-
2
-
-
0004099967
-
-
6th ed., revised by Kenneth W. Thompson (New York: Knopf For the classic statement, see Advocates of the National Interest view need not be moral skeptics; instead they may hold that state leaders have one supreme moral obligation… to serve the national interest…and that this obligation overrides all other principles of morality. Those who espouse the National Interest view may disagree among themselves, of course, as to whether a policy of recourse to preventive force, or any particular decision to use preventive force, is in fact likely to serve the national interest or be detrimental to it
-
For the classic statement, see Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, 6th ed., revised by Kenneth W. Thompson (New York: Knopf, 1985), p. 12. Advocates of the National Interest view need not be moral skeptics; instead they may hold that state leaders have one supreme moral obligation… to serve the national interest…and that this obligation overrides all other principles of morality. Those who espouse the National Interest view may disagree among themselves, of course, as to whether a policy of recourse to preventive force, or any particular decision to use preventive force, is in fact likely to serve the national interest or be detrimental to it.
-
(1985)
Politics among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace
, pp. 12
-
-
Morgenthau, H.J.1
-
4
-
-
85022851401
-
Human Rights
-
The position we endorse is sometimes called Moderate Cosmopolitanism, which allows one to give a limited priority to the interests of one's own nation and does not require strict impartiality. It is a liberal form of cosmopolitanism, since it emphasizes the basic human rights of all persons. One could imagine other kinds of cosmopolitanism, such as Marxism, that forbid discrimination on grounds of nationality, but do not focus on human rights. For a philosophical justification for the assumption that there are human rights, see forthcoming, Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
The position we endorse is sometimes called Moderate Cosmopolitanism, which allows one to give a limited priority to the interests of one's own nation and does not require strict impartiality. It is a liberal form of cosmopolitanism, since it emphasizes the basic human rights of all persons. One could imagine other kinds of cosmopolitanism, such as Marxism, that forbid discrimination on grounds of nationality, but do not focus on human rights. For a philosophical justification for the assumption that there are human rights, see Allen Buchanan, “Human Rights,” in Justice, Legitimacy, and Self-Determination: Moral Foundations for International Law (forthcoming, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003).
-
(2003)
Justice, Legitimacy, and Self-Determination: Moral Foundations for International Law
-
-
Buchanan, A.1
-
5
-
-
33645961025
-
Conspiracy
-
See St. Paul, Minn.: West Group
-
See Arnold H. Loewy, “Conspiracy,” in Criminal Law in a Nutshell (St. Paul, Minn.: West Group, 2000), p. 260
-
(2000)
Criminal Law in a Nutshell
, pp. 260
-
-
Loewy, A.H.1
-
6
-
-
85022775106
-
Inchoate Offenses
-
2nd ed. (St. Paul, Minn.: West Group
-
Joshua Dressler, “Inchoate Offenses,” in Cases and Materials on Criminal Law, 2nd ed. (St. Paul, Minn.: West Group, 1999), p. 765.
-
(1999)
Cases and Materials on Criminal Law
, pp. 765
-
-
Dressler, J.1
-
7
-
-
0010754178
-
Coercive Diplomacy and Ultimata: Theory and Practice in History
-
in Alexander L. George and William E. Simons, eds. Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press
-
Paul Gordon Lauren, “Coercive Diplomacy and Ultimata: Theory and Practice in History,” in Alexander L. George and William E. Simons, eds., The Limits of Coercive Diplomacy (Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press, 1994), p. 23.
-
(1994)
The Limits of Coercive Diplomacy
, pp. 23
-
-
Gordon Lauren, P.1
-
8
-
-
0003472355
-
-
New Haven: Yale University Press
-
Thomas C. Schelling, Arms and Influence (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1966), pp. 69–78.
-
(1966)
Arms and Influence
, pp. 69-78
-
-
Schelling, T.C.1
-
10
-
-
0002429348
-
Conceptualizing Accountability
-
Boulder, Colo.: Lynne Rienner in Andreas Schedler, Larry Diamond, and Marc F. Plat-tner, eds. The word “punishment” could be interpreted in too formal and restrictive a way. We accept this definition only with the proviso that it refers more broadly to a penalty
-
Andreas Schedler, “Conceptualizing Accountability,” in Andreas Schedler, Larry Diamond, and Marc F. Plat-tner, eds., The Self-Restraining State: Power and Accountability in New Democracies (Boulder, Colo.: Lynne Rienner, 1999), p. 17. The word “punishment” could be interpreted in too formal and restrictive a way. We accept this definition only with the proviso that it refers more broadly to a penalty.
