메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 17, Issue 3, 2009, Pages 332-355

On the apparent paradox of ideal theory

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 68249120569     PISSN: 09638016     EISSN: 14679760     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-9760.2008.00317.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (139)

References (150)
  • 1
    • 0033211716 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant, ideal theory, and the justice of exclusionary zoning
    • p. 34
    • I am borrowing this broad definition of ideal theory from Sarah Williams Holtman, 'Kant, ideal theory, and the justice of exclusionary zoning', Ethics, 110 (1999), 32-58, at p. 34.
    • (1999) Ethics , vol.110 , pp. 32-58
    • Holtman, S.W.1
  • 2
    • 0003940096 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Onora O'Neill offers extensive discussions of the notion of idealisation in Towards Justice and Virtue (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), pp. 39-44,
    • (1996) Towards Justice and Virtue , pp. 39-44
    • O'Neill, O.1
  • 3
    • 55449116225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Abstraction, idealization and ideology in ethics
    • ed. J.D.G. Evans (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • and 'Abstraction, idealization and ideology in ethics', Moral Philosophy and Contemporary Problems, ed. J.D.G. Evans (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), pp. 55-69. John Rawls adopts a narrower notion of ideal theory, focusing on two idealisations in particular: full compliance and favourable conditions. In this article, I only discuss the notion of an ideal theory broadly construed, which includes, but is not limited to, Rawls's narrower definition.
    • (1987) Moral Philosophy and Contemporary Problems , pp. 55-69
  • 4
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, rev. ed., (henceforth TJ)
    • John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999 rev. ed.), pp. 4-8 (henceforth TJ);
    • (1999) A Theory of Justice , pp. 4-8
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 5
    • 0004168076 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 8-9 (henceforth LP)
    • and The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), pp. 4-5, 8-9 (henceforth LP).
    • (1999) The Law of Peoples , pp. 4-5
  • 6
    • 84887867135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, TJ, p. 125.
    • TJ , pp. 125
    • Rawls1
  • 8
    • 35948996657 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Justice in ideal theory: A refutation
    • A recent formulation of this critique is offered by Colin Farrelly, 'Justice in ideal theory: a refutation', Political Studies, 55 (2007), 844-64.
    • (2007) Political Studies , vol.55 , pp. 844-864
    • Farrelly, C.1
  • 9
    • 38049080237 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What do we want from a theory of justice?
    • See also Amartya Sen's critique of what he calls 'transcendental' theories of justice in his 'What do we want from a theory of justice?' Journal of Philosophy, 103 (2006), 215-38.
    • (2006) Journal of Philosophy , vol.103 , pp. 215-238
    • Sen's, A.1
  • 10
    • 1842795953 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Facts and principles
    • G.A. Cohen, 'Facts and principles', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 31 (2003), 211-45. To be more precise, Cohen does not talk about fact-sensitive and fact-insensitive normative theories, but rather about fact-sensitive and fact-insensitive normative principles (of justice in particular). Since, however, principles are the main components of theories, Cohen's distinction naturally extends to different ways of theorising about justice.
    • (2003) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.31 , pp. 211-245
    • Cohen, G.A.1
  • 11
    • 52849107991 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Distributive justice, state coercion, and autonomy
    • esp. at pp. 263-4, n.7
    • My discussion here also benefits from Michael Blake's distinction between ideal institutional and non-institutional theorising in 'Distributive justice, state coercion, and autonomy', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 30 (2001), 257-96, esp. at pp. 263-4, n.7,
    • (2001) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.30 , pp. 257-296
    • Blake's, M.1
  • 12
    • 33845390409 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constructing justice for existing practice: Rawls and the status quo
    • at pp. 293-5
    • and from Aaron James's distinction between practice-based and non-practice-based theorising, 'Constructing justice for existing practice: Rawls and the status quo', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 33 (2005), 281-316, at pp. 293-5.
    • (2005) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.33 , pp. 281-316
    • James's, A.1
  • 13
    • 33846708498 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Global justice, reciprocity, and the state
    • pp. 5-8
    • Cf. Andrea Sangiovanni's somewhat wider distinction between relational and nonrelational approaches to justice in 'Global justice, reciprocity, and the state', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 35 (2007), 3-39, at pp. 5-8.
    • (2007) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.35 , pp. 3-39
    • Sangiovanni's, A.1
  • 14
    • 42649131372 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Justice and the priority of politics to morality
    • See also his 'Justice and the priority of politics to morality', Journal of Political Philosophy, 16 (2008), 137-64.
    • (2008) Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.16 , pp. 137-164
  • 15
    • 57349160664 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Power in social organization as the subject of justice
    • In offering this formulation in terms of power I am indebted to Aaron James's discussion in 'Power in social organization as the subject of justice', Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 86 (2005), 25-49.
