메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 101, Issue 4, 2007, Pages 1905-1918

Why supermajoritarianism does not illuminate the interpretive debate between originalists and non-originalists

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 37749002378     PISSN: 00293571     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (6)

References (68)
  • 1
    • 33749851214 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Supermajority Rules and the Judicial Confirmation Process, 26
    • See, e.g
    • See, e.g., John O. McGinnis & Michael B. Rappaport, Supermajority Rules and the Judicial Confirmation Process, 26 CARDOZO L. REV. 543 (2005);
    • (2005) CARDOZO L. REV , vol.543
    • McGinnis, J.O.1    Rappaport, M.B.2
  • 2
    • 23044532121 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John O. McGinnis & Michael B. Rappaport, Our Supermajoritarian Constitution, 80 TEX. L. REV. 703 (2002) [hereinafter McGinnis & Rappaport, Our Supermajoritarian Constitution];
    • John O. McGinnis & Michael B. Rappaport, Our Supermajoritarian Constitution, 80 TEX. L. REV. 703 (2002) [hereinafter McGinnis & Rappaport, Our Supermajoritarian Constitution];
  • 3
    • 0042021734 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Supermajority Rules as a Constitutional Solution, 40
    • John O. McGinnis & Michael B. Rappaport, Supermajority Rules as a Constitutional Solution, 40 WM. & MARY L. REV. 365 (1999);
    • (1999) WM. & MARY L. REV , vol.365
    • McGinnis, J.O.1    Rappaport, M.B.2
  • 4
    • 84937297076 scopus 로고
    • The Constitutionality of Legislative Supermajority Requirements: A Defense, 105
    • John O. McGinnis & Michael B. Rappaport, The Constitutionality of Legislative Supermajority Requirements: A Defense, 105 YALE L.J. 483 (1995).
    • (1995) YALE L.J , vol.483
    • McGinnis, J.O.1    Rappaport, M.B.2
  • 5
    • 37749045220 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed, in a recent article, I draw inspiration from their work and apply many of their insights to argue for supermajoritarian decision rules in the context of criminal jury convictions, an underexplored application of their enthusiasm for supermajoritarian rules in democratic decisionmaking. See generally Ethan J. Leib, Supermajoritarianism and the American Criminal Jury, 33 HASTINGS CONST, L.Q. 141 (2006) (arguing that McGinnis and Rappaport's attention to the supermajoritarian nature of our polity helps recommend supermajoritarian decision rules for conviction by the criminal jury).
    • Indeed, in a recent article, I draw inspiration from their work and apply many of their insights to argue for supermajoritarian decision rules in the context of criminal jury convictions, an underexplored application of their enthusiasm for supermajoritarian rules in democratic decisionmaking. See generally Ethan J. Leib, Supermajoritarianism and the American Criminal Jury, 33 HASTINGS CONST, L.Q. 141 (2006) (arguing that McGinnis and Rappaport's attention to the supermajoritarian nature of our polity helps recommend supermajoritarian decision rules for conviction by the criminal jury).
  • 6
    • 34250175164 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Pragmatic Defense of Originalism, 101
    • See
    • See John O. McGinnis & Michael B. Rappaport, A Pragmatic Defense of Originalism, 101 NW. U. L. REV, 383 (2007), 101
    • (2007) NW. U. L. REV , vol.383 , pp. 101
    • McGinnis, J.O.1    Rappaport, M.B.2
  • 7
    • 37749041873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NW. U. L. REV. COLLOQUY 68 (2007), http://www.law.northwestern.edu/lawreview/colloquy/2007/1/ (subsequent citations refer to 101 NW, U. L. REV. 383 (2007)).
    • NW. U. L. REV. COLLOQUY 68 (2007), http://www.law.northwestern.edu/lawreview/colloquy/2007/1/ (subsequent citations refer to 101 NW, U. L. REV. 383 (2007)).
  • 8
    • 37749033087 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id, at 383
    • Id, at 383.
  • 9
    • 37749022373 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see generally ROBERT A. DAHL, HOW DEMOCRATIC IS THE AMERICAN CONSTITUTION? (2002) (providing a trenchant criticism of the entire document and many of its institutional choices);
    • But see generally ROBERT A. DAHL, HOW DEMOCRATIC IS THE AMERICAN CONSTITUTION? (2002) (providing a trenchant criticism of the entire document and many of its institutional choices);
  • 10
    • 37749018007 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SANFORD LEVINSON, OUR UNDEMOCRATIC CONSTITUTION: WHERE THE CONSTITUTION GOES WRONG (AND HOW WE THE PEOPLE CAN CORRECT IT) (2006) (same).
