메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 123, Issue 8, 2010, Pages 2065-2087

Uncommon goods: On environmental virtues and voluntary carbon offsets
[No Author Info available]

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 78149476385     PISSN: 0017811X     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (13)

References (117)
  • 1
    • 77950132778 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Assessing the options for designing a mandatory U.S. Greenhouse gas reduction program
    • discussing the fact that the federal government has not yet regulated greenhouse gases and providing details of potential regulatory tools, including cap-and-trade
    • See generally Robert R. Nordhaus & Kyle W. Danish, Assessing the Options for Designing a Mandatory U.S. Greenhouse Gas Reduction Program, 32 B.C. ENVTL. AFF. L. REV 97 (2005) (discussing the fact that the federal government has not yet regulated greenhouse gases and providing details of potential regulatory tools, including cap-and-trade).
    • (2005) B.C. Envtl. Aff. L. Rev , vol.32 , pp. 97
    • Nordhaus, R.R.1    Danish, K.W.2
  • 2
    • 78149475396 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Under a cap-and-trade system, the government sets an aggregate limit to the amount of pollution that can be emitted, creates permits that allow the holders to emit some predetermined percentage of that total limit, distributes the permits, and then allows firms to trade permits
    • Under a cap-and-trade system, "the government sets an aggregate limit to the amount of pollution that can be emitted, creates permits that allow the holders to emit some predetermined percentage of that total limit, distributes the permits, and then allows firms to trade permits."
  • 3
    • 0347705209 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • How changes in property regimes influence social norms: Commodifying california's carpool lanes
    • 1284 In this way, the reductions in emissions will be made by those firms able to do so at the lowest cost. Id.
    • Lior Jacob Strahilevitz, How Changes in Property Regimes Influence Social Norms: Commodifying California's Carpool Lanes, 75 IND. LJ. 1231, 1284 (2000). In this way, "the reductions in emissions will be made by those firms able to do so at the lowest cost." Id.
    • (2000) Ind. LJ. , vol.75 , pp. 1231
    • Strahilevitz, L.J.1
  • 4
    • 78149485048 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a comprehensive summary of the nature and mechanics of voluntary carbon markets in recent years, see
    • For a comprehensive summary of the nature and mechanics of voluntary carbon markets in recent years, see KATHERINE HAMILTON ET AL., ECOSYSTEM MARKETPLACE & NEW CARBON FINANCE, FORGING A FRONTIER: STATE OF THE VOLUNTARY CARBON MARKETS 2008 (2008), available at http://www.ecosystemmarketplace.com/ documents/cms-documents/2008-StateofVoluntaryCarbonMarket2.pdf;
    • (2008) Ecosystem Marketplace & New Carbon Finance, Forging a Frontier: State of the Voluntary Carbon Markets 2008
    • Hamilton, K.1
  • 6
    • 4444257477 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a discussion of both regulated and voluntary carbon markets, see
    • For a discussion of both regulated and voluntary carbon markets, see KARAN CAPOOR & PHILIPPE AMBROSI, WORLD BANK, STATE AND TRENDS OF THE CARBON MARKET 2008 (2008), available at http://siteresources. worldbank.org/NEWS/ Resources/State&Trendsformattedo6Mayiopm.pdf.
    • (2008) World Bank, State and Trends of the Carbon Market 2008
    • Capoor, K.1    Ambrosi, P.2
  • 7
    • 38049170960 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The carbon-neutral individual
    • 1718 n.206 (listing examples of companies that offer offsets, including DHL, which will make a shipment carbon-neutral for a two percent premium on its usual shipping charge, and Pacific Gas & Electric, which gives customers the option of paying to offset the greenhouse gas emissions from their electricity use)
    • Michael P. Vandenbergh & Anne C. Steinemann, The Carbon-Neutral Individual, 82 N.Y.U. L. REV 1673, 1718 n.206 (2007) (listing examples of companies that offer offsets, including DHL, which will make a shipment carbon-neutral for a two percent premium on its usual shipping charge, and Pacific Gas & Electric, which gives customers the option of paying to offset the greenhouse gas emissions from their electricity use).
    • (2007) N.Y.U. L. Rev , vol.82 , pp. 1673
    • Vandenbergh, M.P.1    Steinemann, A.C.2
  • 8
    • 78149474008 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, a variety of not-for-profit organizations and governments, id. at 1719, and a lengthening list of big businesses, ranging from the predictable (Ben & Jerry's) to the surprising (Rupert Murdoch's News Corporation), have pledged to become carbon-neutral, id. at 1718
    • For example, a variety of not-for-profit organizations and governments, id. at 1719, and a lengthening list of big businesses, "ranging from the predictable (Ben & Jerry's) to the surprising (Rupert Murdoch's News Corporation)," have pledged to become carbon-neutral, id. at 1718.
  • 9
    • 78149489939 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a discussion of the rise of the carbon neutrality norm, see id. at 1717-2 0
    • For a discussion of the rise of the carbon neutrality norm, see id. at 1717-2 0.
  • 10
    • 78149478399 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HAMILTON ET AL., FORTIFYING THE FOUNDATION, supra note 2, at 6, 31. Note that the aggregate estimates in this report may be conservative; the 2008 figure, for example, is based in part on data obtained from voluntary completion of surveys by 182 developers, aggregators, brokers, and retailers in twenty-eight countries. Id. at 5
    • HAMILTON ET AL., FORTIFYING THE FOUNDATION, supra note 2, at 6, 31. Note that the aggregate estimates in this report may be conservative; the 2008 figure, for example, is based in part on data obtained from voluntary completion of surveys by 182 developers, aggregators, brokers, and retailers in twenty-eight countries. Id. at 5.
  • 11
    • 78149482263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Individual purchases accounted for approximately five percent of the market in 2006 and 2007, prior to the recession; in 2008, this number declined to two percent
    • Individual purchases accounted for approximately five percent of the market in 2006 and 2007, prior to the recession; in 2008, this number declined to two percent.
  • 12
    • 78149480263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 95
    • Id. at 95.
  • 13
    • 78149490286 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The report notes that the number assigned to individuals may be lower than the actual number, as it is difficult to track credits sold to individuals through companies, such as airlines, whose primary business model is not supplying offset credits. Id.
    • The report notes that the number assigned to individuals may be lower than the actual number, as it is "difficult to track credits sold to individuals through companies, such as airlines, whose primary business model is not supplying offset credits." Id.
  • 14
    • 78149487523 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • A second type of difference between the markets that might have some bearing on the question lies in the nature of the actors involved. The standard proposals for regulatory markets, for example, would require corporations, but not individual people, to buy offsets - and it is arguable that corporations are not capable of embodying virtues in the same ways that people are. In this case, the use of regulatory offsets would not be objectionable in and of itself, or at least not in all the same ways that it may be when the actors are people. This is not to say, however, that a regulatory offset market would be unobjectionable. At the very least, any concerns that derive from the regulatory offsets' social significance and impact on individual action, if there is any such impact, would still be applicable.
  • 15
    • 78149472812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • To say that the purchases of offsets are "motivated by" this attitude is not to say that the purchasers always believe that they have an ethical obligation to do so. They might, for example, be buying offsets solely to comply with an externally imposed norm, such as social pressure to "be green." But they would only do so if they thought that these purchases were a way of complying with that norm; in this sense, the purchasers are motivated by the norm, whether or not they internalize it. That this norm is widespread is demonstrated by the size and growth of the voluntary market in recent years. See HAMILTON ET AL., FORTIFYING THE FOUNDATION, supra note 2.
  • 16
    • 82055194301 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Limousine liberal hypocrisy
    • The most thorough academic discussions of these markets have been positive, recommending them as a way of achieving environmental goals. See, e.g., Vandenbergh & Steinemann, supra note 3, at 1720-24. The limited criticisms fall into two categories. First, in the academic literature, there is a concern that offsets do not always provide genuine emissions reductions - that an offset may purport to displace a carbon-emitting activity that would not have occurred without the offset in the first place, or that "the offset-generating activity may have uncertain scientific validity." Id. at 1722 However, these claims are not a criticism of the voluntary offset market per se, but rather of the ways in which the voluntary offsets are created - a problem that could be solved through regulation. Second, in the popular media, offsets have also been criticized on the grounds that they are comparable to papal indulgences. See, e.g.