    • (2005) Pacific Philosophical Quarterly , vol.86 , pp. 25-49
    • James's, A.1
  • 16
    • 1842745538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Cohen himself remarks n.48
    • This approach is defended by G.A. Cohen in 'Facts and principles'. As Cohen himself remarks (p. 244, n.48), Richard Arneson seems to agree with certain aspects of his view.
    • Facts and Principles , pp. 244
    • Cohen, G.A.1
  • 17
    • 0001322125 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Luck egalitarianism and prioritarianism
    • p. 345.
    • See R.J. Arneson, 'Luck egalitarianism and prioritarianism', Ethics, 110 (2000), 339-49, p. 345.
    • (2000) Ethics , vol.110 , pp. 339-349
    • Arneson, R.J.1
  • 19
    • 85055361956 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The value of philosophy in non-ideal circumstances
    • (forthcoming 2008)
    • and Adam Swift, 'The value of philosophy in non-ideal circumstances', Social Theory and Practice (forthcoming 2008) also approve of this form of theorising.
    • Social Theory and Practice
    • Swift, A.1
  • 21
    • 1842745538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This can be taken as a generalised description of what Cohen, 'Facts and principles', p. 241, calls 'principles of regulation' which, he says, are the object of fact-sensitive theories.
    • Facts and Principles , pp. 241
    • Cohen1
  • 22
    • 68249114136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford D.Phil. thesis, forthcoming 2008
    • My understanding of the distinction between theories of type (1) and (2) has benefited from many conversations with Miriam Ronzoni, who explores it in depth in 'Constructivism and the basic structure of society' (Oxford D.Phil. thesis, forthcoming 2008).
    • Constructivism and the Basic Structure of Society
    • Ronzoni, M.1
  • 23
    • 84955120110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Expensive taste rides again
    • (ed. J. Burley Oxford: Blackwell), at p. 18
    • G. A. Cohen, 'Expensive taste rides again', Dworkin and His Critics, ed. J. Burley (Oxford: Blackwell, 2004), pp. 3-29, at p. 18.
    • (2004) Dworkin and His Critics , pp. 3-29
    • Cohen, G.A.1
  • 25
    • 54049121505 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the meta-ethical status of constructivism: Reflections on G.A. Cohen's "Facts and principles"
    • forthcoming
    • For a related discussion see Miriam Ronzoni and Laura Valentini, 'On the meta-ethical status of constructivism: reflections on G.A. Cohen's "Facts and principles"', Politics, Philosophy & Economics (forthcoming).
    • Politics, Philosophy & Economics
    • Ronzoni, M.1    Valentini, L.2
  • 26
    • 0032647108 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What is the point of equality?
    • So-called democratic or relational egalitarians can also be counted among the advocates of the fact-sensitive approach. See, e.g., Elizabeth Anderson, 'What is the point of equality?' Ethics, 109 (1999), 287-337,
    • (1999) Ethics , vol.109 , pp. 287-337
    • Anderson, E.1
  • 28
    • 0003836741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, (henceforth JFR)
    • John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2001), p. 41 (henceforth JFR).
    • (2001) Justice As Fairness: A Restatement , pp. 41
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 29
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press, pp. 44 ff. (henceforth PL)
    • John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996), pp. 44 ff. (henceforth PL).
    • (1996) Political Liberalism
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 31
    • 84887867135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an early statement of this conception of justification see Rawls, TJ, pp. 506 f
    • TJ
    • Rawls1
  • 32
    • 84893362430 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, PL, p. 110.
    • PL , pp. 110
    • Rawls1
  • 33
    • 68249115167 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the divergence between individuals' priority judgements see TJ, pp. 39-40.
    • TJ , pp. 39-40
  • 35
  • 36
    • 0004340089 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and ch. 4
    • Notice that Dworkin uses the notion of political power much more narrowly than I do. Instead of seeing it as the power members of a political community exercise over one another through the operation of their institutions, he conceives of it in terms of the influence members have over political decisions. See Dworkin, SV, ibid., p. 65 and ch. 42E
    • SV , pp. 65
    • Dworkin1
  • 37
    • 68249110294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, SV, Ibid., p. 4, emphasis added.
    • SV , pp. 4
    • Dworkin1
  • 38
    • 84926641780 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ideal theory in theory and practice
    • forthcoming 2008
    • For a detailed taxonomy of ideal theory see Ingrid Robeyns, 'Ideal theory in theory and practice', Social Theory and Practice (forthcoming 2008).
    • Social Theory and Practice
    • Robeyns, I.1
  • 39
    • 85055309830 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Ideal theory" as ideology
    • esp. at pp. 166-7
    • See also Charles W. Mills, ' "Ideal theory" as ideology', Hypatia, 20 (2005), 165-84, esp. at pp. 166-7.