    • SANFORD LEVINSON, OUR UNDEMOCRATIC CONSTITUTION: WHERE THE CONSTITUTION GOES WRONG (AND HOW WE THE PEOPLE CAN CORRECT IT) (2006) (same).
  • 11
    • 37749006039 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McGinnis & Rappaport, supra note 3, at 383
    • McGinnis & Rappaport, supra note 3, at 383.
  • 12
    • 37749047401 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 13
    • 37749020478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 14
    • 37749035911 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 384
    • Id. at 384.
  • 15
    • 37749039699 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 391 n.37.
    • Id. at 391 n.37.
  • 16
    • 28044434403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Foreword: A Political Court, 119
    • Richard A. Posner, Foreword: A Political Court, 119 HARV. L. REV. 32, 90 (2005).
    • (2005) HARV. L. REV , vol.32 , pp. 90
    • Posner, R.A.1
  • 17
    • 37749048864 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RICHARD A. POSNER, LAW, PRAGMATISM, AND DEMOCRACY 71 (2003) (emphasis added).
    • RICHARD A. POSNER, LAW, PRAGMATISM, AND DEMOCRACY 71 (2003) (emphasis added).
  • 18
    • 37748999496 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 59 (Only in exceptional circumstances . . . will the pragmatic judge give controlling weight to systematic consequences, as legal formalism does; that is, only rarely will legal formalism be a pragmatic strategy. And sometimes case-specific circumstances will completely dominate the decisional process.).
    • See id. at 59 ("Only in exceptional circumstances . . . will the pragmatic judge give controlling weight to systematic consequences, as legal formalism does; that is, only rarely will legal formalism be a pragmatic strategy. And sometimes case-specific circumstances will completely dominate the decisional process.").
  • 19
    • 37749002237 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McGinnis & Rappaport, supra note 3, at 384
    • McGinnis & Rappaport, supra note 3, at 384.
  • 20
    • 37749049694 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • POSNER, supra note 12, at 71
    • POSNER, supra note 12, at 71.
  • 21
    • 37749045221 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 72;
    • Id. at 72;
  • 23
    • 37748998702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, not all rule-pragmatists are originalists, and McGinnis and Rappaport might convince a few such rule-pragmatists to join them. But I would imagine that the rule-pragmatists would want to hear a lot more about exactly which sorts of good consequences originalism can achieve. In any case, as I think even McGinnis and Rappaport would agree, rule-pragmatists have not, as a group, been opposed to originalism in the way case-by-case pragmatists have. Accordingly, the need for matchmaking between originalists and rule-pragmatists hardly seems like a pressing academic concern
    • Of course, not all rule-pragmatists are originalists, and McGinnis and Rappaport might convince a few such rule-pragmatists to join them. But I would imagine that the rule-pragmatists would want to hear a lot more about exactly which sorts of good consequences originalism can achieve. In any case, as I think even McGinnis and Rappaport would agree, rule-pragmatists have not, as a group, been opposed to originalism in the way case-by-case pragmatists have. Accordingly, the need for matchmaking between originalists and rule-pragmatists hardly seems like a pressing academic concern.
  • 24
    • 37749029265 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McGinnis & Rappaport, supra note 3, at 389-90
    • McGinnis & Rappaport, supra note 3, at 389-90.
  • 25
    • 37749042016 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McGinnis and Rappaport's justifications for binding blacks and women to the Constitution-despite their exclusion from the supermajoritarian rules that purportedly legitimized the Constitution itself-are extremely weak. See id. at 394-96. It suffices to say that given McGinnis and Rappaport's focus on constitutional enactment as the primary justificatory moment, it is a bit of a cheat to smuggle in a justification for the document that arises only because later provisions somehow purify the original enactment of its defects. More ironic is that the full purification happens neither according to the very Article VII supermajority requirements that they think give the Constitution its supermajoritarian credibility,
    • McGinnis and Rappaport's justifications for binding blacks and women to the Constitution-despite their exclusion from the supermajoritarian rules that purportedly legitimized the Constitution itself-are extremely weak. See id. at 394-96. It suffices to say that given McGinnis and Rappaport's focus on constitutional enactment as the primary justificatory moment, it is a bit of a cheat to smuggle in a justification for the document that arises only because later provisions somehow purify the original enactment of its defects. More ironic is that the full purification happens neither according to the very Article VII supermajority requirements that they think give the Constitution its supermajoritarian credibility,
  • 26
    • 37749027473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see id. at 388, nor according to Article Vs supermajority requirements for constitutional amendment. Indeed, McGinnis and Rappaport find it relevant for the Constitution's legitimacy, for example, that blacks are now equal, thanks to the Voting Rights Act of 1965, and that women are now equal thanks to the Supreme Court's construction of the Fourteenth Amendment.