    • The most thorough academic discussions of these markets have been positive, recommending them as a way of achieving environmental goals. See, e.g., Vandenbergh & Steinemann, supra note 3, at 1720-24. The limited criticisms fall into two categories. First, in the academic literature, there is a concern that offsets do not always provide genuine emissions reductions - that an offset "may purport to displace a carbon-emitting activity that would not have occurred without the offset in the first place," or that "the offset-generating activity may have uncertain scientific validity." Id. at 1722. However, these claims are not a criticism of the voluntary offset market per se, but rather of the ways in which the voluntary offsets are created - a problem that could be solved through regulation. Second, in the popular media, offsets have also been criticized on the grounds that they are comparable to papal indulgences. See, e.g., Charles Krauthammer, Limousine Liberal Hypocrisy, TIME, Mar. 26, 2007, at 24;
    • (2007) TIME, Mar. , vol.26 , pp. 24
    • Krauthammer, C.1
  • 17
    • 77956516027 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Carbon-neutral is hip, but is it green?
    • Apr. 29, § 4 (Week in Review)
    • Andrew C. Revkin, Carbon-Neutral Is Hip, but Is It Green?, N.Y. TIMES, Apr. 29, 2007, § 4 (Week in Review), at 1;
    • (2007) N.Y. Times , pp. 1
    • Revkin, A.C.1
  • 18
    • 0028605434 scopus 로고
    • Selling environmental indulgences
    • note
    • see also Robert E. Goodin, Selling Environmental Indulgences, 47 KYKLOS 573 (1994) (providing a more sophisticated version of the "indulgence" argument, made with respect to pollution offsets and taxes). But this second criticism has generally gained little traction in the academic literature, as it seems that the analogy breaks down in crucial ways: indulgences did not provide an enforceable contract for a place in heaven and did not materially reverse the impact of the predicate sin, whereas a carbon offset can provide an enforceable contract that eliminates carbon from the atmosphere. On the basis of this disanalogy, market advocates reject the "indulgences" criticism. See, e.g., Vandenbergh & Steinemann, supra note 3, at 1722 n.235 (explaining that "[t]he analogy is false," id. at 1723 n.235). However, in making this argument, market advocates assume that eliminating the impact of the emission constitutes an elimination of what, if anything, is ethically objectionable about causing the emission. See, e.g., id. at 1720 ("Carbon neutrality .. . enables individuals to be confident that regardless of others' behavior, they are not contributing to the harm."). It is this assumption that will be challenged in this Note.
    • (1994) Kyklos , vol.47 , pp. 573
    • Goodin, R.E.1
  • 19
    • 33846595327 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Framing effects and regulatory choice
    • For a helpful summary of these debates, see 325-34 and Strahilevitz, supra note 1, at 1284-88. In general, scholars have long suggested that economic analyses and tools do not adequately protect the good of the environment
    • For a helpful summary of these debates, see Jonathan Remy Nash, Framing Effects and Regulatory Choice, 82 NOTRE DAME L. REV 313, 325-34 (2006); and Strahilevitz, supra note 1, at 1284-88. In general, scholars have long suggested that economic analyses and tools do not adequately protect the good of the environment.
    • (2006) Notre Dame L. Rev , vol.82 , pp. 313
    • Nash, J.R.1
  • 20
    • 33747860744 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What good is economics?
    • responding to the standard criticisms and making an environmental case for the use of economics
    • But see Barton H. Thompson, Jr., What Good Is Economics?, 37 U.C. DAVIS L. REV 175 (2003) (responding to the standard criticisms and making an environmental case for the use of economics).
    • (2003) U.C. Davis L. Rev , vol.37 , pp. 175
    • Thompson Jr., B.H.1
  • 21
    • 0345848795 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • From research to policy: The case of environmental economics
    • On the rising role of environmental economics in environmental legal policy over the past thirty years, see
    • On the rising role of environmental economics in environmental legal policy over the past thirty years, see Wallace E. Oates, From Research to Policy: The Case of Environmental Economics, 2000 U. ILL. L. REV 135.
    • U. Ill. L. Rev , vol.2000 , pp. 135
    • Oates, W.E.1
  • 22
    • 21144466470 scopus 로고
    • The use of market incentives in controlling air pollution: California's marketable permits program
    • For a short articulation of this argument, see Nash, supra note 10, at 326. See also III stating that some environmental groups and regulators claim that "creating property rights in pollution is morally wrong
    • For a short articulation of this argument, see Nash, supra note 10, at 326. See also John P. Dwyer, The Use of Market Incentives in Controlling Air Pollution: California's Marketable Permits Program, 20 ECOLOGY L.Q. 103, III (1993) (stating that some environmental groups and regulators claim that "creating property rights in pollution is morally wrong");
    • (1993) Ecology L.Q. , vol.20 , pp. 103
    • Dwyer, J.P.1
  • 23
    • 0037828403 scopus 로고
    • Markets, regulation, and environmental protection
    • 432 Most environmental groups have opposed the tradeable emissions approach, generally on the ground that no one should have a right to pollute
    • James L. Huffman, Markets, Regulation, and Environmental Protection, 55 MONT. L. REV 425, 432 (1994) ("Most environmental groups have opposed the tradeable emissions approach, generally on the ground that no one should have a right to pollute.").
    • (1994) Mont. L. Rev , vol.55 , pp. 425
    • Huffman, J.L.1
  • 24
    • 78149489837 scopus 로고
    • Strahilevitz, supra note i, at 1232; see also The 'license to pollute' that an economic incentives policy implies may influence citizen preferences in a direction that gives achievement of a clean environment less weight
    • Strahilevitz, supra note i, at 1232; see also STEVEN KELMAN, WHAT PRICE INCENTIVES?: ECONOMISTS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 49 (1981) ("The 'license to pollute' that an economic incentives policy implies may influence citizen preferences in a direction that gives achievement of a clean environment less weight.. ..");
    • (1981) What Price Incentives?: Economists and the Environment , vol.49
    • Kelman, S.1
  • 25
    • 38249000630 scopus 로고
    • Motivation as a limit to pricing
    • 652 Decision-makers fear that the use of pricing instruments would lead to a counterproductive effect: the quality of the environment is improved in those areas where tradeable licenses... are applied, but environmental quality is lowered in all other areas because the guiding environmental ethic has weakened or has been completely destroyed
    • Bruno S. Frey, Motivation as a Limit to Pricing, 14 J. ECON. PSYCHOL. 635, 652 (1993) ("Decision-makers fear that the use of pricing instruments would lead to a counterproductive effect: the quality of the environment is improved in those areas where tradeable licenses... are applied, but environmental quality is lowered in all other areas because the guiding environmental ethic has weakened or has been completely destroyed.
    • (1993) J. Econ. Psychol. , vol.14 , pp. 635
    • Frey, B.S.1
  • 26
    • 0348199090 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the expressive function of law
    • This reduced ethic moreover hampers individuals' willingness to accept any kind of action to fight pollution, i.e. political support for environmental policies would also be decreased."; 2045-46 Critics claim that emissions trading has damaging effects on social norms by making environmental amenities seem like any other commodity
    • This reduced ethic moreover hampers individuals' willingness to accept any kind of action to fight pollution, i.e. political support for environmental policies would also be decreased."); Cass R. Sunstein, On the Expressive Function of Law, 144 U. PA. L. REV 2021, 2045-46 (1996) ("Critics claim that emissions trading has damaging effects on social norms by making environmental amenities seem like any other commodity .. ..").
    • (1996) U. Pa. L. Rev , vol.144 , pp. 2021
    • Sunstein, C.R.1
  • 27
    • 78149487315 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a review of the critical responses to these lines of argument, see Nash, supra note 10, at 325-34; and Strahilevitz, supra note 1, at 1284-88
    • For a review of the critical responses to these lines of argument, see Nash, supra note 10, at 325-34; and Strahilevitz, supra note 1, at 1284-88.
