
-
-
Strawson uses the term "reactive attitude" to refer to a set of attitudes (which include indignation, resentment, guilt, and moral blame) that implicitly hold their objects responsible and thus regard them in a distinctively interpersonal (as I put it, "second-personal") way. For ease of expression, I will sometimes speak of actions, and not agents, as blameworthy; strictly speaking, however, it is the agent who is appropriately blamed for performing a "blameworthy action" (speaking loosely)
-
Strawson uses the term "reactive attitude" to refer to a set of attitudes (which include indignation, resentment, guilt, and moral blame) that implicitly hold their objects responsible and thus regard them in a distinctively interpersonal (as I put it, "second-personal") way. For ease of expression, I will sometimes speak of actions, and not agents, as blameworthy; strictly speaking, however, it is the agent who is appropriately blamed for performing a "blameworthy action" (speaking loosely).
-
-
-
-
51
-
-
79251618777
-
-
I use "blame" throughout this essay to refer to an attitude rather than to any specific activity or speech act. It is thus possible to blame someone without ever saying anything to him or to anyone. Blame in this sense also differs from a belief or judgment that someone is blameworthy. One might say, for example: "I know that she still blames me for what I did twenty-five years ago, though we haven't talked in many years"
-
I use "blame" throughout this essay to refer to an attitude rather than to any specific activity or speech act. It is thus possible to blame someone without ever saying anything to him or to anyone. Blame in this sense also differs from a belief or judgment that someone is blameworthy. One might say, for example: "I know that she still blames me for what I did twenty-five years ago, though we haven't talked in many years."
-
-
-
-
52
-
-
79251624447
-
-
That is, it cannot provide such a reason on the assumption we have been making, namely, that a fitting-attitude theory of a normative concept entails buck-passing with respect to reasons for the attitudes that the concept conceptually involves
-
That is, it cannot provide such a reason on the assumption we have been making, namely, that a fitting-attitude theory of a normative concept entails buck-passing with respect to reasons for the attitudes that the concept conceptually involves.
-
-
-
-
53
-
-
79251640686
-
-
Again, such features are "estimable-making" in the sense of being normative grounds of something's being estimable, not in the sense of being facts in which the thing's being estimable consists metaphysically
-
Again, such features are "estimable-making" in the sense of being normative grounds of something's being estimable, not in the sense of being facts in which the thing's being estimable consists metaphysically.
-
-
-
-
54
-
-
84884113538
-
-
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, )
-
Stephen Darwall, Welfare and Rational Care (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2002).
-
(2002)
Welfare and Rational Care
-
-
Darwall, S.1
-
55
-
-
79251603450
-
-
By the "moral community," I mean no actual community, but a regulative ideal like Kant's "kingdom of ends." We could as well say that the authority is one we have as representative persons. I am indebted to David Velleman and Samuel Scheffler for discussion on this point
-
By the "moral community," I mean no actual community, but a regulative ideal like Kant's "kingdom of ends." We could as well say that the authority is one we have as representative persons. I am indebted to David Velleman and Samuel Scheffler for discussion on this point.
-
-
-
-
57
-
-
79251637332
-
-
"What I want to contrast is the attitude (or range of attitudes) of involvement or participation in a human relationship, on the one hand, and what might be called the objective attitude (or range of attitudes) to another human being, on the other. . . . To adopt the objective attitude to another human being is to see him, perhaps, as an object of social policy; as a subject for what, in a wide range of sense, might be called treatment; as something certainly to be taken account, perhaps precautionary account, of; to be managed or handled or cured or trained; perhaps simply to be avoided, though this gerundive is not peculiar to cases of objectivity of attitude
-
"What I want to contrast is the attitude (or range of attitudes) of involvement or participation in a human relationship, on the one hand, and what might be called the objective attitude (or range of attitudes) to another human being, on the other. . . . To adopt the objective attitude to another human being is to see him, perhaps, as an object of social policy; as a subject for what, in a wide range of sense, might be called treatment; as something certainly to be taken account, perhaps precautionary account, of; to be managed or handled or cured or trained; perhaps simply to be avoided, though this gerundive is not peculiar to cases of objectivity of attitude.