    • see id. at 388, nor according to Article Vs supermajority requirements for constitutional amendment. Indeed, McGinnis and Rappaport find it relevant for the Constitution's legitimacy, for example, that blacks are now equal, thanks to the Voting Rights Act of 1965, and that women are now equal thanks to the Supreme Court's construction of the Fourteenth Amendment.
  • 27
    • 37749027128 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 395-96. It rums out that plain-old legislation and judicial activism-processes that are rather different from the supermajoritarian processes that rest at the center of the Constitution's legitimacy for McGinnis and Rappaport, legitimize the Constitution itself! Just how these post-enactment moments work to cleanse the original sin of exclusion retroactively is not well specified in their essay. Moreover, their suggestion that we ought to worry about the exclusion of women from the founding supermajoritarian big bang of beneficence less than the exclusion of blacks therefrom is unsupported by authority and borders on the offensive: they claim that women were virtually represented at the time by their male relatives and that many women apparently believed that they should not have the right to participate. Id. at 395 citing no authority, Finally, in their discussion of exclusions, McGinnis and Rappaport evade one of the mos
    • See id. at 395-96. It rums out that plain-old legislation and "judicial activism"-processes that are rather different from the supermajoritarian processes that rest at the center of the Constitution's legitimacy for McGinnis and Rappaport - legitimize the Constitution itself! Just how these post-enactment moments work to cleanse the original sin of exclusion retroactively is not well specified in their essay. Moreover, their suggestion that we ought to worry about the exclusion of women from the founding supermajoritarian big bang of beneficence less than the exclusion of blacks therefrom is unsupported by authority and borders on the offensive: they claim that "women were virtually represented at the time by their male relatives" and that "many women apparently believed that they should not have the right to participate." Id. at 395 (citing no authority). Finally, in their discussion of exclusions, McGinnis and Rappaport evade one of the most interesting interventions in the voting rule literature, one that presents yet another challenge to their project.
  • 28
    • 37749052664 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Adrian Vermeule, Absolute Voting Rules (Univ. of Chi, Pub. Law Working Paper No. 103, 2005, available at papers.cfm7abstract_id-791724. Vermeule argues, To say that the voting rule should be 'a majority' or 'a supermajority' is an underspecified statement, like saying 'X is more than' or 'three multiplied by, If a voting rule is to be coherently stated, one must ask 'a majority (or supermajority) of what, Id. at 3. In particular, Vermeule demands that those favoring supermajoritarian rules specify their preferred multiplicand, which is usually either a supermajority of (1) those present and voting or (2) the whole membership of the institution, Id. at 4. As Vermeule's paper makes clear, the choice can be quite consequential-and McGinnis and Rappaport simply do not engage the question of the appropriate multiplicand, which is central to their claim that supermajori
    • See Adrian Vermeule, Absolute Voting Rules (Univ. of Chi., Pub. Law Working Paper No. 103, 2005), available at http://papers.ssm. com/sol3/papers.cfm7abstract_id-791724. Vermeule argues, "To say that the voting rule should be 'a majority' or 'a supermajority' is an underspecified statement, like saying 'X is more than' or 'three multiplied by.' If a voting rule is to be coherently stated, one must ask 'a majority (or supermajority) of what?'" Id. at 3. In particular, Vermeule demands that those favoring "supermajoritarian" rules specify their preferred "multiplicand," which is usually either a supermajority of "(1) those present and voting or (2) the whole membership of the institution ... ." Id. at 4. As Vermeule's paper makes clear, the choice can be quite consequential-and McGinnis and Rappaport simply do not engage the question of the appropriate multiplicand, which is central to their claim that supermajoritarianism itself confers legitimacy despite great exclusions from the moment of enactment. Thanks to Seth Barrett Tillman for discussion on this last point.
  • 29
    • 37749040137 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I, § 5, cl. 3
    • U.S. CONST, art. I, § 5, cl. 3.
    • CONST, U.S.1    art2
  • 30
    • 15344341851 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Adrian Vermeule, Submajority Rules: Forcing Accountability upon Majorities, 13 J. POL. PHIL. 74 (2005).
    • See Adrian Vermeule, Submajority Rules: Forcing Accountability upon Majorities, 13 J. POL. PHIL. 74 (2005).