  • 28
    • 78149477290 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is important to note that, unlike the purchase of regulatory offsets, the purchase of voluntary offsets does not involve the purchase of a right to pollute. If the offset is structured as a contract, it does create a right. But unlike in the regulatory context, it is merely a private right against the seller of the offset; the right against the public - the right to emit the carbon - preexists the creation of the contract or commodity
    • It is important to note that, unlike the purchase of regulatory offsets, the purchase of voluntary offsets does not involve the purchase of a right to pollute. If the offset is structured as a contract, it does create a right. But unlike in the regulatory context, it is merely a private right against the seller of the offset; the right against the public - the right to emit the carbon - preexists the creation of the contract or commodity.
  • 29
    • 78149480583 scopus 로고
    • 2d ed. General terms would be useless to us as a medium of communication unless there were such familiar, generally unchallenged cases
    • Cf. H.L.A. HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW 126 (2d ed. 1994) ("General terms would be useless to us as a medium of communication unless there were such familiar, generally unchallenged cases.")
    • (1994) The Concept of Law , vol.126
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 30
    • 34548851842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thoreau, Leopold, and Carson: Toward an Environmental Virtue Ethics
    • On the historical place of virtue ethics in some key environmentalist writings, see generally Ronald Sandler & Philip Cafaro eds
    • On the historical place of virtue ethics in some key environmentalist writings, see generally Philip Cafaro, Thoreau, Leopold, and Carson: Toward an Environmental Virtue Ethics, in ENVIRONMENTAL VIRTUE ETHICS 31 (Ronald Sandler & Philip Cafaro eds., 2005).
    • (2005) Environmental Virtue Ethics , vol.31
    • Cafaro, P.1
  • 31
    • 78149471881 scopus 로고
    • [T] he question comes up, 'What are rattlesnakes good for?' As if nothing that does not obviously make for the benefit of man had any right to exist; as if our ways were God's ways. .. . [T]he are all, head and tail, good for themselves, and we need not begrudge them their share of life
    • See, e.g., JOHN MUIR, OUR NATIONAL PARKS 57-58 (1901) ("[T] he question comes up, 'What are rattlesnakes good for?' As if nothing that does not obviously make for the benefit of man had any right to exist; as if our ways were God's ways. .. . [T]he are all, head and tail, good for themselves, and we need not begrudge them their share of life.");
    • (1901) Our National Parks , vol.57-58
    • Muir, J.1
  • 32
    • 0346488243 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Rhetoric and Reality of Nature Protection: Toward a New Discourse
    • 32-41 providing examples of this theme in American environmental writings and legislation
    • Holly Doremus, The Rhetoric and Reality of Nature Protection: Toward a New Discourse, 57 WASH. & LEE L. REV 11, 32-41 (2000) (providing examples of this theme in American environmental writings and legislation).
    • (2000) WASH. & LEE L. REV , vol.57 , pp. 11
    • Doremus, H.1
  • 33
    • 78149478179 scopus 로고
    • ed., Univ. of Wash. Press 2003 arguing that destruction of the forests threatened the future availability of natural resources essential to human prosperity; Doremus, supra note 17, at 16-23 (providing examples of this theme in American environmental writings and legislation)
    • See, e.g., GEORGE PERKINS MARSH, MAN AND NATURE 42-43 (David Lowenthal ed., Univ. of Wash. Press 2003) (1864) (arguing that destruction of the forests threatened the future availability of natural resources essential to human prosperity); Doremus, supra note 17, at 16-23 (providing examples of this theme in American environmental writings and legislation).
    • (1864) George Perkins Marsh, Man and Nature , vol.42-43
    • Lowenthal, D.1
  • 34
    • 78149483637 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For modern theories of environmental virtue ethics, see generally ENVIRONMENTAL VIRTUE ETHICS, supra note 16
    • For modern theories of environmental virtue ethics, see generally ENVIRONMENTAL VIRTUE ETHICS, supra note 16;
  • 37
    • 78149478513 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (internal quotation mark omitted). While this agent-centered approach is dominant in the literature, there is an alternative "agent-based" approach, according to which an act is right if and only if it exhibits good motivation
    • ROSALIND HURSTHOUSE, ON VIRTUE ETHICS 31 (1999) (internal quotation mark omitted). While this "agent-centered" approach is dominant in the literature, there is an alternative "agent-based" approach, according to which an act is right if and only if it exhibits good motivation.
    • (1999) On Virtue Ethics , vol.31
    • Hursthouse, R.1
  • 38
    • 0003952106 scopus 로고
    • developing an agent-based approach
    • See generally, e.g., MICHAEL SLOTE, FROM MORALITY TO VIRTUE (1992) (developing an agent-based approach).
    • (1992) From Morality to Virtue
    • Slote, M.1
  • 39
    • 33750720398 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Commons-based peer production and virtue
    • 404
    • Yochai Benkler & Helen Nissenbaum, Commons-based Peer Production and Virtue, 14 J. POL. PHIL. 394, 404 (2006).
    • (2006) J. Pol. Phil. , vol.14 , pp. 394
    • Benkler, Y.1    Nissenbaum, H.2
  • 41
    • 68949134356 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Land virtues
    • 865 The moral (or, perhaps more frequently, immoral) quality of certain sorts of conduct are often sufficiently categorical that their status can be captured by rules of thumb of varying degrees of breadth
    • Eduardo M. Peñalver, Land Virtues, 94 CORNELL L. REV 821, 865 (2009) ("The moral (or, perhaps more frequently, immoral) quality of certain sorts of conduct are often sufficiently categorical that their status can be captured by 'rules of thumb' of varying degrees of breadth.")
    • (2009) Cornell L. Rev , vol.94 , pp. 821
    • Peñalver, E.M.1
  • 42
    • 78149476756 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Peñalver, supra note 22, at 865 ("An action is virtuous because it is the sort of action a virtuous person undertakes; rules merely describe or generalize about what those actions would be under a range of uncontroversial circumstances.")
    • See Peñalver, supra note 22, at 865 ("An action is virtuous because it is the sort of action a virtuous person undertakes; rules merely describe or generalize about what those actions would be under a range of uncontroversial circumstances.").
  • 43
    • 78149486653 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • arguing that virtue is not only a manifestation of action, but a manifestation of appropriate emotions as well
    • See ROBERT MERRIHEW ADAMS, A THEORY OF VIRTUE: EXCELLENCE IN BEING FOR THE GOOD 9 (2006) (arguing that virtue is not only a manifestation of action, but a manifestation of appropriate emotions as well).
    • (2006) Robert Merrihew Adams, a Theory of Virtue: Excellence in Being for the Good , vol.9
  • 44
    • 78149475087 scopus 로고
    • For example, ojne who saves a child from drowning solely to enjoy the acclaim and publicity his act would most likely bring, has done the right thing but not in the right spirit, has done a good thing but not done it well, with a good motive
    • For example, "[ojne who saves a child from drowning solely to enjoy the acclaim and publicity his act would most likely bring, has done the right thing but not in the right spirit, has done a good thing but not done it well, with a good motive." N.J.H. DENT, THE MORAL PSYCHOLOGY OF THE VIRTUES 7 (1984).
    • (1984) N.J.H. Dent, the Moral Psychology of the Virtues , vol.7
  • 45
    • 78149482262 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, one who engages in acts of charity with a sense of condescension or disgust toward the people he helps has not acted with the right mode of relation. Peñalver, supra note 22, at 865. See also HURSTHOUSE, supra note 20, at 118-19, 123-26 (noting that the agent must have the "appropriate feeling(s) or attitude(s) when she acts," id. at 125)
    • For example, one "who engages in acts of charity with a sense of condescension or disgust toward the people he helps" has not acted with the right mode of relation. Peñalver, supra note 22, at 865. See also HURSTHOUSE, supra note 20, at 118-19, 123-26 (noting that the agent must have the "appropriate feeling(s) or attitude(s) when she acts," id. at 125).
