메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 35, Issue 3, 2009, Pages 485-512

Egalitarian challenges to global egalitarianism: A critique

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 74549177740     PISSN: 02602105     EISSN: 14699044     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0260210509008626     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (46)

References (177)
  • 1
    • 84921819528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Recent theoretical defences of this idea are offered by, Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Recent theoretical defences of this idea are offered by Simon Caney, Justice beyond Borders: A Global Political Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005),
    • (2005) Justice beyond Borders: A Global Political Theory
    • Caney, S.1
  • 4
    • 74549189024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This point is forcefully made by Thomas W. Pogge in World Poverty and Human Rights: Cosmopolitan Responsibilities and Reforms Cambridge: Polity, 2002
    • This point is forcefully made by Thomas W. Pogge in World Poverty and Human Rights: Cosmopolitan Responsibilities and Reforms (Cambridge: Polity, 2002).
  • 5
    • 8844270971 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Responsibility and Global Labour Justice
    • See, for example
    • See, for example, Iris Marion Young, 'Responsibility and Global Labour Justice', Journal of Political Philosophy, 12 (2004), pp. 365-88,
    • (2004) Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.12 , pp. 365-388
    • Marion Young, I.1
  • 7
    • 33644907973 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Thomas Nagel's remarks in his 'The Problem of Global Justice', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 33 (2005), pp. 113-47, p. 141.
    • See also Thomas Nagel's remarks in his 'The Problem of Global Justice', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 33 (2005), pp. 113-47, p. 141.
  • 8
    • 74549226193 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Prominent advocates of realism are E.H. Carr, The Twenty Years' Crisis 1919-1939: An Introduction to the Study of International Relations (London: Palgrave, 2001),
    • Prominent advocates of realism are E.H. Carr, The Twenty Years' Crisis 1919-1939: An Introduction to the Study of International Relations (London: Palgrave, 2001),
  • 14
    • 0039033270 scopus 로고
    • Equality as a Moral Ideal' in his
    • See, for example, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See, for example, Harry Frankfurt, 'Equality as a Moral Ideal' in his The Importance of What We Care About (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988),
    • (1988) The Importance of What We Care About
    • Frankfurt, H.1
  • 15
    • 0003956640 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), pp. 217-44,
    • (1986) The Morality of Freedom , pp. 217-244
    • Raz, J.1
  • 16
    • 0040349812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Equality and Priority
    • and Derek Parfit, 'Equality and Priority', Ratio, 10 (2007), pp. 202-21.
    • (2007) Ratio , vol.10 , pp. 202-221
    • Parfit, D.1
  • 17
    • 0004295144 scopus 로고
    • For an illuminating discussion of these issues see, New York: Oxford University Press
    • For an illuminating discussion of these issues see Larry Temkin, Inequality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993).
    • (1993) Inequality
    • Temkin, L.1
  • 18
    • 74549144326 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Rawls
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Most notably, John Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999),
    • (1999) The Law of Peoples
    • Most notably1
  • 19
    • 0004002174 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • and David Miller, On Nationality (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995)
    • (1995) On Nationality
    • Miller, D.1
  • 20
    • 74549156338 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and National Responsibility and Global Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).
    • and National Responsibility and Global Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).
  • 21
    • 33847325333 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In order to be maximally comprehensive, we do not commit ourselves to any specific account of justice. For the purposes of this article, principles of justice are understood as a class of principles grounding particularly stringent distributive duties. Global egalitarians take different views on the justification of such principles. Some, for instance, see them as dependent on the existence of certain kinds of social institutions or relations (for example, Thomas Pogge, Charles Beitz, in his early work, and Darrel Moellendorf) while others reject this institutionalist view (for example, Simon Caney and Kok-Chor Tan, Our account aims to be neutral across these different positions. 10 This point is made by David Miller in 'Against Global Egalitarianism, The Journal of Ethics, 9 (2005, pp. 55-79, esp. pp. 58-9. Notice that Miller's definition of global egalitarianism is narrower than ours. In particular, unlike Miller, we do not claim that (i) global egalitarians always condem
    • In order to be maximally comprehensive, we do not commit ourselves to any specific account of justice. For the purposes of this article, principles of justice are understood as a class of principles grounding particularly stringent distributive duties. Global egalitarians take different views on the justification of such principles. Some, for instance, see them as dependent on the existence of certain kinds of social institutions or relations (for example, Thomas Pogge, Charles Beitz - in his early work - and Darrel Moellendorf) while others reject this institutionalist view (for example, Simon Caney and Kok-Chor Tan). Our account aims to be neutral across these different positions. 10 This point is made by David Miller in 'Against Global Egalitarianism', The Journal of Ethics, 9 (2005), pp. 55-79, esp. pp. 58-9. Notice that Miller's definition of global egalitarianism is narrower than ours. In particular, unlike Miller, we do not claim that (i) global egalitarians always condemn global inequalities as intrinsically wrong - as opposed to wrong because they undermine some other, more foundational, value - and (ii) the only inequalities that matter to them are inequalities between persons - rather than between states or groups. We shortly elaborate on these points in the main text.
  • 22
    • 74549148089 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brian Barry once held a position of this kind. See his 'Do Countries Have Moral Obligations? The Case of World Poverty', in Sterling M. McMurrin (ed.), The Tanner Lectures on Human Values II (Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press, 1981).
    • Brian Barry once held a position of this kind. See his 'Do Countries Have Moral Obligations? The Case of World Poverty', in Sterling M. McMurrin (ed.), The Tanner Lectures on Human Values Volume II (Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press, 1981).
  • 23
    • 74549172538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • David Miller also gestures towards this position when discussing power inequalities between societies in National Responsibility and Global Justice, pp. 75-6
    • David Miller also gestures towards this position when discussing power inequalities between societies in National Responsibility and Global Justice, pp. 75-6.
