메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 110, Issue 4, 2000, Pages 722-748

Sentiment and value

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0039592585     PISSN: 00141704     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1086/233371     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (236)

References (86)
  • 1
    • 0004088235 scopus 로고
    • ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge and P. H. Niddich, 2d ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge and P. H. Niddich, 2d ed. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978), p. 470.
    • (1978) A Treatise of Human Nature , pp. 470
    • Hume, D.1
  • 4
    • 0004160442 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • This thought is, in itself, no concession to skepticism about value. Even such avowedly nonskeptical moral philosophers as Korsgaard, Nagel, and Railton hold something to this effect, though their views vary considerably in detail. See Christine Korsgaard, The Sources of Normativity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996); Thomas Nagel, The View from Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986); and Peter Railton, "Moral Realism," Philosophical Review 95 (1987): 163-207.
    • (1996) The Sources of Normativity
    • Korsgaard, C.1
  • 5
    • 0004207980 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • This thought is, in itself, no concession to skepticism about value. Even such avowedly nonskeptical moral philosophers as Korsgaard, Nagel, and Railton hold something to this effect, though their views vary considerably in detail. See Christine Korsgaard, The Sources of Normativity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996); Thomas Nagel, The View from Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986); and Peter Railton, "Moral Realism," Philosophical Review 95 (1987): 163-207.
    • (1986) The View from Nowhere
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 6
    • 0001443553 scopus 로고
    • Moral realism
    • This thought is, in itself, no concession to skepticism about value. Even such avowedly nonskeptical moral philosophers as Korsgaard, Nagel, and Railton hold something to this effect, though their views vary considerably in detail. See Christine Korsgaard, The Sources of Normativity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996); Thomas Nagel, The View from Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986); and Peter Railton, "Moral Realism," Philosophical Review 95 (1987): 163-207.
    • (1987) Philosophical Review , vol.95 , pp. 163-207
    • Railton, P.1
  • 7
    • 85037777018 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Our principal term here is 'sentiment', which we will use broadly to refer to any occurrent, object-directed, affect-laden mental state. Moods are affective states - that is, states that feel a certain way - which are not sentiments, since they lack objects. Emotions are paradigm cases of sentiments, but we want to restrict the term 'emotion' to a central class of such mental states found across cultures and epochs: Hume's "common sentiments of mankind."
  • 8
    • 4043074169 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reasons, motives, and the demands of morality: An introduction
    • ed. Stephen Darwall, Allan Gibbard, and Peter Railton Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Indeed, even our formulation is contentious, since internalism can be offered as a thesis about evaluative properties rather than judgments. See Stephen Darwall, "Reasons, Motives, and the Demands of Morality: An Introduction," Moral Discourse and Practice, ed. Stephen Darwall, Allan Gibbard, and Peter Railton (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997). Many philosophers would deny internalism about morality, as Hume did, and hold that it's possible for a "sensible knave" to know right from wrong yet not to care about doing right. But it is much less plausible to deny all internalist constraints on the concept of self-interest or on an agent's reasons for acting. See Railton, "Moral Realism," for a view that is externalist about morality but internalist, in a subtle and powerful way, about self-interest.
    • (1997) Moral Discourse and Practice
    • Darwall, S.1
  • 9
    • 0040622644 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • for a view that is externalist about morality but internalist, in a subtle and powerful way, about self-interest
    • Indeed, even our formulation is contentious, since internalism can be offered as a thesis about evaluative properties rather than judgments. See Stephen Darwall, "Reasons, Motives, and the Demands of Morality: An Introduction," Moral Discourse and Practice, ed. Stephen Darwall, Allan Gibbard, and Peter Railton (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997). Many philosophers would deny internalism about morality, as Hume did, and hold that it's possible for a "sensible knave" to know right from wrong yet not to care about doing right. But it is much less plausible to deny all internalist constraints on the concept of self-interest or on an agent's reasons for acting. See Railton, "Moral Realism," for a view that is externalist about morality but internalist, in a subtle and powerful way, about self-interest.
    • Moral Realism
    • Railton1
  • 10
    • 85037773345 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Behavior must be understood broadly, so as to include more than deliberate action. Thus, simply the impulse to flee, or a "cold sweat," can be taken as evidence of the constellation of motives involved in fear.
