메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 22, Issue 4, 2008, Pages 369-393

Humanitarian Intervention and the Distribution of Sovereignty in International Law

(1)  Macklem, Patrick a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 77950727253     PISSN: 08926794     EISSN: 17477093     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1747-7093.2008.00172.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (10)

References (96)
  • 1
    • 84927083833 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Humanitarian Intervention Debate
    • J. L. Holzgrefe and Robert O. Keohane, eds. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • J. L. Holzgrefe, “The Humanitarian Intervention Debate,” in J. L. Holzgrefe and Robert O. Keohane, eds., Humanitarian Intervention: Ethical, Legal, and Political Dilemmas (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), p. 18.
    • (2003) Humanitarian Intervention: Ethical, Legal, and Political Dilemmas , pp. 18
    • Holzgrefe, J.L.1
  • 2
    • 0004064132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press See also (humanitarian intervention as “the threat or use of force by a state, group of states, or international organization primarily for the purpose of protecting the nationals of the target state from widespread deprivations of internationally recognized human rights”)
    • See also Sean D. Murphy, Humanitarian Intervention: The United Nations in an Evolving World Order (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1996), pp. 11–12 (humanitarian intervention as “the threat or use of force by a state, group of states, or international organization primarily for the purpose of protecting the nationals of the target state from widespread deprivations of internationally recognized human rights”).
    • (1996) Humanitarian Intervention: The United Nations in an Evolving World Order , pp. 11-12
    • Murphy, S.D.1
  • 3
    • 84871953131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Article 2(4)
    • UN Charter, Article 2(4).
    • UN Charter
  • 11
    • 85011455670 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • threat to the peace
    • The precise language in Article 39 on this point is a or
    • The precise language in Article 39 on this point is a “threat to the peace” or “breach of the peace.”
    • breach of the peace
  • 12
    • 84871953131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Article 2(7)
    • UN Charter, Article 2(7).
    • UN Charter
  • 13
    • 0039753936 scopus 로고
    • The Right of States to Use Force
    • See (the Charter does not prohibit the use of force if it does not threaten the “territorial integrity or political independence of a state”)
    • See Oscar Schachter, “The Right of States to Use Force,” Michigan Law Review 82 (1984), p. 1625 (the Charter does not prohibit the use of force if it does not threaten the “territorial integrity or political independence of a state”).
    • (1984) Michigan Law Review , vol.82 , pp. 1625
    • Schachter, O.1
  • 14
    • 84928448007 scopus 로고
    • The Law of Force and the Force of Law: Grenada, the Falklands and Humanitarian Intervention
    • But see (“a state's political independence is compromised whenever another state attempts through armed force to coerce it, to limit its choices on the international plane, or to interfere with its domestic political regime”)
    • But see Michael J. Levitin, “The Law of Force and the Force of Law: Grenada, the Falklands and Humanitarian Intervention,” Harvard International Law Journal 27 (1986), p. 612 (“a state's political independence is compromised whenever another state attempts through armed force to coerce it, to limit its choices on the international plane, or to interfere with its domestic political regime”).
    • (1986) Harvard International Law Journal , vol.27 , pp. 612
    • Levitin, M.J.1
  • 15
    • 84871953131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Article 42
    • UN Charter, Article 42.
    • UN Charter
  • 16
    • 85011474551 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • we are prepared to take collective action, in a timely and decisive manner, through the Security Council, in accordance with the Charter, including Chapter VII, on a case-by-case basis and in cooperation with relevant regional organizations as appropriate, should peaceful means be inadequate and national authorities are manifestly failing to protect their populations from genocide, war crimes, ethnic cleansing and crimes 14 against humanity.
    • In the 2005 World Summit Outcome, the UN General Assembly stated that at para. 139
    • In the 2005 World Summit Outcome, the UN General Assembly stated that “we are prepared to take collective action, in a timely and decisive manner, through the Security Council, in accordance with the Charter, including Chapter VII, on a case-by-case basis and in cooperation with relevant regional organizations as appropriate, should peaceful means be inadequate and national authorities are manifestly failing to protect their populations from genocide, war crimes, ethnic cleansing and crimes 14 against humanity.” UN A/Res/60/1, at para. 139.