    • (2005) Hypatia , vol.20 , pp. 165-184
    • Mills, C.W.1
  • 40
    • 68249126734 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In 'What do we want from a theory of justice?' Amartya Sen has challenged this claim, arguing that theories of justice can also be purely comparative. Such theories tell us how different societies ought to be ranked from the viewpoint of justice, without specifying what a perfectly just society would look like. I thank Christian Barry for drawing my attention to this issue.
  • 41
    • 85048308407 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What's ideal about ideal theory?
    • forthcoming 2008
    • Zofia Stemplowska has recently argued in favour of a different technical definition of ideal theory, based on the particular function ideal theory is meant to perform. See her 'What's ideal about ideal theory?' Social Theory and Practice (forthcoming 2008).
    • Social Theory and Practice
  • 42
    • 0003940096 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Onora O'Neill, for instance, argues that, unlike abstractions, idealisations can (and perhaps should) be avoided. For discussion see O'Neill, Towards Justice and Virtue, pp. 39-44.
    • Towards Justice and Virtue , pp. 39-44
    • O'Neill1
  • 44
    • 43249174367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Abstraction, idealization, and oppression
    • Lisa H. Schwartzman, 'Abstraction, idealization, and oppression', Metaphilosophy, 37 (2006), 565-88,
    • (2006) Metaphilosophy , vol.37 , pp. 565-588
    • Schwartzman, L.H.1
  • 45
    • 84975992288 scopus 로고
    • Political ideals and political practice
    • esp. at pp. 40-5
    • and Robert E. Goodin, 'Political ideals and political practice', British Journal of Political Science, 25 (1995), 37-56, esp. at pp. 40-5.
    • (1995) British Journal of Political Science , vol.25 , pp. 37-56
    • Goodin, R.E.1
  • 46
    • 84887867135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, TJ, pp. 118-23.
    • TJ , pp. 118-123
    • Rawls1
  • 47
    • 84887867135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, TJ, Ibid., pp. 137-8.
    • TJ , pp. 137-138
    • Rawls1
  • 48
    • 84887867135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, TJ, Ibid., pp. 123-5.
    • TJ , pp. 123-125
    • Rawls1
  • 49
    • 68249110294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, SV, p. 172.
    • SV , pp. 172
    • Dworkin1
  • 50
    • 68249110294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • pp. 66 ff
    • Dworkin, SV, Ibid., pp. 66 ff.
    • SV
    • Dworkin1
  • 51
    • 0004024838 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • For a helpful summary of Dworkin's theory to which I am indebted see Will Kymlicka, Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Introduction (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), pp. 75-88.
    • (2002) Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Introduction , pp. 75-88
    • Kymlicka1
  • 52
    • 68249110294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, SV, pp. 67-8.
    • SV , pp. 67-68
    • Dworkin1
  • 53
    • 68249110294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • pp. 73 ff
    • Dworkin, SV, Ibid., pp. 73 ff.
    • SV
    • Dworkin1
  • 54
    • 68249110294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and 161-2 respectively
    • Dworkin, SV, Ibid., pp. 147-61 and 161-2 respectively.
    • SV , pp. 147-161
    • Dworkin1
  • 55
    • 68249110294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, SV, Ibid., pp. 162-80.
    • SV , pp. 162-180
    • Dworkin1
  • 56
    • 68249117586 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, what counts as 'humanly achievable' is a controversial, largely speculative, matter
    • Of course, what counts as 'humanly achievable' is a controversial, largely speculative, matter.
  • 57
    • 0003465228 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, esp. ch. 8
    • In so saying, I am not suggesting that a theory of justice cannot be 'incentive-compatible'. Indeed, one of the most discussed features of Rawls's difference principle is its attempted incentive-compatibility. Recall that the principle justifies inequalities so long as they are needed to benefit the worse-off, and these include inequalities generated to incentivise talented people to make occupational choices that maximise productivity. Compatibility of a theory of justice with a certain degree of human self-interestedness seems necessary given that justice, as a value, makes sense only because human beings are partly self-interested, as opposed to angelically altruistic. The point I am making in the main text is that, once the principles of justice have been defined (whatever their degree of incentive-compatibility) each individual in society is assumed to do her part in upholding them. For a critique of Rawls's incentives argument for inequality, see G.A. Cohen, If You're an Egalitarian, How Come You're So Rich? (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000), esp. ch. 8. I am grateful to Christian List for bringing this issue to my attention.
    • (2000) If You're An Egalitarian, How Come You're so Rich?
    • Cohen, G.A.1
  • 58
    • 64749086123 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Neither history nor praxis
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • For a discussion see Raymond Geuss, 'Neither history nor praxis', Outside Ethics (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2005), pp. 29-39.