  • 11
    • 0040944776 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • See Simon Blackburn, Spreading the Ward (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), Essays in Quasi-Realism (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), and Ruling Passions (New York: Oxford University Press, 1998); Allan Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990); John McDowell, "Values and Secondary Qualities," and "Projection and Truth in Ethics," in Darwall, Gibbard, and Railton, eds.; and David Wiggins, "A Sensible Subjectivism?" in ibid. Another contemporary philosopher in this tradition is Elizabeth Anderson, whose rational attitude theory is also a form of sophisticated sentimentalism. Since Anderson's theory is driven by normative, more than metaethical, considerations, we will not take it up here, but a similar argument can be made against her view. See Elizabeth Anderson, Value in Ethics and Economics (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1993).
    • (1984) Spreading the Ward
    • Blackburn, S.1
  • 12
    • 0003925356 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • See Simon Blackburn, Spreading the Ward (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), Essays in Quasi-Realism (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), and Ruling Passions (New York: Oxford University Press, 1998); Allan Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990); John McDowell, "Values and Secondary Qualities," and "Projection and Truth in Ethics," in Darwall, Gibbard, and Railton, eds.; and David Wiggins, "A Sensible Subjectivism?" in ibid. Another contemporary philosopher in this tradition is Elizabeth Anderson, whose rational attitude theory is also a form of sophisticated sentimentalism. Since Anderson's theory is driven by normative, more than metaethical, considerations, we will not take it up here, but a similar argument can be made against her view. See Elizabeth Anderson, Value in Ethics and Economics (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1993).
    • (1993) Essays in Quasi-Realism
  • 13
    • 0004241094 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • See Simon Blackburn, Spreading the Ward (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), Essays in Quasi-Realism (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), and Ruling Passions (New York: Oxford University Press, 1998); Allan Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990); John McDowell, "Values and Secondary Qualities," and "Projection and Truth in Ethics," in Darwall, Gibbard, and Railton, eds.; and David Wiggins, "A Sensible Subjectivism?" in ibid. Another contemporary philosopher in this tradition is Elizabeth Anderson, whose rational attitude theory is also a form of sophisticated sentimentalism. Since Anderson's theory is driven by normative, more than metaethical, considerations, we will not take it up here, but a similar argument can be made against her view. See Elizabeth Anderson, Value in Ethics and Economics (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1993).
    • (1998) Ruling Passions
  • 14
    • 0003541293 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • See Simon Blackburn, Spreading the Ward (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), Essays in Quasi-Realism (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), and Ruling Passions (New York: Oxford University Press, 1998); Allan Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990); John McDowell, "Values and Secondary Qualities," and "Projection and Truth in Ethics," in Darwall, Gibbard, and Railton, eds.; and David Wiggins, "A Sensible Subjectivism?" in ibid. Another contemporary philosopher in this tradition is Elizabeth Anderson, whose rational attitude theory is also a form of sophisticated sentimentalism. Since Anderson's theory is driven by normative, more than metaethical, considerations, we will not take it up here, but a similar argument can be made against her view. See Elizabeth Anderson, Value in Ethics and Economics (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1993).
    • (1990) Wise Choices, Apt Feelings
    • Gibbard, A.1
  • 15
    • 85037753983 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Darwall, Gibbard, and Railton, eds.
    • See Simon Blackburn, Spreading the Ward (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), Essays in Quasi-Realism (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), and Ruling Passions (New York: Oxford University Press, 1998); Allan Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990); John McDowell, "Values and Secondary Qualities," and "Projection and Truth in Ethics," in Darwall, Gibbard, and Railton, eds.; and David Wiggins, "A Sensible Subjectivism?" in ibid. Another contemporary philosopher in this tradition is Elizabeth Anderson, whose rational attitude theory is also a form of sophisticated sentimentalism. Since Anderson's theory is driven by normative, more than metaethical, considerations, we will not take it up here, but a similar argument can be made against her view. See Elizabeth Anderson, Value in Ethics and Economics (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1993).
    • "Values and Secondary Qualities," and "Projection and Truth in Ethics,"
    • McDowell, J.1
  • 16
    • 0040944767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A sensible subjectivism?