  • 46
    • 78149483439 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HURSTHOUSE, supra note 20, at 11 ("If you have the virtues of, say, generosity, honesty, and justice, generous, honest, and just is the sort of person you are."); Peñalver, supra note 22, at 865 ("An action is 'brave' and therefore virtuous, not (ultimately) because it is consistent with a moral rule mandating a particular sort of action under a particular set of circumstances. The action is brave because it is the sort of action that a brave person would undertake when confronted by that situation.")
    • See HURSTHOUSE, supra note 20, at 11 ("If you have the virtues of, say, generosity, honesty, and justice, generous, honest, and just is the sort of person you are."); Peñalver, supra note 22, at 865 ("An action is 'brave' and therefore virtuous, not (ultimately) because it is consistent with a moral rule mandating a particular sort of action under a particular set of circumstances. The action is 'brave' because it is the sort of action that a brave person would undertake when confronted by that situation.").
  • 47
    • 0002046313 scopus 로고
    • developing a neo-Kantian, duty-based approach to ethics that treats virtue and character as important
    • Cf MÁRCIA W. BARON, KANTIAN ETHICS ALMOST WITHOUT APOLOGY (1995) (developing a neo-Kantian, duty-based approach to ethics that treats virtue and character as important);
    • (1995) Kantian Ethics Almost Without Apology
    • Baron, M.W.1
  • 49
    • 4544365118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • developing a version of consequentialism that draws on the insights of virtue ethics
    • Cf. JULIA DRIVER, UNEASY VIRTUE (2001) (developing a version of consequentialism that draws on the insights of virtue ethics);
    • (2001) Uneasy Virtue
    • Driver, J.1
  • 51
    • 0011101393 scopus 로고
    • Ways not to think about plastic trees: New foundations for environmental law
    • discussing the emergence of artificial environments and concluding that the logic that prompts the creation of plastic trees to satisfy our desires "leads finally not to human satisfaction but to the loss of humanity," id. at 1348
    • Cf. Laurence H. Tribe, Ways Not To Think About Plastic Trees: New Foundations for Environmental Law, 83 YALE L.J. 1315 (1974) (discussing the emergence of artificial environments and concluding that the logic that prompts the creation of plastic trees to satisfy our desires "leads finally not to human satisfaction but to the loss of humanity," id. at 1348).
    • (1974) Yale L.J. , vol.83 , pp. 1315
    • Tribe, L.H.1
  • 52
    • 78149478398 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ARISTOTLE, NlCOMACHEAN ETHICS bk. Ill, ch. 12, 1. 1119b, at 59 (Lesley Brown ed., David Ross trans., Oxford Univ. Press 2009) ("TJhe temperate man craves for the things he ought, as he ought, and when he ought; and this is what reason directs.")
    • See, e.g., ARISTOTLE, NlCOMACHEAN ETHICS bk. Ill, ch. 12, 1. 1119b, at 59 (Lesley Brown ed., David Ross trans., Oxford Univ. Press 2009) ("[TJhe temperate man craves for the things he ought, as he ought, and when he ought; and this is what reason directs.").
  • 53
    • 78149486545 scopus 로고
    • Phaedrus
    • Candace Ward ed., Benjamin Jowett trans., Dover Publ'ns The desire of eating, which gets the better of the higher reason and the other desires, is called gluttony, and he who is possessed by this is called a glutton
    • See, e.g., PLATO, Phaedrus, in SYMPOSIUM AND PHAEDRUS 45, 54 (Candace Ward ed., Benjamin Jowett trans., Dover Publ'ns 1993) ("The desire of eating, which gets the better of the higher reason and the other desires, is called gluttony, and he who is possessed by this is called a glutton . . ..").
    • (1993) Symposium and Phaedrus , vol.45 , pp. 54
    • Ward, C.1
  • 54
    • 78149491321 scopus 로고
    • discussing the "way out of the wastefulness of consumerism," id. at in, and, in the context of environmental conservation, referring to the logic of the glutton" and "man eating himself to death, id. at 181
    • Cf. WENDELL BERRY, A CONTINUOUS HARMONY m, 181 (1972) (discussing the "way out of the wastefulness of consumerism," id. at in, and, in the context of environmental conservation, referring to the logic of the "glutton" and "man eating himself to death," id. at 181).
    • (1972) A Continuous Harmony m , vol.181
    • Berry, W.1
  • 55
    • 78149481591 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Benkler & Nissenbaum, supra note 21, at 403-04
    • Benkler & Nissenbaum, supra note 21, at 403-04.
  • 56
    • 33750159669 scopus 로고
    • The regulation of social meaning
    • See generally, e.g., Lawrence Lessig, The Regulation of Social Meaning, 62 U. CHI. L. REV 943 (1995);
    • (1995) U. Chi. L. Rev , vol.62 , pp. 943
    • Lessig, L.1
  • 57
    • 0347614747 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Social meaning and social norms
    • Lawrence Lessig, Social Meaning and Social Norms, 144 U. PA. L. REV 2181 (1996);
    • (1996) U. Pa. L. Rev , vol.144 , pp. 2181
    • Lessig, L.1
  • 58
    • 60249090452 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Accounting for norms
    • Richard H. McAdams, Comment, Accounting for Norms, 1997 WIS. L. REV 625;
    • Wis. L. Rev , vol.1997 , pp. 625
    • McAdams, R.H.1
  • 59
    • 0001695934 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The origin, development, and regulation of norms
    • Richard H. McAdams, The Origin, Development, and Regulation of Norms, 96 MlCH. L. REV 338 (1997).
    • (1997) MlCH. L. REV , vol.96 , pp. 338
    • McAdams, R.H.1
  • 60
    • 2542452461 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Expressive theories of law: A general restatement
    • The scholarship on the expressive functions of law is particularly relevant here. See generally
    • The scholarship on the expressive functions of law is particularly relevant here. See generally Elizabeth S. Anderson & Richard H. Pildes, Expressive Theories of Law: A General Restatement, 148 U. PA. L. REV 1503 (2000);
    • (2000) U. Pa. L. Rev , vol.148 , pp. 1503
    • Anderson, E.S.1    Pildes, R.H.2
  • 61
    • 78149476427 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sunstein, supra note 12
    • Sunstein, supra note 12.
  • 62
    • 23044518161 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Expressive theories of law: A skeptical overview
    • For a criticism of this approach to law, see
    • For a criticism of this approach to law, see Matthew D. Adler, Expressive Theories of Law: A Skeptical Overview, 148 U. PA. L. REV 1363 (2000).
    • (2000) U. Pa. L. Rev , vol.148 , pp. 1363
    • Adler, M.D.1
  • 63
    • 78149488215 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Benkler & Nissenbaum, supra note 21 (arguing that participation in commonsbased peer production can foster important moral and political virtues); Peñalver, supra note 22 (developing a virtue-oriented approach to land use). Also relevant here is the scholarship in the social sciences showing that vjalues may be 'built into' technical design characteristics of technologies, which, in interaction with the social, political, economic and cultural characteristics of the contexts in which they are embedded, produce outcomes skewed in one way or another. Benkler & Nissenbaum, supra note 21, at 416.
    • See, e.g., Benkler & Nissenbaum, supra note 21 (arguing that participation in commonsbased peer production can foster important moral and political virtues); Peñalver, supra note 22 (developing a virtue-oriented approach to land use). Also relevant here is the scholarship in the social sciences showing that "[vjalues may be 'built into' technical design characteristics of technologies, which, in interaction with the social, political, economic and cultural characteristics of the contexts in which they are embedded, produce outcomes skewed in one way or another." Benkler & Nissenbaum, supra note 21, at 416.
  • 64
    • 78149489938 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lessig, The Regulation of Social Meaning, supra note 35, at 952 (noting that the meaning conveyed by buckling a seatbelt in a Budapest taxi, where no seatbelt is required by law, may signal mistrust of the driver, but that a similar action in a city with a seatbelt requirement may convey no meaning or, at most, signal that the occupant is law-abiding)
    • See, e.g., Lessig, The Regulation of Social Meaning, supra note 35, at 952 (noting that the meaning conveyed by buckling a seatbelt in a Budapest taxi, where no seatbelt is required by law, may signal mistrust of the driver, but that a similar action in a city with a seatbelt requirement may convey no meaning or, at most, signal that the occupant is law-abiding).
