메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 32, Issue 6, 2004, Pages 801-824

Multiple principles of political obligation

Author keywords

Common good; Fairness; Natural duties; Political obligation

Indexed keywords


EID: 10144237215     PISSN: 00905917     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/0090591704265933     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (22)

References (108)
  • 1
    • 0003890812 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • Most notable are A. J. Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979); L. Green, The Authority of the State (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1988); J. Raz, The Authority of Law (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1979), chap. 12; M. B. E. Smith, "Is There a Prima Facie Obligation to Obey the Law?" Yale Law Journal 82 (1973). For purposes of discussion here, "political obligations" can be taken to be more or less equivalent to moral requirements to support the state or to obey the law. For basic features of political obligations, see Simmons, Moral Principles, chaps. 1 and 2; G. Klosko, The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligations, new ed. (Savage, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2004), chap. 1. I should also note that throughout, discussion is confined to laws that are reasonably just and to liberal, democratic societies that can also be assumed to be reasonably just. In the literature, it is widely believed that liberal political theory is unable to establish political obligations even in such societies. It is this contention that I attempt to refute. Although I believe that the principles I discuss can be extended to other kinds of societies (to different extents), this important subject cannot be discussed in this essay.
    • (1979) Moral Principles and Political Obligations
    • Simmons, A.J.1
  • 2
    • 0004048651 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press
    • Most notable are A. J. Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979); L. Green, The Authority of the State (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1988); J. Raz, The Authority of Law (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1979), chap. 12; M. B. E. Smith, "Is There a Prima Facie Obligation to Obey the Law?" Yale Law Journal 82 (1973). For purposes of discussion here, "political obligations" can be taken to be more or less equivalent to moral requirements to support the state or to obey the law. For basic features of political obligations, see Simmons, Moral Principles, chaps. 1 and 2; G. Klosko, The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligations, new ed. (Savage, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2004), chap. 1. I should also note that throughout, discussion is confined to laws that are reasonably just and to liberal, democratic societies that can also be assumed to be reasonably just. In the literature, it is widely believed that liberal political theory is unable to establish political obligations even in such societies. It is this contention that I attempt to refute. Although I believe that the principles I discuss can be extended to other kinds of societies (to different extents), this important subject cannot be discussed in this essay.
    • (1988) The Authority of the State
    • Green, L.1
  • 3
    • 0003880778 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, chap. 12
    • Most notable are A. J. Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979); L. Green, The Authority of the State (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1988); J. Raz, The Authority of Law (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1979), chap. 12; M. B. E. Smith, "Is There a Prima Facie Obligation to Obey the Law?" Yale Law Journal 82 (1973). For purposes of discussion here, "political obligations" can be taken to be more or less equivalent to moral requirements to support the state or to obey the law. For basic features of political obligations, see Simmons, Moral Principles, chaps. 1 and 2; G. Klosko, The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligations, new ed. (Savage, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2004), chap. 1. I should also note that throughout, discussion is confined to laws that are reasonably just and to liberal, democratic societies that can also be assumed to be reasonably just. In the literature, it is widely believed that liberal political theory is unable to establish political obligations even in such societies. It is this contention that I attempt to refute. Although I believe that the principles I discuss can be extended to other kinds of societies (to different extents), this important subject cannot be discussed in this essay.
    • (1979) The Authority of Law
    • Raz, J.1
  • 4
    • 0000516383 scopus 로고
    • Is there a prima facie obligation to obey the law?
    • Most notable are A. J. Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979); L. Green, The Authority of the State (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1988); J. Raz, The Authority of Law (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1979), chap. 12; M. B. E. Smith, "Is There a Prima Facie Obligation to Obey the Law?" Yale Law Journal 82 (1973). For purposes of discussion here, "political obligations" can be taken to be more or less equivalent to moral requirements to support the state or to obey the law. For basic features of political obligations, see Simmons, Moral Principles, chaps. 1 and 2; G. Klosko, The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligations, new ed. (Savage, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2004), chap. 1. I should also note that throughout, discussion is confined to laws that are reasonably just and to liberal, democratic societies that can also be assumed to be reasonably just. In the literature, it is widely believed that liberal political theory is unable to establish political obligations even in such societies. It is this contention that I attempt to refute. Although I believe that the principles I discuss can be extended to other kinds of societies (to different extents), this important subject cannot be discussed in this essay.