  • 31
    • 37749003469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, McGinnis and Rappaport already know all this. In their earlier articles on supermajoritarianism, they develop a much more nuanced approach to supermajoritarianism-one that acknowledges that supermajoritarian benefits accrue only in particular contexts. See, e.g, McGinnis & Rappaport, Our Supermajoritarian Constitution, supra note 1, at 728
    • Of course, McGinnis and Rappaport already know all this. In their earlier articles on supermajoritarianism, they develop a much more nuanced approach to supermajoritarianism-one that acknowledges that supermajoritarian benefits accrue only in particular contexts. See, e.g., McGinnis & Rappaport, Our Supermajoritarian Constitution, supra note 1, at 728.
  • 32
    • 37749026332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Elsewhere, I have catalogued critiques routinely offered against supermajority rule, ones that find no rebuttal in McGinnis and Rappaport's essay, despite their potential application to the particular context of Constitution-making. Supermajoritarian decision rules for constitutional choices can: result, in compromises no one really wants because ideas and policies get thinned out to garner substantial agreement, privileged the status quo, fail to] result in higher likelihood of correct answers because just as the probability of correct decision[s] increases with move[s] toward unanimity [away from simple majority rule, so does the probability that the minority is wrong increase; accordingly, providing the minority veto power may be unwise, lead to] coalition-building [that] reifies groups and can be balkanizing, be] no better than simple majority at avoiding Condorcet losers i.e, choices that might win in a ranking system but that would fail in pair-wise
    • Elsewhere, I have catalogued critiques routinely offered against supermajority rule, ones that find no rebuttal in McGinnis and Rappaport's essay, despite their potential application to the particular context of Constitution-making. Supermajoritarian decision rules for constitutional choices can: result[] in compromises no one really wants because ideas and policies get thinned out to garner substantial agreement[;] privileged the status quo...[;] [fail to] result in higher likelihood of "correct" answers because just as the probability of correct decision[s] increases with move[s] toward unanimity [away from simple majority rule], so does the probability that the minority is wrong increase; accordingly, providing the minority veto power may be unwise[;] [lead to] coalition-building [that] reifies groups and can be balkanizing[;] [be] no better than simple majority at avoiding Condorcet losers (i.e., choices that might win in a ranking system but that would fail in pair-wise competition with other choices). Leib, supra note 2, at 153-54.
  • 34
    • 37749048534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Amy Gutmann, Deliberative Democracy and Majority Rule: Reply to Waldron, in DELIBERATIVE DEMOCRACY & HUMAN RIGHTS 227, 230 (Harold Hongju Koh & Ronald C Slye eds., 1999) (To give a minority veto power is morally more dangerous in the legislative arena than it is in criminal trials,...).
    • Amy Gutmann, Deliberative Democracy and Majority Rule: Reply to Waldron, in DELIBERATIVE DEMOCRACY & HUMAN RIGHTS 227, 230 (Harold Hongju Koh & Ronald C Slye eds., 1999) ("To give a minority veto power is morally more dangerous in the legislative arena than it is in criminal trials,...").
  • 35
    • 37749049693 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The attractive baselines argument is developed in McGinnis & Rappaport, Our Supermajoritarian Constitution, supra note 1, at 742.
    • The "attractive baselines" argument is developed in McGinnis & Rappaport, Our Supermajoritarian Constitution, supra note 1, at 742.
  • 36
    • 37749037688 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Gutmann, supra note 24, at 230 (The likelihood of achieving justifiable agreement [with supermajority rules] differs depending on what the issue is and who the deliberators are.). In my recent article that aims to apply McGinnis and Rappaport's insights to jury decision rules, context-sensitivity led me to embrace supermajoritarian rules for conviction by the criminal jury but to reject them for acquittal. The same considerations do not apply to the decision to acquit, so I don't think it is appropriate to require jurors to reach consensus on acquittal beyond simple majority agreement. See Leib, supra note 2, at 187-88.
    • See Gutmann, supra note 24, at 230 ("The likelihood of achieving justifiable agreement [with supermajority rules] differs depending on what the issue is and who the deliberators are."). In my recent article that aims to apply McGinnis and Rappaport's insights to jury decision rules, context-sensitivity led me to embrace supermajoritarian rules for conviction by the criminal jury but to reject them for acquittal. The same considerations do not apply to the decision to acquit, so I don't think it is appropriate to require jurors to reach consensus on acquittal beyond simple majority agreement. See Leib, supra note 2, at 187-88.
  • 37
    • 37749011077 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed, McGinnis and Rappaport want us to believe that this was a double supermajoritarian hurdle because a supermajority of states also had to support the Constitutional Convention in the first place. McGinnis & Rappaport, supra note 3, at 388-89
    • Indeed, McGinnis and Rappaport want us to believe that this was a double supermajoritarian hurdle because "a supermajority of states also had to support the Constitutional Convention in the first place." McGinnis & Rappaport, supra note 3, at 388-89.