  • 65
    • 78149483116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For example, even if there were strong agreement that "environmentally conscious activity deserves esteem," or that "one should not pollute unnecessarily," the underlying categories of action might be reconstituted by applications of the norm to new situations. In a world with carbon offsets, there may be new questions about what counts as "polluting." If someone emits carbon, but buys an offset, he has not caused an aggregate increase in carbon, so one might question whether he has "caused pollution."
  • 66
    • 0019392722 scopus 로고
    • The framing of decisions and the psychology of choice
    • In general, the idea of framing effects is that the precise way in which a problem or choice is presented - i.e., its frame - may affect the decisionmaker's perception of the problem or choice, and ultimately the decisionmaker's preference. Nash, supra note 10, at 316. For more detailed discussions of this concept, see id. at 316-20 (presenting an overview of behavioral law and economics and its insights into framing effects); explaining framing effects and their significance to rational-choice theory
    • In general, the idea of framing effects is that "the precise way in which a problem or choice is presented - i.e., its frame - may affect the decisionmaker's perception of the problem or choice, and ultimately the decisionmaker's preference." Nash, supra note 10, at 316. For more detailed discussions of this concept, see id. at 316-20 (presenting an overview of behavioral law and economics and its insights into framing effects); and Amos Tversky & Daniel Kahneman, The Framing of Decisions and the Psychology of Choice, 211 SCI. 453 (1981) (explaining framing effects and their significance to rational-choice theory).
    • (1981) Sci. , vol.211 , pp. 453
    • Tversky, A.1    Kahneman, D.2
  • 67
    • 0035212713 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Motivation crowding theory
    • 603-04
    • See Bruno S. Frey & Reto Jegen, Motivation Crowding Theory, 15 J. ECON. SURVEYS 589, 603-04 (2001).
    • (2001) J. Econ. Surveys , vol.15 , pp. 589
    • Frey, B.S.1    Jegen, R.2
  • 69
    • 22744444496 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sharing Nicely: On Shareable Goods and the Emergence of Sharing as a Modality of Economic Production
    • Frey & Jegen, supra note 41 (surveying the literature on the crowding out effect). For an overview of the literature and some points of disagreement within it, see 321-28
    • See Frey & Jegen, supra note 41 (surveying the literature on the crowding out effect). For an overview of the literature and some points of disagreement within it, see Yochai Benkler, Sharing Nicely: On Shareable Goods and the Emergence of Sharing as a Modality of Economic Production, 114 YALE LJ. 273, 321-28 (2004).
    • (2004) Yale LJ. , vol.114 , pp. 273
    • Benkler, Y.1
  • 70
    • 78149475518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One of the most developed accounts is Professor Bruno Frey's psychological model of crowding out, which Benkler summarizes clearly: A simple statement of this model is that individuals have intrinsic and extrinsic motivations. . .. Extrinsic motivations are said to crowd out intrinsic motivations because they (a) impair self-determination - that is, a person feels pressured by an external force, and therefore feels overjustified in maintaining her intrinsic motivation rather than complying with the will of the source of the extrinsic reward; or (b) impair selfesteem - they cause an individual to feel that his internal motivation is rejected, not valued, leading him to reduce his self-esteem and thus to reduce effort
    • One of the most developed accounts is Professor Bruno Frey's psychological model of crowding out, which Benkler summarizes clearly: A simple statement of this model is that individuals have intrinsic and extrinsic motivations. . .. Extrinsic motivations are said to "crowd out" intrinsic motivations because they (a) impair self-determination - that is, a person feels pressured by an external force, and therefore feels overjustified in maintaining her intrinsic motivation rather than complying with the will of the source of the extrinsic reward; or (b) impair selfesteem - they cause an individual to feel that his internal motivation is rejected, not valued, leading him to reduce his self-esteem and thus to reduce effort.
  • 71
    • 78149476863 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Benkler, supra note 43, at 323-24
    • Benkler, supra note 43, at 323-24.
  • 72
    • 78149487762 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 325 ("Frey's psychologically based extrinsic-/intrinsic- motivation distinction is helpful, and the empirical evidence is powerful. The psychological construct does not, however, seem fully to account for motivation in social sharing frameworks.")
    • Id. at 325 ("Frey's psychologically based extrinsic-/intrinsic- motivation distinction is helpful, and the empirical evidence is powerful. The psychological construct does not, however, seem fully to account for motivation in social sharing frameworks.").
  • 73
    • 78149489836 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Environmental morale and motivation
    • Even Frey, the main proponent of the psychological explanation, is sympathetic to the idea that framing plays a central role. See, e.g., Frey & Jegen, supra note 41, at 592 (suggesting that crowding out may be the result of changes in "the perceived nature of the performed task" or "the task-environment" (emphasis omitted)); see also Working Paper No. 288, arguing that tradeable emissions rights and emissions taxes could create different crowding-out effects because of differences in their "expressive connotation id. at 15
    • Even Frey, the main proponent of the psychological explanation, is sympathetic to the idea that framing plays a central role. See, e.g., Frey & Jegen, supra note 41, at 592 (suggesting that crowding out may be the result of changes in "the perceived nature of the performed task" or "the task-environment" (emphasis omitted)); see also Bruno S. Frey & Alois Stutzer, Environmental Morale and Motivation 14-16 (Univ. of Zurich, Inst, for Empirical Research in Econ., Working Paper No. 288, 2006), available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract-id=900370 (arguing that tradeable emissions rights and emissions taxes could create different crowding-out effects because of differences in their "expressive connotation," id. at 15).
    • (2006) Univ. of Zurich, Inst, for Empirical Research in Econ. , vol.14-16
    • Frey, B.S.1    Stutzer, A.2
  • 74
    • 0004181556 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 20th anniversary ed. arguing that capitalism and the culture it creates harbors the origins of its own collapse by creating a need among successful people for personal gratification - a need that corrodes the work ethic that originally led to their success
    • Cf. DANIEL BELL, THE CULTURAL CONTRADICTIONS OF CAPITALISM (20th anniversary ed. 1996) (arguing that capitalism and the culture it creates harbors the origins of its own collapse by creating a need among successful people for personal gratification - a need that corrodes the work ethic that originally led to their success).
    • (1996) The Cultural Contradictions of Capitalism
    • Bell, D.1
  • 75
    • 78149482694 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Consumption in this context can be conceptualized in two ways that are directly related: the consumption of the resource that produces the emissions, and the consumption of the ability of the atmosphere to process the emissions
    • Consumption in this context can be conceptualized in two ways that are directly related: the consumption of the resource that produces the emissions, and the consumption of the ability of the atmosphere to process the emissions.
  • 76
    • 0347303712 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mixed theories of tort law: Affirming both deterrence and corrective justice
    • This development parallels one in tort law, where the standard of negligence has shifted from being an evaluation of whether the act that caused the harm was ethically objectionable to being an evaluation of whether the act was economically efficient. See 1802-11 providing a brief overview of the corrective justice and economic efficiency views of tort law
    • This development parallels one in tort law, where the standard of negligence has shifted from being an evaluation of whether the act that caused the harm was ethically objectionable to being an evaluation of whether the act was economically efficient. See Gary T. Schwartz, Mixed Theories of Tort Law: Affirming Both Deterrence and Corrective Justice, 75 TEX. L. REV 1801, 1802-11 (1997) (providing a brief overview of the corrective justice and economic efficiency views of tort law).
    • (1997) Tex. L. Rev , vol.75 , pp. 1801
    • Schwartz, G.T.1
  • 77
    • 0142231545 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Twentieth-century tort theory
    • For a more detailed exposition and analysis of the development of the dominant theories of tort law in the twentieth century, see generally
    • For a more detailed exposition and analysis of the development of the dominant theories of tort law in the twentieth century, see generally John CP. Goldberg, Twentieth-Century Tort Theory, 91 GEO. L.J. 513 (2003).