    • (1973) Yale Law Journal , vol.82
    • Smith, M.B.E.1
  • 5
    • 0004344619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chaps. 1 and 2
    • Most notable are A. J. Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979); L. Green, The Authority of the State (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1988); J. Raz, The Authority of Law (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1979), chap. 12; M. B. E. Smith, "Is There a Prima Facie Obligation to Obey the Law?" Yale Law Journal 82 (1973). For purposes of discussion here, "political obligations" can be taken to be more or less equivalent to moral requirements to support the state or to obey the law. For basic features of political obligations, see Simmons, Moral Principles, chaps. 1 and 2; G. Klosko, The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligations, new ed. (Savage, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2004), chap. 1. I should also note that throughout, discussion is confined to laws that are reasonably just and to liberal, democratic societies that can also be assumed to be reasonably just. In the literature, it is widely believed that liberal political theory is unable to establish political obligations even in such societies. It is this contention that I attempt to refute. Although I believe that the principles I discuss can be extended to other kinds of societies (to different extents), this important subject cannot be discussed in this essay.
    • Moral Principles
    • Simmons1
  • 6
    • 10144226200 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • new ed. Savage, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, chap. 1
    • Most notable are A. J. Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979); L. Green, The Authority of the State (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1988); J. Raz, The Authority of Law (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1979), chap. 12; M. B. E. Smith, "Is There a Prima Facie Obligation to Obey the Law?" Yale Law Journal 82 (1973). For purposes of discussion here, "political obligations" can be taken to be more or less equivalent to moral requirements to support the state or to obey the law. For basic features of political obligations, see Simmons, Moral Principles, chaps. 1 and 2; G. Klosko, The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligations, new ed. (Savage, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2004), chap. 1. I should also note that throughout, discussion is confined to laws that are reasonably just and to liberal, democratic societies that can also be assumed to be reasonably just. In the literature, it is widely believed that liberal political theory is unable to establish political obligations even in such societies. It is this contention that I attempt to refute. Although I believe that the principles I discuss can be extended to other kinds of societies (to different extents), this important subject cannot be discussed in this essay.
    • (2004) The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligations
    • Klosko, G.1
  • 7
    • 0004344619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 2
    • For different accounts of the requirements theories of political obligation should satisfy, see Simmons, Moral Principles, chap. 2; Klosko, Principle of Fairness, 2-6; J. Wolff, "Political Obligation: A Pluralistic Approach," in Pluralism: The Philosophy and Politics of Diversity, ed. M. Baghramian and A. Ingram (London: Routledge, 2000), 182-87.
    • Moral Principles
    • Simmons1
  • 8
    • 0040610230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For different accounts of the requirements theories of political obligation should satisfy, see Simmons, Moral Principles, chap. 2; Klosko, Principle of Fairness, 2-6; J. Wolff, "Political Obligation: A Pluralistic Approach," in Pluralism: The Philosophy and Politics of Diversity, ed. M. Baghramian and A. Ingram (London: Routledge, 2000), 182-87.
    • Principle of Fairness , pp. 2-6
    • Klosko1
  • 9
    • 0142251930 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political obligation: A pluralistic approach
    • ed. M. Baghramian and A. Ingram London: Routledge
    • For different accounts of the requirements theories of political obligation should satisfy, see Simmons, Moral Principles, chap. 2; Klosko, Principle of Fairness, 2-6; J. Wolff, "Political Obligation: A Pluralistic Approach," in Pluralism: The Philosophy and Politics of Diversity, ed. M. Baghramian and A. Ingram (London: Routledge, 2000), 182-87.
    • (2000) Pluralism: The Philosophy and Politics of Diversity , pp. 182-187
    • Wolff, J.1
  • 10
    • 0004344619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Simmons also examines consequentialist and "conceptual" arguments, though he devotes less attention to them
    • Simmons, Moral Principles. Simmons also examines consequentialist and "conceptual" arguments, though he devotes less attention to them. Similar approaches are employed by Smith, "Prima Facie Obligation"; Raz, Authority of Law; and R. Dworkin, Law's Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986), chap. 6.
    • Moral Principles
    • Simmons1
  • 11
    • 10144247044 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Simmons, Moral Principles. Simmons also examines consequentialist and "conceptual" arguments, though he devotes less attention to them. Similar approaches are employed by Smith, "Prima Facie Obligation"; Raz, Authority of Law; and R. Dworkin, Law's Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986), chap. 6.
    • Prima Facie Obligation
    • Smith1
  • 12
    • 0003880778 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Simmons, Moral Principles. Simmons also examines consequentialist and "conceptual" arguments, though he devotes less attention to them. Similar approaches are employed by Smith, "Prima Facie Obligation"; Raz, Authority of Law; and R. Dworkin, Law's Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986), chap. 6.