  • 24
    • 74549119537 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • So-called 'cosmopolitan' theorists typically hold this view. Prominent contemporary defences of cosmopolitanism are offered by Charles R. Beitz in Political Theory and International Relations with a new afterword (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1999)
    • So-called 'cosmopolitan' theorists typically hold this view. Prominent contemporary defences of cosmopolitanism are offered by Charles R. Beitz in Political Theory and International Relations with a new afterword (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1999)
  • 25
    • 0004248343 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ithaca: Cornell University Press
    • and Thomas W. Pogge, Realizing Rawls (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1989).
    • (1989) Realizing Rawls
    • Pogge, T.W.1
  • 26
    • 4544265154 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • More recent statements of cosmopolitanism are offered by
    • More recent statements of cosmopolitanism are offered by Moellendorf, Cosmopolitan Justice,
    • Cosmopolitan Justice
    • Moellendorf1
  • 29
    • 0004274013 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Amartya K. Sen, Inequality Reexamined (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992), p. 73.
    • (1992) Inequality Reexamined , pp. 73
    • Sen, A.K.1
  • 30
    • 74549184168 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leading discussions of such goods include John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971),
    • Leading discussions of such goods include John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971),
  • 31
    • 0001991872 scopus 로고
    • Social Unity and Primary Goods
    • Amartya Sen and Bernard Williams eds, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • John Rawls, 'Social Unity and Primary Goods,' in Amartya Sen and Bernard Williams (eds), Utilitarianism and Beyond (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), pp. 159-86,
    • (1982) Utilitarianism and Beyond , pp. 159-186
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 33
    • 74549120261 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and the essays in Amartya Sen and Martha Nussbaum (eds), The Quality of Life (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993).
    • and the essays in Amartya Sen and Martha Nussbaum (eds), The Quality of Life (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993).
  • 34
    • 0000655024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For discussions of the relevant goods in the global context, see also Simon Caney, 'Cosmopolitan Justice and Equalizing Opportunities', Metaphilosophy, 32 (2001), pp. 113-34,
    • For discussions of the relevant goods in the global context, see also Simon Caney, 'Cosmopolitan Justice and Equalizing Opportunities', Metaphilosophy, 32 (2001), pp. 113-34,
  • 35
    • 0011343714 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Human Flourishing and Universal Justice
    • reprinted as chapter 1 of his World Poverty and Human Rights
    • and Thomas Pogge, 'Human Flourishing and Universal Justice', Social Philosophy and Policy, 16 (1999), pp. 333-61 (reprinted as chapter 1 of his World Poverty and Human Rights).
    • (1999) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.16 , pp. 333-361
    • Pogge, T.1
  • 36
    • 0032647108 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. the position on domestic justice known as luck-egalitarianism discussed in Elizabeth Anderson, 'What is the Point of Equality?'
    • We shall discuss the relevance of considerations of (national) responsibility to global equality in section V of this article
    • We shall discuss the relevance of considerations of (national) responsibility to global equality in section V of this article. Cf. the position on domestic justice known as luck-egalitarianism discussed in Elizabeth Anderson, 'What is the Point of Equality?', Ethics, 109 (1999), pp. 287-337.
    • (1999) Ethics , vol.109 , pp. 287-337
  • 37
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is because Rawls treats equality as a morally privileged benchmark that he counts as an egalitarian in our sense. Strict prioritarians, who enjoin us simply to maximise the worst representative socioeconomic position, would not be egalitarians in our sense, since they do not maintain that there are restrictions on permissible inequalities
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice. It is because Rawls treats equality as a morally privileged benchmark that he counts as an egalitarian in our sense. Strict prioritarians - who enjoin us simply to maximise the worst representative socioeconomic position - would not be egalitarians in our sense, since they do not maintain that there are restrictions on permissible inequalities.
    • A Theory of Justice
    • Rawls1
  • 38
    • 33846708498 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As also pointed out by Andrea Sangiovanni in his 'Global Justice, Reciprocity, and the State', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 35 (2007), pp. 3-39, p. 8.
    • As also pointed out by Andrea Sangiovanni in his 'Global Justice, Reciprocity, and the State', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 35 (2007), pp. 3-39, p. 8.
  • 39
    • 74549121998 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We borrow this phrase from Shelly Kagan. See his 'The Structure of Normative Ethics', Philosophical Perspectives, 6 (1992), pp. 223-42.
    • We borrow this phrase from Shelly Kagan. See his 'The Structure of Normative Ethics', Philosophical Perspectives, 6 (1992), pp. 223-42.
  • 40
    • 33644912578 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Law of Peoples, Social Cooperation, Human Rights, and Distributive Justice
    • See, for example
    • See, for example, Samuel Freeman, 'The Law of Peoples, Social Cooperation, Human Rights, and Distributive Justice', Social Philosophy and Policy, 23 (2006), pp. 29-68, p. 37.
    • (2006) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.23
    • Freeman, S.1
  • 42
  • 43
    • 36748998924 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arash Abizadeh has forcefully argued for this conclusion in 'Cooperation, Pervasive Impact, and Coercion: On the Scope (not Site) of Distributive Justice', Philosophy & Public Affairs, 35 (2007), pp. 318-58, at pp. 330-1. In particular, Abizadeh helpfully distinguishes between three different understandings of what a Rawlsian basic structure is - in terms of social cooperation, pervasive impact and coercion - and argues that, on none of these interpretations, the scope of egalitarian demands can plausibly be restricted to the domestic arena.