    • See Simon Blackburn, Spreading the Ward (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), Essays in Quasi-Realism (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), and Ruling Passions (New York: Oxford University Press, 1998); Allan Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990); John McDowell, "Values and Secondary Qualities," and "Projection and Truth in Ethics," in Darwall, Gibbard, and Railton, eds.; and David Wiggins, "A Sensible Subjectivism?" in ibid. Another contemporary philosopher in this tradition is Elizabeth Anderson, whose rational attitude theory is also a form of sophisticated sentimentalism. Since Anderson's theory is driven by normative, more than metaethical, considerations, we will not take it up here, but a similar argument can be made against her view. See Elizabeth Anderson, Value in Ethics and Economics (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1993).
    • "Values and Secondary Qualities," and "Projection and Truth in Ethics,"
    • Wiggins, D.1
  • 17
    • 0004113926 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • See Simon Blackburn, Spreading the Ward (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), Essays in Quasi-Realism (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), and Ruling Passions (New York: Oxford University Press, 1998); Allan Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990); John McDowell, "Values and Secondary Qualities," and "Projection and Truth in Ethics," in Darwall, Gibbard, and Railton, eds.; and David Wiggins, "A Sensible Subjectivism?" in ibid. Another contemporary philosopher in this tradition is Elizabeth Anderson, whose rational attitude theory is also a form of sophisticated sentimentalism. Since Anderson's theory is driven by normative, more than metaethical, considerations, we will not take it up here, but a similar argument can be made against her view. See Elizabeth Anderson, Value in Ethics and Economics (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1993).
    • (1993) Value in Ethics and Economics
    • Anderson, E.1
  • 18
    • 85037763192 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Alternatively, the theory can identify the judgment that an object Y is good (or bad) with desire for (or aversion to) Y. The same criticisms tell against this proposal, mutatis mutandis.
  • 19
    • 0003631346 scopus 로고
    • New York: Dover Press
    • The theory given in A. J. Ayer, Language, Truth, and Logic (New York: Dover Press, 1936), is the closest thing to pure emotivism. Stevenson adds an outward-looking prescription to others to feel similarly, which is needed to get anything like dispute. See Charles Stevenson, "The Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms," Mind 46 (1937): 14-31. Consider that the "yea" and "boo" of fans of rival sports teams are precisely not intended to influence or persuade dissenters, nor must I think you are getting something wrong in your disappointment over my team's ultimate triumph. (What could that be - the sheer goodness of my side prevailing? It seems far more plausible to think that you are right: your team's pitiful effort really is the way your disappointment presents it to you as being, namely, bad for your side.) This is disagreement in attitude without real dispute.
    • (1936) Language, Truth, and Logic
    • Ayer, A.J.1
  • 20
    • 0002628831 scopus 로고
    • The emotive meaning of ethical terms
    • The theory given in A. J. Ayer, Language, Truth, and Logic (New York: Dover Press, 1936), is the closest thing to pure emotivism. Stevenson adds an outward-looking prescription to others to feel similarly, which is needed to get anything like dispute. See Charles Stevenson, "The Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms," Mind 46 (1937): 14-31. Consider that the "yea" and "boo" of fans of rival sports teams are precisely not intended to influence or persuade dissenters, nor must I think you are getting something wrong in your disappointment over my team's ultimate triumph. (What could that be - the sheer goodness of my side prevailing? It seems far more plausible to think that you are right: your team's pitiful effort really is the way your disappointment presents it to you as being, namely, bad for your side.) This is disagreement in attitude without real dispute.
    • (1937) Mind , vol.46 , pp. 14-31
    • Stevenson, C.1
  • 21
    • 0003964105 scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge & Kegan Paul
    • Both common sense and the best theories of the emotions are agreed that such disparity between a bout of emotion and one's considered judgment is quite possible. See Patricia Greenspan, Emotions and Reason: An Inquiry into Emotional Justification (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1988); and Gibbard, Wise Choices.
    • (1988) Emotions and Reason: An Inquiry into Emotional Justification
    • Greenspan, P.1
  • 22
    • 0039166219 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Both common sense and the best theories of the emotions are agreed that such disparity between a bout of emotion and one's considered judgment is quite possible. See Patricia Greenspan, Emotions and Reason: An Inquiry into Emotional Justification (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1988); and Gibbard, Wise Choices.