    • UN A/Res/60/1
  • 18
    • 33644635461 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Heidelberg: Müller This formulation leaves open the question of what consequences count as constituting a threat to the peace. Compare (the Security Council can recognize a threat to the peace beyond the transborder context if there is a “physical threat to internationally protected values and rights of high standing”)
    • This formulation leaves open the question of what consequences count as constituting a threat to the peace. Compare Matthias Herdegen, Die Befugnisse des UN-Sicherheitsrates: Aufgeklärter Absolutismus im Völkerrecht? (Heidelberg: Müller, 1998), p. 15 (the Security Council can recognize a threat to the peace beyond the transborder context if there is a “physical threat to internationally protected values and rights of high standing”)
    • (1998) Matthias Herdegen, Die Befugnisse des UN-Sicherheitsrates: Aufgeklärter Absolutismus im Völkerrecht? , pp. 15
  • 19
    • 27744525969 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Review Essay: Qui judicabit? The Security Council, Its Powers and Its Legal Control
    • quoted in
    • quoted in Bardo Fassbender, “Review Essay: Qui judicabit? The Security Council, Its Powers and Its Legal Control,” European Journal of International Law 11, no. 1 (2000), pp. 219–232.
    • (2000) European Journal of International Law , vol.11 , Issue.1 , pp. 219-232
    • Fassbender, B.1
  • 20
    • 85011516526 scopus 로고
    • Resolution 688, however, did not authorize military force under Chapter 17 VII
    • UN Doc. S/RES/688 (1991). Resolution 688, however, did not authorize military force under Chapter 17 VII.
    • (1991) UN Doc. S/RES/688
  • 22
    • 33645943087 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Humanitarian Intervention and Pretexts for War
    • see also citing extensive scholarship supporting this conclusion
    • see also Ryan Goodman, “Humanitarian Intervention and Pretexts for War,” American Journal of International Law 100 (2006), p. 107, citing extensive scholarship supporting this conclusion.
    • (2006) American Journal of International Law , vol.100 , pp. 107
    • Goodman, R.1
  • 23
    • 0040759304 scopus 로고
    • Forcible Self-Help to Protect Human Rights: Recent Views from the UN
    • Richard B. Lillich, ed. See (Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press
    • See Jean-Pierre Fonteyne, “Forcible Self-Help to Protect Human Rights: Recent Views from the UN,” in Richard B. Lillich, ed., Humanitarian Intervention and the United Nations (Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press, 1973), pp. 209–211.
    • (1973) Humanitarian Intervention and the United Nations , pp. 209-211
    • Fonteyne, J.-P.1
  • 24
    • 85011519934 scopus 로고
    • UN Declaration on the Inadmissibility of Intervention in the Domestic Affairs of States and the Protection of their Independence and Sovereignty
    • See 20 UN GAOR, Supp. (No. 14), UN Doc. A/6014
    • See UN Declaration on the Inadmissibility of Intervention in the Domestic Affairs of States and the Protection of their Independence and Sovereignty, G.A. Res. 2131 (XX) 20 UN GAOR, Supp. (No. 14), UN Doc. A/6014 (1965)
    • (1965) G.A. Res , vol.2131 , Issue.XX
  • 25
    • 84862692845 scopus 로고
    • UN Declaration of Principles of International Law concerning Friendly Relations and Cooperation among States
    • and UN GAOR, Supp. (No. 28) at 121, UN Doc. A/8028
    • and UN Declaration of Principles of International Law concerning Friendly Relations and Cooperation among States, G.A. Res. 2625, 25 UN GAOR, Supp. (No. 28) at 121, UN Doc. A/8028 (1970).
    • (1970) G.A. Res , vol.2625 , pp. 25
  • 26
    • 85011522093 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Boston: Kluwer notes that “similar proscriptions of intervention” can be found in the Charter of the Organization of African Unity, the Charter of the Organization of American States, and in the Principles of the Final Act of the Helsinki Conference in 1975
    • Francis Kofi Abiew, The Evolution of the Doctrine and Practice of Humanitarian Intervention (Boston: Kluwer, 1999), p. 70, notes that “similar proscriptions of intervention” can be found in the Charter of the Organization of African Unity, the Charter of the Organization of American States, and in the Principles of the Final Act of the Helsinki Conference in 1975.
    • (1999) The Evolution of the Doctrine and Practice of Humanitarian Intervention , pp. 70
    • Abiew, F.K.1
  • 27
    • 33645696913 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Unilateral Action and the Transformations of the World Constitutive Process: The Special Problem of Humanitarian Intervention
    • The primary concern with a humanitarian exception to the absolute ban is that states would rely on it for ulterior motives. See, e.g. (describing this concern as “the primary juridical objection to a humanitarian exception”)
    • The primary concern with a humanitarian exception to the absolute ban is that states would rely on it for ulterior motives. See, e.g., W. Michael Reisman, “Unilateral Action and the Transformations of the World Constitutive Process: The Special Problem of Humanitarian Intervention,” European Journal of International Law 11 (2000), p. 16 (describing this concern as “the primary juridical objection to a humanitarian exception”).
