메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 35, Issue 4, 2007, Pages 318-358

Cooperation, pervasive impact, and coercion: On the scope (not site) of distributive justice

(1)  Abizadeh, Arash a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 36748998924     PISSN: 00483915     EISSN: 10884963     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1088-4963.2007.00116.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (188)

References (89)
  • 1
    • 36749026840 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In this article, unless otherwise noted, the term justice refers to distributive justice, and not to what Rawls called natural justice; by cosmopolitan I simply mean the view that the scope of distributive justice is global, by anticosmopolitan the view that it is not
    • In this article, unless otherwise noted, the term justice refers to distributive justice, and not to what Rawls called natural justice; by cosmopolitan I simply mean the view that the scope of distributive justice is global, by anticosmopolitan the view that it is not.
  • 2
    • 36749059204 scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press) cf. p. 457: the "boundaries"of "the basic structures of well-ordered societies...are [assumed to be] given by the notion of a self-contained national community."
    • John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 4, 96, 7; cf. p. 457: The "boundaries"of "the basic structures of well-ordered societies...are [assumed to be] given by the notion of a self-contained national community."
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice , vol.96 , Issue.7 , pp. 4
    • John, R.1
  • 3
    • 36749034499 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I say "Rawlsian" rather than "Rawls's" because (as an Editor of Philosophy & Public Affairs has pointed out) whether Rawls himself was ultimately committed to the basic structure argument is a matter of some interpretive ambiguity. On the one hand, in paperback ed. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press) Rawls presented his anticosmopolitanism merely as a provisional but methodologically useful assumption. He did not provide an explicit argument for his anticosmopolitanism and, in The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999), when he did provide one, he did so without explicitly appealing to the basic structure argument. On the other hand, the basic structure argument is arguably implicit to Theory of Justice. When in that work Rawls relaxed the assumption of closed, self-sufficient societies to consider the issue of international justice, he did not conclude that "justice between states" requires distributive justice.
    • I say "Rawlsian" rather than "Rawls's" because (as an Editor of Philosophy & Public Affairs has pointed out) whether Rawls himself was ultimately committed to the basic structure argument is a matter of some interpretive ambiguity. On the one hand, in Theory of Justice and Political Liberalism, paperback ed. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1996), Rawls presented his anticosmopolitanism merely as a provisional but methodologically useful assumption. He did not provide an explicit argument for his anticosmopolitanism and, in The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999), when he did provide one, he did so without explicitly appealing to the basic structure argument. On the other hand, the basic structure argument is arguably implicit to Theory of Justice. When in that work Rawls relaxed the assumption of closed, self-sufficient societies to consider the issue of international justice, he did not conclude that "justice between states" requires distributive justice but, rather, that it requires principles familiar from traditional international law for "adjudicat[ing] conflicting claims among states" (pp. 377-79). The implicit assumption backing this conclusion seems to have been that while empirical reality requires relaxing the assumption of self-sufficiency, it does not require relaxing the assumption that there is no global basic structure: Even when he relaxed the assumption of self-sufficiency to consider issues in international justice, he continued to assume that "we have already derived the principles of justice as these apply to societies as units and to the basic structure" (p. 377, my emphasis). Moreover, as
    • (1996) Theory of Justice and Political Liberalism
  • 4
    • 0001156411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Rawls's Law of Peoples: Rules for a Vanished Westphalian World"
    • Allen Buchanan, "Rawls's Law of Peoples: Rules for a Vanished Westphalian World" Ethics 110 (2000): 697-721,
    • (2000) Ethics , vol.110 , pp. 697-721
    • Buchanan, A.1
  • 5
    • 0242472981 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Rawls and Habermas on Public Reason"
    • J. Donald Moon, "Rawls and Habermas on Public Reason," Annual Review of Political Science 6 (2003): 257-74,
    • (2003) Annual Review of Political Science , vol.6 , pp. 257-274
    • Moon, J.D.1
  • 6
    • 0007028682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "The Limits of Cosmopolitan Justice"
    • I borrow the expression "comparative principles" from ed. David R. Mapel and Terry Nardin (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press) at p. 169. As I define the terms, Andrea Sangiovanni's recent article denies that principles of distributive justice (which, in my sense, are concerned with equality) are global in scope
    • I borrow the expression "comparative principles" from David Miller, "The Limits of Cosmopolitan Justice," International Society, ed. David R. Mapel and Terry Nardin (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1998), pp. 164-81, at p. 169. As I define the terms, Andrea Sangiovanni's recent article denies that principles of distributive justice (which, in my sense, are concerned with equality) are global in scope.
    • (1998) International Society , pp. 164-181
    • Miller, D.1
  • 7
    • 33846708498 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Global Justice, Reciprocity, and the State"
    • "Global Justice, Reciprocity, and the State," Philosophy & Public Affairs 35 (2007): 3-39.