    • Arash Abizadeh has forcefully argued for this conclusion in 'Cooperation, Pervasive Impact, and Coercion: On the Scope (not Site) of Distributive Justice', Philosophy & Public Affairs, 35 (2007), pp. 318-58, at pp. 330-1. In particular, Abizadeh helpfully distinguishes between three different understandings of what a Rawlsian basic structure is - in terms of social cooperation, pervasive impact and coercion - and argues that, on none of these interpretations, the scope of egalitarian demands can plausibly be restricted to the domestic arena.
  • 44
    • 51149122777 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Global Distributive Justice and the State
    • On similar issues see also
    • On similar issues see also Simon Caney, 'Global Distributive Justice and the State', Political Studies, 57 (2008), pp. 487-518.
    • (2008) Political Studies , vol.57 , pp. 487-518
    • Caney, S.1
  • 46
    • 0004248343 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For discussion see, esp. pp
    • For discussion see Pogge, Realizing Rawls, esp. pp. 23-5.
    • Realizing Rawls , pp. 23-25
    • Pogge1
  • 47
    • 0004043443 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a general discussion of the multiple dimensions of global 'social cooperation' so understood see John Baylis and Steve Smith eds, Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • For a general discussion of the multiple dimensions of global 'social cooperation' so understood see John Baylis and Steve Smith (eds), The Globalization of World Politics: An Introduction to International Relations (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005).
    • (2005) The Globalization of World Politics: An Introduction to International Relations
  • 48
    • 74549118936 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brian Barry, 'Humanity and Justice in Global Perspective', in B. Barry, Liberty and Justice: Essays in Political Theory, 2 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991), pp. 182-210, esp. 194 and Sangiovanni, 'Global Justice'.
    • Brian Barry, 'Humanity and Justice in Global Perspective', in B. Barry, Liberty and Justice: Essays in Political Theory, 2 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991), pp. 182-210, esp. 194 and Sangiovanni, 'Global Justice'.
  • 50
    • 0007034941 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • O'Neill's distinction between primary and secondary agents of justice in her 'Agents of Justice'
    • Cf. Onora O'Neill's distinction between primary and secondary agents of justice in her 'Agents of Justice', Metaphilosophy, 32 (2001), pp. 180-95.
    • (2001) Metaphilosophy , vol.32 , pp. 180-195
    • Onora, C.1
  • 53
    • 51149096347 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, what reciprocity requires depends a great deal on the particular relationship in question. For a helpful discussion, see Richard J. Arneson, Do Patriotic Ties Limit Global Justice Duties, The Journal of Ethics, 9 2005, pp. 127-50, esp. pp. 135-6
    • Of course, what reciprocity requires depends a great deal on the particular relationship in question. For a helpful discussion, see Richard J. Arneson, 'Do Patriotic Ties Limit Global Justice Duties?', The Journal of Ethics, 9 (2005), pp. 127-50, esp. pp. 135-6.
  • 54
    • 74549163625 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sangiovanni offers a good one, arguing that even though some may contribute more to the overall joint social product then others, their having made such contributions depends on background institutions to which all contributed, even if only through their submission. Sangiovanni, 'Global Justice', p. 26.
    • Sangiovanni offers a good one, arguing that even though some may contribute more to the overall joint social product then others, their having made such contributions depends on background institutions to which all contributed, even if only through their submission. Sangiovanni, 'Global Justice', p. 26.
  • 55
    • 74549164213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arash Abizadeh also considers this version of the argument from social cooperation and forcefully challenges the idea that the provision of primary goods could be an 'existence condition' of justice. Abizadeh, Cooperation, Pervasive Impact, and Coercion, pp. 336-7
    • Arash Abizadeh also considers this version of the argument from social cooperation and forcefully challenges the idea that the provision of primary goods could be an 'existence condition' of justice. Abizadeh, 'Cooperation, Pervasive Impact, and Coercion', pp. 336-7.
  • 56
    • 42049095712 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • International Property Rights and the Resource Curse
    • For an interesting discussion, see
    • For an interesting discussion, see Leif Wenar, 'International Property Rights and the Resource Curse', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 36 (2008), pp. 2-32.
    • (2008) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.36 , pp. 2-32
    • Wenar, L.1
  • 57
    • 34248034167 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An Immigration-pressure Model of Global Distributive Justice
    • See, for example, the discussion in
    • See, for example, the discussion in Eric Cavallero, 'An Immigration-pressure Model of Global Distributive Justice', Politics, Philosophy & Economics, 5 (2006), pp. 97-127.
    • (2006) Politics, Philosophy & Economics , vol.5 , pp. 97-127
    • Cavallero, E.1
  • 58
    • 74549211969 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for example, Nigel Harris, 'Migration without Borders: The Economic Perspective' (2004), draft, Migration without borders series. Available at http://unesdoc.unesco.org/images/0013/001391/139151e.pdf
    • See, for example, Nigel Harris, 'Migration without Borders: The Economic Perspective' (2004), draft, Migration without borders series. Available at http://unesdoc.unesco.org/images/0013/001391/139151e.pdf
  • 59
    • 52849107991 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Distributive Justice, State Coercion, and Autonomy
    • Michael Blake, 'Distributive Justice, State Coercion, and Autonomy', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 30 (2001), pp. 257-96,
    • (2001) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.30 , pp. 257-296
    • Blake, M.1
  • 60
    • 74549160970 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Problem of Global Justice'. Some of these points were originally made by Richard W. Miller in 'Cosmopolitan Respect and Patriotic Concern'
    • Nagel, 'The Problem of Global Justice'. Some of these points were originally made by Richard W. Miller in 'Cosmopolitan Respect and Patriotic Concern', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 27 (1998), pp. 202-24.
    • (1998) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.27 , pp. 202-224
    • Nagel1
  • 61
    • 74549203940 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Our account of the coercion view follows principally Michael Blake's in 'Distributive Justice
    • Our account of the coercion view follows principally Michael Blake's in 'Distributive Justice'.