    • Authority of Law
    • Raz1
  • 13
    • 84936068266 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, chap. 6
    • Simmons, Moral Principles. Simmons also examines consequentialist and "conceptual" arguments, though he devotes less attention to them. Similar approaches are employed by Smith, "Prima Facie Obligation"; Raz, Authority of Law; and R. Dworkin, Law's Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986), chap. 6.
    • (1986) Law's Empire
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 14
    • 0004344619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Simmons explicitly rejects the "universality" requirement that a single principle must account for all political obligations (Moral Principles, 35). The main previous work with a "multiprinciple" approach is Wolff, "Political Obligation," to which I am indebted. The approach is suggested in Klosko, Principle of Fairness, 98-99; see also C. Gans, Philosophical Anarchism and Political Disobedience (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1992), which does not work out the details of the position.
    • Moral Principles , pp. 35
  • 15
    • 0040610230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Simmons explicitly rejects the "universality" requirement that a single principle must account for all political obligations (Moral Principles, 35). The main previous work with a "multiprinciple" approach is Wolff, "Political Obligation," to which I am indebted. The approach is suggested in Klosko, Principle of Fairness, 98-99; see also C. Gans, Philosophical Anarchism and Political Disobedience (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1992), which does not work out the details of the position.
    • Principle of Fairness , pp. 98-99
    • Klosko1
  • 16
    • 0043083076 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
    • Simmons explicitly rejects the "universality" requirement that a single principle must account for all political obligations (Moral Principles, 35). The main previous work with a "multiprinciple" approach is Wolff, "Political Obligation," to which I am indebted. The approach is suggested in Klosko, Principle of Fairness, 98-99; see also C. Gans, Philosophical Anarchism and Political Disobedience (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1992), which does not work out the details of the position.
    • (1992) Philosophical Anarchism and Political Disobedience
    • Gans, C.1
  • 18
    • 0035402785 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Toward a liberal theory of political obligation
    • C. Wellman, "Toward a Liberal Theory of Political Obligation," Ethics 111 (2001).
    • (2001) Ethics , vol.111
    • Wellman, C.1
  • 19
    • 0004344619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See note 3. I should note that, after refuting the principles separately, Simmons claims that a combination of them will not satisfy the generality requirement (Moral Principles, 191). I am indebted to an anonymous reader for this point.
    • Moral Principles , pp. 191
  • 20
    • 0004344619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The term is taken from Simmons, Moral Principles, 55-56. For reasons of space, I cannot discuss additional requirements, although I believe the position developed here could address them.
    • Moral Principles , pp. 55-56
    • Simmons1
  • 22
    • 84981677015 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The best defense of consent theory in the literature is Beran, Consent Theory; his position is criticized in G. Klosko, "Reformist Consent and Political Obligation," Political Studies 39 (1991).
    • Consent Theory
    • Beran1
  • 23
    • 84981677015 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reformist consent and political obligation
    • The best defense of consent theory in the literature is Beran, Consent Theory; his position is criticized in G. Klosko, "Reformist Consent and Political Obligation," Political Studies 39 (1991).
    • (1991) Political Studies , vol.39
    • Klosko, G.1
  • 24
    • 10144254229 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • My focus on the comprehensiveness requirement might seem unusual, because we might simply assume that a theory of obligation will explain obligations to obey the law across the board, rather than only some laws, with additional principles required for other laws. The problem, however, is that at the current time no theory is generally viewed as able to do this. Multiple principle (MP) theory, even with its unconventional approach to comprehensiveness, appears to be the only alternative to no satisfactory theory at all.
  • 25
    • 10144257682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Mutual support and overlap are closely related. But in cases that involve the former, a single principle is not able to generate a given moral requirement without the help of another. With overlap, both principles A and B are able to generate independent moral requirements, which are strengthened by having the same (or closely similar) application.
  • 26
    • 10144227574 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Especially notable is a general duty to obey the law based on the contention that law is a seamless web, and so violation of any given law undermines the legal system as a whole. Although this is potentially an important argument, it raises many questions that cannot be addressed in this essay.
  • 27
    • 0004344619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 4
    • An excellent account is Simmons, Moral Principles, chap. 4. For the distinction between express and tacit consent, see J. Locke, Second Treatise of Civil Government, sees. 119-22.
    • Moral Principles
    • Simmons1
  • 28
    • 0004227351 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An excellent account is Simmons, Moral Principles, chap. 4. For the distinction between express and tacit consent, see J. Locke, Second Treatise of Civil Government, sees. 119-22.