    • Wise Choices
    • Gibbard1
  • 23
    • 0001963741 scopus 로고
    • Colour as a secondary quality
    • There are disputes even about the dispositional account of color, but most sides accept the truth of the biconditional; the dispute is over whether a more substantive analysis of color terms is needed or can be given. See Paul Boghossian and David Velleman, "Colour as a Secondary Quality," Mind 98 (1989): 81-103.
    • (1989) Mind , vol.98 , pp. 81-103
    • Boghossian, P.1    Velleman, D.2
  • 25
    • 84974050699 scopus 로고
    • Naturalism and prescriptivity
    • Peter Railton, "Naturalism and Prescriptivity," Social Philosophy and Policy 7 (1989): 151-74, p. 158.
    • (1989) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.7 , pp. 151-174
    • Railton, P.1
  • 26
    • 85037753603 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It may be that there are two distinct senses of 'disgusting', one normative (in the way we're suggesting) and the other dispositional. The latter is most frequently used relationally, as in: "Yak cheese is disgusting to most Westerners, but it's a staple of the Tibetan diet." Take our remarks above, then, as being concerned with the first, and most distinctively evaluative, sense.
  • 27
    • 85037752533 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Of course, the reactions and opinions of others are likely to influence our own, and it seems to us only reasonable to remain generally open to such influence. But this is a far cry from embracing dispositionalism.
  • 28
    • 33748449410 scopus 로고
    • Of the standard of taste
    • ed. Eugene Miller Indianapolis: Liberty Classics
    • David Hume, "Of the Standard of Taste," in Essays, Moral, Political, and Literary, ed. Eugene Miller (Indianapolis: Liberty Classics, 1987).
    • (1987) Essays, Moral, Political, and Literary
    • Hume, D.1
  • 29
    • 0038483000 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aesthetic value, moral value, and the ambitions of naturalism
    • ed. Jarrold Levinson Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • This is a simplified account of Hume's view. His theory of taste is sufficiently sophisticated to take account of the corrupting effects of prejudice and to allow for certain "blameless" disagreements that cannot be reconciled, among other complications. We hope that our debt to Hume, as a founder of sentimentalism, is evident, despite our conviction that his account cannot succeed as it stands. For two disparate but fruitful ways of developing Hume's theory, see David Wiggins; and Peter Railton, "Aesthetic Value, Moral Value, and the Ambitions of Naturalism," in Aesthetics and Ethics: Essays at the Intersection, ed. Jarrold Levinson (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998).
    • (1998) Aesthetics and Ethics: Essays at the Intersection
    • Wiggins, D.1    Railton, P.2
  • 30
    • 85037762169 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Our thanks to David Hills for pointing out the relevance of the fable and the challenge it provides for Hume's account of delicacy.
  • 31
    • 0004241094 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • esp. chap. 8
    • This point is most clearly made in Blackburn, Ruling Passions, esp. chap. 8.
    • Ruling Passions
    • Blackburn1
  • 32
    • 85037751940 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although "response dependence" is sometimes associated with forms of dispositionalism, we will use the term in the overtly normative sense suggested by the neosentimentalist program.
  • 34
    • 85037784500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McDowell, "Values and Secondary Qualities," p. 208. See also Wiggins, p. 197.
    • Wiggins1
  • 35
    • 63549105015 scopus 로고
    • Nonfactualism about normative discourse
    • The noncognitivists' appropriation of ordinary normative locutions makes even stating the difference between these views difficult. Perhaps the best way is to distinguish between "factualists" and "nonfactualists," but it will then be contentious whether even the cognitivist sentimentalists count as factualists. See Peter Railton, "Nonfactualism about Normative Discourse," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (1992): 961-68.
    • (1992) Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , vol.52 , pp. 961-968
    • Railton, P.1
  • 37
    • 85037751977 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • A sentimentalist must be able to insist, however, that it isn't merely our thinking wanton cruelty to be wrong which makes it so. It would be cruel even if we didn't realize it. The worry that sentimentalists are not entitled to say such things about the independence of evaluative properties can be pressed against the cognitivists and noncognitivists alike. Both defend themselves against such worries through some fancy philosophical footwork, of which an unregenerate realist (or antirealist) would be suspicious.