    • (2007) Philosophy & Public Affairs , vol.35 , pp. 3-39
  • 8
    • 52849107991 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Distributive Justice, State Coercion, and Autonomy"
    • Michael Blake, "Distributive Justice, State Coercion, and Autonomy," Philosophy & Public Affairs 30 (2002): 257-96
    • (2002) Philosophy & Public Affairs , vol.30 , pp. 257-296
    • Blake, M.1
  • 9
    • 33644907973 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "The Problem of Global Justice"
    • Thomas Nagel, "The Problem of Global Justice," Philosophy & Public Affairs 33 (2005): 113-47.
    • (2005) Philosophy & Public Affairs , vol.33 , pp. 113-147
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 10
    • 44949256273 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Do Rawls's Two Theories of Justice Fit Together?"
    • in ed. Rex Martin and David A. Reidy (Oxford: Blackwell), for questions about whether Rawls's assumptions about the moral integrity of peoples is compatible with the moral individualism he defends in Theory of Justice. Although I do not make the case here, I believe that Rawls's toleration of peoples argument in Law of Peoples is detachable from his theory of justice as fairness as a whole
    • See Thomas W. Pogge, "Do Rawls's Two Theories of Justice Fit Together?" in Rawls's Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia?, ed. Rex Martin and David A. Reidy (Oxford: Blackwell, 2006), for questions about whether Rawls's assumptions about the moral integrity of peoples is compatible with the moral individualism he defends in Theory of Justice. Although I do not make the case here, I believe that Rawls's toleration of peoples argument in Law of Peoples is detachable from his theory of justice as fairness as a whole.
    • (2006) Rawls's Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia?
    • Thomas, W.P.1
  • 11
    • 0003556319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the debate concerning contemporary levels of globalization, see David Held etal., Global Transformations (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1999) and the articles collected in The Global Transformations Reader, ed. David Held and McGrew Anthony (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2000)
    • See, e.g., Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations, pp. 169-70. For the debate concerning contemporary levels of globalization, see David Held etal., Global Transformations (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1999) and the articles collected in The Global Transformations Reader, ed. David Held and McGrew Anthony (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2000).
    • Political Theory and International Relations , pp. 169-170
    • Beitz, C.R.1
  • 12
    • 36749098158 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As noted above in Theory of Justice Rawls was willing to relax the assumption of self-sufficiency but not that the basic structure is domestic in scope
    • See Moon, "Rawls and Habermas on Public Reason," p. 265. As noted above (n. 3), in Theory of Justice Rawls was willing to relax the assumption of self-sufficiency but not that the basic structure is domestic in scope.
    • "Rawls and Habermas on Public Reason" , Issue.3 , pp. 265
    • Moon, D.1
  • 13
    • 36749077800 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This important distinction, between scope and site, has not been adequately appreciated in the literature. Andrew Williams, for example, uses the term "scope" to refer to what I call site. See his
    • This important distinction, between scope and site, has not been adequately appreciated in the literature. Andrew Williams, for example, uses the term "scope" to refer to what I call site. See his
  • 14
    • 0009184104 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Incentives, Inequality, and Publicity"
    • "Incentives, Inequality, and Publicity," Philosophy & Public Affairs 27 (1998): 225-47,
    • (1998) Philosophy & Public Affairs , vol.27 , pp. 225-247
  • 15
    • 36749053732 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As we shall see, this is Samuel Freeman's interpretation, according to whom an already existing shared basic structure is a necessary condition for relations of justice to arise in the first place ("Distributive Justice and The Law of Peoples ")
    • As we shall see, this is Samuel Freeman's interpretation, according to whom an already existing shared basic structure is a necessary condition for relations of justice to arise in the first place ("Distributive Justice and The Law of Peoples ").
  • 16
    • 36749025942 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I borrow the term "existence condition" from
    • I borrow the term "existence condition" from
  • 17
    • 0001305299 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Cosmopolitan Ideals and National Sentiment"
    • at p. 595
    • Charles R. Beitz, "Cosmopolitan Ideals and National Sentiment" The Journal of Philosophy 80 (1983): 591-600, at p. 595.
    • (1983) The Journal of Philosophy , vol.80 , pp. 591-600
    • Beitz, C.R.1
  • 18
    • 77956285247 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I quote Rawls's most mature formulation, from which follows very closely the wording of Rawls, Theory of Justice, p. 7. See also Thomas W. Pogge, Realizing Rawls (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1989), pp. 20-23
    • I quote Rawls's most mature formulation, from Justice as Fairness, p. 10, which follows very closely the wording of Rawls, Theory of Justice, p. 7. See also Thomas W. Pogge, Realizing Rawls (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1989), pp. 20-23.
    • Justice As Fairness , pp. 10
  • 19
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Justice as Fairness, p. 10. Cf. Theory of Justice, p. 7
    • John Rawls, Political Liberalism, p. 258, and Justice as Fairness, p. 10. Cf. Theory of Justice, p. 7.
    • Political Liberalism , pp. 258
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 20
    • 36749028505 scopus 로고
    • "Rawls's Theory of Justice"
    • ed. Norman Daniels (New York: Basic Books), especially
    • See Thomas Scanlon, "Rawls's Theory of Justice," Reading Rawls, ed. Norman Daniels (New York: Basic Books, 1974), especially pp. 192-93.