    • Second Treatise of Civil Government , pp. 119-122
    • Locke, J.1
  • 30
    • 10144263111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Because of difficulties identifying individuals who have clearly consented to government - aside from naturalized citizens - consent contributes little to MP theory as developed below, though of course, it is an important source of obligations for individuals who have consented.
  • 31
    • 0000982081 scopus 로고
    • Are there any natural rights?
    • H. L. A. Hart, "Are There Any Natural Rights?" Philosophical Review 64 (1955): 185. For full discussion of political obligations based on the principle of fairness, see Klosko, Principle of Fairness.
    • (1955) Philosophical Review , vol.64 , pp. 185
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 32
    • 0040610230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • H. L. A. Hart, "Are There Any Natural Rights?" Philosophical Review 64 (1955): 185. For full discussion of political obligations based on the principle of fairness, see Klosko, Principle of Fairness.
    • Principle of Fairness
    • Klosko1
  • 33
    • 0004214471 scopus 로고
    • Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press
    • D. Lyons, Forms and Limits of Utilitarianism (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1965), 164; J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 112. The underlying moral principle is analyzed by R. Arneson, "The Principle of Fairness and Free-Rider Problems," Ethics 92 (1982); see also C. Strang, "What If Everyone Did That?" Durham University Journal 53 (1960).
    • (1965) Forms and Limits of Utilitarianism , pp. 164
    • Lyons, D.1
  • 34
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • D. Lyons, Forms and Limits of Utilitarianism (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1965), 164; J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 112. The underlying moral principle is analyzed by R. Arneson, "The Principle of Fairness and Free-Rider Problems," Ethics 92 (1982); see also C. Strang, "What If Everyone Did That?" Durham University Journal 53 (1960).
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice , pp. 112
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 35
    • 0001207085 scopus 로고
    • The principle of fairness and free-rider problems
    • D. Lyons, Forms and Limits of Utilitarianism (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1965), 164; J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 112. The underlying moral principle is analyzed by R. Arneson, "The Principle of Fairness and Free-Rider Problems," Ethics 92 (1982); see also C. Strang, "What If Everyone Did That?" Durham University Journal 53 (1960).
    • (1982) Ethics , vol.92
    • Arneson, R.1
  • 36
    • 0039424783 scopus 로고
    • What if everyone did that?
    • D. Lyons, Forms and Limits of Utilitarianism (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1965), 164; J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 112. The underlying moral principle is analyzed by R. Arneson, "The Principle of Fairness and Free-Rider Problems," Ethics 92 (1982); see also C. Strang, "What If Everyone Did That?" Durham University Journal 53 (1960).
    • (1960) Durham University Journal , vol.53
    • Strang, C.1
  • 37
    • 10144263733 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In such cases, we can assume that, if the benefit can be withheld from A, it should be his decision whether he should receive it at the specified price. Within the liberal tradition, liberty is a central value. The decision whether A will have his liberty curtailed by having to contribute to a cooperative scheme should be made by him rather than by the scheme members.
  • 38
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The need to accept benefits is noted by Rawls, Theory of Justice, 113-16; similarly, R. Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), 95; Dworkin, Law's Empire, 192-93.
    • Theory of Justice , pp. 113-116
    • Rawls1
  • 39
    • 0004273805 scopus 로고
    • New York: Basic Books
    • The need to accept benefits is noted by Rawls, Theory of Justice, 113-16; similarly, R. Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), 95; Dworkin, Law's Empire, 192-93.
    • (1974) Anarchy, State, and Utopia , pp. 95
    • Nozick, R.1
  • 40
    • 84936068266 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The need to accept benefits is noted by Rawls, Theory of Justice, 113-16; similarly, R. Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), 95; Dworkin, Law's Empire, 192-93.
    • Law's Empire , pp. 192-193
    • Dworkin1
  • 41
    • 0040610230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For reasons of space, I discuss only (i) and (ii) in this essay. Throughout, I assume that (iii) is met. For discussion of these and other aspects of the principle, see Klosko, Principle of Fairness.
    • Principle of Fairness
    • Klosko1
  • 42
    • 10144250074 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Though I will not discuss other possible members of this class, I do not rule them out
    • Though I will not discuss other possible members of this class, I do not rule them out.
  • 43
    • 0040610230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 2, which also considers and counters other possible arguments against obligations in these cases.