  • 38
    • 0040350678 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In praise of immoral art
    • For an argument against comic moralism, see Daniel Jacobson, "In Praise of Immoral Art," Philosophical Topics 25 (1997): 155-99.
    • (1997) Philosophical Topics , vol.25 , pp. 155-199
    • Jacobson, D.1
  • 39
    • 0040350680 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The moralistic fallacy: On the 'appropriateness' of emotion
    • For an argument that such moral considerations about whether to feel an emotion F at some object X are systematically irrelevant to whether X is F, see Justin D'Arms and Daniel Jacobson, "The Moralistic Fallacy: On the 'Appropriateness' of Emotion," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61 (2000): 65-90.
    • (2000) Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , vol.61 , pp. 65-90
    • D'Arms, J.1    Jacobson, D.2
  • 40
    • 85037757983 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • While it would admittedly be odd to say that "envy isn't appropriate" on grounds of expedience (as opposed to propriety), it wou d be quite natural to conclude that "envy isn't rational," and 'rational' is Gibbard's prefer-ed normative term in RDT. Similar problems will arise for all the normative terms used by the sentimentalists under consideration here.
  • 41
    • 85037768107 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In fact, McDowell and Wiggins grant the possibility of scientific, even evolutionary stories of the type Blackburn and Gibbard suggest. And the cognitivists' insistence that there is no "purely phenomenological" account of the sentiments is a bit of a red herring, since neither Blackburn nor Gibbard hold that the sentiments are mere feelings. They can both make use of the objects and causes of our responses in individuating them.
  • 43
    • 0004195469 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • Williams offers a particularly clear and interesting argument that this dispute should be framed in terms of knowledge rather than truth. See Bernard Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985).
    • (1985) Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy
    • Williams, B.1
  • 49
    • 0039758757 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Levinson, ed.; also see Anderson
    • Indeed, Gaut and Anderson seem to use the term this way, as is evident from their acceptance of comic moralism. But every locution, including our own talk of the "fittingness" of emotion, has this semantic wobble to some degree, for the same (explicable) reasons. See Berys Gaut, "The Ethical Criticism of Art," in Levinson, ed.; also see Anderson.
    • The Ethical Criticism of Art
    • Gaut, B.1
  • 52
    • 85037749973 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • However, this approach seems uncongenial to someone who takes talk of the virtues as seriously as does McDowell. If you hold the doctrine of the unity of the virtues, and that virtue always issues in right action, then it looks like you're stuck saying that how the virtuous person would respond - presumably with disdain at morally obnoxious jokes, however viciously funny - is the appropriate way to feel. But then one must give up RDT.
  • 53
    • 0040974355 scopus 로고
    • Natural pride and natural shame
    • Unless one holds shame to present its object - roughly, some flaw or weakness in the affected agent - as something one is responsible for. While some philosophers are tempted to moralize such emotions as amusement, shame, and envy, we think this is a systematic error with a common cause: the natural reluctance to endorse, in anyway, an emotion one deems it wrong to feel. On shame, see Arnold Isenberg, "Natural Pride and Natural Shame," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 10 (1949); and on envy, John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971). On the notion of reciprocal emotions, see Gibbard, Wise Choices.
    • (1949) Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , vol.10
    • Isenberg, A.1
  • 54
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • Unless one holds shame to present its object - roughly, some flaw or weakness in the affected agent - as something one is responsible for. While some philosophers are tempted to moralize such emotions as amusement, shame, and envy, we think this is a systematic error with a common cause: the natural reluctance to endorse, in anyway, an emotion one deems it wrong to feel. On shame, see Arnold Isenberg, "Natural Pride and Natural Shame," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 10 (1949); and on envy, John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971). On the notion of reciprocal emotions, see Gibbard, Wise Choices.
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 55
    • 0039166219 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Unless one holds shame to present its object - roughly, some flaw or weakness in the affected agent - as something one is responsible for. While some philosophers are tempted to moralize such emotions as amusement, shame, and envy, we think this is a systematic error with a common cause: the natural reluctance to endorse, in anyway, an emotion one deems it wrong to feel. On shame, see Arnold Isenberg, "Natural Pride and Natural Shame," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 10 (1949); and on envy, John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971). On the notion of reciprocal emotions, see Gibbard, Wise Choices.