    • (1974) Reading Rawls , pp. 192-193
    • Thomas, S.1
  • 21
    • 77956285247 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The principles of justice as fairness "do not apply directly to or regulate internally the institutions and associations within society. Firms and labor unions, churches, universities, and the family are bound by constraints arising from the principles of justice, but these constraints arise indirectly from just background institutions within which associations and groups exist, and by which the conduct of their members is restricted." Justice as Fairness, p. 10; see also pp. 7, 162-68.
    • Justice As Fairness , pp. 10
  • 23
    • 36749084270 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The assumption that Rawlsian distributive justice is in the first instance addressed to the allocation of goods is one of the shortcomings of Joseph Heath's recent defense of anticosmopolitan Rawlsianism in "Rawls on Global Distributive Justice: A Defence," in Global Justice, Global Institutions: Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supplementary Volume 31, ed. Daniel Weinstock (Calgary: University of Calgary Press, 2005)
    • Freeman, "Distributive Justice and The Law of Peoples," p. 245. The assumption that Rawlsian distributive justice is in the first instance addressed to the allocation of goods is one of the shortcomings of Joseph Heath's recent defense of anticosmopolitan Rawlsianism in "Rawls on Global Distributive Justice: A Defence,"in Global Justice, Global Institutions: Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supplementary Volume 31, ed. Daniel Weinstock (Calgary: University of Calgary Press, 2005).
    • "Distributive Justice and The Law of Peoples" , pp. 245
    • Freeman, S.1
  • 24
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Justice as Fairness, pp. 52-55
    • Political Liberalism, pp. 265-69; Justice as Fairness, pp. 52-55.
    • Political Liberalism , pp. 265-269
  • 26
    • 0003836741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The instrumental character of Rawls's division of labor argument for taking the basic structure as the primary site of justice assumes that a normative aim of both institutions of the basic structure and the individuals who inhabit them ought to be distributive justice. The division of labor argument simply asserts that as a matter of empirical fact the best way to realize this aim is to apply the principles directly to the basic structure. This means that, given the way that
    • Justice as Fairness, p. 54. The instrumental character of Rawls's division of labor argument for taking the basic structure as the primary site of justice assumes that a normative aim of both institutions of the basic structure and the individuals who inhabit them ought to be distributive justice. The division of labor argument simply asserts that as a matter of empirical fact the best way to realize this aim is to apply the principles directly to the basic structure. This means that, given the way that
    • Justice As Fairness , pp. 54
  • 27
    • 49749115129 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Institutions and the Demands of Justice"
    • Liam B. Murphy, "Institutions and the Demands of Justice" Philosophy & Public Affairs 27 (1999): 252-91,
    • (1999) Philosophy & Public Affairs , vol.27 , pp. 252-291
    • Murphy, L.B.1
  • 29
    • 36749038020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It might be argued that, for Rawls, a (just) basic structure is a constituent part of the ideal of justice, not merely an instrument for realizing it. This would not undermine the argument that follows, because (unlike existence conditions) constitutive and instrumental conditions both merely impose feasibility limits on the scope of justice
    • It might be argued that, for Rawls, a (just) basic structure is a constituent part of the ideal of justice, not merely an instrument for realizing it. This would not undermine the argument that follows, because (unlike existence conditions) constitutive and instrumental conditions both merely impose feasibility limits on the scope of justice.
  • 30
    • 0042033181 scopus 로고
    • "Humanity and Justice in Global Perspective"
    • in ed. J. Roland Pennock and John W. Chapman (New York: New York University Press) Barry argues that duties of "justice as fair play" arise only from social coordination that meets "conditions for reciprocity."
    • Something like this view is advanced by Brian Barry, "Humanity and Justice in Global Perspective," in Ethics, Economics, and the Law: NOMOS XXIV, ed. J. Roland Pennock and John W. Chapman (New York: New York University Press, 1982), pp. 232-33. Barry argues that duties of "justice as fair play" arise only from social coordination that meets "conditions for reciprocity."
    • (1982) Ethics, Economics, and the Law: NOMOS XXIV , pp. 232-233
    • Barry, B.1
  • 31
    • 0003556319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • makes a similar point in his example of slaves forced to contribute to a scheme of social coordination against their will without any advantage to themselves
    • Charles Beitz makes a similar point in his example of slaves forced to contribute to a scheme of social coordination against their will without any advantage to themselves (Political Theory and International Relations, p. 131).
    • Political Theory and International Relations , pp. 131
    • Beitz, C.1
  • 32
    • 0003555163 scopus 로고
    • Others, including Barry himself, have worried that a status quo bias plagues Rawls's theory of justice. See (Oxford: Clarendon). Cf
    • Others, including Barry himself, have worried that a status quo bias plagues Rawls's theory of justice. See Brian Barry, Justice as Impartiality (Oxford: Clarendon, 1995). Cf.
    • (1995) Justice As Impartiality
    • Barry, B.1
  • 33
    • 33845390409 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Constructing Justice for Existing Practice: Rawls and the Status Quo"
    • Aaron James, "Constructing Justice for Existing Practice: Rawls and the Status Quo," Philosophy & Public Affairs 33 (2005): 281-316.