    • Discussion here draws on Klosko, Principle of Fairness, chap. 2, which also considers and counters other possible arguments against obligations in these cases. Important, recent criticisms of the position presented here are presented by A. J. Simmons, On the Edge of Anarchy (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993), chap. 8; and Justification and Legitimacy (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2001), chap. 2. A response to the former is presented in G. Klosko, "The Natural Basis of Political Obligation," Social Philosophy and Policy 18 (2001). In regard to the latter, note the example of the well Simmons uses on page 34. This is a poor example, because, as Simmons presents it, the benefit in question is easily supplied through the labor of one person, in contrast to the indispensable public goods discussed throughout this essay.
    • Principle of Fairness
    • Klosko1
  • 44
    • 0010195165 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, chap. 8
    • Discussion here draws on Klosko, Principle of Fairness, chap. 2, which also considers and counters other possible arguments against obligations in these cases. Important, recent criticisms of the position presented here are presented by A. J. Simmons, On the Edge of Anarchy (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993), chap. 8; and Justification and Legitimacy (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2001), chap. 2. A response to the former is presented in G. Klosko, "The Natural Basis of Political Obligation," Social Philosophy and Policy 18 (2001). In regard to the latter, note the example of the well Simmons uses on page 34. This is a poor example, because, as Simmons presents it, the benefit in question is easily supplied through the labor of one person, in contrast to the indispensable public goods discussed throughout this essay.
    • (1993) On the Edge of Anarchy
    • Simmons, A.J.1
  • 45
    • 0009267278 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, chap. 2
    • Discussion here draws on Klosko, Principle of Fairness, chap. 2, which also considers and counters other possible arguments against obligations in these cases. Important, recent criticisms of the position presented here are presented by A. J. Simmons, On the Edge of Anarchy (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993), chap. 8; and Justification and Legitimacy (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2001), chap. 2. A response to the former is presented in G. Klosko, "The Natural Basis of Political Obligation," Social Philosophy and Policy 18 (2001). In regard to the latter, note the example of the well Simmons uses on page 34. This is a poor example, because, as Simmons presents it, the benefit in question is easily supplied through the labor of one person, in contrast to the indispensable public goods discussed throughout this essay.
    • (2001) Justification and Legitimacy
  • 46
    • 8344275996 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The natural basis of political obligation
    • Discussion here draws on Klosko, Principle of Fairness, chap. 2, which also considers and counters other possible arguments against obligations in these cases. Important, recent criticisms of the position presented here are presented by A. J. Simmons, On the Edge of Anarchy (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993), chap. 8; and Justification and Legitimacy (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2001), chap. 2. A response to the former is presented in G. Klosko, "The Natural Basis of Political Obligation," Social Philosophy and Policy 18 (2001). In regard to the latter, note the example of the well Simmons uses on page 34. This is a poor example, because, as Simmons presents it, the benefit in question is easily supplied through the labor of one person, in contrast to the indispensable public goods discussed throughout this essay.
    • (2001) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.18
    • Klosko, G.1
  • 48
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • J. Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), 54-58.
    • (1993) Political Liberalism , pp. 54-58
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 49
    • 0040610230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 3
    • For discussion, see Klosko, Principle of Fairness, chap. 3. Similar procedures should be used to determine the form in which indispensable public goods are supplied.
    • Principle of Fairness
    • Klosko1
  • 50
    • 10144246377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Self-benefit principle
    • See Arneson's discussion of the "self-benefit principle" ("Principle of Fairness").
    • Principle of Fairness
    • Arneson1
  • 51
    • 10144247045 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The claim in this essay is not that such services must necessarily be provided by the state but only that, if the state does provide them, this must be justified.
  • 52
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, Theory of Justice , sees. 19 and 51; Simmons, Moral Principles, chap. 6; J. Waldron, "Special Ties and Natural Duties," Philosophy and Public Affairs 22 (1993); G. Klosko, "Political Obligation and the Natural Duties of Justice," Philosophy and Public Affairs 23 (1994).
    • Theory of Justice , pp. 19
    • Rawls1
  • 53
    • 0004344619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 6
    • Rawls, Theory of Justice , sees. 19 and 51; Simmons, Moral Principles, chap. 6; J. Waldron, "Special Ties and Natural Duties," Philosophy and Public Affairs 22 (1993); G. Klosko, "Political Obligation and the Natural Duties of Justice," Philosophy and Public Affairs 23 (1994).