    • (2000) European Journal of International Law , vol.11 , pp. 16
    • Michael Reisman, W.1
  • 28
    • 84952368035 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the view that the opposite concern is equally or more likely true, see
    • For the view that the opposite concern is equally or more likely true, see Goodman, “Humanitarian Intervention and Pretexts for War.”
    • Humanitarian Intervention and Pretexts for War
  • 29
    • 84900197170 scopus 로고
    • Response by Professors McDougall and Reisman
    • See
    • See Myres S. McDougall and W. Michael Reisman, “Response by Professors McDougall and Reisman,” International Lawyer 3 (1969), p. 444.
    • (1969) International Lawyer , vol.3 , pp. 444
    • McDougall, M.S.1    Michael Reisman, W.2
  • 30
    • 0344064281 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a critique of the view that customary international law authorizes humanitarian intervention without Security Council approval, see (New York: Oxford University Press
    • For a critique of the view that customary international law authorizes humanitarian intervention without Security Council approval, see Simon Chesterman, Just War or Just Peace? Humanitarian Intervention and International Law (New York: Oxford University Press, 2001).
    • (2001) Just War or Just Peace? Humanitarian Intervention and International Law
    • Chesterman, S.1
  • 31
    • 85011522067 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reforming the Law of Humanitarian Intervention
    • Buchanan also proposes treaty arrangements authorizing humanitarian intervention, which would, on the one hand, violate the UN Charter by authorizing what the Charter prohibits, but, on the other hand, displace the Charter's current role as the preeminent international legal instrument in international law. See Holzgrefe and Keohane, eds.
    • Buchanan also proposes treaty arrangements authorizing humanitarian intervention, which would, on the one hand, violate the UN Charter by authorizing what the Charter prohibits, but, on the other hand, displace the Charter's current role as the preeminent international legal instrument in international law. See Allen Buchanan, “Reforming the Law of Humanitarian Intervention,” in Holzgrefe and Keohane, eds., Humanitarian Intervention, pp. 138–141.
    • Humanitarian Intervention , pp. 138-141
    • Buchanan, A.1
  • 32
    • 85011455647 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Changing the Rules About Rules
    • Holzgrefe and Keohane, eds.
    • Michael Byers and Simon Chesterman, “Changing the Rules About Rules,” in Holzgrefe and Keohane, eds., Humanitarian Intervention, p. 177.
    • Humanitarian Intervention , pp. 177
    • Byers, M.1    Chesterman, S.2
  • 33
    • 0344824783 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Franck likens the role of the Security Council (and the General Assembly) in this ex post context to that of a jury, whose members “are not without feelings and biases, but whose first concern is to do the right thing by the norms under which we all live” (p. 187)
    • Thomas M. Franck, Recourse to Force: State Action Against Threats and Armed Attacks (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), p. 186. Franck likens the role of the Security Council (and the General Assembly) in this ex post context to that of a jury, whose members “are not without feelings and biases, but whose first concern is to do the right thing by the norms under which we all live” (p. 187).
    • (2002) Recourse to Force: State Action Against Threats and Armed Attacks , pp. 186
    • Franck, T.M.1
  • 34
    • 79957891492 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moralizing Humanitarian Intervention
    • Terry Nardin and Melissa Williams, eds. For a critique, see (New York: New York University Press
    • For a critique, see Thomas Pogge, “Moralizing Humanitarian Intervention,” in Terry Nardin and Melissa Williams, eds., Humanitarian Intervention (New York: New York University Press, 2006).
    • (2006) Humanitarian Intervention
    • Pogge, T.1
  • 35
    • 3142783294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Preventive Use of Force: A Cosmopolitan Institutional Proposal
    • See (arguing for ex ante and ex post contractual arrangements requiring an “evidence-based case” for intervention to be put to the Security Council, authorization by a coalition of democratic states if the Security Council does not approve of the intervention, and evaluation by an impartial body after the fact)
    • See Allen Buchanan and Robert O. Keohane, “The Preventive Use of Force: A Cosmopolitan Institutional Proposal,” Ethics & International Affairs 18, no. 1 (2004) (arguing for ex ante and ex post contractual arrangements requiring an “evidence-based case” for intervention to be put to the Security Council, authorization by a coalition of democratic states if the Security Council does not approve of the intervention, and evaluation by an impartial body after the fact).