  • 38
    • 37749026042 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Akhil Reed Amar, The Consent of the Governed: Constitutional Amendment Outside Article V, 94 COLUM. L. REV. 457, 487 n.l 12 (1994) (emphasis omitted).
    • Akhil Reed Amar, The Consent of the Governed: Constitutional Amendment Outside Article V, 94 COLUM. L. REV. 457, 487 n.l 12 (1994) (emphasis omitted).
  • 39
    • 37749029623 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Akhil Reed Amar, The Central Meaning of Republican Government: Popular Sovereignty, Majority Rule, and the Denominator Problem, 65 U. COLO. L. REV. 749, 774 (1994) (Most remarkable is what was not said in antebellum debates. Almost no one denied that. , . the proper voting rule for popular sovereignty in making or changing constitutions is simple majority rule. Almost no one, for example, argued that conventions or popular ratification must be supermajoritarian.).
    • See Akhil Reed Amar, The Central Meaning of Republican Government: Popular Sovereignty, Majority Rule, and the Denominator Problem, 65 U. COLO. L. REV. 749, 774 (1994) ("Most remarkable is what was not said in antebellum debates. Almost no one denied that. , . the proper voting rule for popular sovereignty in making or changing constitutions is simple majority rule. Almost no one, for example, argued that conventions or popular ratification must be supermajoritarian.").
  • 40
    • 37749023632 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • They might reply that national supermajorities would likely still be necessary to achieve the Article VII and Article V thresholds. Perhaps-but perhaps not. Nothing in the enactment and amendment rules requires it, and the differences between small population states and large population states is not merely a modem anomaly
    • They might reply that national supermajorities would likely still be necessary to achieve the Article VII and Article V thresholds. Perhaps-but perhaps not. Nothing in the enactment and amendment rules requires it, and the differences between small population states and large population states is not merely a modem anomaly.
  • 41
    • 37749021865 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pub. L. No. 88-352, 78 Stat. 241 (codified as amended at 42 U.S.C. §§ 1981-200Oh 2000
    • Pub. L. No. 88-352, 78 Stat. 241 (codified as amended at 42 U.S.C. §§ 1981-200Oh (2000)).
  • 42
    • 37749044760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See WILLIAM N. ESKRIDGE, JR. ET AL., CASES AND MATERIALS ON LEGISLATION: STATUTES AND THE CREATION OF PUBLIC POLICY 22-23 (3d ed. 2001).
    • See WILLIAM N. ESKRIDGE, JR. ET AL., CASES AND MATERIALS ON LEGISLATION: STATUTES AND THE CREATION OF PUBLIC POLICY 22-23 (3d ed. 2001).
  • 44
    • 37749012576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (citing JAMES M. BUCHANAN & GORDON TULLOCK, THE CALCULUS OF CONSENT 233-48 (1962));
    • (citing JAMES M. BUCHANAN & GORDON TULLOCK, THE CALCULUS OF CONSENT 233-48 (1962));
  • 45
    • 37749019641 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DENNIS C MUELLER, CONSTITUTIONAL DEMOCRACY 193-95 (1996);
    • DENNIS C MUELLER, CONSTITUTIONAL DEMOCRACY 193-95 (1996);
  • 46
    • 0348050646 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Textualism and the Equity of the Statute, 101
    • John F. Manning, Textualism and the Equity of the Statute, 101 COLUM. L. REV. 1, 74-75 (2001);
    • (2001) COLUM. L. REV , vol.1 , pp. 74-75
    • Manning, J.F.1
  • 47
    • 37749009988 scopus 로고
    • The Possibilities of Collective Choice: Arrow's Theorem, Article I, and the Delegation of Legislative Power to Administrative Agencies, 1986
    • William T. Mayton, The Possibilities of Collective Choice: Arrow's Theorem, Article I, and the Delegation of Legislative Power to Administrative Agencies, 1986 DUKE L.J. 948, 956 (1986);
    • (1986) DUKE L.J , vol.948 , pp. 956
    • Mayton, W.T.1
  • 48
    • 37749047779 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Julian N. Eule, Judicial Review of Direct Democracy, 99 YALE L.J. 1503, 1557 (1990) (Bicameralism forces majorities to seek broader coalitions. It imposes something like a supermajoritarian voting rule.).
    • see also Julian N. Eule, Judicial Review of Direct Democracy, 99 YALE L.J. 1503, 1557 (1990) ("Bicameralism forces majorities to seek broader coalitions. It imposes something like a supermajoritarian voting rule.").