  • 63
    • 0003875144 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the specific effects of coercion on persons' will see, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, ch. 5
    • On the specific effects of coercion on persons' will see Onora O'Neill, Bounds of Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), ch. 5.
    • (2000) Bounds of Justice
    • O'Neill, O.1
  • 64
    • 74549215687 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For this reason some have contested the assumption that coercion is indeed prima facie morally problematic, see Arneson, 'Do Patriotic Ties Limit Global Justice Duties?', pp. 136-42,
    • For this reason some have contested the assumption that coercion is indeed prima facie morally problematic, see Arneson, 'Do Patriotic Ties Limit Global Justice Duties?', pp. 136-42,
  • 65
    • 42149155468 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political Coercion and the Scope of Distributive Justice
    • and Ryan Pevnick, 'Political Coercion and the Scope of Distributive Justice', Political Studies, 56 (2008), pp. 399-413.
    • (2008) Political Studies , vol.56 , pp. 399-413
    • Pevnick, R.1
  • 70
    • 74549196344 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For valuable discussions of these points see, New Haven and London: Yale University Press
    • For valuable discussions of these points see David Grewal, Globalization and Network Power (New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 2008),
    • (2008) Globalization and Network Power
    • Grewal, D.1
  • 71
    • 85044998696 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What to Say About the State
    • esp. p. 681
    • and Mathias Risse, 'What to Say About the State', Social Theory and Practice, 32 (2006), pp. 671-98, esp. p. 681.
    • (2006) Social Theory and Practice , vol.32 , pp. 671-698
    • Risse, M.1
  • 72
    • 0012145190 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thomas Pogge has argued that the global economic order is coercively imposed by the world's wealthy and privileged on the world's poor in his, ch. 4
    • Thomas Pogge has argued that the global economic order is coercively imposed by the world's wealthy and privileged on the world's poor in his World Poverty and Human Rights, esp. ch. 4.
    • World Poverty and Human Rights, esp
  • 77
    • 84865551527 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Related to this is Risse's claim that what makes state coercion special is its distinctive immediacy and directness. See
    • Related to this is Risse's claim that what makes state coercion special is its distinctive immediacy and directness. See Risse, 'What to Say About the State', pp. 685ff.
    • What to Say About the State
    • Risse1
  • 80
    • 49749132352 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This claim is explicitly made by Saladin Meckled-Garcia, On the Very Idea of Cosmopolitan Justice: Constructivism and International Agency, Journal of Political Philosophy, 2008, pp. 245-71
    • This claim is explicitly made by Saladin Meckled-Garcia, 'On the Very Idea of Cosmopolitan Justice: Constructivism and International Agency', Journal of Political Philosophy, (2008), pp. 245-71.
  • 81
    • 74549134013 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • So, for instance, Samuel Freeman argues that a 'global difference principle would be without both agency and object, no legal person to implement it, and no legal system to which it is applicable, See
    • So, for instance, Samuel Freeman argues that a 'global difference principle would be without both agency and object - no legal person to implement it, and no legal system to which it is applicable'. See Freeman, 'The Law of Peoples', p. 61.
    • The Law of Peoples , pp. 61
    • Freeman1
  • 82
    • 74549181064 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The mere fact that no single agent can, acting alone, further the demands of a principle would not seem a good basis for dismissing the principle as impracticable
    • The mere fact that no single agent can, acting alone, further the demands of a principle would not seem a good basis for dismissing the principle as impracticable.
  • 83
    • 74549226574 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for example, Meckled-Garcia, 'On the Very Idea of Cosmopolitan Justice'.
    • See, for example, Meckled-Garcia, 'On the Very Idea of Cosmopolitan Justice'.
  • 86
    • 74549174122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the US of 1800, for example, it may have been that there were no agents who, acting together, could have realised principles of racial equality completely, at least in the short term
    • In the US of 1800, for example, it may have been that there were no agents who, acting together, could have realised principles of racial equality completely, at least in the short term.
  • 87
    • 74549220433 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We take it as obvious that the mere fact that a state is characterised by weak institutions or rapacious officials such that no agents are causally capable of promoting significantly egalitarian goals does not in itself show that egalitarian demands would not apply to such a society
    • We take it as obvious that the mere fact that a state is characterised by weak institutions or rapacious officials such that no agents are causally capable of promoting significantly egalitarian goals does not in itself show that egalitarian demands would not apply to such a society.
  • 88
    • 1642631623 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Joseph Carens also discusses the example of slavery to highlight the potentially conservative implications of 'realistic, hence likely to be effective) political theorising in his 'Realistic and Idealistic Approaches to the Ethics of Migration, International Migration Review, 30 1996, pp. 156-70, esp. pp. 164-6
    • Joseph Carens also discusses the example of slavery to highlight the potentially conservative implications of 'realistic' (hence likely to be effective) political theorising in his 'Realistic and Idealistic Approaches to the Ethics of Migration', International Migration Review, 30 (1996), pp. 156-70, esp. pp. 164-6.
  • 89
  • 90
    • 74549201634 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Meckled-Garcia, 'On the Very Idea of Cosmopolitan Justice'.
    • Meckled-Garcia, 'On the Very Idea of Cosmopolitan Justice'.
  • 91
    • 74549175182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Here we follow the accounts developed in Onora O'Neill, Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant's Practical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990)
    • Here we follow the accounts developed in Onora O'Neill, Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant's Practical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990)
  • 94
    • 0001639313 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Consequential Evaluation and Practical Reason
    • For discussion, see
    • For discussion, see Amartya Sen, 'Consequential Evaluation and Practical Reason', Journal of Philosophy, 96 (2000), pp. 477-502,
    • (2000) Journal of Philosophy , vol.96 , pp. 477-502
    • Sen, A.1
  • 95
    • 74549175181 scopus 로고
    • O'Neill on Rights and Duties'
    • and Thomas Pogge, 'O'Neill on Rights and Duties', Grazer Philosophische Studien, 43 (1992), pp. 233-47.