    • (2004) Ethics & International Affairs , vol.18 , Issue.1
    • Buchanan, A.1    Keohane, R.O.2
  • 36
    • 85011443226 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Franck details the history of Article 11(2) and its use in this respect. The International Court of Justice has interpreted Article 11(2) in the event of a veto by a Security Council permanent member as authorizing a “secondary” role for the General Assembly “to organize peace-keeping operations … by means of recommendation” and only “at the request, or with the consent, of the States concerned.” Certain Expenses of the United Nations, Advisory Opinion of 20 July 1962, ICJ (1962), p. 164. It should be noted that Article 11(2) does not stipulate state request or consent as a precondition of the exercise of General Assembly authority
    • Franck, Recourse to Force, p. 35. Franck details the history of Article 11(2) and its use in this respect. The International Court of Justice has interpreted Article 11(2) in the event of a veto by a Security Council permanent member as authorizing a “secondary” role for the General Assembly “to organize peace-keeping operations … by means of recommendation” and only “at the request, or with the consent, of the States concerned.” Certain Expenses of the United Nations, Advisory Opinion of 20 July 1962, ICJ (1962), p. 164. It should be noted that Article 11(2) does not stipulate state request or consent as a precondition of the exercise of General Assembly authority.
    • Recourse to Force , pp. 35
    • Franck1
  • 37
    • 24944510305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Political Origins of the UN Security Council's Ability to Legitimize the Use of Force
    • To be sure, Security Council authorization provides political legitimacy to the use of force to the extent that it provides some “political reassurance about the consequences of proposed military adventures.” The distinction, to be clear, is one between legal validity and political morality or justice
    • To be sure, Security Council authorization provides political legitimacy to the use of force to the extent that it provides some “political reassurance about the consequences of proposed military adventures.” Erik Voeten, “The Political Origins of the UN Security Council's Ability to Legitimize the Use of Force,” International Organization 59, no. 3 (2005), p. 528. The distinction, to be clear, is one between legal validity and political morality or justice.
    • (2005) International Organization , vol.59 , Issue.3 , pp. 528
    • Voeten, E.1
  • 39
    • 70349525766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Morality of War and the Law of War
    • David Rodin and Henry Shue, eds. (New York: Oxford University Press
    • Jeff McMahan, “The Morality of War and the Law of War,” in David Rodin and Henry Shue, eds., Just and Unjust Warriors: The Legal and Moral Status of Soldiers (New York: Oxford University Press, 2008).
    • (2008) Just and Unjust Warriors: The Legal and Moral Status of Soldiers
    • McMahan, J.1
  • 41
    • 33847362797 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and (Peterborough, Ont.: Broadview Press
    • and Brian Orend, The Morality of War (Peterborough, Ont.: Broadview Press, 2006).
    • (2006) The Morality of War
    • Orend, B.1
  • 42
    • 0004255702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally W. E. Rumble, ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See generally, J. Austin, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined, W. E. Rumble, ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995)
    • (1995) The Province of Jurisprudence Determined
    • Austin, J.1
  • 45
    • 0004255702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g. (a law is valid because it is the command of a sovereign)
    • See, e.g., Austin, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined (a law is valid because it is the command of a sovereign)
    • The Province of Jurisprudence Determined
    • Austin1
  • 46
    • 0003516637 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. Anders Wedberg (Clark, N.J.: Lawbook Exchange (a legal norm is valid if authorized by another legal norm of a higher rank)
    • Hans Kelsen, General Theory of Law and State, trans. Anders Wedberg (Clark, N.J.: Lawbook Exchange, 1999) (a legal norm is valid if authorized by another legal norm of a higher rank)
    • (1999) General Theory of Law and State
    • Kelsen, H.1
  • 47
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and (a law is valid if it conforms with “secondary rules” or laws that authorize the enactment of law). Some have drawn a distinction between political and analytic positivism, with the former as an interpretive strategy and the latter as objective description
    • and Hart, The Concept of Law (a law is valid if it conforms with “secondary rules” or laws that authorize the enactment of law). Some have drawn a distinction between political and analytic positivism, with the former as an interpretive strategy and the latter as objective description.
    • The Concept of Law
    • Hart1
  • 48
    • 33748926618 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • See Ronald Dworkin, Justice in Robes (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2006), pp. 26–33.