    • (2005) Outside Ethics , pp. 29-39
    • Geuss, R.1
  • 59
    • 1642631623 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Realistic and idealistic approaches to the ethics of migration
    • For a helpful account of the 'psychological, sociological, and epistemological' constraints to be taken into account by a theory that aims to be practically effective see Joseph H. Carens, 'Realistic and idealistic approaches to the ethics of migration', International Migration Review, 30 (1996), 156-70.
    • (1996) International Migration Review , vol.30 , pp. 156-170
    • Carens, J.H.1
  • 60
    • 0347569028 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The feasibility condition in political theory
    • On related issues, see also Juha Räikkä, 'The feasibility condition in political theory', The Journal of Political Philosophy, 6 (1998), 27-40;
    • (1998) The Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.6 , pp. 27-40
    • Räikkä, J.1
  • 61
    • 68249094786 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The role of apparent constraints in normative reasoning: A methodological statement and application to global justice
    • Sanjay Reddy, 'The role of apparent constraints in normative reasoning: a methodological statement and application to global justice', The Journal of Ethics, 9 (2005), 119-25,
    • (2005) The Journal of Ethics , vol.9 , pp. 119-125
    • Reddy, S.1
  • 63
    • 0002452611 scopus 로고
    • On the common saying: This may be true in theory, but it does not apply in practice
    • ed. H.S. Reiss (ambridge: Cambridge University Press) at p. 61
    • Immanuel Kant, 'On the common saying: this may be true in theory, but it does not apply in practice', Kant's Political Writings, ed. H.S. Reiss (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), pp. 61-92, at p. 61.
    • (1970) Kant's Political Writings , pp. 61-92
    • Kant, I.1
  • 65
    • 68249110560 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., the complex argument through which Sarah Williams Holtman shows how Kantian ideal theory might offer guidance in establishing the legitimacy of real-world policies in 'Kant, ideal theory, and the justice of exclusionary zoning'
    • See, e.g., the complex argument through which Sarah Williams Holtman shows how Kantian ideal theory might offer guidance in establishing the legitimacy of real-world policies in 'Kant, ideal theory, and the justice of exclusionary zoning'.
  • 69
    • 68049117818 scopus 로고
    • Reflections on the transition from ideal to non-ideal theory
    • For a sustained discussion of this difficulty see Michael Phillips, 'Reflections on the transition from ideal to non-ideal theory', Noûs, 19 (1985), 551-70.
    • (1985) Noûs , vol.19 , pp. 551-570
    • Phillips, M.1
  • 70
    • 68049117818 scopus 로고
    • Reflections on the transition from ideal to non-ideal theory
    • For similar examples see Michael Phillips, 'Reflections on the transition from ideal to non-ideal theory', Nous, 19 (1985) Ibid., pp. 559-60.
    • (1985) Nous , vol.19 , pp. 559-560
    • Phillips, M.1
  • 72
    • 55449116225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Notice, however, that O'Neill's overall critique of idealisation does not so much focus on the issue of guidance, but rather on the difficulty of justifying idealised premises without appealing to controversial metaphysical claims. For O'Neill's remarks on issues of guidance see 'Abstraction, idealization and ideology in ethics'.
    • Abstraction, Idealization and Ideology in Ethics
    • O'Neill's1
  • 74
    • 68249124708 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I point this out because critics often fail to distinguish between GC2 and GC3
    • I point this out because critics often fail to distinguish between GC2 and GC3.
  • 75
    • 68249087282 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political philosophy and racial injustice: From normative to critical theory
    • eds S. Benhabib and N. Fraser Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, at p. 165
    • Thomas McCarthy, 'Political philosophy and racial injustice: from normative to critical theory', Pragmatism, Critique, Judgement, eds S. Benhabib and N. Fraser (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2004), pp. 147-70, at p. 165, emphasis original.
    • (2004) Pragmatism, Critique, Judgement , pp. 147-170
    • McCarthy, T.1
  • 77
    • 68249121193 scopus 로고
    • Duty and obligation in the non-ideal world
    • Joel Feinberg also offers some sceptical remarks on the guidance capacity of Rawls's ideal theory, particularly with reference to the case of civil disobedience, in 'Duty and obligation in the non-ideal world', Journal of Philosophy, 70 (1973), 263-75.
    • (1973) Journal of Philosophy , vol.70 , pp. 263-275
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 79
    • 68249114373 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • My argument is thus limited in scope. I only discuss deontological liberal approaches to justice and do not consider whether the 'guidance critique' would also apply to other types of outlooks. For instance, as David Grewal and Gabriel Wollner have (independently) pointed out to me, consequentialist theories of justice might be immune to the challenges discussed here.
  • 80
    • 68249095307 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, JFR, p. 66.