    • (2005) Philosophy & Public Affairs , vol.33 , pp. 281-316
    • James, A.1
  • 34
    • 36749006388 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • James's reconstruction of Rawls ("Constructing Justice") identifies an existence condition for Rawlsian justice as well, but James fails to distinguish social interaction as such from a basic structure (or social interaction regulated by it). As a result, his discussion tends to slide from invoking mere social interaction (p. 295: any "principle of social justice has as a condition of its application the existence of some social practice") to invoking basic structure (p. 298: "among the many and various existing social practices⋯we should attend first to the most 'basic' of existing social structures"). But this slide from social practices in general to the basic structure in particular, which leads James to conclude that the "very existence" of a basic structure "cannot be socially just or unjust" (p. 314), rests on a confusion.
    • James's reconstruction of Rawls ("Constructing Justice") identifies an existence condition for Rawlsian justice as well, but James fails to distinguish social interaction as such from a basic structure (or social interaction regulated by it). As a result, his discussion tends to slide from invoking mere social interaction (p. 295: any "principle of social justice has as a condition of its application the existence of some social practice") to invoking basic structure (p. 298: "among the many and various existing social practices...we should attend first to the most 'basic'of existing social structures"). But this slide from social practices in general to the basic structure in particular, which leads James to conclude that the "very existence" of a basic structure "cannot be socially just or unjust" (p. 314), rests on a confusion. The cooperation theory's justification for focusing on social practices in general, and, even more generally, on social interaction, establishes mere social interaction as an existence condition of justice. The justification for focusing on the basic structure, by contrast, does not establish it as an existence condition: The cooperation theory's appeal to the basic structure is instrumental. It is hence no surprise that when James himself justifies the focus on the basic structure, he appeals to its pervasive impact (pp. 298-99).
  • 35
    • 36749075875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Despite his claim that the absence of a world state makes claims for global principles of justice "absurd,"Freeman adopts a cooperation and not a coercion theory of justice, as he makes clear when distinguishing his position from Nagel's, on p. 259, n. 4
    • Freeman, "Distributive Justice and The Law of Peoples," p. 245-47. Despite his claim that the absence of a world state makes claims for global principles of justice "absurd," Freeman adopts a cooperation and not a coercion theory of justice, as he makes clear when distinguishing his position from Nagel's, on p. 259, n. 4.
    • "Distributive Justice The Law of Peoples" , pp. 245-247
    • Freeman, S.1
  • 36
    • 33644912578 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "The Law of Peoples, Social Cooperation, Human Rights, and Distributive Justice"
    • Samuel Freeman, "The Law of Peoples, Social Cooperation, Human Rights, and Distributive Justice," Social Philosophy & Policy 23 (2006): 29-68,
    • (2006) Social Philosophy & Policy , vol.23 , pp. 29-68
    • Freeman, S.1
  • 37
    • 36749070660 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • provides another example of the failure to see the instrumental role of the basic structure in the cooperation theory: "far from instrumentalizing social institutions"of the basic structure, he claims, Rawls "takes them as his point of departure."The putative "absence of a basic structure at the international level" is thus not "merely an implementation problem" the "rule of law" enforced by effective institutions of the basic structure is, rather, an existence condition of justice: "the absence of the rule of law at the international level is not simply...an implementation problem" (Heath, "Rawls on Global Distributive Justice," pp. 200, 201, 205). Heath's thesis is problematic on several fronts. First, his primary argument consists in pointing out that the basic structure is the "subject" of justice (p. 200), hence equivocating between site and scope.
    • Joseph Heath provides another example of the failure to see the instrumental role of the basic structure in the cooperation theory: "far from instrumentalizing social institutions" of the basic structure, he claims, Rawls "takes them as his point of departure. "The putative "absence of a basic structure at the international level" is thus not "merely an implementation problem" the "rule of law" enforced by effective institutions of the basic structure is, rather, an existence condition of justice: "the absence of the rule of law at the international level is not simply⋯an implementation problem" (Heath, "Rawls on Global Distributive Justice," pp. 200, 201, 205). Heath's thesis is problematic on several fronts. First, his primary argument consists in pointing out that the basic structure is the "subject" of justice (p. 200), hence equivocating between site and scope. Second, he argues that certain "types of free-rider problems," whose resolution may be necessary for realizing social cooperation in Rawls's normative sense, "can only be resolved through" coercive enforcement via institutions of a basic structure (p. 204). Heath's point, then, is that justice requires social cooperation (in Rawls's sense) and social cooperation requires terms of cooperation coercively enforced by a basic structure. This may be true, but on the cooperation theory that Heath apparently favors, coercive enforcement is "required" only in the instrumental sense; enforcement is not an existence condition of justice. Finally, Heath argues that Rawlsian justice is constituted by considerations of both equality and efficiency, meaning that "Efficiency questions, for Rawls, are normative, not instrumental." As such, "the loss of efficiency" that would result from "global redistribution of national savings" would "trump the gain in equality" (p. 211). The problems with this final argument are at least two. First, Heath's argument against global redistribution of national savings proceeds by applying his interpretation of the Rawlsian principle of distributive justice to the globe, not by showing that it is inapplicable. Second, his distinction between "instrumental" and "normative" considerations fails to distinguish between two kinds of normative considerations. He merely shows that efficiency considerations specify constitutive conditions of justice, but not, as his anticosmopolitan argument requires, existence conditions.