    • (1992) Grazer Philosophische Studien , vol.43 , pp. 233-247
    • Pogge, T.1
  • 96
    • 84935222192 scopus 로고
    • Justice and Charity
    • On the implausibility of confining justice to the realm of perfect duties see, esp. pp
    • On the implausibility of confining justice to the realm of perfect duties see Allen Buchanan, 'Justice and Charity', Ethics, 97 (1987), pp. 558-75, esp. pp. 570-1.
    • (1987) Ethics , vol.97
    • Buchanan, A.1
  • 97
    • 74549122499 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For further critical discussion of agency-based arguments against global egalitarianism see Laura Valentini, Global Justice: Cosmopolitanism, Social Liberalism, and the Coercion View, University College London: Ph.D. Thesis, 2008, ch. 5
    • For further critical discussion of agency-based arguments against global egalitarianism see Laura Valentini, 'Global Justice: Cosmopolitanism, Social Liberalism, and the Coercion View' (University College London: Ph.D. Thesis, 2008), ch. 5.
  • 98
    • 74549151135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This type of argument has been advanced by John Rawls, The Law of Peoples, pp. 117-8
    • This type of argument has been advanced by John Rawls, The Law of Peoples, pp. 117-8,
  • 99
    • 0000127042 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Justice and Global Inequality
    • Andrew Hurrel and Ngaire Woods eds, Oxford: Oxford University Press, esp. pp. 193-5
    • David Miller, 'Justice and Global Inequality', in Andrew Hurrel and Ngaire Woods (eds), Inequality, Globalization, and World Politics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), pp. 187-210, esp. pp. 193-5,
    • (1999) Inequality, Globalization, and World Politics , pp. 187-210
    • Miller, D.1
  • 101
    • 74549121997 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Miller puts it: 'Why be an ant, if the grasshoppers are guaranteed equal access to your store of winter provisions?' in National Responsibility and Global Justice, p. 71. Detailed discussion of all three claims may be found in chapter 3 of Miller's book.
    • As Miller puts it: 'Why be an ant, if the grasshoppers are guaranteed equal access to your store of winter provisions?' in National Responsibility and Global Justice, p. 71. Detailed discussion of all three claims may be found in chapter 3 of Miller's book.
  • 102
    • 74549194531 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is noted by Miller in National Responsibility and Global Justice, pp. 69-70
    • This is noted by Miller in National Responsibility and Global Justice, pp. 69-70.
  • 103
    • 74549148088 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Such a global egalitarian view is explored by Alexander Cappelen in 'Responsibility and International Distributive Justice, Andreas Føllesdal and Thomas Pogge eds, Berlin: Springer
    • Such a global egalitarian view is explored by Alexander Cappelen in 'Responsibility and International Distributive Justice', in Andreas Føllesdal and Thomas Pogge (eds), Real World Justice (Berlin: Springer, 2005), pp. 209-22.
    • (2005) Real World Justice , pp. 209-222
  • 104
    • 74549138571 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This point is forcefully made by Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights, ch. 4
    • This point is forcefully made by Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights, ch. 4,
  • 106
    • 33845479011 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (anti-global-egalitarian) discussion of what he calls geographical, institutional, and integration factors in 'How Does the Global Order Harm the Poor'
    • See, for example
    • See, for example, Mathias Risse's (anti-global-egalitarian) discussion of what he calls geographical, institutional, and integration factors in 'How Does the Global Order Harm the Poor', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 33 (2005), pp. 349-76.
    • (2005) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.33 , pp. 349-376
    • Risse's, M.1
  • 108
    • 0001156410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls's Law of Peoples
    • See, for discussion
    • See Charles R. Beitz, 'Rawls's Law of Peoples', Ethics, 110 (2000), pp. 669-96, p. 690, for discussion.
    • (2000) Ethics , vol.110
    • Beitz, C.R.1
  • 109
    • 2442720070 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Holding Nations Responsible
    • For a very interesting discussion, see
    • For a very interesting discussion, see David Miller, 'Holding Nations Responsible', Ethics, 114 (2003-2004), pp. 240-68,
    • (2003) Ethics , vol.114 , pp. 240-268
    • Miller, D.1
  • 110
    • 74549200364 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and National Responsibility and Global Justice, ch. 6.
    • and National Responsibility and Global Justice, ch. 6.
  • 111
    • 0000163203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls on International Justice
    • See, esp. pp
    • See Thomas W. Pogge, 'Rawls on International Justice', Philosophical Quarterly, 51 (2001), pp. 246-53, esp. pp. 249-50,
    • (2001) Philosophical Quarterly , vol.51
    • Pogge, T.W.1
  • 112
    • 74549148982 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and 'Do Rawls's two Theories of Justice Fit Together?', in Rex Martin and David Reidy (eds), Rawls's Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia? (Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2006), pp. 206-25.
    • and 'Do Rawls's two Theories of Justice Fit Together?', in Rex Martin and David Reidy (eds), Rawls's Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia? (Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2006), pp. 206-25.
  • 113
    • 74549179682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Two Models of Equality and Responsibility
    • In so saying we are not suggesting that Rawls is a 'luck-egalitarian, but simply pointing to the centrality of considerations of responsibility in his theory of domestic justice. For discussion see
    • In so saying we are not suggesting that Rawls is a 'luck-egalitarian', but simply pointing to the centrality of considerations of responsibility in his theory of domestic justice. For discussion see Mathias Risse and Michael Blake, 'Two Models of Equality and Responsibility', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, (2008), pp. 165-99.