-
-
-
-
58
-
-
79251638865
-
-
The objective attitude may be emotionally toned in many ways, but not in all ways: it may include repulsion or fear, it may include pity or even love, though not all kinds of love. But it cannot include the range of reactive feelings and attitudes which belong to involvement or participation with others in inter-personal human relationships; it cannot include resentment, gratitude, forgiveness, anger, or the sort of love which two adults can sometimes be said to feel reciprocally, for each other. If your attitude towards someone is wholly objective, then though you may fight him, you cannot quarrel with him, and though you may talk to him, even negotiate with him, you cannot reason with him. You can at most pretend to quarrel, or to reason, with him"
-
The objective attitude may be emotionally toned in many ways, but not in all ways: it may include repulsion or fear, it may include pity or even love, though not all kinds of love. But it cannot include the range of reactive feelings and attitudes which belong to involvement or participation with others in inter-personal human relationships; it cannot include resentment, gratitude, forgiveness, anger, or the sort of love which two adults can sometimes be said to feel reciprocally, for each other. If your attitude towards someone is wholly objective, then though you may fight him, you cannot quarrel with him, and though you may talk to him, even negotiate with him, you cannot reason with him. You can at most pretend to quarrel, or to reason, with him."
-
-
-
-
59
-
-
79251625523
-
-
But might the concepts of moral obligation and moral wrong be analyzed in terms of morally conclusive reasons-a moral obligation being something there is conclusive moral reason to do, and being wrong being something there is conclusive moral reason not to do? But what is it for reasons to be morally conclusive?
-
But might the concepts of moral obligation and moral wrong be analyzed in terms of morally conclusive reasons-a moral obligation being something there is conclusive moral reason to do, and being wrong being something there is conclusive moral reason not to do? But what is it for reasons to be morally conclusive?
-
-
-
-
60
-
-
79251610561
-
-
On the one hand, if we give this an epistemic sense, such that reasons are conclusive if they conclusively establish that a certain act is what morality most recommends, then this really adds nothing to the possibility just canvassed. On the other hand, if reasons are morally conclusive when they warrant a moral requirement or demand, then this possibility amounts to the one I go on to consider presently
-
On the one hand, if we give this an epistemic sense, such that reasons are conclusive if they conclusively establish that a certain act is what morality most recommends, then this really adds nothing to the possibility just canvassed. On the other hand, if reasons are morally conclusive when they warrant a moral requirement or demand, then this possibility amounts to the one I go on to consider presently.
-
-
-
-
61
-
-
79251639681
-
-
In order for there to be some other possibility, we would have to have a notion of morally conclusive reason that we understand independently of the idea of moral requirement or demand, which we could then use to understand this latter idea. I doubt that this is so. I am indebted to Samuel Scheffler for discussion on these points
-
In order for there to be some other possibility, we would have to have a notion of morally conclusive reason that we understand independently of the idea of moral requirement or demand, which we could then use to understand this latter idea. I doubt that this is so. I am indebted to Samuel Scheffler for discussion on these points.
-
-
-
-
62
-
-
79251639140
-
-
For this reason, I argue in The Second-Person Standpoint that the normativity of moral obligation is not adequately captured by the Kantian idea that moral demands are demands of reason. Of course, it could still be the case that what is morally demanded is also demanded by reason. I argue that the most promising line of argument supporting this, indeed, proceeds from a second-personal account of moral obligation's normativity
-
For this reason, I argue in The Second-Person Standpoint that the normativity of moral obligation is not adequately captured by the Kantian idea that moral demands are demands of reason. Of course, it could still be the case that what is morally demanded is also demanded by reason. I argue that the most promising line of argument supporting this, indeed, proceeds from a second-personal account of moral obligation's normativity.
-
-
-
-
63
-
-
79251631758
-
-
Indeed, the very idea of an "excuse" is not internal to the rules of logic; it must be understood in relation to a broader context that includes other norms
-
Indeed, the very idea of an "excuse" is not internal to the rules of logic; it must be understood in relation to a broader context that includes other norms.