    • Joseph, H.1
  • 39
    • 0001305299 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Cosmopolitan Ideals and National Sentiment"
    • Compare with Beitz's afterword to the revised edition of Political Theory and International Relations, p. 203. See also Richards, "International Distributive Justice," p. 292
    • Beitz, "Cosmopolitan Ideals and National Sentiment," p. 595. Compare with Beitz's afterword to the revised edition of Political Theory and International Relations, p. 203. See also Richards, "International Distributive Justice,"p. 292.
    • Beitz, C.R.1
  • 40
    • 37149030193 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As such, one could argue that Beitz's own original reformulation of the Rawlsian account in which avoids including cooperation in the idealized sense as an existence condition of justice, already avoids the conflation
    • As such, one could argue that Beitz's own original reformulation of the Rawlsian account in Political Theory and International Relations, which avoids including cooperation in the idealized sense as an existence condition of justice, already avoids the conflation.
    • Political Theory and International Relations
  • 41
    • 0039205652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Humanity and Justice"
    • Barry, "Humanity and Justice," p. 227.
    • Barry, B.1
  • 42
    • 0039205652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Humanity and Justice"
    • "Justice as fair play arises not from simple exchange but from either the provision of public goods that are collectively enjoyed⋯or from quasi-insurance schemes for mutual aid" Sangiovanni's proposed existence condition of reciprocity is even more restricting: he argues that comparative principles of distributive justice arise only "among those who support and maintain the state's capacity to provide the basic collective goods necessary to protect us from physical attack and to maintain and reproduce a stable system of property rights and entitlements" ("Global Justice," p. 20)
    • "Justice as fair play arises not from simple exchange but from either the provision of public goods that are collectively enjoyed⋯or from quasi-insurance schemes for mutual aid"(Barry, "Humanity and Justice," p. 233). Sangiovanni's proposed existence condition of reciprocity is even more restricting: He argues that comparative principles of distributive justice arise only "among those who support and maintain the state's capacity to provide the basic collective goods necessary to protect us from physical attack and to maintain and reproduce a stable system of property rights and entitlements" ("Global Justice," p. 20).
    • Barry, B.1
  • 43
    • 79957519447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Discussing the principle of fairness or fair play, Rawls says: "We are not to gain from the cooperative labors of others without doing our fair share. The two principles of justice define what is a fair share in the case of institutions belonging to the basic structure. So if these arrangements are just, each person receives a fair share when all (himself included) do their part" emphasis added)
    • Discussing the principle of fairness or fair play, Rawls says: "We are not to gain from the cooperative labors of others without doing our fair share. The two principles of justice define what is a fair share in the case of institutions belonging to the basic structure. So if these arrangements are just, each person receives a fair share when all (himself included) do their part" (Theory of Justice, p. 112, emphasis added).
    • Theory of Justice , pp. 112
  • 44
    • 0007078915 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "International Distributive Justice"
    • has made the same point about Barry's argument
    • Richards, "International Distributive Justice," has made the same point about Barry's argument.
    • Richards, D.A.J.1
  • 45
    • 36749068085 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rather than a constituent, this overlapping consensus may be a necessary means for realizing justice (or, at least, for maintaining its stability over time)
    • Rather than a constituent, this overlapping consensus may be a necessary means for realizing justice (or, at least, for maintaining its stability over time).
  • 46
    • 36749097045 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • critique of Rorty's interpretation of Rawls, in (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), chap. 2, particularly See also Beitz, "Cosmopolitan Ideals and National Sentiment," p. 596
    • See Jürgen Habermas's critique of Rorty's interpretation of Rawls, in Between Facts and Norms (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1996), chap. 2, particularly pp. 58-63. See also Beitz, "Cosmopolitan Ideals and National Sentiment," p. 596.
    • (1996) Between Facts and Norms , pp. 58-63
    • Jürgen, H.1
  • 47
    • 36749055987 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Incentives, Inequality, and Publicity"
    • The same point can be made regarding Andrew Williams's claim that the public recognition of rules is a constitutive feature of the institutions of the basic structure The public recognition of rules is a constitutive condition of justice, not an existence condition
    • The same point can be made regarding Andrew Williams's claim that the public recognition of rules is a constitutive feature of the institutions of the basic structure ("Incentives, Inequality, and Publicity"). The public recognition of rules is a constitutive condition of justice, not an existence condition.
  • 48
    • 33644928463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Rawls's Theory of Justice"
    • See Scanlon, "Rawls's Theory of Justice," p. 202.