    • (2006) Justice in Robes , pp. 26-33
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 49
    • 84925780847 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legal Positivism as Normative Politics: International Society, Balance of Power and Lassa Oppenheim's Positive International Law
    • For a defense of political positivism in international law, see
    • For a defense of political positivism in international law, see Benedict Kingsbury, “Legal Positivism as Normative Politics: International Society, Balance of Power and Lassa Oppenheim's Positive International Law,” European Journal of International Law 13 (2002), p. 401.
    • (2002) European Journal of International Law , vol.13 , pp. 401
    • Kingsbury, B.1
  • 50
    • 67349202175 scopus 로고
    • ed. (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press What the concept of the rule of law requires, of course, is hotly contested, and legal theorists have arrayed themselves on a spectrum ranging from thin, formal conceptions of what is necessary for law to generate obedience, to thicker conceptions of justice that posit substantive normative preconditions of specific laws and, more generally, of legal orders
    • Lon L. Fuller, The Morality of Law, rev. ed. (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1969). What the concept of the rule of law requires, of course, is hotly contested, and legal theorists have arrayed themselves on a spectrum ranging from thin, formal conceptions of what is necessary for law to generate obedience, to thicker conceptions of justice that posit substantive normative preconditions of specific laws and, more generally, of legal orders.
    • (1969) The Morality of Law, rev
    • Fuller, L.L.1
  • 51
    • 84920662244 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (New York: Oxford University Press For a conception considerably thicker than Fuller's, see (“the principles of equality and due process, and associated freedoms of expression, association and conscience, must be regarded as integral features of law which limit the kinds of state action that can qualify as legitimate sources of legal obligation”)
    • For a conception considerably thicker than Fuller's, see T. R. S. Allan, Constitutional Justice: A Liberal Theory of the Rule of Law (New York: Oxford University Press, 2001), p. 76 (“the principles of equality and due process, and associated freedoms of expression, association and conscience, must be regarded as integral features of law which limit the kinds of state action that can qualify as legitimate sources of legal obligation”).
    • (2001) Constitutional Justice: A Liberal Theory of the Rule of Law , pp. 76
    • Allan, T.R.S.1
  • 52
    • 84926971160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Dilemma of Legality and the Moral Limits of Law
    • Austin Sarat, Lawrence Douglas, and Martha Merrill Um-phrey, eds. For an illuminating account that comprehends formal equality as an essential feature of law, see (Palo Alto, Calif.: Stanford University Press
    • For an illuminating account that comprehends formal equality as an essential feature of law, see David Dyzenhaus, “The Dilemma of Legality and the Moral Limits of Law,” in Austin Sarat, Lawrence Douglas, and Martha Merrill Um-phrey, eds., The Limits of Law (Palo Alto, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 2005).
    • (2005) The Limits of Law
    • Dyzenhaus, D.1
  • 53
    • 84924150998 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a history and typology of scholarship on the rule of law, see (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • For a history and typology of scholarship on the rule of law, see Brian Tamanaha, On the Rule of Law: History, Politics, Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004).
    • (2004) On the Rule of Law: History, Politics, Theory
    • Tamanaha, B.1
  • 54
    • 0012674058 scopus 로고
    • The Rule of Law and Its Virtue
    • Joseph Raz On both points, see (Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • On both points, see Joseph Raz, “The Rule of Law and Its Virtue,” in Joseph Raz, The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979).
    • (1979) The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality
    • Raz, J.1
  • 56
    • 0004287704 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2d ed., trans. Max Knight (Clark, N.J.: Lawbook Exchange
    • Hans Kelsen, Pure Theory of Law, 2d ed., trans. Max Knight (Clark, N.J.: Lawbook Exchange, 2005).
    • (2005) Pure Theory of Law
    • Kelsen, H.1
  • 57
    • 0042534340 scopus 로고
    • Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals
    • H. L. A. Hart (New York: Oxford University Press
    • H. L. A. Hart, “Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals,” in H. L. A. Hart, Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy (New York: Oxford University Press, 1983), pp. 49–87.
    • (1983) Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy , pp. 49-87
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 58
    • 0344824783 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The closest one can come to treating the Security Council as exercising judicial authority, I think, is Tom Franck's characterization of the Security Council operating like a jury in the context of humanitarian intervention. See
    • The closest one can come to treating the Security Council as exercising judicial authority, I think, is Tom Franck's characterization of the Security Council operating like a jury in the context of humanitarian intervention. See Franck, Recourse to Force.