-
-
-
-
64
-
-
79251611192
-
-
I do not mean, of course, that logical errors are not subject to criticism, or that we do not sometimes use words like "blame," as when a teacher says that he does not blame his student for a given error on a first try
-
I do not mean, of course, that logical errors are not subject to criticism, or that we do not sometimes use words like "blame," as when a teacher says that he does not blame his student for a given error on a first try.
-
-
-
-
65
-
-
33644780455
-
-
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, ), 29
-
John Skorupski, Ethical Explorations (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 29, 142.
-
(1999)
Ethical Explorations
, pp. 142
-
-
Skorupski, J.1
-
66
-
-
79251603960
-
-
This claim is, however, too strong, since one may not blame someone for acting wrongly if the person has some adequate excuse for doing so
-
This claim is, however, too strong, since one may not blame someone for acting wrongly if the person has some adequate excuse for doing so.
-
-
-
-
73
-
-
79251606609
-
-
In addition to negative personal reactive attitudes, Strawson also mentions gratitude, which he regards as a (positive) personal reactive attitude-an attitude which, in this case, is felt as if from the perspective of a beneficiary
-
In addition to negative personal reactive attitudes, Strawson also mentions gratitude, which he regards as a (positive) personal reactive attitude-an attitude which, in this case, is felt as if from the perspective of a beneficiary.
-
-
-
-
76
-
-
79251604240
-
-
Thus, an attitude can be second-personal in the requisite sense and be third-party or "impersonal" in Strawson's sense. And the phenomenon of guilt shows that it is possible to take a second-personal attitude toward oneself. What makes an attitude second-personal is its having an implicit addressee
-
Thus, an attitude can be second-personal in the requisite sense and be third-party or "impersonal" in Strawson's sense. And the phenomenon of guilt shows that it is possible to take a second-personal attitude toward oneself. What makes an attitude second-personal is its having an implicit addressee.
-
-
-
-
77
-
-
79251627109
-
-
Again, by wrong-making features, I mean features that provide grounds or normative reasons for something's being wrong, not the features, if there are any, in which something's being wrong might consist metaphysically
-
Again, by wrong-making features, I mean features that provide grounds or normative reasons for something's being wrong, not the features, if there are any, in which something's being wrong might consist metaphysically.
-
-
-
-
78
-
-
79251619571
-
-
For convenience, I shall shorten "moral right" to "right"
-
For convenience, I shall shorten "moral right" to "right."
-
-
-
-
79
-
-
79251643756
-
-
I take it that it would be incoherent to assert that one has a right to something but that someone would do no wrong, not even other things being equal, if she were to deprive one of it
-
I take it that it would be incoherent to assert that one has a right to something but that someone would do no wrong, not even other things being equal, if she were to deprive one of it.
-
-
-
-
80
-
-
0003396771
-
-
ed. Walter Wheeler Cook (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, )
-
Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld, Fundamental Legal Conceptions, ed. Walter Wheeler Cook (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1923).
-
(1923)
Fundamental Legal Conceptions
-
-
Hohfeld, W.N.1
-
81
-
-
0007445191
-
The nature and value of rights
-
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, )
-
Joel Feinberg, "The Nature and Value of Rights," in Feinberg, Rights, Justice, and the Bounds of Liberty (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1980), 151.
-
(1980)
Feinberg, Rights, Justice, and the Bounds of Liberty
, pp. 151
-
-
Feinberg, J.1
-
82
-
-
0001501318
-
Kantian constructivism in moral theory
-
John Rawls, "Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory," The Journal of Philosophy 77 (1980): 546.
-
(1980)
The Journal of Philosophy
, vol.77
, pp. 546
-
-
Rawls, J.1
-
84
-
-
84922062307
-
-
For directed obligation, see, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, )
-
For directed obligation, see Margaret Gilbert, A Theory of Political Obligation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), 40;
-
(2006)
A Theory of Political Obligation
, pp. 40
-
-
Gilbert, M.1
-
85
-
-
38949190999
-
What is it to wrong someone? A puzzle about justice
-
And for bipolar obligation, see , ed. R. Jay Wallace et al. (New York: Oxford University Press, )
-
And for bipolar obligation, see Michael Thompson, "What Is It to Wrong Someone? A Puzzle about Justice," in Reason and Value: Themes from the Moral Philosophy of Joseph Raz, ed. R. Jay Wallace et al. (New York: Oxford University Press, 2006).