    • (2003) Geo. L.J. , vol.91 , pp. 513
    • Goldberg, J.C.P.1
  • 79
    • 78149472168 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The average price of carbon in the over-the-counter market in 2008 was $7.34 per metric ton. HAMILTON ET AL., FORTIFYING THE FOUNDATION, supra note 2, at 7
    • The average price of carbon in the over-the-counter market in 2008 was $7.34 per metric ton. HAMILTON ET AL., FORTIFYING THE FOUNDATION, supra note 2, at 7.
  • 80
    • 78149486324 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, the individual might decide that the cost of driving the SUV over the sedan is not as high as he had thought - that the enjoyment of driving the SUV is worth an extra nine dollars per year - and choose to buy the SUV and pay for this offset, thereby remaining carbon neutral (that is, with respect to the baseline of buying the sedan). Or he might conclude that the impact on the environment is not as high as he had imagined, and thus decide to buy the SUV without the offsets, without feeling any guilt
    • For example, the individual might decide that the cost of driving the SUV over the sedan is not as high as he had thought - that the enjoyment of driving the SUV is worth an extra nine dollars per year - and choose to buy the SUV and pay for this offset, thereby remaining "carbon neutral" (that is, with respect to the baseline of buying the sedan). Or he might conclude that the impact on the environment is not as high as he had imagined, and thus decide to buy the SUV without the offsets, without feeling any guilt.
  • 81
    • 78149480810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On this account, the consumers without a market are failing to act in accordance with their own environmental preferences or values by over- and under-correcting for their personal emissions
    • On this account, the consumers without a market are failing to act in accordance with their own environmental preferences or values by over- and under-correcting for their personal emissions.
  • 82
    • 78149492072 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Vandenbergh & Steinemann, supra note 3, at 1725
    • Vandenbergh & Steinemann, supra note 3, at 1725.
  • 83
    • 0002563028 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Endogenous preferences: The cultural consequences of markets and other economic institutions
    • 75 also id. at 77 ("EJconomic institutions are situations in the social psychological sense and thus have framing and other situation construal effects; people make different choices depending on whether the identical feasible set they face is generated by a market-like process or not. . ..")
    • Samuel Bowles, Endogenous Preferences: The Cultural Consequences of Markets and Other Economic Institutions, 36 J. ECON. LITERATURE 75, 75 (1998); see also id. at 77 ("[EJconomic institutions are situations in the social psychological sense and thus have framing and other situation construal effects; people make different choices depending on whether the identical feasible set they face is generated by a market-like process or not. . ..").
    • (1998) J. Econ. Literature , vol.36 , pp. 75
    • Bowles, S.1
  • 84
    • 0001303186 scopus 로고
    • Economic theory and environmental law
    • 1402-03
    • See Mark Sagoff, Economic Theory and Environmental Law, 79 MICH. L. REV 1393, 1402-03 (1981);
    • (1981) Mich. L. Rev , vol.79 , pp. 1393
    • Sagoff, M.1
  • 85
    • 0003491171 scopus 로고
    • At the shrine of our lady of fátima or why political questions are not all economic
    • 1286 I speed on the highway; yet I want the police to enforce laws against speeding. ... I love my car; I hate the bus. Yet I vote for candidates who promise to tax gasoline to pay for public transportation. ... I support almost any political cause that I think will defeat my consumer interests. This is because I have contempt for - although I act upon - those interests. I have an 'Ecology Now' sticker on a car that leaks oil everywhere it's parked
    • see also Mark Sagoff, At the Shrine of Our Lady of Fátima or Why Political Questions Are Not All Economic, 23 ARIZ. L. REV 1283, 1286 (1981) ("I speed on the highway; yet I want the police to enforce laws against speeding. ... I love my car; I hate the bus. Yet I vote for candidates who promise to tax gasoline to pay for public transportation. ... I support almost any political cause that I think will defeat my consumer interests. This is because I have contempt for - although I act upon - those interests. I have an 'Ecology Now' sticker on a car that leaks oil everywhere it's parked.").
    • (1981) Ariz. L. Rev , vol.23 , pp. 1283
    • Sagoff, M.1
  • 86
    • 78149483328 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gneezy & Rustichini, supra note 42
    • See Gneezy & Rustichini, supra note 42.
  • 87
    • 78149486652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 13-14. For other possible explanations, see id. at 10-13. Notably, the subsequent removal of the fine did not bring back the norm. Id. at 15. The authors suggest that this might be explained by another social convention: Once a commodity, always a commodity. Id. at 16
    • Id. at 13-14. For other possible explanations, see id. at 10-13. Notably, the subsequent removal of the fine did not bring back the norm. Id. at 15. The authors suggest that this might be explained by another social convention: "Once a commodity, always a commodity." Id. at 16.
  • 88
    • 0006916513 scopus 로고
    • Reforming environmental law: The democratic case for market incentives
    • On this view, it would seem that a market may not be democracy-enhancing, as many advocates of regulatory markets suggest. See, e.g., 178-88 arguing that, in the regulatory context, the shift from command and control to cap-and-trade will catalyze meaningful discussion by the public about the environment in which we want to live
    • On this view, it would seem that a market may not be democracy-enhancing, as many advocates of regulatory markets suggest. See, e.g., Bruce A. Ackerman & Richard B. Stewart, Reforming Environmental Law: The Democratic Case for Market Incentives, 13 COLUM. J. ENVTL. L. 171, 178-88 (1988) (arguing that, in the regulatory context, the shift from command and control to cap-and-trade will catalyze meaningful discussion by the public about the environment in which we want to live).
    • (1988) Colum. J. Envtl. L. , vol.13 , pp. 171
    • Ackerman, B.A.1    Stewart, R.B.2
  • 89
    • 84929302778 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • arguing that bioethics has become thin in recent decades, focused no longer on an inquiry into what ends are worth achieving, but rather on finding the most efficacious means of achieving assumed ends
    • Cf. JOHN H. EVANS, PLAYING GOD?: HUMAN GENETIC ENGINEERING AND THE RATIONALIZATION OF PUBLIC BIOETHICAL DEBATE (2002) (arguing that bioethics has become thin in recent decades, focused no longer on an inquiry into what ends are worth achieving, but rather on finding the most efficacious means of achieving assumed ends);
    • (2002) Playing God?: Human Genetic Engineering and the Rationalization of Public Bioethical Debate
    • Evans, J.H.1
  • 90
    • 77950254583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • From thick to thin: Two moral reduction plans
    • 515-16 Many philosophers of the last century thought all moral judgments can be expressed using a few basic concepts - what are today called thin moral concepts such as 'good,' 'bad,' 'right,' and 'wrong.' ... In recent decades a contrary view has emerged .... According to its proponents, terms like 'courageous' and 'kindly' have both morally evaluative and descriptive meaning, but the two interpenetrate each other in a way that makes the separation a reductive analysis requires impossible. Thick concepts are therefore not derivative from thin ones.... On the contrary, on some versions of this anti-reductive view it is the thick concepts that are primary, with the thin ones mere abstractions from them.". Advocates of carbon offsets seem to accept the idea that the norm of carbon neutrality is fairly thin, in that it requires only a minimal conception of the nature of the good life
    • Daniel Y. Elstein & Thomas Hurka, From Thick to Thin: Two Moral Reduction Plans, 39 CANADIAN J. PHIL. 515, 515-16 (2009) ("Many philosophers of the last century thought all moral judgments can be expressed using a few basic concepts - what are today called 'thin' moral concepts such as 'good,' 'bad,' 'right,' and 'wrong.' ... In recent decades a contrary view has emerged .... According to its proponents, terms like 'courageous' and 'kindly' have both morally evaluative and descriptive meaning, but the two interpenetrate each other in a way that makes the separation a reductive analysis requires impossible. Thick concepts are therefore not derivative from thin ones.... On the contrary, on some versions of this anti-reductive view it is the thick concepts that are primary, with the thin ones mere abstractions from them."). Advocates of carbon offsets seem to accept the idea that the norm of carbon neutrality is fairly thin, in that it requires only a minimal conception of the nature of the good life.