    • Recourse to Force
    • Franck1
  • 59
    • 33748098882 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constitutional Analogies in the International Legal System
    • For a discussion of the domestic analogy, see
    • For a discussion of the domestic analogy, see Laurence R. Helfer, “Constitutional Analogies in the International Legal System,” Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review 37 (2004), p. 193.
    • (2004) Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review , vol.37 , pp. 193
    • Helfer, L.R.1
  • 63
    • 0008658288 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff See Brownlie outlines several criteria to assess the legality of Security Council decision-making, including the exercise of its Chapter VII powers
    • See Ian Brownlie, The Rule of Law in International Affairs: International Law at the Fiftieth Anniversary of the United Nations (Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff, 1998). Brownlie outlines several criteria to assess the legality of Security Council decision-making, including the exercise of its Chapter VII powers.
    • (1998) The Rule of Law in International Affairs: International Law at the Fiftieth Anniversary of the United Nations
    • Brownlie, I.1
  • 64
    • 0036823260 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Security Council Starts Legislating
    • Security Council Resolution 1373, UN SCOR, 56th Sess., 4385th mtg., at 2, UN Doc. S/RES/1373 (2001), which requires all states to take certain measures to combat terrorism in the wake of September 11, 2001, veers even closer to international legislation by its general and nontemporary nature. See Resolution 1373 also delegates the task of monitoring implementation of its terms to a plenary committee of the Security Council
    • Security Council Resolution 1373, UN SCOR, 56th Sess., 4385th mtg., at 2, UN Doc. S/RES/1373 (2001), which requires all states to take certain measures to combat terrorism in the wake of September 11, 2001, veers even closer to international legislation by its general and nontemporary nature. See Paul C. Szasz, “The Security Council Starts Legislating,” American Journal of International Law 96 (2002), p. 901. Resolution 1373 also delegates the task of monitoring implementation of its terms to a plenary committee of the Security Council.
    • (2002) American Journal of International Law , vol.96 , pp. 901
    • Szasz, P.C.1
  • 65
    • 30944435628 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Rule of (Administrative) Law in International Law
    • For the view that such delegation lacks legal authority because it offends the rule of law, see
    • For the view that such delegation lacks legal authority because it offends the rule of law, see David Dyzenhaus, “The Rule of (Administrative) Law in International Law,” Law and Contemporary Problems 68 (2005), p. 127.
    • (2005) Law and Contemporary Problems , vol.68 , pp. 127
    • Dyzenhaus, D.1
  • 67
    • 84997982072 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Humanitarian Intervention Before and After 9/11: Legality and Legitimacy
    • On the Security Council as a “global parliament,” see Holzgrefe and Keohane, eds.
    • On the Security Council as a “global parliament,” see Tom Farer, “Humanitarian Intervention Before and After 9/11: Legality and Legitimacy,” in Holzgrefe and Keohane, eds., Humanitarian Intervention.
    • Humanitarian Intervention
    • Farer, T.1
  • 68
    • 0042534325 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Defence of Radbruch's Formula
    • David Dyzenhaus, ed. In the words of Gustav Radbruch, “positive law, established by enactment and by power, has primacy even when its content is unjust and improper. It is only when the contradiction between positive law and justice reaches an intolerable level that the law is supposed to give way as a ‘false law’ to justice.” This formulation has become known as the “Radbruch formula.” Radbruch continues as follows: “when justice is not even aimed at, where equality—the core of justice—is deliberately disavowed in the enactment of a positive law, then the law is not simply ‘false law,’ it has no claim at all to legal status.” For analysis, see (Oxford: Hart
    • In the words of Gustav Radbruch, “positive law, established by enactment and by power, has primacy even when its content is unjust and improper. It is only when the contradiction between positive law and justice reaches an intolerable level that the law is supposed to give way as a ‘false law’ to justice.” This formulation has become known as the “Radbruch formula.” Radbruch continues as follows: “when justice is not even aimed at, where equality—the core of justice—is deliberately disavowed in the enactment of a positive law, then the law is not simply ‘false law,’ it has no claim at all to legal status.” For analysis, see Robert Alexy, “A Defence of Radbruch's Formula,” in David Dyzenhaus, ed., Recrafting the Rule of Law (Oxford: Hart, 1999), pp. 15–39.
    • (1999) Recrafting the Rule of Law , pp. 15-39
    • Alexy, R.1
  • 69
    • 84928951487 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Legitimacy of International Law: A Constitutionalist Framework of Analysis
    • See (“the principle of international legality generally requires that addressees of international law should obey it”)
    • See Mattias Kumm, “The Legitimacy of International Law: A Constitutionalist Framework of Analysis,” European Journal of International Law 15 (2004), p. 918 (“the principle of international legality generally requires that addressees of international law should obey it”).