    • Wise Choices
    • Gibbard1
  • 57
    • 85037780334 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid.
    • Ibid., p. 195n.
  • 58
    • 85037777420 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The basic emotions, which have cross-cultural equivalents and about which evolutionary stories can most plausibly be told, are least amenable to this approach, whereas, if there are distinct responses associated with more culturally specific "thick" evaluative concepts (such as chivalrous and lewd), they might well be more deeply "made for" these properties. See Williams for a discussion of thick concepts; also see Allan Gibbard, "Morality and Thick Concepts: I, Thick Concepts and Warrant for Feelings," and Simon Blackburn, "Morality and Thick Concepts: II, Through Thick and Thin," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 66, suppl. (1992): 267-83, 285-99. We think there is more to say about these cases, but that must be the task of another day.
    • Discussion of Thick Concepts
    • Williams1
  • 59
    • 85037753117 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The basic emotions, which have cross-cultural equivalents and about which evolutionary stories can most plausibly be told, are least amenable to this approach, whereas, if there are distinct responses associated with more culturally specific "thick" evaluative concepts (such as chivalrous and lewd), they might well be more deeply "made for" these properties. See Williams for a discussion of thick concepts; also see Allan Gibbard, "Morality and Thick Concepts: I, Thick Concepts and Warrant for Feelings," and Simon Blackburn, "Morality and Thick Concepts: II, Through Thick and Thin," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 66, suppl. (1992): 267-83, 285-99. We think there is more to say about these cases, but that must be the task of another day.
    • Morality and Thick Concepts: I, Thick Concepts and Warrant for Feelings
    • Gibbard, A.1
  • 60
    • 0006888995 scopus 로고
    • Morality and thick concepts: II, through thick and thin
    • The basic emotions, which have cross-cultural equivalents and about which evolutionary stories can most plausibly be told, are least amenable to this approach, whereas, if there are distinct responses associated with more culturally specific "thick" evaluative concepts (such as chivalrous and lewd), they might well be more deeply "made for" these properties. See Williams for a discussion of thick concepts; also see Allan Gibbard, "Morality and Thick Concepts: I, Thick Concepts and Warrant for Feelings," and Simon Blackburn, "Morality and Thick Concepts: II, Through Thick and Thin," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 66, suppl. (1992): 267-83, 285-99. We think there is more to say about these cases, but that must be the task of another day.
    • (1992) Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , vol.66 , Issue.SUPPL. , pp. 267-283
    • Blackburn, S.1
  • 61
    • 0013153016 scopus 로고
    • Moral cognitivism, moral relativism and motivating moral beliefs
    • See David Wiggins, "Moral Cognitivism, Moral Relativism and Motivating Moral Beliefs," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91 (1991): 61-85.
    • (1991) Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , vol.91 , pp. 61-85
    • Wiggins, D.1
  • 64
    • 85037750286 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Gibbard uses 'rational' and 'makes sense' synonymously. As he notes, there is something unfortunate about each locution (or any other available in ordinary language). 'Makes sense' can be read empirically, as what we would expect or can explain. Gibbard is not concerned with this empirical "makes sense that," but with the normative "makes sense to." For simplicity's sake, we will stick to 'rational' here, but the quotations from Gibbard use both locutions interchangeably.
  • 65
    • 85037768757 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Two of Gibbard's three arguments concern weakness of will. The first is given here, and the second takes up the Milgram experiment. The conclusion Gibbard correctly draws from the famous experiment is that most of the participants are more strongly in the grip of norms (about obedience) other than those they most strongly endorse (about not harming the innocent). Hence, they do what does not seem best to them, i.e., they continue to administer electric shocks to subjects under orders from the experimenter. Or so they think.
  • 67
    • 0039166219 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., pp. 9-22; and Darwall, Gibbard, and Railton, "Toward Fin de Siècle Ethics."
    • Wise Choices , pp. 9-22
  • 69
    • 85037769606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Perhaps not all intrinsic desires, but we won't worry about the many complications to this issue that don't bear on the matter at hand.