    • (2008) Canadian Journal of Philosophy , pp. 165-199
    • Risse, M.1    Blake, M.2
  • 114
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • with a New Introduction and the 'Reply to Habermas, New York: Columbia University Press
    • John Rawls, Political Liberalism with a New Introduction and the 'Reply to Habermas' (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996), p. 267.
    • (1996) Political Liberalism , pp. 267
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 116
    • 74549163627 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • So, for instance, Pogge argues that Rawls's own (anti-egalitarian) approach to international justice 'does not protect poor societies against skewed (and deteriorating) terms of cooperation exacted from them through the greater (and increasing) bargaining power of the affluent'. Pogge, 'Rawls on International Justice', p. 251.
    • So, for instance, Pogge argues that Rawls's own (anti-egalitarian) approach to international justice 'does not protect poor societies against skewed (and deteriorating) terms of cooperation exacted from them through the greater (and increasing) bargaining power of the affluent'. Pogge, 'Rawls on International Justice', p. 251.
  • 117
    • 84891289656 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • David Miller also expresses similar worries (though in the context of a much more sympathetic analysis of Rawls), saying that 'inequalities between peoples may also constitute inequalities of power, which will have a distorting effect on future terms of international cooperation'. See David Miller, 'Collective Responsibility and International Inequality in The Law of Peoples' in Rawls's Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia?, pp. 191-205, p. 203.
    • David Miller also expresses similar worries (though in the context of a much more sympathetic analysis of Rawls), saying that 'inequalities between peoples may also constitute inequalities of power, which will have a distorting effect on future terms of international cooperation'. See David Miller, 'Collective Responsibility and International Inequality in The Law of Peoples' in Rawls's Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia?, pp. 191-205, p. 203.
  • 118
    • 74549143198 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In fact, Miller has recently argued that 'self-determination also gives us a reason to limit global inequality, in National Responsibility and Global Justice, p. 74, n. 22, emphasis in original
    • In fact, Miller has recently argued that 'self-determination also gives us a reason to limit global inequality', in National Responsibility and Global Justice, p. 74, n. 22, emphasis in original.
  • 119
    • 74549176630 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • David Miller and John Rawls seem to be both aware of this. See
    • David Miller and John Rawls seem to be both aware of this. See, respectively, The Law of Peoples, p. 53
    • The Law of Peoples , pp. 53
    • respectively1
  • 120
    • 74549186499 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and National Responsibility and Global Justice, pp. 75-6.
    • and National Responsibility and Global Justice, pp. 75-6.
  • 121
    • 0036522561 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This point is forcefully made against Rawls by Simon Caney in 'Cosmopolitanism and the Law of Peoples, Journal of Political Philosophy, 10 2002, pp. 95-123, p. 118
    • This point is forcefully made against Rawls by Simon Caney in 'Cosmopolitanism and the Law of Peoples', Journal of Political Philosophy, 10 (2002), pp. 95-123, p. 118,
  • 122
    • 3042793950 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Incoherence between Rawls's Theories of Justice
    • and by
    • and by Thomas W. Pogge in 'The Incoherence between Rawls's Theories of Justice', Fordham Law Review, 72 (2004), pp. 1739-59, p. 1751.
    • (2004) Fordham Law Review , vol.72
    • Pogge, T.W.1
  • 125
    • 74549181357 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Caney's Global Political Theory
    • A more recent statement of this type of argument is offered by, sec. 1
    • A more recent statement of this type of argument is offered by Gillian Brock, 'Caney's Global Political Theory', Journal of Global Ethics, 3 (2007), sec. 1.
    • (2007) Journal of Global Ethics , pp. 3
    • Brock, G.1
  • 126
    • 0000655024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cosmopolitan Justice and Equalizing Opportunities
    • For responses to this type of criticisms see, esp. pp
    • For responses to this type of criticisms see Simon Caney, 'Cosmopolitan Justice and Equalizing Opportunities', Metaphilosophy, 32 (2001), pp. 113-34, esp. pp. 118-22
    • (2001) Metaphilosophy , vol.32
    • Caney, S.1
  • 127
    • 74549141794 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and 'Justice, Borders and the Cosmopolitan Ideal: A Reply to Two Critics', Journal of Global Ethics, 3 (2007), pp. 269-76, esp. 269-272.
    • and 'Justice, Borders and the Cosmopolitan Ideal: A Reply to Two Critics', Journal of Global Ethics, 3 (2007), pp. 269-76, esp. 269-272.
  • 128
    • 74549162767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Against Global Egalitarianism
    • Miller, 'Against Global Egalitarianism', p. 63.
    • Miller1
  • 129
    • 59349119571 scopus 로고
    • Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory
    • Samuel Freeman ed, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • John Rawls, 'Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory' (1980), in Samuel Freeman (ed.) John Rawls: Collected Papers (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), pp. 303-58.
    • (1980) John Rawls: Collected Papers , pp. 303-358
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 130
    • 74549208536 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Miller's words, 'It is essentially the problem of saying what equality of opportunity means in a culturally plural world in which different societies will construct goods in different ways and also rank them in different ways'. See National Responsibility and Global Justice, p. 67, emphasis in original.
    • In Miller's words, 'It is essentially the problem of saying what equality of opportunity means in a culturally plural world in which different societies will construct goods in different ways and also rank them in different ways'. See National Responsibility and Global Justice, p. 67, emphasis in original.
  • 132
    • 74549212597 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. the (controversial) list of capabilities defended by Martha Nussbaum in Women and Human Development (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), pp. 78-80.