-
(2006)
Reason and Value: Themes from the Moral Philosophy of Joseph Raz
-
-
Thompson, M.1
-
86
-
-
79251647208
-
-
Again, "the moral community" refers here not to any actual social collectivity but to a regulative ideal like Kant's "kingdom of ends"
-
Again, "the moral community" refers here not to any actual social collectivity but to a regulative ideal like Kant's "kingdom of ends."
-
-
-
-
89
-
-
79251610685
-
-
Thus, if it is a conceptual truth that violations of rights (wrongings) are also, other things being equal, wrongs period-that violations of "bipolar" obligations to someone are also, other things being equal, violations of moral obligations period-then it follows that a personal reactive attitude, such as resentment, can be warranted only if an impersonal reactive attitude would be (at least, other things being equal)
-
Thus, if it is a conceptual truth that violations of rights (wrongings) are also, other things being equal, wrongs period-that violations of "bipolar" obligations to someone are also, other things being equal, violations of moral obligations period-then it follows that a personal reactive attitude, such as resentment, can be warranted only if an impersonal reactive attitude would be (at least, other things being equal).
-
-
-
-
90
-
-
79251608263
-
-
I believe this conceptual thesis is true, but notice that the claim that the fact that an action is wrong is a reason not to perform it (consisting in the fact that the act violates a legitimate demand we make of one another as representative persons) does not strictly depend on this conceptual thesis. I am indebted here to discussion with Verity Harte and Jules Coleman
-
I believe this conceptual thesis is true, but notice that the claim that the fact that an action is wrong is a reason not to perform it (consisting in the fact that the act violates a legitimate demand we make of one another as representative persons) does not strictly depend on this conceptual thesis. I am indebted here to discussion with Verity Harte and Jules Coleman.
-
-
-
-
92
-
-
79251636262
-
-
Or, alternatively, though it violates your right and would be wrong (period) if I lacked this further justification, it is not wrong because the justification exists. What violates someone's rights would be wrong to do lacking some justification, just as what is wrong would be blameworthy if done without adequate excuse. It follows that what violates someone's rights would be blameworthy if it were done without either a justification or an excuse
-
Or, alternatively, though it violates your right and would be wrong (period) if I lacked this further justification, it is not wrong because the justification exists. What violates someone's rights would be wrong to do lacking some justification, just as what is wrong would be blameworthy if done without adequate excuse. It follows that what violates someone's rights would be blameworthy if it were done without either a justification or an excuse.
-
-
-
-
94
-
-
0039610491
-
Internal reasons and the obscurity of blame
-
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, )
-
See Bernard Williams, "Internal Reasons and the Obscurity of Blame," in Williams, Making Sense of Humanity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), 40-44;
-
(1995)
Williams, Making Sense of Humanity
, pp. 40-44
-
-
Williams, B.1
-
98
-
-
79251624978
-
-
For valuable insights about the relevance of prospective guilt, I am indebted to the work of Howard Nye
-
For valuable insights about the relevance of prospective guilt, I am indebted to the work of Howard Nye.
-
-
-
-
99
-
-
79251648919
-
-
It should be clear that I am not saying that this is a wrong-making feature, in the sense of a ground or of normative reason for an act's wrongness. I am saying that this is what being wrong consists in, and that this fact provides a reason not to perform the wrongful act that is additional to the act's wrong-making features (grounds of or normative reasons for its being wrong)
-
It should be clear that I am not saying that this is a wrong-making feature, in the sense of a ground or of normative reason for an act's wrongness. I am saying that this is what being wrong consists in, and that this fact provides a reason not to perform the wrongful act that is additional to the act's wrong-making features (grounds of or normative reasons for its being wrong).
-
-
-
|