    • Scanlon, T.1
  • 49
    • 33644624226 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kok-Chor Tan makes this point in (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press) 169-70, 174
    • Kok-Chor Tan makes this point in Justice without Borders (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), pp. 33-34, 169-70, 174.
    • (2004) Justice Without Borders , pp. 33-34
  • 50
    • 79957519447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Or, more weakly, social coordination may be a normative demand of broader normative considerations (not necessarily of justice), and demands of distributive justice may arise not only when a scheme of social coordination exists, but also when it ought to exist. In either case, the demands of justice would arise, as Rawls puts it when specifying the circumstances of justice, when "human cooperation is both possible and necessary" For discussion of potential duties to create institutions of social coordination and cooperation, see
    • Or, more weakly, social coordination may be a normative demand of broader normative considerations (not necessarily of justice), and demands of distributive justice may arise not only when a scheme of social coordination exists, but also when it ought to exist. In either case, the demands of justice would arise, as Rawls puts it when specifying the circumstances of justice, when "human cooperation is both possible and necessary" (Theory of Justice, p. 126). For discussion of potential duties to create institutions of social coordination and cooperation, see
    • Theory of Justice , pp. 126
  • 51
    • 85055360329 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Contractualism and Poverty Relief"
    • Pablo Gilabert, "Contractualism and Poverty Relief" Social Theory and Practice 33 (2007): 277-310.
    • (2007) Social Theory and Practice , vol.33 , pp. 277-310
    • Gilabert, P.1
  • 52
    • 33644892801 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Rawls's Law of Peoples"
    • Buchanan, "Rawls's Law of Peoples."
    • Buchanan, A.1
  • 53
    • 0004168076 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intolerably unjust because the question is not whether the ideal is fully realizable in practice, but whether attempts to realize the ideal through a basic structure would undermine or contribute to the realization of the ideal. One can extrapolate the claim that it would be intolerably unjust from Rawls's assertion that "a unified political regime with the legal powers normally exercised by central governments⋯would either be a global despotism or else would rule over a fragile empire torn by frequent civil strife" This kind of argument, it seems to me, rests on rather old-fashioned Hobbesian views about the indivisible and centralized nature of sovereignty. A more plausible Rawlsian argument for why a (just) global basic structure is unfeasible appeals to the claim that a just basic structure requires an overlapping consensus.
    • Intolerably unjust because the question is not whether the ideal is fully realizable in practice, but whether attempts to realize the ideal through a basic structure would undermine or contribute to the realization of the ideal. One can extrapolate the claim that it would be intolerably unjust from Rawls's assertion that "a unified political regime with the legal powers normally exercised by central governments⋯would either be a global despotism or else would rule over a fragile empire torn by frequent civil strife" (Law of Peoples, p. 36). This kind of argument, it seems to me, rests on rather old-fashioned Hobbesian views about the indivisible and centralized nature of sovereignty. A more plausible Rawlsian argument for why a (just) global basic structure is unfeasible appeals to the claim that a just basic structure requires an overlapping consensus, and that the overlapping consensus required by Rawlsian justice in particular-about the freedom and equality of persons-is not a part of whatever global public political culture there is. (A "well-ordered society," Rawls argues, is one whose basic structure is effectively regulated by a public conception of justice accepted by all its members [Theory of Justice, pp. 453-54; cf. Justice as Fairness, p. 9].) But, if an overlapping consensus is an instrumental or constitutive condition rather than an existence condition for a just basic structure, then the existence of such a consensus is not the issue here: The issue is whether such a consensus is feasible. For if an overlapping consensus about the equality and freedom of persons is instrumentally or constitutively necessary for realizing or stably maintaining Rawlsian justice over time, then Rawlsian justice would demand the recognition of the equality and freedom of persons. It is not at all clear why such recognition is not feasible at the global level in the long run; the secular trend since World War II arguably points in such a direction.
    • Law of Peoples , pp. 36
  • 54
    • 84931428234 scopus 로고
    • "What Is So Special about Our Fellow Countrymen?"
    • at p. 683
    • Robert E. Goodin, "What Is So Special about Our Fellow Countrymen?" Ethics 98 (1988): 663-86, at p. 683.
    • (1988) Ethics , vol.98 , pp. 663-686
    • Goodin, R.E.1
  • 55
    • 77956285247 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See footnote 59 in
    • See footnote 59 in Justice as Fairness, p. 176.
    • Justice As Fairness , pp. 176
  • 56
    • 0003836741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Rawls, Theory of Justice, p. 96: "The primary subject of justice...is the basic structure of society. The reason for this is that its effects are so profound and pervasive, and present from birth." In Political Liberalism, p. 269, Rawls also says that "the basic structure shapes the way the social system produces and reproduces over time a certain form of culture shared by persons with certain conceptions of their good." See also Justice as Fairness, pp. 52-57
    • Justice as Fairness, p. 10. Cf. Rawls, Theory of Justice, p. 96: "The primary subject of justice...is the basic structure of society. The reason for this is that its effects are so profound and pervasive, and present from birth." In Political Liberalism, p. 269, Rawls also says that "the basic structure shapes the way the social system produces and reproduces over time a certain form of culture shared by persons with certain conceptions of their good." See also Justice as Fairness, pp. 52-57. Cf. Rawls, Theory of Justice, p. 96: "The primary subject of justice⋯is the basic structure of society. The reason for this is that its effects are so profound and pervasive, and present from birth." In Political Liberalism, p. 269, Rawls also says that "the basic structure shapes the way the social system produces and reproduces over time a certain form of culture shared by persons with certain conceptions of their good." See also Justice as Fairness, pp. 52-57.
