메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 39, Issue 4, 2009, Pages 515-535

From thick to thin: Two moral reduction plans

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 77950254583     PISSN: 00455091     EISSN: 19110820     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1353/cjp.0.0063     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (62)

References (36)
  • 1
    • 61449325192 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Through thick and thin: Good and its determinates
    • e.g.
    • See, e.g., Christine Tappolet, 'Through Thick and Thin: Good and its Determinates, ' Dialectica 58 (2004) 207-20
    • (2004) Dialectica , vol.58 , pp. 207-220
    • Tappolet, C.1
  • 2
    • 84977360988 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In defense of thick concepts
    • e.g., in Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling, Jr., and Howard K. Wettstein, eds., (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press
    • See, e.g., Jonathan Dancy, 'In Defense of Thick Concepts, ' in Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling, Jr., and Howard K. Wettstein, eds., Midwest Studies in Philosophy XX: Moral Concepts (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press 1996), 263-79
    • (1996) Midwest Studies in Philosophy XX: Moral Concepts , pp. 263-279
    • Dancy, J.1
  • 4
    • 0000322565 scopus 로고
    • Virtue and reason
    • 'Virtue and Reason, ' The Monist 62 (1979) 331-50
    • (1979) The Monist , vol.62 , pp. 331-350
  • 5
    • 85068201368 scopus 로고
    • Non-cognitivism and rule-following
    • in S. H. Holtzman and C. M. Leich, eds., (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul
    • and 'Non-Cognitivism and Rule-Following, ' in S. H. Holtzman and C. M. Leich, eds., Wittgenstein: To Follow a Rule (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul 1981) 141-62
    • (1981) Wittgenstein: To Follow a Rule , pp. 141-162
  • 6
    • 61049538895 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The acceptance of supervenience and denial of universalizability come in
    • The acceptance of supervenience and denial of universalizability come in 'Non-Cognitivism and Rule-Following, ' 144-5
    • Non-Cognitivism and Rule-Following , pp. 144-145
  • 8
    • 85036754335 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We do not of course claim that adherents of the reductive view typically accept uncodifiability; most reject it. Our claim is just that if uncodifiability applies to thin as well as thick judgments, it cuts no ice against the reductive view
    • We do not of course claim that adherents of the reductive view typically accept uncodifiability; most reject it. Our claim is just that if uncodifiability applies to thin as well as thick judgments, it cuts no ice against the reductive view
  • 10
    • 0004195469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Bernard Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press 1985), 130, 141-2
    • (1985) Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy , vol.130 , pp. 141-142
    • Williams, B.1
  • 12
    • 77950291798 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The entanglement of fact and value
    • in, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, at 34-40
    • Hilary Putnam, 'The Entanglement of Fact and Value, ' in The Collapse of the Fact/Value Dichotomy and Other Essays (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press 2002) 28-45, at 34-40
    • (2002) The Collapse of the Fact/Value Dichotomy and Other Essays , pp. 28-45
    • Putnam, H.1
  • 13
    • 25444477820 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ethics and ontology
    • at 305-6
    • Charles Taylor, 'Ethics and Ontology, ' Journal of Philosophy 100 (2003) 305-20, at 305-6
    • (2003) Journal of Philosophy , vol.100 , pp. 305-320
    • Taylor, C.1
  • 15
    • 0005415497 scopus 로고
    • Through Thick and Thin
    • Simon Blackburn has implicitly denied it, when he argues that most proposed thick concepts are purely descriptive, with no specific evaluations built into their content. 'Frugal, ' for example, while often a term of praise, is the opposite when used of a host dispensing hospitality (', and, at 285-7) , While this is a possible response to the disentanglement argument, we will follow a different tack and grant both that thick concepts have specific evaluations built into their contents and that their extensions depend on evaluations
    • Simon Blackburn has implicitly denied it, when he argues that most proposed thick concepts are purely descriptive, with no specific evaluations built into their content. 'Frugal, ' for example, while often a term of praise, is the opposite when used of a host dispensing hospitality ('Through Thick and Thin, 'Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 66 (1992) 285-99, at 285-7). While this is a possible response to the disentanglement argument, we will follow a different tack and grant both that thick concepts have specific evaluations built into their contents and that their extensions depend on evaluations
    • (1992) Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume , vol.66 , pp. 285-299
  • 16
    • 0004133850 scopus 로고
    • (New Haven: Yale University Press
    • C. L. Stevenson, Ethics and Language (New Haven: Yale University Press 1944), 206-7
    • (1944) Ethics and Language , pp. 206-207
    • Stevenson, C.L.1
  • 17
    • 0003599888 scopus 로고
    • (Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • R. M. Hare, The Language of Morals (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1952), 121
    • (1952) The Language of Morals , pp. 121
    • Hare, R.M.1
  • 18
    • 0004123120 scopus 로고
    • (Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Hare, Freedom and Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1963), 121-9
    • (1963) Freedom and Reason , pp. 121-129
    • Hare1
  • 19
    • 0039674432 scopus 로고
    • (Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • and Simon Blackburn, Spreading the Word (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1984), 148-9
    • (1984) Spreading the Word , pp. 148-149
    • Blackburn, S.1
  • 20