  • 49
    • 37749051623 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is similar to the challenge supermajoritarians often hear: Any theory that might justify the use of a three-fifths (60, or two-thirds (66.6, decision rule should be equally effective at justifying a nine-tenths (90, decision rule, or even the rule of a single person (99.9999, Brett W. King, Wild Political Dreaming: Historical Context, Popular Sovereignty, and Supermajority Rules, 2 U. PA. J. CONST. L. 609, 611 2000
    • This is similar to the challenge supermajoritarians often hear: "Any theory that might justify the use of a three-fifths (60%) or two-thirds (66.6%) decision rule should be equally effective at justifying a nine-tenths (90%) decision rule, or even the rule of a single person (99.9999%)." Brett W. King, Wild Political Dreaming: Historical Context, Popular Sovereignty, and Supermajority Rules, 2 U. PA. J. CONST. L. 609, 611 (2000).
  • 50
    • 37749025072 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arguably, the procedures of standard legislation might often be more supermajoritarian than constitutional provisions because bills may be subject to Senate Rule V, requiring unanimous consent of all Senators to achieve consideration on the floor of the Senate chamber. See ESKRIDGE ET AL., supra note 32, at 32 (explaining how Senate Rule V operates as a supermajoritarian vetogate).
    • Arguably, the procedures of standard legislation might often be more supermajoritarian than constitutional provisions because bills may be subject to Senate Rule V, requiring unanimous consent of all Senators to achieve consideration on the floor of the Senate chamber. See ESKRIDGE ET AL., supra note 32, at 32 (explaining how Senate Rule V operates as a supermajoritarian vetogate).
  • 51
    • 37749050309 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See McGinnis & Rappaport, supra note 3, at 389-91
    • See McGinnis & Rappaport, supra note 3, at 389-91.
  • 52
    • 37749025073 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 389
    • Id. at 389.
  • 53
    • 37749026992 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See McCulloch v. Maryland, 17 U.S. (Wheat.) 316, 407 (1819) (A constitution, to contain an accurate detail of all the subdivisions of which its great powers will admit, and of all the means by which they may be carried into execution, would partake of the prolixity of a legal code, and could scarcely be embraced by the human mind. It would probably never be understood by the public. Its nature, therefore, requires, that only its great outlines should be marked, its important objects designated, and the minor ingredients which compose those objects be deduced from the nature of the objects themselves. That this idea was entertained by the framers of the American constitution, is not only to be inferred from the nature of the instrument, but from the language,).
    • See McCulloch v. Maryland, 17 U.S. (Wheat.) 316, 407 (1819) ("A constitution, to contain an accurate detail of all the subdivisions of which its great powers will admit, and of all the means by which they may be carried into execution, would partake of the prolixity of a legal code, and could scarcely be embraced by the human mind. It would probably never be understood by the public. Its nature, therefore, requires, that only its great outlines should be marked, its important objects designated, and the minor ingredients which compose those objects be deduced from the nature of the objects themselves. That this idea was entertained by the framers of the American constitution, is not only to be inferred from the nature of the instrument, but from the language,").
  • 54
    • 37749014245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Certainly, some ratifiers were all too aware that deep ambiguities in the document seemed to give free rein to future federal authorities to do whatever they wanted. Despite this awareness, they voted to ratify. See H, Jefferson Powell, The Original Understanding of Original Intent, 98 HARV. L. REV. 885, 912 n.143 1985, explaining the views of Edmund Randolph, a delegate in Philadelphia, who ultimately played an important role in getting Virginia to ratify the document despite his misgivings about serious vagueness and ambiguity injurious to the states, This evidence suggests that some drafters and ratifiers might have recognized that the Constitution would not be fully interpreted in light of contemporaneous interpretive conventions. And there is much more evidence in Powell's article that tends to show that many Anti-Federalists were deeply concerned about the radical interpretive freedom the Constitution gave to future Congresses and members of the
    • Certainly, some ratifiers were all too aware that deep ambiguities in the document seemed to give free rein to future federal authorities to do whatever they wanted. Despite this awareness, they voted to ratify. See H, Jefferson Powell, The Original Understanding of Original Intent, 98 HARV. L. REV. 885, 912 n.143 (1985) (explaining the views of Edmund Randolph, a delegate in Philadelphia, who ultimately played an important role in getting Virginia to ratify the document despite his misgivings about serious vagueness and ambiguity injurious to the states). This evidence suggests that some drafters and ratifiers might have recognized that the Constitution would not be fully interpreted in light of contemporaneous interpretive conventions. And there is much more evidence in Powell's article that tends to show that many Anti-Federalists were deeply concerned about the radical interpretive freedom the Constitution gave to future Congresses and members of the federal judiciary, The views of these important members of the founding generation are surely relevant in ascertaining the interpretive conventions prevalent at the time of enactment and how they were expected to be applied to the Constitution's open-textured and ambiguous provisions.