    • (2004) European Journal of International Law , vol.15 , pp. 918
    • Kumm, M.1
  • 70
    • 85011483171 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Concept and the Rule of Law
    • draft September 14 Compare (“to guide action is to indicate and highlight reasons for action which those being guided are to apply to their own behavior”)
    • Compare Jeremy Waldron, “The Concept and the Rule of Law” (unpublished paper, September 14, 2006, draft), p. 25 (“to guide action is to indicate and highlight reasons for action which those being guided are to apply to their own behavior”).
    • (2006) unpublished paper , pp. 25
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 72
    • 77649265887 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constitutional Courts as Deliberative Institutions: Towards an Institutional Theory of Constitutional Justice
    • (Boston: Kluwer Wojciech Sadurski, ed. See (the duty to give reasons intensifies as democratic accountability diminishes)
    • See John Ferejohn and Pasquale Pasquino, “Constitutional Courts as Deliberative Institutions: Towards an Institutional Theory of Constitutional Justice,” in Wojciech Sadurski, ed., Constitutional Justice, East and West (Boston: Kluwer, 2002) (the duty to give reasons intensifies as democratic accountability diminishes).
    • (2002) Constitutional Justice, East and West
    • Ferejohn, J.1    Pasquino, P.2
  • 73
    • 85011511652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the view that legal consistency has not been the Security Council's strong suit in relation to the legality of the use of force, see
    • For the view that legal consistency has not been the Security Council's strong suit in relation to the legality of the use of force, see Voeten, “The Political Origins of the UN Security Council's Ability to Legitimize the Use of Force,” pp. 535–536.
    • The Political Origins of the UN Security Council's Ability to Legitimize the Use of Force , pp. 535-536
    • Voeten1
  • 75
    • 0038751705 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These provisions reveal the explanatory power of what is known as inclusive legal positivism—a positivist account of law that notes the possibility that positive law can impose moral constraints on the exercise of discretion. See (New York: Oxford University Press
    • These provisions reveal the explanatory power of what is known as inclusive legal positivism—a positivist account of law that notes the possibility that positive law can impose moral constraints on the exercise of discretion. See Jules Coleman, The Practice of Principle: In Defense of a Pragmatist Approach to Legal Theory (New York: Oxford University Press, 2001).
    • (2001) The Practice of Principle: In Defense of a Pragmatist Approach to Legal Theory
    • Coleman, J.1
  • 76
    • 84969875147 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a critique, see
    • For a critique, see Dworkin, Justice in Robes, pp. 187–198.
    • Justice in Robes , pp. 187-198
    • Dworkin1
  • 79
    • 0003809625 scopus 로고
    • For a classic articulation of this conception of the field, see (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press
    • For a classic articulation of this conception of the field, see Jack Donnelly, Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1989).
    • (1989) Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice
    • Donnelly, J.1
  • 80
    • 0012145190 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pogge refers to these conceptions as “interactional” and “institutional.” 2d ed. (Cambridge: Polity
    • Pogge refers to these conceptions as “interactional” and “institutional.” Thomas Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights, 2d ed. (Cambridge: Polity, 2008).
    • (2008) World Poverty and Human Rights
    • Pogge, T.1
  • 81
    • 79960249028 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Humanitarian Intervention as a Perfect Duty
    • Nardin and Williams, eds.
    • Carla Bagnoli, “Humanitarian Intervention as a Perfect Duty,” in Nardin and Williams, eds., Humanitarian Intervention, p. 133.
    • Humanitarian Intervention , pp. 133
    • Bagnoli, C.1
  • 83
    • 84971914996 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare (“The national state, then, in its legal existence, appears determined in all directions by international law, that is, as a legal order delegated by international law in its validity and sphere of validity”)
    • Compare Kelsen, Pure Theory of Law, p. 338 (“The national state, then, in its legal existence, appears determined in all directions by international law, that is, as a legal order delegated by international law in its validity and sphere of validity”).