    • 85036734993 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McDowell and Williams sometimes blur the distinction between the intended and actual extensions of a thick concept, which can make their positions seem relativist. Our formulations are meant to avoid any hint of relativism by clearly separating the claim that a speaker's intended extension for a thick term depends on his evaluative beliefs from the claim that its actual extension depends on evaluative truths. Our defense of the reductive view could be mounted with respect to either claim, but for clarity's sake we keep them separate
    • McDowell and Williams sometimes blur the distinction between the intended and actual extensions of a thick concept, which can make their positions seem relativist. Our formulations are meant to avoid any hint of relativism by clearly separating the claim that a speaker's intended extension for a thick term depends on his evaluative beliefs from the claim that its actual extension depends on evaluative truths. Our defense of the reductive view could be mounted with respect to either claim, but for clarity's sake we keep them separate
  • 22
    • 61149150974 scopus 로고
    • "Thick" concepts revisited
    • Stephan L. Burton has proposed an analysis of thick concepts that also involves partial indeterminacy but locates it in a different place. He reads 'x is F' as 'x is good for having some instance of properties X, Y, and Z (for specific X, Y, and Z)
    • Stephan L. Burton has proposed an analysis of thick concepts that also involves partial indeterminacy but locates it in a different place. He reads 'x is F' as 'x is good for having some instance of properties X, Y, and Z (for specific X, Y, and Z), ' where other instances of the same properties need not make what has them good ('"Thick" Concepts Revisited, ' Analysis 52 (1992) 28-32). For many terms the specified properties will have to be disjunctive, for example, 'is an equal distribution, or one proportioned to merit, or...' But Burton denies that one can specify, even in principle, any narrower property such that all and only the instances of X, Y, and Z that do make things good have that property. Whatever property one selects, even one as specific as equality, some instances of it will be good-making while others are not. Apparently influenced by McDowell's argument about uncodifiability, Burton here denies universalizability; his analyses may therefore appeal to those who likewise reject it. But we wish to retain universalizability, as Sidgwick, Hare, and others did, and therefore take a different line. We do not hold, as Burton does, that the sense of a thick term fully specifies a set of properties; it leaves them partly indeterminate. But there is always some property that fully determines the term's extension, in the sense that all and only instances of it are in the relevant way good-making
    • (1992) Analysis , vol.52 , pp. 28-32
  • 23
    • 60949502588 scopus 로고
    • Morality through thick and thin: A critical notice of ethics and the limits of philosophy
    • at 417-18
    • Scheffler, 'Morality Through Thick and Thin: A Critical Notice of Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, Philosophical Review 96 (1987) 411-34, at 417-18
    • (1987) Philosophical Review , vol.96 , pp. 411-434
    • Scheffler1
  • 25
    • 85036755349 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Though Gibbard's analysis of 'lewd' makes it involve evaluations of the agent, it does not refer to her motivations but seems to concern only her acts and whether, motivation apart, they exceed some limits. For us this makes Gibbard's 'lewd' not a virtue-concept but one suited to the first pattern of analysis and explicable using 'wrong.'
    • Though Gibbard's analysis of 'lewd' makes it involve evaluations of the agent, it does not refer to her motivations but seems to concern only her acts and whether, motivation apart, they exceed some limits. For us this makes Gibbard's 'lewd' not a virtue-concept but one suited to the first pattern of analysis and explicable using 'wrong.'
  • 27
    • 85036738818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Oxford English Dictionary defines 'cruelty' as involving 'delight in or indifference to another's pain'; our refinement builds those psychological elements into the term's analysis
    • The Oxford English Dictionary defines 'cruelty' as involving 'delight in or indifference to another's pain'; our refinement builds those psychological elements into the term's analysis
  • 29
    • 4544246386 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (New York: Oxford University Press, for such a defense
    • See Thomas Hurka, Virtue, Vice, and Value (New York: Oxford University Press 2001) for such a defense
    • (2001) Virtue, Vice, and Value
    • Hurka, T.1
  • 30
    • 0004255852 scopus 로고
    • 7th ed. (London: Macmillan
    • Henry Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics, 7th ed. (London: Macmillan 1907), 392-3
    • (1907) The Methods of Ethics , pp. 392-393
    • Sidgwick, H.1
  • 31
    • 79957222465 scopus 로고
    • (London: Oxford University Press
    • Hastings Rashdall, The Theory of Good and Evil, 2 vols. (London: Oxford University Press 1907), vol. 1, 59
    • (1907) The Theory of Good and Evil , vol.1-2 , pp. 59
    • Rashdall, H.1
  • 33
    • 0004240210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an argument of this type,
    • For an argument of this type, see Ross, The Right and the Good, 135
    • The Right and the Good , pp. 135
    • Ross1
  • 34
    • 85036768968 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some versions of the anti-reductive view may deny that such independent judgments of goodness are possible, since all thin judgments derive ultimately from thick ones. But these are more radical versions of the anti-reductive view than are commonly defended
    • Some versions of the anti-reductive view may deny that such independent judgments of goodness are possible, since all thin judgments derive ultimately from thick ones. But these are more radical versions of the anti-reductive view than are commonly defended
  • 35
    • 85036728874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We owe this second response to Simon Kirchin
    • We owe this second response to Simon Kirchin
  • 36
    • 0003986649 scopus 로고
    • trans. D. Ross (Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, trans. D. Ross (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1980), 1096a2
    • (1980) Nicomachean Ethics
    • Aristotle1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.