  • 55
    • 37749019640 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Consider, for example, Congress's failure to define the term discriminate in the antidiscrimination provisions of the Civil Rights Act of 1964. See United Steelworkers of America v. Weber, 443 U.S. 193, 239-43 (1979, Rehnquist, J, dissenting, noting Congress's failure to define the word discriminate in the Civil Rights Act of 1964 and trying to derive its meaning not from the statute directly but from legislative history, Gaps in legal text virtually guarantee that the judicial function and judicial power will require more than simple law-application. See, e.g, Rex v. Liggetts-Findley Drug-Stores Ltd, 1919] 3 W.W.R. 1025 rejecting an argument that because a statute required drug shops to close by 10 P.M, but did not specify that they must remain closed for any period of time, the statute thus left open the possibility that the shop owner could reopen at 10:10 P.M
    • Consider, for example, Congress's "failure" to define the term "discriminate" in the antidiscrimination provisions of the Civil Rights Act of 1964. See United Steelworkers of America v. Weber, 443 U.S. 193, 239-43 (1979) (Rehnquist, J., dissenting) (noting Congress's failure to define the word "discriminate" in the Civil Rights Act of 1964 and trying to derive its meaning not from the statute directly but from legislative history), Gaps in legal text virtually guarantee that the judicial function and judicial power will require more than simple law-application. See, e.g., Rex v. Liggetts-Findley Drug-Stores Ltd., [1919] 3 W.W.R. 1025 (rejecting an argument that because a statute required drug shops to close by 10 P.M., but did not specify that they must remain closed for any period of time, the statute thus left open the possibility that the shop owner could reopen at 10:10 P.M.);
  • 56
    • 37749052947 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also ESKRIDGE ET AL., supra note 32, at 100 (Can we expect Congress, drafting statutory language in an environment of imperfect information and substantial time pressure, to anticipate specific questions that will arise under the law, or is it more realistic to expect general statements of policy that will require agencies and courts to use discretion in executing and interpreting law?).
    • see also ESKRIDGE ET AL., supra note 32, at 100 ("Can we expect Congress, drafting statutory language in an environment of imperfect information and substantial time pressure, to anticipate specific questions that will arise under the law, or is it more realistic to expect general statements of policy that will require agencies and courts to use discretion in executing and interpreting law?").
  • 57
    • 37749018400 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., ESKRIDGE ET AL., supra note 32, at 572 (citing HENRY HART, JR. & ALBERT SACKS, THE LEGAL PROCESS: BASIC PROBLEMS IN THE MAKING AND APPLICATION OF LAW 147, 362-403, 545-70 (William Eskridge, Jr. & Philip Frickey eds., 1994) for the proposition that legislatures sometimes need to enact very broadly worded standards rather than specific rules, and that enacting ambiguous or vague provisions essentially delegates] rulemaking responsibilities to courts [and] agencies).
    • See, e.g., ESKRIDGE ET AL., supra note 32, at 572 (citing HENRY HART, JR. & ALBERT SACKS, THE LEGAL PROCESS: BASIC PROBLEMS IN THE MAKING AND APPLICATION OF LAW 147, 362-403, 545-70 (William Eskridge, Jr. & Philip Frickey eds., 1994) for the proposition that legislatures sometimes need to enact very broadly worded standards rather than specific rules, and that enacting ambiguous or vague provisions "essentially delegates] rulemaking responsibilities to courts [and] agencies").
  • 58
    • 37749013332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John O. McGinnis & Michael B. Rappaport, Original Interpretive Principles as the Core of Originalism, 24 CONST. COMMEN. (forthcoming 2007) (manuscript at 9), available at http://ssrn.com/ abstract-962142.
    • John O. McGinnis & Michael B. Rappaport, Original Interpretive Principles as the Core of Originalism, 24 CONST. COMMEN. (forthcoming 2007) (manuscript at 9), available at http://ssrn.com/ abstract-962142.