    • Justice As Fairness , pp. 10
  • 57
    • 84937266898 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Where the Action Is: On the Site of Distributive Justice"
    • G. A. Cohen, "Where the Action Is: On the Site of Distributive Justice," Philosophy & Public Affairs 26 (1997): 3-30,
    • (1997) Philosophy & Public Affairs , vol.26 , pp. 3-30
    • Cohen, G.A.1
  • 58
    • 0037646114 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • discussion of the "distributive objection" in (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
    • See Samuel Scheffler's discussion of the "distributive objection" in Boundaries and Allegiances (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001).
    • (2001) Boundaries and Allegiances
    • Samuel, S.1
  • 59
    • 33747064435 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "On the Site of Distributive Justice"
    • Thomas W. Pogge, "On the Site of Distributive Justice" Philosophy & Public Affairs 29 (2000): 137-69,
    • (2000) Philosophy & Public Affairs , vol.29 , pp. 137-169
    • Pogge, T.W.1
  • 60
    • 33644892801 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Rawls's Law of Peoples"
    • for the argument that there is indeed a global basic structure (which he construes in terms of institutions having profound and pervasive impact). Rawls claims that the life chances of persons in impoverished, politically weak states are mostly determined by the country's own "political culture-its members'political and civic virtues" Domestic factors surely matter as well, but Rawls flatly ignores how international factors help shape precisely those domestic factors he thinks decisive in the first place. For a critique of Rawls's "explanatory nationalism," and the pervasive role of international financial institutions, see Thomas W. Pogge, "Human Rights and Human Responsibilities," in Global Justice and Transnational Politics, ed. Pablo De Greiff and Ciaran Cronin (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2002), pp. 151-95, and World Poverty and Human Rights (Cambridge: Polity, 2002)
    • See Buchanan, "Rawls's Law of Peoples,"for the argument that there is indeed a global basic structure (which he construes in terms of institutions having profound and pervasive impact). Rawls claims that the life chances of persons in impoverished, politically weak states are mostly determined by the country's own "political culture-its members'political and civic virtues"(Law of Peoples, p. 117). Domestic factors surely matter as well, but Rawls flatly ignores how international factors help shape precisely those domestic factors he thinks decisive in the first place. For a critique of Rawls's "explanatory nationalism,"and the pervasive role of international financial institutions, see Thomas W. Pogge, "Human Rights and Human Responsibilities,"in Global Justice and Transnational Politics, ed. Pablo De Greiff and Ciaran Cronin (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2002), pp. 151-95, and World Poverty and Human Rights (Cambridge: Polity, 2002).
    • Law of Peoples , pp. 117
    • Buchanan, E.1
  • 61
    • 33846654540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Distributive Justice"
    • "Coercion, not cooperation, is the sine qua non of distributive justice, making relevant principles of relative deprivation" Cf. Nagel, "Problem of Global Justice," p. 128
    • "Coercion, not cooperation, is the sine qua non of distributive justice, making relevant principles of relative deprivation"(Blake, "Distributive Justice,"p. 289). Cf. Nagel, "Problem of Global Justice," p. 128.
    • Blake, M.1
  • 62
    • 0003956640 scopus 로고
    • 154 (Oxford: Clarendon Press)
    • Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), pp. 369, 154.
    • (1986) The Morality of Freedom , pp. 369
    • Raz, J.1
  • 63
    • 33846654540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Distributive Justice"
    • See ibid. pp. 377-78
    • See ibid., pp. 377-78; Blake, "Distributive Justice," p. 270.
    • Blake, M.1
  • 64
    • 33846654540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Distributive Justice"
    • 265
    • Blake, "Distributive Justice," pp. 272, 265.
    • Blake, M.1
  • 65
    • 36749001321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid
    • Ibid., p. 280.
  • 66
    • 36749029085 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., pp. 260
    • Ibid., pp. 260, 289.
  • 67
    • 36749081831 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., pp. 258, 264
    • Ibid., pp. 258, 264, 265.
  • 68
    • 36749032869 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., pp. 258
    • Ibid., pp. 258, 276.
  • 69
    • 36748999663 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Since according to the autonomy principle A1 all ongoing acts of state coercion require justification, I shall henceforth drop the qualifying parenthetical phrase "requiring justification."
    • Since according to the autonomy principle A1 all ongoing acts of state coercion require justification, I shall henceforth drop the qualifying parenthetical phrase "requiring justification."
  • 70
    • 33846654540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Distributive Justice"
    • Blake "Distributive Justice," p. 265.
    • Blake, M.1
  • 71
    • 36748999115 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid
    • Ibid., p. 287.