    • Pure Theory of Law , pp. 338
    • Kelsen1
  • 87
    • 0007275615 scopus 로고
    • The Law of the United Nations
    • (London: London Institute of World Affairs Compare (“As an organ of the United Nations the Security Council acts on behalf of the United Nations, not on behalf of its Members…. Acts of the Council … are … to be imputed to the Organisation, not to its Members. To disregard this imputation is the tendency of the sovereignty-dogma which is incompatible with the idea of a legal order binding upon the states…. It is not the Members, it is the Charter which confers responsibilities on the Security Council”)
    • Compare Hans Kelsen, The Law of the United Nations: A Critical Examination of its Fundamental Problems (London: London Institute of World Affairs, 1951), p. 280 (“As an organ of the United Nations the Security Council acts on behalf of the United Nations, not on behalf of its Members…. Acts of the Council … are … to be imputed to the Organisation, not to its Members. To disregard this imputation is the tendency of the sovereignty-dogma which is incompatible with the idea of a legal order binding upon the states…. It is not the Members, it is the Charter which confers responsibilities on the Security Council”).
    • (1951) A Critical Examination of its Fundamental Problems , pp. 280
    • Kelsen, H.1
  • 89
    • 0004284229 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Responsibility to Protect
    • (Ottawa: International Development Research Centre for ICISS available at www.iciss.gc.ca
    • The Responsibility to Protect, Report of the International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty (Ottawa: International Development Research Centre for ICISS, 2001); available at www.iciss.gc.ca.
    • (2001) Report of the International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty
  • 90
    • 85011511741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • large scale ‘ethnic cleansing,’ actual or apprehended, whether carried out by killing, forced expulsion, acts of terror or rape.
    • According to the ICISS, military intervention is justified to halt or avert: (a) “large scale loss of life, actual or apprehended, with genocidal intent or not, which is the product either of deliberate state action, or state neglect or inability to act, or a failed state situation”; or (b)
    • According to the ICISS, military intervention is justified to halt or avert: (a) “large scale loss of life, actual or apprehended, with genocidal intent or not, which is the product either of deliberate state action, or state neglect or inability to act, or a failed state situation”; or (b) “large scale ‘ethnic cleansing,’ actual or apprehended, whether carried out by killing, forced expulsion, acts of terror or rape.” Report of the International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty, p. 32.
    • Report of the International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty , pp. 32
  • 91
    • 85011483017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The ICISS states that the relevant principles to assess the necessity of force are: right authority, just cause, right intention, last resort, proportional means, and reasonable prospects
    • The ICISS states that the relevant principles to assess the necessity of force are: right authority, just cause, right intention, last resort, proportional means, and reasonable prospects. Report of the International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty, p. 32.
    • Report of the International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty , pp. 32
  • 92
    • 0036846986 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Responsibility to Protect
    • For the view that the concept of humanitarian intervention should be reframed in terms of the responsibility to protect, see
    • For the view that the concept of humanitarian intervention should be reframed in terms of the responsibility to protect, see Gareth Evans and Mohamed Sahnoun, “The Responsibility to Protect,” Foreign Affairs 81, no. 6 (2002)
    • (2002) Foreign Affairs , vol.81 , Issue.6
    • Evans, G.1    Sahnoun, M.2
  • 93
    • 33846967447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Impact of the Responsibility to Protect on Peacekeeping
    • for an analysis of the responsibility to protect in the context of UN peacekeeping, see
    • for an analysis of the responsibility to protect in the context of UN peacekeeping, see Susan Breau, “The Impact of the Responsibility to Protect on Peacekeeping,” Journal of Conflict and Security Law 11, no. 3 (2006), pp. 429–464.
    • (2006) Journal of Conflict and Security Law , vol.11 , Issue.3 , pp. 429-464
    • Breau, S.1
  • 94
    • 85011502071 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • John Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999), p. 80.
    • (1999) The Law of Peoples , pp. 80
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 95
    • 85011443908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls sees the role of international human rights as restricting “the justifying reasons for war and its conduct” and specifying “limits of a regime's internal autonomy.”
    • Rawls
    • Rawls sees the role of international human rights as restricting “the justifying reasons for war and its conduct” and specifying “limits of a regime's internal autonomy.” Rawls, The Law of Peoples, p. 79.
    • The Law of Peoples , pp. 79
  • 96
    • 84924665846 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Human Rights and the Law of Peoples
    • Deen K. Chatterjee, ed For an illuminating analysis of his account, see (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • For an illuminating analysis of his account, see Charles R. Beitz, “Human Rights and the Law of Peoples,” in Deen K. Chatterjee, ed., The Ethics of Assistance: Morality and the Distant Needy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), pp. 193–214.
    • (2004) The Ethics of Assistance: Morality and the Distant Needy , pp. 193-214
    • Beitz, C.R.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.