    • (2009) Canadian J. Phil. , vol.39 , pp. 515
    • Elstein, D.Y.1    Hurka, T.2
  • 91
    • 78149481041 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Vandenbergh & Steinemann, supra note 3, at 1721 ("Compliance with the carbon-neutrality norm does not require that individuals adopt other environmental beliefs, norms, or lifestyles that are inconsistent with their own.")
    • See, e.g., Vandenbergh & Steinemann, supra note 3, at 1721 ("Compliance with the carbon-neutrality norm does not require that individuals adopt other environmental beliefs, norms, or lifestyles that are inconsistent with their own.").
  • 92
    • 78149486439 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Undervaluation is not inherent to the market framework, as the market may just as likely place a dollar value on an activity that is higher than expected or that overvalues the environment
    • Undervaluation is not inherent to the market framework, as the market may just as likely place a dollar value on an activity that is higher than expected or that "overvalues" the environment.
  • 93
    • 0004289733 scopus 로고
    • discussing the history of American approaches to military service
    • See generally GUIDO CALABRESI & PHILIP BOBBITT, TRAGIC CHOICES 158-65 (1978) (discussing the history of American approaches to military service);
    • (1978) Tragic Choices , vol.158-165
    • Calabresi, G.1    Bobbitt, P.2
  • 94
    • 78149478734 scopus 로고
    • providing an overview of the Civil War system of conscription
    • JAMES M. MCPHERSON, BATTLE CRY OF FREEDOM 600-11 (1988) (providing an overview of the Civil War system of conscription).
    • (1988) Battle Cry of Freedom , vol.600 , Issue.11
    • Mcpherson, J.M.1
  • 95
    • 78149481588 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The view that embodied action and payment are not morally equivalent presumably prevails in other contexts as well. Take, for example, a debate about vegetarianism. The market logic would suggest that someone who feels compelled by vegetarian arguments could, rather than changing his own eating habits, pay someone else to change instead - that morally speaking, there would be no difference. It seems likely, however, that many people would disagree on the grounds that paying another and changing one's personal consumption are not equivalent
    • The view that embodied action and payment are not morally equivalent presumably prevails in other contexts as well. Take, for example, a debate about vegetarianism. The market logic would suggest that someone who feels compelled by vegetarian arguments could, rather than changing his own eating habits, pay someone else to change instead - that morally speaking, there would be no difference. It seems likely, however, that many people would disagree on the grounds that paying another and changing one's personal consumption are not equivalent.
  • 96
    • 78149490879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some people would likely argue that military service is a type of action that can belong in a special category of civic duties that require all individuals to do their part by sharing equally in the burden of action - and that environmental duties do not or should not have this status. Others would respond that environmental protection, like national security, is about protecting a special form of common good and that similar types of social norms should protect both
    • Some people would likely argue that military service is a type of action that can belong in a special category of civic duties that require all individuals to "do their part" by sharing equally in the burden of action - and that environmental duties do not or should not have this status. Others would respond that environmental protection, like national security, is about protecting a special form of common good and that similar types of social norms should protect both.
  • 97
    • 0006914518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rethinking environmental controls: Management strategies for common resources
    • 34 When we reconceptualize the use of common resources as individual property rights, we attenuate the moral rhetoric of contribution and trying harder for the common good
    • Cf. Carol M. Rose, Rethinking Environmental Controls: Management Strategies for Common Resources, 1991 DUKE LJ. 1, 34 ("When we reconceptualize the use of common resources as individual property rights, we attenuate the moral rhetoric of contribution and trying harder for the common good.").
    • Duke LJ. , vol.1991 , pp. 1
    • Rose, C.M.1
  • 98
    • 78149475988 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is, of course, not the only way that a voluntary carbon market might function. For example, one can imagine a society in which it is agreed that only certain types of activities (such as those that are seen as reasonable) can be meaningfully offset - a society in which, for example, the owner of a mega-yacht cannot comply with environmental norms merely by buying offsets for it. In the interest of clarifying the core market case, however, this section will explore the environmental significance of a society in which there are no such limitations
    • This is, of course, not the only way that a voluntary carbon market might function. For example, one can imagine a society in which it is agreed that only certain types of activities (such as those that are seen as reasonable) can be meaningfully offset - a society in which, for example, the owner of a mega-yacht cannot comply with environmental norms merely by buying offsets for it. In the interest of clarifying the core market case, however, this section will explore the environmental significance of a society in which there are no such limitations.
  • 99
    • 78149484267 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note that categorical prohibitions do have a place in virtue ethics. See sources cited supra note 22
    • Note that categorical prohibitions do have a place in virtue ethics. See sources cited supra note 22.
  • 100
    • 78149478397 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Economic incentives for environmental protection: Opportunities and obstacles
    • note
    • Nash, supra note io, at 360-61 ("Pollution is a necessary byproduct of many beneficial activities and services; racial discrimination and murder simply are not. Thus, while it is appropriate fully to condemn racial discrimination and murder, the same is not true of pollution." (footnotes omitted)); see also, e.g., Huffman, supra note 11, at 432-33 ("Most environmental groups have opposed the tradeable emissions approach, generally on the ground that no one should have a right to pollute. . .. These moral arguments lead inexorably to the implausible case for zero pollution. In a world of organic and inorganic processes, with or without humans, zero pollution is neither possible nor desirable."); Rose, supra note 65, at 7 ("Most people are willing to put up with some level of air pollution, because we think we need to do so for our transportation and electricity, among other things, which in themselves may be more important to our health and well-being than the next increment of clean air."); Richard B. Stewart, Economic Incentives for Environmental Protection: Opportunities and Obstacles, in ENVIRONMENTAL LAW, THE ECONOMY, AND SUSTAINABLE DEVELOPMENT 171, 199 (Richard L. Revesz et al. eds., 2000) ("The discharge within proper limits of residuals from socially productive activities. . . can by no means be equated with sin or murder or racial discrimination. The laws of physics make such residuals an inevitable consequence of human activity. Zero residuals discharge is an unattainable and undesirable objective."). As Professor Nash notes, however, "even if the eradication of pollution is not itself viable, it can be identified - and indeed is identified in various pollution control statutes - as a societal aspiration."
    • (2000) Environmental Law, the Economy, and Sustainable Development , vol.171 , pp. 199
    • Stewart, R.B.1
  • 101
    • 78149474865 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nash, supra note 10, at 340 n.105
    • Nash, supra note 10, at 340 n.105;
  • 102
    • 78149477182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Clean Water Act § 101(a)(1), 33 U.S.C § 1251(a)(1) (2006) ("IJt is the national goal that the discharge of pollutants into the navigable waters be eliminated by 1985 . . ..")
    • see also Clean Water Act § 101(a)(1), 33 U.S.C § 1251(a)(1) (2006) ("[IJt is the national goal that the discharge of pollutants into the navigable waters be eliminated by 1985 . . ..").
  • 103
    • 78149489629 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nash, supra note 10, at 334-43
    • See Nash, supra note 10, at 334-43;
  • 104
    • 0042715443 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Global environmental regulation: Instrument choice in legal context
    • 724 noting that it is conduct rules and fixed quantity rules, ironically, that truly license a right to pollute for free
    • see also Jonathan Baert Wiener, Global Environmental Regulation: Instrument Choice in Legal Context, 108 YALE LJ. 677, 724 (1999) (noting that "it is conduct rules and fixed quantity rules, ironically, that truly license a right to pollute for free").
    • (1999) Yale LJ. , vol.108 , pp. 677
    • Wiener, J.B.1
  • 105
    • 78149492504 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nash, supra note 10, at 361
    • Nash, supra note 10, at 361.
  • 106
    • 78149482027 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. id. ("The appropriateness of a pollution emission can ... be judged in light of the benefit that results from the activity that produces the pollution as a byproduct")
    • Cf. id. ("The appropriateness of a pollution emission can ... be judged in light of the benefit that results from the activity that produces the pollution as a byproduct").