    • JFR , pp. 66
    • Rawls1
  • 81
    • 68249120090 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Racism, sexism and preferential treatment: An approach to the topics
    • eds R. Goodin and P. Pettit Oxford: Blackwell
    • For a general discussion of racial and sexual discrimination containing helpful methodological reflections on the relation between 'ideals' and 'social realities' see Richard A. Wasserstrom, 'Racism, sexism and preferential treatment: an approach to the topics', Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Anthology, eds R. Goodin and P. Pettit (Oxford: Blackwell, 1997), pp. 579-604.
    • (1997) Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Anthology , pp. 579-604
    • Wasserstrom, R.A.1
  • 83
    • 68249095307 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, JFR, pp. 162-8.
    • JFR , pp. 162-168
    • Rawls1
  • 84
    • 68249095307 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, JFR, Ibid., p. 167.
    • JFR , pp. 167
    • Rawls1
  • 85
    • 33747064435 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the site of distributive justice: Reflections on Cohen and Murphy
    • esp. at p. 165
    • This point is defended and discussed in Thomas W. Pogge, 'On the site of distributive justice: reflections on Cohen and Murphy', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 29 (2000), 137-69, esp. at p. 165.
    • (2000) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.29 , pp. 137-169
    • Pogge, T.W.1
  • 86
    • 84937266898 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Where the action is: On the site of distributive justice
    • Cf. G.A. Cohen, 'Where the action is: on the site of distributive justice', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 26 (1997), 3-30,
    • (1997) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.26 , pp. 3-30
    • Cohen, G.A.1
  • 87
    • 0011478290 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Institutions and the demands of justice
    • and Liam B. Murphy, 'Institutions and the demands of justice', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 27 (1998), 251-91, who criticise the basic structural (political) focus of Rawls's theory. As I note later, here I do not discuss this critique.
    • (1998) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.27 , pp. 251-291
    • Murphy, L.B.1
  • 88
    • 68249095307 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls seems to be more radical on this point, suggesting that how to best realise women's equality 'in particular historical conditions is not for political philosophy to decide', Rawls, JFR, p. 167. Here I am making the weaker claim that this is not for political philosophy alone to decide.
    • JFR , pp. 167
    • Rawls1
  • 89
    • 84887867135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, TJ, p. 327.
    • TJ , pp. 327
    • Rawls1
  • 90
    • 84887867135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, TJ, p. 327. Ibid.
    • TJ , pp. 327
    • Rawls1
  • 91
    • 84887867135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In particular, Rawls thinks that violations of the difference principle are the most difficult injustices to detect, while violations of the first principle and 'blatant violations' of fair equality of opportunity are more likely to be 'obvious to all', Rawls, TJ, Ibid., pp. 326-7.
    • TJ , pp. 326-327
    • Rawls1
  • 92
    • 68249117585 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am grateful to an anonymous referee for raising this concern
    • I am grateful to an anonymous referee for raising this concern.
  • 93
    • 51349085651 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I wish to thank Miriam Ronzoni for bringing this point to my attention. Ronzoni offers a sustained defence of Rawls's basic structural approach in 'Constructivism and the basic structure of society'. See also Pogge, 'On the site of distributive justice: reflections on Cohen and Murphy'.
    • On the Site of Distributive Justice: Reflections on Cohen and Murphy
    • Pogge1
  • 94
    • 33846941157 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Resources versus capabilities: Social endowments in egalitarian theory
    • at p. 141, emphasis original.
    • Roland Pierik and Ingrid Robeyns, 'Resources versus capabilities: social endowments in egalitarian theory27, Political Studies, 55 (200729, 133-52, at p. 141, emphasis original.
    • (2007) Political Studies , vol.55 , pp. 133-152
    • Pierik, R.1    Robeyns, I.2
  • 95
    • 84937333162 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Review of Sovereign Virtue
    • For a critique of Dworkin's methodology see also Philip Abbott, 'Review of Sovereign Virtue', Rhetoric & Public Affairs, 4 (2001), 576-8.
    • (2001) Rhetoric & Public Affairs , vol.4 , pp. 576-578
    • Abbott, P.1
  • 97
    • 68249110294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, SV, p. 165.
    • SV , pp. 165
    • Dworkin1
  • 98
    • 68249119362 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In spite of her critique of Dworkin, Robeyns ('Ideal theory in theory and practice') now recognizes the legitimacy of such idealisations for the purpose of designing an ideal theory of justice
    • In spite of her critique of Dworkin, Robeyns ('Ideal theory in theory and practice') now recognizes the legitimacy of such idealisations for the purpose of designing an ideal theory of justice.