  • 72
    • 36749081246 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Democratic Theory and Border Coercion: No Right to Unilaterally Control Your Own Borders"
    • For analysis of the nature of border coercion, see forthcoming. Blake's recognition that coercion "in the international arena" may "exist in forms other than state coercion" ("Distributive Justice," p. 265) ignores the fact that states are themselves institutions who act in the international arena. Indeed, states are arguably the most important actors in the international arena, and they regularly act in that arena coercively. It is true that there is no world state that acts coercively against the world's population, but there certainly are states that do. On different types of state coercion, see
    • For analysis of the nature of border coercion, see Arash Abizadeh, "Democratic Theory and Border Coercion: No Right to Unilaterally Control Your Own Borders," Political Theory, forthcoming. Blake's recognition that coercion "in the international arena "may" exist in forms other than state coercion" ("Distributive Justice," p. 265) ignores the fact that states are themselves institutions who act in the international arena. Indeed, states are arguably the most important actors in the international arena, and they regularly act in that arena coercively. It is true that there is no world state that acts coercively against the world's population, but there certainly are states that do. On different types of state coercion, see
    • Political Theory
    • Arash, A.1
  • 74
    • 33846654540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Distributive Justice"
    • emphasis mine. Cf.: "There is no ongoing coercion of the sort observed in the domestic arena in the international legal arena. It is...only this form of coercion that makes a concern for relative deprivation relevant for a liberal political theory... Material equality becomes relevant only in the context of certain forms of coercion, forms not found outside the domestic arena"(ibid., pp. 280, 284, emphasis mine)
    • Blake, "Distributive Justice,"p. 280, n. 30, emphasis mine. Cf.: "There is no ongoing coercion of the sort observed in the domestic arena in the international legal arena. It is⋯only this form of coercion that makes a concern for relative deprivation relevant for a liberal political theory⋯.Material equality becomes relevant only in the context of certain forms of coercion, forms not found outside the domestic arena" (ibid., pp. 280, 284, emphasis mine).
    • , Issue.30 , pp. 280
    • Blake, M.1
  • 75
    • 36749014230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid
    • Ibid., p. 280.
  • 76
    • 36749014741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid. emphasis mine
    • Ibid., p. 282, emphasis mine.
  • 77
    • 36749054917 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "International legal institutions⋯do not engage in coercive practices against individual human agents" (Ibid.; cf. p. 279)
    • "International legal institutions⋯do not engage in coercive practices against individual human agents"(Ibid., p. 280; cf. p. 279).
  • 78
    • 36749001320 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid
    • Ibid., p. 284.
  • 79
    • 34548245835 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Problem of Global Justice"
    • Nagel, "Problem of Global Justice," pp. 128-29.
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 80
    • 36749043973 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid
    • Ibid., p. 129.
  • 81
    • 36749091377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Nagel's Atlas"
    • On this point, see
    • On this point, see Julius, "Nagel's Atlas," pp. 179-83.
    • Julius, A.J.1
  • 82
    • 33846654540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Distributive Justice"
    • emphasis mine
    • Blake, "Distributive Justice," pp. 281-82, emphasis mine.
    • Blake, M.1
  • 83
    • 36749009891 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Though not because it is regulated by laws: its coerciveness is sufficient to require justification. The justification, to be successful, may in turn require the rule of law
    • Though not because it is regulated by laws: Its coerciveness is sufficient to require justification. The justification, to be successful, may in turn require the rule of law.
  • 84
    • 33846654540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Distributive Justice"
    • emphasis mine
    • Blake, "Distributive Justice," p. 265, emphasis mine.
    • Blake, M.1
  • 85
    • 36749021899 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Blake has in fact argued this in a personal communication to me
    • Blake has in fact argued this in a personal communication to me.
  • 86
    • 36749026838 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Global Justice"
    • For some doubts, however, see Sangiovanni
    • For some doubts, however, see Sangiovanni, "Global Justice," pp. 10-13.
  • 87
    • 36749065814 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See
    • See
  • 88
    • 36749005818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "What We Owe to the Global Poor"
    • Mathias Risse, "What We Owe to the Global Poor" The Journal of Ethics 9 (2004): 81-117,
    • (2004) The Journal of Ethics , vol.9 , pp. 81-117
    • Risse, M.1
  • 89
    • 84868799399 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For ethnographic evidence of the tremendous significance of this point, see (New Brunswick, N.J.: Rutgers University Press). On the historical origins of the enforcement of membership-boundaries as an economic tool, see Rogers Brubaker, Citizenship and Nationhood in France and Germany (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1992), especially pp. 64-72
    • For ethnographic evidence of the tremendous significance of this point, see Charles V. Carengie, Postnationalism Prefigured: Caribbean Borderlands (New Brunswick, N.J.: Rutgers University Press, 2002). On the historical origins of the enforcement of membership-boundaries as an economic tool, see Rogers Brubaker, Citizenship and Nationhood in France and Germany (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1992), especially pp. 64-72.
    • (2002) Postnationalism Prefigured: Caribbean Borderlands
    • Charles, V.C.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.