  • 107
    • 0346039201 scopus 로고
    • Reassessing boomer: Justice, efficiency, and nuisance law
    • In some cases, there will be disagreement. For example, while the law and economics literature often suggests that a tort is a mere price, there have been some objections to this theory on the grounds that the tortfeasor is being permitted to steal or condemn the other's entitlement. See generally, e.g., Peter Hay & Michael H. Hoeflich eds., arguing that victims of egregious nuisances "should be presumptively entitled to an injunction, id. at 8
    • In some cases, there will be disagreement. For example, while the law and economics literature often suggests that a tort is a mere price, there have been some objections to this theory on the grounds that the tortfeasor is being permitted to "steal" or condemn the other's entitlement. See generally, e.g., Daniel A. Färber, Reassessing Boomer: Justice, Efficiency, and Nuisance Law, in PROPERTY LAW AND LEGAL EDUCATION 7 (Peter Hay & Michael H. Hoeflich eds., 1988) (arguing that victims of egregious nuisances "should be presumptively entitled to an injunction," id. at 8);
    • (1988) Property Law and Legal Education , vol.7
    • Färber, D.A.1
  • 108
    • 0041964522 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Unifying remedies: Property rules, liability rules, and startling rules
    • 2165 n.48
    • see also Saul Levmore, Unifying Remedies: Property Rules, Liability Rules, and Startling Rules, 106 YALE LJ. 2149, 2165 n.48 (1997).
    • (1997) Yale LJ. , vol.106 , pp. 2149
    • Levmore, S.1
  • 109
    • 0345848931 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Norms as Supplements
    • arguing that norms help us to know whether to regard legal rules and sanctions as mere prices or as something to be followed even where we are willing to pay the stated, legal price associated with a violation, id. at 1990
    • Cf. Saul Levmore, Norms as Supplements, 86 VA. L. REV 1989 (2000) (arguing that "norms help us to know whether to regard legal rules and sanctions as mere prices or as something to be followed even where we are willing to pay the stated, legal price associated with a violation," id. at 1990);
    • (2000) Va. L. Rev , vol.86 , pp. 1989
    • Levmore, S.1
  • 110
    • 84935322680 scopus 로고
    • Prices and sanctions
    • 1524-31 discussing the different functions of prices and sanctions
    • see also Robert Cooter, Prices and Sanctions, 84 COLUM. L. REV 1523, 1524-31 (1984) (discussing the different functions of prices and sanctions).
    • (1984) Colum. L. Rev , vol.84 , pp. 1523
    • Cooter, R.1
  • 111
    • 0347569386 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What do alternative sanctions mean?
    • In the criminal law context, for example, Professor Dan Kahan has argued that we should reject proposals to replace imprisonment with more cheaply administered sanctions, such as fines, because it is easy to see a fine as a mere price, which fails to condemn the activity sufficiently - an important goal according to both deterrent and retributive theories of punishment. See Thus, he argues, the government should combine fines with prison sentences, which stigmatize the action in a way that causes internalization of the categorical prohibition. Id. at 650-51; see also Lessig, Social Meaning and Social Norms, supra note 35, at 2188 ("By tying the fine to some other unambiguously condemnatory punishment, one reduces on the margin the ambiguity in fining .. . .")
    • In the criminal law context, for example, Professor Dan Kahan has argued that we should reject proposals to replace imprisonment with more cheaply administered sanctions, such as fines, because it is easy to see a fine as a mere price, which fails to condemn the activity sufficiently - an important goal according to both deterrent and retributive theories of punishment. See Dan M. Kahan, What Do Alternative Sanctions Mean?, 63 U. CHI. L. REV 591 (1996). Thus, he argues, the government should combine fines with prison sentences, which stigmatize the action in a way that causes internalization of the categorical prohibition. Id. at 650-51; see also Lessig, Social Meaning and Social Norms, supra note 35, at 2188 ("By tying the fine to some other unambiguously condemnatory punishment, one reduces on the margin the ambiguity in fining .. . .").
    • (1996) U. Chi. L. Rev , vol.63 , pp. 591
    • Kahan, D.M.1
  • 112
    • 78149482478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is an argument that has been widely advanced in the regulatory context. See, e.g., Stewart, supra note 68, at 198 ("CJommand-and-control regulation does not stigmatize or send any negative signal with respect to the residuals that are permitted by command standards. By contrast, [economic incentive systems] impose an economic cost on all residuals, reminding sources that any level of residuals may impose social costs.); Wiener, supra note 69, at 724 (Taxes and tradeable allowances, by contrast, force the polluter to pay for every unit of emissions. .. ."). Regarding voluntary offsets, it has been argued that individuals who mitigate their contribution to social harms expect reciprocity from others, including the government. See, e.g., Vandenbergh & Steinemann, supra note 3, at 1723
    • This is an argument that has been widely advanced in the regulatory context. See, e.g., Stewart, supra note 68, at 198 ("[CJommand-and-control regulation does not stigmatize or send any negative signal with respect to the residuals that are permitted by command standards. By contrast, [economic incentive systems] impose an economic cost on all residuals, reminding sources that any level of residuals may impose social costs."); Wiener, supra note 69, at 724 ("Taxes and tradeable allowances, by contrast, force the polluter to pay for every unit of emissions. .. ."). Regarding voluntary offsets, it has been argued that individuals who mitigate their contribution to social harms expect reciprocity from others, including the government. See, e.g., Vandenbergh & Steinemann, supra note 3, at 1723.
  • 113
    • 78149472923 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is not to say that under the market, no unit can have a high value. Rather, the point is that no unit matters very much relative to any other. There is no differentiation of types of emission units, and in this sense, none has particular significance. All units are fungible
    • This is not to say that under the market, no unit can have a high value. Rather, the point is that no unit matters very much relative to any other. There is no differentiation of types of emission units, and in this sense, none has particular significance. All units are fungible.
  • 114
    • 78149474225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Benkler, supra note 43, at 324 (noting that the crowding out effect seems to arise from a "culturally contingent notion of what one 'ought' to do if one is a well-adjusted human being and member of a decent society")
    • Cf. Benkler, supra note 43, at 324 (noting that the crowding out effect seems to arise from a "culturally contingent notion of what one 'ought' to do if one is a well-adjusted human being and member of a decent society").
  • 115
    • 78149486438 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. HART, supra note 15, at 88-91 (distinguishing between the internal and external view of social rules). Professor H.L.A. Hart explains: What the external point of view, which limits itself to the observable regularities of behaviour, cannot reproduce is the way in which the rules function as rules in the lives of those who normally are the majority of society. .. . For them the violation of a rule is not merely a basis for the prediction that a hostile reaction will follow but a reason for hostility
    • Cf. HART, supra note 15, at 88-91 (distinguishing between the internal and external view of social rules). Professor H.L.A. Hart explains: What the external point of view, which limits itself to the observable regularities of behaviour, cannot reproduce is the way in which the rules function as rules in the lives of those who normally are the majority of society. .. . For them the violation of a rule is not merely a basis for the prediction that a hostile reaction will follow but a reason for hostility.
  • 116
    • 78149476647 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 90. On community and reason, Professor Stanley Cavell writes: The philosophical appeal to what we say, and the search for our criteria on the basis of which we say what we say, are claims to community. And the claim to community is always a search for the basis upon which it can or has been established. I have nothing more to go on than my conviction, my sense that I make sense. It may prove to be the case that I am wrong, that my conviction isolates me, from all others, from myself. That will not be the same as a discovery that I am dogmatic or egomaniacal. The wish and search for community are the wish and search for reason
    • Id. at 90. On community and reason, Professor Stanley Cavell writes: The philosophical appeal to what we say, and the search for our criteria on the basis of which we say what we say, are claims to community. And the claim to community is always a search for the basis upon which it can or has been established. I have nothing more to go on than my conviction, my sense that I make sense. It may prove to be the case that I am wrong, that my conviction isolates me, from all others, from myself. That will not be the same as a discovery that I am dogmatic or egomaniacal. The wish and search for community are the wish and search for reason.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.