  • 99
    • 68249097894 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Critics sometimes recognize this point, but lament that, apart from sporadic remarks (for instance, Dworkin says 'If proper civil rights laws were enacted and enforced, the influence of prejudice . . . would wane', SV, pp. 345-6), Dworkin seldom discusses the question of how to bring socially generated inequalities to an end directly in connection with his ideal theory. See Pierik and Robeyns, 'Resources versus capabilities', pp. 143-6
    • Resources Versus Capabilities , pp. 143-146
    • Pierik1    Robeyns2
  • 100
    • 77956464148 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Robeyns, 'Ideal theory in theory and practice'. This may very well be true but, as I already noticed, the absence of explicit discussion does not mean that a fruitful discussion could not be developed on the basis of Dworkin's theory.
    • Ideal Theory in Theory and Practice
    • Robeyns1
  • 101
    • 68249110294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chs 11 and 12
    • Dworkin, SV, chs 11 and 12.
    • SV
    • Dworkin1
  • 102
    • 0347144930 scopus 로고
    • Equal treatment and compensatory discrimination
    • eds M. Cohen, T. Nagel and T. Scanlon Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • For discussion see Thomas Nagel, 'Equal treatment and compensatory discrimination', Equality and Preferential Treatment, eds M. Cohen, T. Nagel and T. Scanlon (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1977), pp. 3-18.
    • (1977) Equality and Preferential Treatment , pp. 3-18
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 103
    • 68249132399 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Though this accusation is probably unfair in the case of Dworkin, who devotes about half of Sovereign Virtue to the 'practice' of equality
    • Though this accusation is probably unfair in the case of Dworkin, who devotes about half of Sovereign Virtue to the 'practice' of equality.
  • 104
    • 84903835051 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 10
    • Rawls, LP, pp. 3, 10, emphasis original.
    • LP , pp. 3
    • Rawls1
  • 105
    • 84903835051 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • n.7
    • In Rawls's words (Rawls, LP, Ibid., p. 6, n.7), as a realistic utopia the Law of Peoples 'sets limits to the reasonable exercise of power'.
    • LP , pp. 6
    • Rawls1
  • 106
    • 84903835051 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For Rawls's list see Rawls, LP, Ibid., p. 37.
    • LP , pp. 37
    • Rawls1
  • 107
    • 84903835051 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, LP, Ibid., p. 4.
    • LP , pp. 4
    • Rawls1
  • 108
    • 84903835051 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • More precisely, burdened societies are societies which 'lack the political and cultural traditions, the human capital and know-how, and, often, the material and technological resources needed to be well-ordered'. Rawls, LP, Ibid., p. 106.
    • LP , pp. 106
    • Rawls1
  • 109
    • 0001156411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls's Law of Peoples: Rules for a vanished Westphalian world
    • esp. at pp. 716-20
    • Allen Buchanan, 'Rawls's Law of Peoples: rules for a vanished Westphalian world', Ethics, 110 (2000), 697-721, esp. at pp. 716-20.
    • (2000) Ethics , vol.110 , pp. 697-721
    • Buchanan, A.1
  • 110
    • 0036522561 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cosmopolitanism and the law of peoples
    • at pp. 118-9
    • Simon Caney, 'Cosmopolitanism and the Law of Peoples', Journal of Political Philosophy, 10 (2002), 95-123, at pp. 118-9.
    • (2002) Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.10 , pp. 95-123
    • Caney, S.1
  • 112
    • 85004434322 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral universalism and global economic justice
    • esp. at pp. 46-9
    • Thomas W. Pogge, 'Moral universalism and global economic justice', Politics, Philosophy & Economics, 1 (2002), 29-58, esp. at pp. 46-9,
    • (2002) Politics, Philosophy & Economics , vol.1 , pp. 29-58
    • Pogge, T.W.1
  • 114
    • 0000163203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Critical study: Rawls on international justice
    • For an overall critical appraisal of The Law of Peoples see also Pogge's 'Critical study: Rawls on international justice', Philosophical Quarterly, 51 (2001), 246-53.
    • (2001) Philosophical Quarterly , vol.51 , pp. 246-253
    • Pogge's1
  • 115
    • 34248063193 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Network power and globalization
    • On this see, e.g., David Singh Grewal, 'Network power and globalization', Ethics and International Affairs, 17 (2003), 89-98;
    • (2003) Ethics and International Affairs , vol.17 , pp. 89-98
    • Grewal, D.S.1
  • 116
    • 33644595138 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The World Trade Organization and egalitarian justice
    • Darrell Moellendorf, 'The World Trade Organization and egalitarian justice', Metaphilosophy, 36 (2005), 145-62;
    • (2005) Metaphilosophy , vol.36 , pp. 145-162
    • Moellendorf, D.1
  • 117
    • 0036083447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the shadow of law or power? Consensus-based bargaining and outcomes in the GATT/WTO
    • and Richard H. Steinberg, 'In the shadow of law or power? Consensus-based bargaining and outcomes in the GATT/WTO', International Organizations, 56 (2002), 339-74.