    • Cf. the (controversial) list of capabilities defended by Martha Nussbaum in Women and Human Development (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), pp. 78-80.
  • 133
    • 74549213861 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Humanity and Equality in the Work of David Miller
    • As Leif Wenar has recently pointed out, the egalitarian can say that our goal should be to leave aside the more difficult cases and 'make individuals equal in ways they clearly and uncontroversially are now not, See
    • As Leif Wenar has recently pointed out, the egalitarian can say that our goal should be to leave aside the more difficult cases and 'make individuals equal in ways they clearly and uncontroversially are now not'. See Leif Wenar, 'Humanity and Equality in the Work of David Miller', Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 11 (2008) pp. 401-11, p. 403.
    • (2008) Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy , vol.11
    • Wenar, L.1
  • 136
    • 0000143744 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This critique has been advanced, for instance, by Kok-Chor Tan, Liberal Toleration in Rawls's Law of Peoples, Ethics, 108 1998, pp. 275-95, at pp. 282ff
    • This critique has been advanced, for instance, by Kok-Chor Tan, 'Liberal Toleration in Rawls's Law of Peoples', Ethics, 108 (1998), pp. 275-95, at pp. 282ff.,
  • 137
    • 0034340760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Andrew Kuper, 'Rawlsian Global Justice: Beyond The Law of Peoples to a Cosmopolitan Law of Persons', Political Theory, 28 (2000), pp. 640-74, at pp. 648-53,
    • Andrew Kuper, 'Rawlsian Global Justice: Beyond The Law of Peoples to a Cosmopolitan Law of Persons', Political Theory, 28 (2000), pp. 640-74, at pp. 648-53,
  • 139
    • 84992799212 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and 'An Egalitarian Law of Peoples', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 23 (1994), pp. 195-224, at. pp. 214-7.
    • and 'An Egalitarian Law of Peoples', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 23 (1994), pp. 195-224, at. pp. 214-7.
  • 142
    • 0001156411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Allen Buchanan, 'Rawls's Law of Peoples: Rules for a Vanished Westphalian World', Ethics, 110 (2000), pp. 697-721, at pp. 718-9,
    • Allen Buchanan, 'Rawls's Law of Peoples: Rules for a Vanished Westphalian World', Ethics, 110 (2000), pp. 697-721, at pp. 718-9,
  • 143
    • 74549134581 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Saladin Meckled-Garcia, 'International Justice, Human Rights and Neutrality', Res Publica, 10 (2004), pp. 153-74, at pp. 160-3.
    • and Saladin Meckled-Garcia, 'International Justice, Human Rights and Neutrality', Res Publica, 10 (2004), pp. 153-74, at pp. 160-3.
  • 144
    • 0007027218 scopus 로고
    • The Law of Peoples
    • Samuel Freeman ed, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Rawls, 'The Law of Peoples', (1993), in Samuel Freeman (ed.), John Rawls: Collected Papers, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), pp. 529-64, p. 561.
    • (1993) John Rawls: Collected Papers
    • Rawls1
  • 145
    • 74549149488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for discussion
    • See Tan, 'Liberal Toleration', pp. 282-4 for discussion.
    • Liberal Toleration , pp. 282-284
    • Tan1
  • 146
    • 85004271194 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Similar suggestions are made, for instance, by Henry Shue, 'Rawls and the Outlaws', Politics, Philosophy & Economics, 1 (2002), pp. 307-23, p. 311
    • Similar suggestions are made, for instance, by Henry Shue, 'Rawls and the Outlaws', Politics, Philosophy & Economics, 1 (2002), pp. 307-23, p. 311
  • 149
    • 2542511721 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This reading of Rawls's The Law of Peoples is forcefully defended by David A. Reidy in his, Rawls on International Justice: A Defense, Political Theory, 32 2004, pp. 291-319, pp. 306-16
    • This reading of Rawls's The Law of Peoples is forcefully defended by David A. Reidy in his, 'Rawls on International Justice: A Defense', Political Theory, 32 (2004), pp. 291-319, pp. 306-16.
  • 151
    • 0004168076 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a description of the features of decent societies see
    • For a description of the features of decent societies see Rawls see The Law of Peoples, pp. 64-8.
    • The Law of Peoples , pp. 64-68
    • Rawls see1
  • 152
    • 74549165458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is the main thrust of the criticisms raised against The Law of Peoples by the critics mentioned at footnote 90
    • This is the main thrust of the criticisms raised against The Law of Peoples by the critics mentioned at footnote 90.
  • 153
    • 74549197678 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We discussed the implausible implications of feasibility understood as 'realisability in the here and now' in the section on agency
    • We discussed the implausible implications of feasibility understood as 'realisability in the here and now' in the section on agency.
  • 155
    • 26444458127 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, Cambridge: Polity Press, ch. 2
    • See Harry Brighouse, Justice (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2004), ch. 2.
    • (2004) Justice
    • Brighouse, H.1
  • 156
    • 84921848852 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We borrow the concept of moral accessibility from Allen Buchanan, Justice, Legitimacy, and Self-Determination (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), p. 61.
    • We borrow the concept of moral accessibility from Allen Buchanan, Justice, Legitimacy, and Self-Determination (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), p. 61.
  • 157
    • 0347569028 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Feasibility Condition in Political Theory
    • See also
    • See also Juha Räikkä, 'The Feasibility Condition in Political Theory', Journal of Political Philosophy, 6 (1998), pp. 27-40.
    • (1998) Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.6 , pp. 27-40
    • Räikkä, J.1
  • 158
    • 74549155110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Räikkä maintains that, in assessing the plausibility of an ideal theory, we should take into account the 'moral costs of changeover, p. 35
    • Räikkä maintains that, in assessing the plausibility of an ideal theory, we should take into account the 'moral costs of changeover', p. 35.