    • Moral Principles
    • Simmons1
  • 54
    • 84860836792 scopus 로고
    • Special ties and natural duties
    • Rawls, Theory of Justice , sees. 19 and 51; Simmons, Moral Principles, chap. 6; J. Waldron, "Special Ties and Natural Duties," Philosophy and Public Affairs 22 (1993); G. Klosko, "Political Obligation and the Natural Duties of Justice," Philosophy and Public Affairs 23 (1994).
    • (1993) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.22
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 55
    • 85023995431 scopus 로고
    • Political obligation and the natural duties of justice
    • Rawls, Theory of Justice , sees. 19 and 51; Simmons, Moral Principles, chap. 6; J. Waldron, "Special Ties and Natural Duties," Philosophy and Public Affairs 22 (1993); G. Klosko, "Political Obligation and the Natural Duties of Justice," Philosophy and Public Affairs 23 (1994).
    • (1994) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.23
    • Klosko, G.1
  • 58
    • 79957519447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • additional natural duties are discussed in sec. 51
    • Ibid., 337; additional natural duties are discussed in sec. 51.
    • Theory of Justice , pp. 337
  • 60
    • 0004344619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Simmons also divorces the natural duties from the context of the original position (Moral Principles, 143-44).
    • Moral Principles , pp. 143-144
  • 62
    • 0003439620 scopus 로고
    • Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press
    • For an excellent defense of a duty of mutual aid, see J. Feinberg, Harm to Others (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1984), 126-86. For survey research on attitudes toward the natural duties, see D. Klein and G. Klosko, "Political Obligation: The Empirical Approach" (paper presented at the 2001 meeting of the American Political Science Association, San Francisco). Subjects were University of Virginia undergraduates; although Ns are small and the sample not representative of the American population, the percentages are striking.
    • (1984) Harm to Others , pp. 126-186
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 63
    • 10144264380 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political obligation: The empirical approach
    • paper presented
    • For an excellent defense of a duty of mutual aid, see J. Feinberg, Harm to Others (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1984), 126-86. For survey research on attitudes toward the natural duties, see D. Klein and G. Klosko, "Political Obligation: The Empirical Approach" (paper presented at the 2001 meeting of the American Political Science Association, San Francisco). Subjects were University of Virginia undergraduates; although Ns are small and the sample not representative of the American population, the percentages are striking.
    • 2001 Meeting of the American Political Science Association, San Francisco
    • Klein, D.1    Klosko, G.2
  • 67
    • 79957519447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 334, 115. Simmons, for one, appears to attach the cost qualifier to both political duties (Moral Principles, 193; see also 154); Waldron does not discuss the question of costs in "Special Ties."
    • Theory of Justice , pp. 334
  • 68
    • 0004344619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 334, 115. Simmons, for one, appears to attach the cost qualifier to both political duties (Moral Principles, 193; see also 154); Waldron does not discuss the question of costs in "Special Ties."
    • Moral Principles , pp. 193
    • Simmons1
  • 69
    • 10144240846 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 334, 115. Simmons, for one, appears to attach the cost qualifier to both political duties (Moral Principles, 193; see also 154); Waldron does not discuss the question of costs in "Special Ties."
    • Special Ties
    • Waldron1
  • 71
    • 10144235305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the first of the political duties not to be qualified in regard to cost while all other natural duties are would require explanation. This difference would suggest the likelihood of further, deeper differences and that the duty to comply's derivation would differ from those of the other duties; for discussion, see Klosko, "Natural Duties."
    • Natural Duties
    • Klosko1
  • 72
    • 10144222716 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wellman's principle of samaratinism is similarly cost-qualified, "Toward a Liberal Theory," 744, 748, 752 n. 21.
    • Toward a Liberal Theory , Issue.21 , pp. 744
    • Wellman1
  • 73
    • 0142219332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Samaritanism and political obligation: A response to Christopher Wellman's 'liberal theory of political obligation'
    • For criticisms of Wellman's position in regard to cost, see G. Klosko, "Samaritanism and Political Obligation: A Response to Christopher Wellman's 'Liberal Theory of Political Obligation,'" Ethics 113 (2003).
    • (2003) Ethics , vol.113
    • Klosko, G.1
  • 74
    • 10144226198 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What do countries really spend on social policies? A comparative note
    • For levels of social spending in different countries, see W. Adema, "What Do Countries Really Spend on Social Policies? A Comparative Note," OECD Economic Studies 28 (1997).
    • (1997) OECD Economic Studies , vol.28
    • Adema, W.1
  • 75
    • 0004344619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Simmons, Moral Principles, 31-35. I assume the legitimacy of requiring that natural duties of justice be fulfilled by supporting state agencies. For discussion, see Daniel McDermott, "Natural Duties and State Legitimacy" (paper presented at the 2001 meeting of the American Political Science Association, San Francisco).