  • 59
    • 37749028268 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In this more recent work, McGinnis and Rappaport cite Powell to instruct us on the interpretive conventions of the founding generation. Id. at 8 (citing Powell, supra note 39, And Powell at least provides McGinnis and Rappaport some useful support when he announces: Although the Philadelphia framers did not discuss in detail how they intended their end product to be interpreted, they clearly assumed that future interpreters would adhere to then-prevalent methods of statutory construction. Powell, supra note 39, at 904. Moreover, there is much material in Powell that dovetails neatly with McGinnis and Rappaport's sympathy for original meaning originalism though the evidence is far from univocal on the question, However, even if these excavations are historically accurate, McGinnis and Rappaport still need an argument for why any of this history should matter. And supermajoritarianism cannot fill that gap
    • In this more recent work, McGinnis and Rappaport cite Powell to instruct us on the interpretive conventions of the founding generation. Id. at 8 (citing Powell, supra note 39). And Powell at least provides McGinnis and Rappaport some useful support when he announces: "Although the Philadelphia framers did not discuss in detail how they intended their end product to be interpreted, they clearly assumed that future interpreters would adhere to then-prevalent methods of statutory construction." Powell, supra note 39, at 904. Moreover, there is much material in Powell that dovetails neatly with McGinnis and Rappaport's sympathy for original meaning originalism (though the evidence is far from univocal on the question). However, even if these excavations are historically accurate, McGinnis and Rappaport still need an argument for why any of this history should matter. And supermajoritarianism cannot fill that gap.
  • 60
    • 37749012517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Powell argues, at the time of the enactment of the Constitution, there were sharp disagreements over which interpretive approach was acceptable. Powell, supra note 39, at 912
    • As Powell argues, at the time of the enactment of the Constitution, "there were sharp disagreements over which interpretive approach was acceptable." Powell, supra note 39, at 912.
  • 61
    • 37749047935 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 62
    • 37749043852 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ESKRIDGE ET AL., supra note 32, at 671-73 (summarizing the founding generation's eclectic approach to statutory interpretation, which included considerations of equity);
    • See ESKRIDGE ET AL., supra note 32, at 671-73 (summarizing the founding generation's eclectic approach to statutory interpretation, which included considerations of "equity");
  • 63
    • 37749013975 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Powell, supra note 39, at 887 suggesting that the interpretive conventions of some of the drafters and ratifiers of the Constitution evidenced a willingness to interpret the constitutional text in accordance with the common law principles that had been used to construe statutes
    • see also Powell, supra note 39, at 887 (suggesting that the interpretive conventions of some of the drafters and ratifiers of the Constitution evidenced a "willingness to interpret the constitutional text in accordance with the common law principles that had been used to construe statutes").
  • 64
    • 0348202109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally William N. Eskridge, Jr. & John Ferejohn, Super-Statutes, 50 DUKE L.J. 1215 (2001) (developing the idea of a super-statute that wins broad consensus and commands dynamic, rather than originalist, interpretation in the courts).
    • See generally William N. Eskridge, Jr. & John Ferejohn, Super-Statutes, 50 DUKE L.J. 1215 (2001) (developing the idea of a super-statute that wins broad consensus and commands dynamic, rather than originalist, interpretation in the courts).
  • 65
    • 37749013886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1271 (arguing that the entrenched norms of super-statutes form under conditions of consensus and require a continuing process of deliberation and consensus-building).
    • Id. at 1271 (arguing that the entrenched norms of super-statutes "form under conditions of consensus" and require "a continuing process of deliberation" and "consensus-building").
  • 66
    • 37749030863 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1234
    • Id. at 1234.
  • 67
    • 37749018601 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 68
    • 37748999922 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Another interesting aspect of Eskridge and Ferejohn's essay is their claim that super-statutes will have a gravitational pull on constitutional law itself. Id. at 1232, 1236. This highlights the challenge I offered earlier in this Essay: supermajoritarianism's legitimating force (if indeed it does do something to confer legitimacy) cannot be isolated to constitutional enactment and Article V amendment. Rather, our society will come to agreement and deliberative consensus on new principles that themselves will have special legitimacy. And these new equilibria should have and do have effects on the interpretation of the Constitution itself. Id. at 1267-76. This tends to show that a thoroughgoing commitment to supermajoritarianism does not rest well with originalism. If McGinnis and Rappaport want us to be originalists, supermajoritarianism surely doesn't get us there directly
    • Another interesting aspect of Eskridge and Ferejohn's essay is their claim that super-statutes will have a "gravitational pull on constitutional law itself." Id. at 1232, 1236. This highlights the challenge I offered earlier in this Essay: supermajoritarianism's legitimating force (if indeed it does do something to confer legitimacy) cannot be isolated to constitutional enactment and Article V amendment. Rather, our society will come to agreement and deliberative consensus on new principles that themselves will have special legitimacy. And these new equilibria should have and do have effects on the interpretation of the Constitution itself. Id. at 1267-76. This tends to show that a thoroughgoing commitment to supermajoritarianism does not rest well with originalism. If McGinnis and Rappaport want us to be originalists, supermajoritarianism surely doesn't get us there directly.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.