  • 70
    • 0004293486 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Gibbard cites James Griffin, Well-Being (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986). See also Darwall; Korsgaard.
    • (1986) Well-Being
    • Griffin, J.1
  • 71
    • 85037779137 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Korsgaard
    • Gibbard cites James Griffin, Well-Being (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986). See also Darwall; Korsgaard.
    • Darwall1
  • 72
    • 85037751308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Strictly speaking, this is an account of the blameworthiness of an action, because unless the agent is responsible for his wrongdoing, guilt and anger at him are not rational. But, following Gibbard, we will ignore this complication here by assuming that the agent's responsibility is not at issue.
  • 74
    • 85037771634 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Dennis need not think this true of all the traits he deems shameful; such strategic considerations are most powerful specifically when it would be debilitating actually to be ashamed. By contrast, the clichéd "98-pound weakling" who gets sand kicked in his face until he goes in for the weightlifting regimen is constructively motivated by his shame. Note, too, that to abjure endorsing shame at an admittedly shameful trait, on strategic or moral grounds, does not commit one to holding I hat others would be in any sense irrational to disdain you for this trait, even if (as Gibbard suggests, and we accept) one's norms for the warrant of first-person shame and third-person disdain must mesh. We are grateful to an anonymous editor for encouraging us to clarify these points.
  • 77
    • 0039166219 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 49; emphasis added.
    • Wise Choices , pp. 49
  • 79
    • 85037752019 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • To deny this is, in effect, to insist that evidential reasons always settle what to feel. This is a substantive normative position which norm expressivism is not intended to involve. It also happens to be a crazy normative position. The thought that a feeling is warranted may always count in favor of feeling it, but moral and prudential reasons not to feel it can count too and are sometimes more important.
  • 80
    • 85037759897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Whether he endorses desiring to feel shame is a further question, presumably to be settled by consideration of the reasons for and against having this desire. Except in certain extraordinary circumstances, he would not endorse this desire either.
  • 81
    • 85037778859 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This may be the best interpretation of Gibbard's account of judgments of rationality. It should be noted, though, that this view would require rethinking the arguments that Gibbard uses to motivate norm expressivism in the first place. See appendix.
  • 82
    • 84937301137 scopus 로고
    • Expressivism, morality, and the emotions
    • See Justin D'Arms and Daniel Jacobson, "Expressivism, Morality, and the Emotions," Ethics 104 (1994): 739-63.
    • (1994) Ethics , vol.104 , pp. 739-763
    • D'Arms, J.1    Jacobson, D.2
  • 83
    • 0039758745 scopus 로고
    • Moral valuation
    • This terminology follows Richard Brandt, "Moral Valuation," Ethics 56 (1946): 106 -21, an important and insightful paper which nevertheless fails to deal with the conflation problem. The notion of emotional fittingness is considered in more depth in D'Arms and Jacobson, "The Moralistic Fallacy"; we hope to develop a theory of rational sentimentalism further in our subsequent work.
    • (1946) Ethics , vol.56 , pp. 106-121
    • Brandt, R.1
  • 84
    • 0040350675 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This terminology follows Richard Brandt, "Moral Valuation," Ethics 56 (1946): 106 -21, an important and insightful paper which nevertheless fails to deal with the conflation problem. The notion of emotional fittingness is considered in more depth in D'Arms and Jacobson, "The Moralistic Fallacy"; we hope to develop a theory of rational sentimentalism further in our subsequent work.
    • The Moralistic Fallacy
    • D'Arms1    Jacobson2
  • 85
    • 0003056192 scopus 로고
    • Freedom and resentment
    • ed. Gary Watson Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • See P. F. Strawson, "Freedom and Resentment," reprinted in Free Will, ed. Gary Watson (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982), p. 80.
    • (1982) Free Will , pp. 80
    • Strawson, P.F.1
  • 86
    • 85037769330 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This is perhaps most obvious with respect to doubts about whether there is any such sentiment as moral disapprobation, and doubts about whether contingent, human responses could have the special sort of authority that morality has been thought to invoke. But we think that worries about the circularity of response-dependent accounts, which some sentimentalists deny (as does Gibbard) and others admit but claim not to be vicious (like Wiggins), also have more bite when applied to accounts of good and right than to funny and shameful.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.