    • Moral Principles , pp. 31-35
    • Simmons1
  • 76
    • 10144242460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Natural duties and state legitimacy
    • paper presented
    • Simmons, Moral Principles, 31-35. I assume the legitimacy of requiring that natural duties of justice be fulfilled by supporting state agencies. For discussion, see Daniel McDermott, "Natural Duties and State Legitimacy" (paper presented at the 2001 meeting of the American Political Science Association, San Francisco).
    • 2001 Meeting of the American Political Science Association, San Francisco
    • McDermott, D.1
  • 77
    • 0004344619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 6
    • For problems with Rawls's view in this regard, see Simmons, Moral Principles, chap. 6.
    • Moral Principles
    • Simmons1
  • 78
    • 84931428234 scopus 로고
    • What is so special about our fellow countrymen?
    • See, for example, R. Goodin, "What Is So Special about Our Fellow Countrymen?" Ethics 98 (1988); C. Wellman, "Relational Facts in Liberal Political Theory: Is There Magic in the Pronoun 'My'?" Ethics 110 (2000). The latter is criticized by C. Coons, "Wellman's 'Reductive' Justifications for Redistributive Policies That Favor Compatriots," Ethics 111 (2001).
    • (1988) Ethics , vol.98
    • Goodin, R.1
  • 79
    • 0034164763 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Relational facts in liberal political theory: Is there magic in the pronoun 'my'?
    • See, for example, R. Goodin, "What Is So Special about Our Fellow Countrymen?" Ethics 98 (1988); C. Wellman, "Relational Facts in Liberal Political Theory: Is There Magic in the Pronoun 'My'?" Ethics 110 (2000). The latter is criticized by C. Coons, "Wellman's 'Reductive' Justifications for Redistributive Policies That Favor Compatriots," Ethics 111 (2001).
    • (2000) Ethics , vol.110
    • Wellman, C.1
  • 80
    • 0035402626 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wellman's 'reductive' justifications for redistributive policies that favor compatriots
    • See, for example, R. Goodin, "What Is So Special about Our Fellow Countrymen?" Ethics 98 (1988); C. Wellman, "Relational Facts in Liberal Political Theory: Is There Magic in the Pronoun 'My'?" Ethics 110 (2000). The latter is criticized by C. Coons, "Wellman's 'Reductive' Justifications for Redistributive Policies That Favor Compatriots," Ethics 111 (2001).
    • (2001) Ethics , vol.111
    • Coons, C.1
  • 81
    • 10144240845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Philosophical Anarchism, Gans attempts to solve the particularity problem by combining natural duty and "communal" (association) principles (pp. 81-82).
    • Philosophical Anarchism , pp. 81-82
    • Gans1
  • 82
    • 0004344619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Notably, Simmons, Moral Principles; this is also true of public choice theorists, for example, M. Taylor, The Possibility of Cooperation (Cambridge. UK: Cambridge University Press, 1987). For discussion, see Klosko, "Natural Basis."
    • Moral Principles
    • Simmons1
  • 83
    • 0004052665 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge. UK: Cambridge University Press
    • Notably, Simmons, Moral Principles; this is also true of public choice theorists, for example, M. Taylor, The Possibility of Cooperation (Cambridge. UK: Cambridge University Press, 1987). For discussion, see Klosko, "Natural Basis."
    • (1987) The Possibility of Cooperation
    • Taylor, M.1
  • 84
    • 10144254905 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Notably, Simmons, Moral Principles; this is also true of public choice theorists, for example, M. Taylor, The Possibility of Cooperation (Cambridge. UK: Cambridge University Press, 1987). For discussion, see Klosko, "Natural Basis."
    • Natural Basis
    • Klosko1
  • 86
    • 0002169439 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cosmopolitan respect and patriotic concern
    • See R. Miller, "Cosmopolitan Respect and Patriotic Concern," Philosophy and Public Affairs 27 (1998). I should note that this does not justify blackmail by Grey's fellow citizens, that it is legitimate for them not to obey the law unless they are bribed with social welfare programs. As indicated, the primary reason to address their needs is recognition and reciprocation, but these pragmatic considerations are also relevant and should be mentioned. I am grateful to anonymous readers of this journal for discussion on this point.
    • (1998) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.27
    • Miller, R.1
  • 87
    • 10144245094 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For discussion of this point, I am indebted to David Klein
    • For discussion of this point, I am indebted to David Klein.