    • (2002) International Organizations , vol.56 , pp. 339-374
    • Steinberg, R.H.1
  • 118
    • 84924702856 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Assisting" the global poor
    • ed. D.K. Chatterjee Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Thomas W. Pogge, ' "Assisting" the global poor', The Ethics of Assistance: Morality and the Distant Needy, ed. D.K. Chatterjee (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), pp. 260-88.
    • (2004) The Ethics of Assistance: Morality and the Distant Needy , pp. 260-288
    • Pogge, T.W.1
  • 119
    • 68249121955 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 53
    • Notice that Rawls is not unaware that existing liberal states are far less well-ordered than his 'peoples' (LP, pp. 48, 53), yet he seems to ignore this in his discussion of non-ideal theory.
    • LP , pp. 48
  • 121
    • 84910028206 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Do we need a liberal theory of minority rights? Reply to Carens, Young, Parekh and Forst
    • at p. 75
    • Will Kymlicka, 'Do we need a liberal theory of minority rights? Reply to Carens, Young, Parekh and Forst', Constellations, 4 (1997), 72-87, at p. 75.
    • (1997) Constellations , vol.4 , pp. 72-87
    • Kymlicka, W.1
  • 122
    • 79955216982 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • n.11, 109
    • Kymlicka, MC, pp. 214, n.11, 109.
    • MC , pp. 214
    • Kymlicka1
  • 123
    • 79955216982 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kymlicka, MC, Ibid., p. 152, emphases original.
    • MC , pp. 152
    • Kymlicka1
  • 124
    • 79955216982 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ch. 8
    • Kymlicka, MC, Ibid., ch. 8.
    • MC
    • Kymlicka1
  • 125
    • 79955216982 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 169
    • Kymlicka, MC, Ibid., pp. 165, 169.
    • MC , pp. 165
    • Kymlicka1
  • 126
    • 0004323817 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Polity Press, ch. 4
    • See, e.g., Brian Barry, Culture and Equality (Cambridge: Polity Press, 20031), ch. 4.
    • (2003) Culture and Equality
    • Barry, B.1
  • 127
    • 0042046194 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Multiculturalism as fairness: Will Kymlicka's Multicultural Citizenship
    • p. 420
    • See also Chandran Kukathas, 'Multiculturalism as fairness: Will Kymlicka's Multicultural Citizenship', Journal of Political Philosophy, 5 (1997), 406-27, at p. 420,
    • (1997) Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.5 , pp. 406-427
    • Kukathas, C.1
  • 128
    • 84992845486 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Equality, autonomy, and cultural rights
    • esp. at pp. 227 ff
    • and Geoffrey Brahm Levey, 'Equality, autonomy, and cultural rights', Political Theory, 25 (1997), 215-48, esp. at pp. 227 ff.
    • (1997) Political Theory , vol.25 , pp. 215-248
    • Levey, G.B.1
  • 129
    • 0037713511 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Applied political philosophy at the Rubicon: Will Kymlicka's multicultural citizenship
    • For a sustained critical discussion of the limitations of Kymlicka's ideal theoretic approach to which I am indebted see Adrian Favell, 'Applied political philosophy at the Rubicon: Will Kymlicka's multicultural citizenship', Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 1 (1998), 255-78.
    • (1998) Ethical Theory and Moral Practice , vol.1 , pp. 255-278
    • Favell, A.1
  • 130
  • 131
    • 68249117292 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • As Cécile Laborde has suggested to me, this clearly emerges from the fact that Kymlicka defends national minorities because they provide a context of choice. This implicitly assumes minorities to be already liberal (just). Otherwise, how could they be a context of choice?
  • 132
  • 133
    • 68249125772 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • As Zofia Stemplowska has helpfully pointed out to me, right-libertarians would disagree with this claim, arguing that egalitarians like Rawls and Dworkin have an implausibly idealised conception of the state. For right-libertarians the complex state apparatus necessary to realise egalitarian policies would inevitably fall prey to corruption and power abuses, thus hindering, rather than promoting, the pursuit of justice. My argument in this article is entirely internal to liberal egalitarianism and thus does not respond to this libertarian critique.
  • 134
    • 84903835051 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • n.52
    • Rawls, LP, p. 42, n.52.
    • LP , pp. 42
    • Rawls1
  • 136
    • 3042793950 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The incoherence between Rawls's theories of justice
    • at p. 1751.
    • and Thomas W. Pogge, 'The incoherence between Rawls's theories of justice', Fordham Law Review, 72 (2004), 1739-59, at p. 1751. Pogge offers a detailed critical analysis of the structural differences between Rawls's domestic and international theories of justice, which has informed my own discussion here. In particular, he argues that while Rawls's domestic theory is three-tiered and institutional, his international theory is two-tiered and interactional. In Pogge's view, these structural asymmetries explain much of what is problematic about The Law of Peoples. For further discussion of Pogge's view in the relation to the argument presented here, see footnote 106 of this article.