  • 159
    • 74549151136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For discussion of these points see also Valentini, 'Global Justice', ch. 2,
    • For discussion of these points see also Valentini, 'Global Justice', ch. 2,
  • 160
    • 74549133506 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and 'The Law of Peoples between Ideal and Non-ideal Theory' (University College London: MA thesis, 2005).
    • and 'The Law of Peoples between Ideal and Non-ideal Theory' (University College London: MA thesis, 2005).
  • 162
    • 74549124878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This point is noted and discussed by Beitz in 'Rawls's Law of Peoples, pp. 681-2
    • This point is noted and discussed by Beitz in 'Rawls's Law of Peoples', pp. 681-2.
  • 164
    • 0003335371 scopus 로고
    • Perpetual Peace
    • See also, H. Reiss ed, London: Cambridge University Press
    • See also Immanuel Kant, Perpetual Peace, in H. Reiss (ed.), Kant's Political Writings (London: Cambridge University Press, 1970).
    • (1970) Kant's Political Writings
    • Kant, I.1
  • 166
    • 0003556319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Our argument here is very much in line with his. These issues have been explored illuminatingly and at length by
    • These issues have been explored illuminatingly and at length by Beitz in Political Theory and International Relations, pp. 156-7. Our argument here is very much in line with his.
    • Political Theory and International Relations , pp. 156-157
    • Beitz in1
  • 167
    • 84925677087 scopus 로고
    • Cosmopolitanism and Sovereignty
    • Thomas W. Pogge, 'Cosmopolitanism and Sovereignty', Ethics, 103 (1992), pp. 48-75.
    • (1992) Ethics , vol.103 , pp. 48-75
    • Pogge, T.W.1
  • 168
    • 74549188450 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Andrew Kuper, who sketches a system of 'functional plural sovereignty', in Kuper 'Rawlsian Global Justice', and more fully in his Democracy beyond Borders: Justice and Representation in Global Institutions (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004).
    • See also Andrew Kuper, who sketches a system of 'functional plural sovereignty', in Kuper 'Rawlsian Global Justice', and more fully in his Democracy beyond Borders: Justice and Representation in Global Institutions (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004).
  • 169
    • 39349088373 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Statist Cosmopolitanism
    • For a 'state-centred' account of how this might be possible see
    • For a 'state-centred' account of how this might be possible see Lea L. Ypi, 'Statist Cosmopolitanism', Journal of Political Philosophy, 16 (2008), pp. 48-71.
    • (2008) Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.16 , pp. 48-71
    • Ypi, L.L.1
  • 170
    • 1442306182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Taking People as They Are?
    • On the capacity of institutions to shape persons' character see
    • On the capacity of institutions to shape persons' character see Joshua Cohen, 'Taking People as They Are?', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 30 (2001), pp. 363-86.
    • (2001) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.30 , pp. 363-386
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 171
    • 74549183507 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arash Abizadeh makes a similar point in his discussion of the feasibility of a just global basic structure in his 'Cooperation, Pervasive Impact, and Coercion, pp. 340-1
    • Arash Abizadeh makes a similar point in his discussion of the feasibility of a just global basic structure in his 'Cooperation, Pervasive Impact, and Coercion', pp. 340-1.
  • 172
    • 38049080237 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In a similar vein, Amartya Sen distinguishes between what he calls 'transcendental' and 'purely comparative' approaches to justice. See Sen, What Do We Want from a Theory of Justice, The Journal of Philosophy, 103 (2006, pp. 215-38. Sen maintains (incorrectly in our view) that Rawls's principles are 'transcendental
    • In a similar vein, Amartya Sen distinguishes between what he calls 'transcendental' and 'purely comparative' approaches to justice. See Sen, 'What Do We Want from a Theory of Justice?', The Journal of Philosophy, 103 (2006), pp. 215-38. Sen maintains (incorrectly in our view) that Rawls's principles are 'transcendental'.
  • 173
    • 74549120263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This suggestion is made by Michael Phillips in his 'Reflections on the Transition from Ideal to Non-Ideal Theory, Noûs, 19 1985, 551-70, esp. p. 557
    • This suggestion is made by Michael Phillips in his 'Reflections on the Transition from Ideal to Non-Ideal Theory', Noûs, 19 (1985), 551-70, esp. p. 557.
  • 174
    • 74549148361 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Robert Goodin's helpful discussion of second-best theories in 'Political Ideals and Political Practice'.
    • See Robert Goodin's helpful discussion of second-best theories in 'Political Ideals and Political Practice'.
  • 175
    • 33645977484 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Institutionalizing the Just War
    • For an interesting discussion of the forceful imposition of democracy see
    • For an interesting discussion of the forceful imposition of democracy see Allen Buchanan, 'Institutionalizing the Just War', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 34 (2006), pp. 2-38.
    • (2006) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.34 , pp. 2-38
    • Buchanan, A.1
  • 176
    • 0001305299 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beitz's remarks in 'Cosmopolitan Ideals and National Sentiment
    • See, 80 1983, pp
    • See Charles R. Beitz's remarks in 'Cosmopolitan Ideals and National Sentiment', The Journal of Philosophy, 80 (1983), pp. 591-600, p. 595.
    • The Journal of Philosophy
    • Charles, R.1
  • 177
    • 74549156337 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For further discussion of the relation between ideal theory and political practice in theorising about global justice see Charles R. Beitz, Justice and International Relations, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 4 1975, pp. 360-89, esp. pp. 383-9
    • For further discussion of the relation between ideal theory and political practice in theorising about global justice see Charles R. Beitz, 'Justice and International Relations', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 4 (1975), pp. 360-89, esp. pp. 383-9.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.