-
(1999)
The Self-Restraining State: Power and Accountability in New Democracies
, pp. 17
-
-
Schedler, A.1
-
12
-
-
85022774143
-
-
Richard Crawley, trans., bk. para. 84 (New York: Modern Library
-
Thucydides, The Peloponnesian War, Richard Crawley, trans., bk. V, para. 84 (New York: Modern Library, 1982), p. 351.
-
(1982)
The Peloponnesian War
, vol.V
, pp. 351
-
-
Thucydides1
-
13
-
-
0035285370
-
Governance in a Partially Globalized World
-
March For a more general argument, see
-
For a more general argument, see Robert O. Keohane, “Governance in a Partially Globalized World,” American Political Science Review 95, no. 1 (March 2001), pp. 1–13.
-
(2001)
American Political Science Review
, vol.95
, Issue.1
, pp. 1-13
-
-
Keohane, R.O.1
-
16
-
-
33747809897
-
Crafting the Financial Settlement
-
New Haven: Yale University Press, for the Council on Foreign Relations Here it might be objected that the strongest states might agree ex ante to pay compensation if an ex post review found their preventive actions to be unjustified, but simply fail to pay up. To avoid this problem, assets could be escrowed ex ante. Such an arrangement was used in the agreements that ended the U.S.-Iran hostage crisis in 1981 and that established the U.S.-Iran Claims Tribunal. See in Warren Christopher et al., eds
-
Here it might be objected that the strongest states might agree ex ante to pay compensation if an ex post review found their preventive actions to be unjustified, but simply fail to pay up. To avoid this problem, assets could be escrowed ex ante. Such an arrangement was used in the agreements that ended the U.S.-Iran hostage crisis in 1981 and that established the U.S.-Iran Claims Tribunal. See Robert Carswell and Richard Davis, “Crafting the Financial Settlement,” in Warren Christopher et al., eds., American Hostages in Iran: The Conduct of a Crisis (New Haven: Yale University Press, for the Council on Foreign Relations, 1985), pp. 201–34
-
(1985)
American Hostages in Iran: The Conduct of a Crisis
, pp. 201-234
-
-
Carswell, R.1
Davis, R.2
-
18
-
-
85005305538
-
The Market for Lemons
-
See August
-
See George Akerlof,“The Market for Lemons,” Quarterly Journal of Economics 84, no. 3 (August 1970), pp. 488–500.
-
(1970)
Quarterly Journal of Economics
, vol.84
, Issue.3
, pp. 488-500
-
-
Akerlof, G.1
-
19
-
-
0003717499
-
-
I. L. Claude likens the UN Security Council veto to “a fuse in an electrical circuit,” reflecting the wise conviction that “in cases of sharp conflict among the great powers the Council ought, for safety's sake, to be incapacitated.” New York: Random House
-
I. L. Claude likens the UN Security Council veto to “a fuse in an electrical circuit,” reflecting the wise conviction that “in cases of sharp conflict among the great powers the Council ought, for safety's sake, to be incapacitated.” I. L. Claude, Power and International Relations (New York: Random House, 1962), p. 160.
-
(1962)
Power and International Relations
, pp. 160
-
-
Claude, I.L.1
-
20
-
-
0036823271
-
Inspections and Their Enforcement: A Modest Proposal
-
This necessity raises the problem of an ex post veto by the intervening state or states of the findings of the impartial commission or penalties implied by those findings. This problem could be solved by adapting a suggestion recently made by Thomas Franck, who points out that Article 27 provides that “decisions of the Security Council on procedural matters shall be made by an affirmative vote of nine members.” That is, on procedural matters, the veto is inapplicable. Ex ante the Council could decide that votes on the composition and report of the impartial commission, and on any recommendations for penalties, would be considered procedural. (Professor Franck's proposal concerns specification of what constitutes a “material breach” regarding UN resolutions concerning Iraq. See his October
-
This necessity raises the problem of an ex post veto by the intervening state or states of the findings of the impartial commission or penalties implied by those findings. This problem could be solved by adapting a suggestion recently made by Thomas Franck, who points out that Article 27 provides that “decisions of the Security Council on procedural matters shall be made by an affirmative vote of nine members.” That is, on procedural matters, the veto is inapplicable. Ex ante the Council could decide that votes on the composition and report of the impartial commission, and on any recommendations for penalties, would be considered procedural. (Professor Franck's proposal concerns specification of what constitutes a “material breach” regarding UN resolutions concerning Iraq. See his “Inspections and Their Enforcement: A Modest Proposal,” American Journal of International Law 96 (October 2002), pp. 899–900.
-
(2002)
American Journal of International Law
, vol.96
, pp. 899-900
-
-
|