    • (2004) Fordham Law Review , vol.72 , pp. 1739-1759
    • Pogge, T.W.1
  • 137
    • 3042640045 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What self-governing peoples owe to one another: Universalism, diversity, and the Law of Peoples
    • esp. at p. 1727
    • Interestingly, some scholars have emphasised this aspect of Rawls's theory to defend it against cosmopolitan objections. In their view, since Rawls's principles are meant to apply in 'ideal theory'-where no power abuses occur-they should not be objected to on the grounds that they are misguiding (or unhelpful) in real-world circumstances. Obviously, this defence of The Law of Peoples only succeeds if we reject the claim that any sound normative theory should be action-guiding. For this line of argument see, e.g., Stephen Macedo, 'What self-governing peoples owe to one another: universalism, diversity, and The Law of Peoples', Fordham Law Review, 72 (2004), 1721-38, esp. at p. 1727
    • (2004) Fordham Law Review , vol.72 , pp. 1721-1738
    • Macedo, S.1
  • 138
    • 33644912578 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Law of Peoples, social cooperation, human rights, and distributive justice
    • at pp. 32-3
    • and Samuel Freeman, 'The Law of Peoples, social cooperation, human rights, and distributive justice', Social Philosophy and Policy, 23 (2006), 29-68, at pp. 32-3.
    • (2006) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.23 , pp. 29-68
    • Freeman, S.1
  • 139
    • 68249091463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I borrow this expression from Phillips, 'Reflections on the transition from ideal to non-ideal theory'
    • I borrow this expression from Phillips, 'Reflections on the transition from ideal to non-ideal theory'.
  • 141
    • 84869576503 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Interestingly, this is acknowledged even by advocates of non-ideal theory, for instance by Mills, '"Ideal theory" as ideology', p. 171, when he says that 'nonideal theory can and does appeal to an ideal'.
    • "Ideal Theory" As Ideology , pp. 171
    • Mills1
  • 142
    • 68249112221 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In connection with this point, Ingrid Robeyns and Miriam Ronzoni have suggested to me that a dimension along which we may distinguish between good and bad idealisations is their flexibility, that is the extent to which they constitute an integral part of a theory. The more idealisations are integral to a theory, the harder it is for the theory to adjust to its 'real-world' object and to provide valuable tools for studying it. Robeyns further discusses how to distinguish between good and bad idealisations in 'Ideal theory in theory and practice'.
  • 143
    • 68249105142 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I owe this point to a very helpful discussion with Christian List
    • I owe this point to a very helpful discussion with Christian List.
  • 145
    • 68249104878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pogge's distinction between two-tiered and three-tiered theories (introduced at footnote 98 of this article) helps explain this aspect of Rawls's approach to international justice. In particular, Pogge claims that while Rawls's domestic theory of justice is three-tiered-the parties in the original position (1) select principles (2) to govern the basic structure of society (3)-the 'Law of Peoples' is two-tiered: the representatives of peoples (1) select principles for guiding peoples' conduct (2). In light of our discussion, we might say that while three-tiered theories ensure a separation between the justification of principles (1 and 2) and their application to the subject of justice (3), this does not happen with two-tiered ones, such as the Law of Peoples. This is why idealisations that would be appropriate at the level of its justification end up characterizing the subjects to which Rawls's theory of international justice is meant to apply. See Pogge, 'The incoherence between Rawls's theories of justice'.
    • The Incoherence between Rawls's Theories of Justice
    • Pogge, S.1
  • 147
    • 8844286244 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • O'Neill also briefly remarks on the use of idealisations in theoretical, as opposed to practical, reasoning, in Towards Justice and Virtue, pp. 41-2.
    • Towards Justice and Virtue , pp. 41-42
  • 148
    • 68249113293 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am grateful to Robert E. Goodin for suggesting these examples
    • I am grateful to Robert E. Goodin for suggesting these examples.
  • 149
    • 0037980677 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Philosophy of economics
    • ed. Edward N. Zalta (Summer 2006 edn)
    • See Daniel M. Hausman, 'Philosophy of economics', The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta (Summer 2006 edn); available at: http://plato.stanford.edu/ archives/sum2006/entries/economics/.
    • The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
    • Hausman, D.M.1
  • 150
    • 68249118827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In recent years, however, behavioural economists have considered more empirically informed behavioural assumptions and investigated how these affect standard results in economic theory
    • In recent years, however, behavioural economists have considered more empirically informed behavioural assumptions and investigated how these affect standard results in economic theory.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.