  • 88
    • 10144258469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For convenience, in various contexts below, I will not mention supply of necessary discretionary goods covered by the indirect argument along with goods that are themselves indispensable. Their inclusion can be assumed.
  • 89
    • 84861979919 scopus 로고
    • ed. E. Mossner Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin, 8
    • D. Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. E. Mossner (Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin, 1969), III, ii, 8, p. 590. Although the examples that Hume provides are public goods, "common provisions" under CG will also include excludable goods, if these satisfy the conditions discussed below.
    • (1969) A Treatise of Human Nature , vol.3 , Issue.2 , pp. 590
    • Hume, D.1
  • 90
    • 10144226889 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am grateful to an anonymous reader for discussion of this point
    • I am grateful to an anonymous reader for discussion of this point.
  • 91
    • 10144245095 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. note above
    • Cf. note above.
  • 92
    • 84936068266 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, Law's Empire, 196-216; J. Horton, Political Obligation (London: Macmillan, 1992), chap. 6; also, M. Gilbert, "Group Membership and Political Obligation," Monist 76 (1993).
    • Law's Empire , pp. 196-216
    • Dworkin1
  • 93
    • 0004295247 scopus 로고
    • London: Macmillan, chap. 6
    • Dworkin, Law's Empire, 196-216; J. Horton, Political Obligation (London: Macmillan, 1992), chap. 6; also, M. Gilbert, "Group Membership and Political Obligation," Monist 76 (1993).
    • (1992) Political Obligation
    • Horton, J.1
  • 94
    • 84921941517 scopus 로고
    • Group membership and political obligation
    • Dworkin, Law's Empire, 196-216; J. Horton, Political Obligation (London: Macmillan, 1992), chap. 6; also, M. Gilbert, "Group Membership and Political Obligation," Monist 76 (1993).
    • (1993) Monist , vol.76
    • Gilbert, M.1
  • 95
    • 0001556235 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Associative political obligations
    • See A. J. Simmons, "Associative Political Obligations," Ethics 106 (1996); but see the response of J. Horton, "Political Obligation, Identity, and Political Community" (paper presented at the 2001 meeting of the American Political Science Association, San Francisco).
    • (1996) Ethics , vol.106
    • Simmons, A.J.1
  • 96
    • 0001556235 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political obligation, identity, and political community
    • paper presented
    • See A. J. Simmons, "Associative Political Obligations," Ethics 106 (1996); but see the response of J. Horton, "Political Obligation, Identity, and Political Community" (paper presented at the 2001 meeting of the American Political Science Association, San Francisco).
    • 2001 Meeting of the American Political Science Association, San Francisco
    • Horton, J.1
  • 97
    • 84925931073 scopus 로고
    • Public goods and the theory of government
    • J. Kalt, "Public Goods and the Theory of Government," Cato Journal 1 (1981): 580.
    • (1981) Cato Journal , vol.1 , pp. 580
    • Kalt, J.1
  • 98
    • 10144226199 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • A possible problem with the common good principle (CG) is that common provisions are frequently not public goods but excludable. This implies that, ordinarily, they should be funded through user fees, although considerations of social justice could require that economically disadvantaged members of society have access. Exploration of these issues is beyond the scope of this essay.
  • 99
  • 101
    • 84921981845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, chap. 8
    • Empirical evidence suggests that there is greater agreements on fair procedures than on fair distribution; for discussion, see G. Klosko, Democratic Procedures and Liberal Consensus (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2000), chap. 8.
    • (2000) Democratic Procedures and Liberal Consensus
    • Klosko, G.1
  • 102
    • 0004344619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Simmons, Moral Principles, 65-68. As is clear in the philosophy of Rousseau, rights to participate by themselves do not provide adequate safeguards.
    • Moral Principles , pp. 65-68
    • Simmons1
  • 103
    • 85047372223 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia, 93-95. For discussion of the example, see Klosko, Principle of Fairness, chap. 2.
    • Anarchy, State, and Utopia , pp. 93-95
    • Nozick1
  • 104
    • 0040610230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 2
    • Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia, 93-95. For discussion of the example, see Klosko, Principle of Fairness, chap. 2.
    • Principle of Fairness
    • Klosko1
  • 105
    • 84928458490 scopus 로고
    • The anarchist position: A reply to klosko and senor
    • his emphasis
    • A. J. Simmons, "The Anarchist Position: A Reply to Klosko and Senor," Philosophy and Public Affairs 16 (1987): 274 (his emphasis).
    • (1987) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.16 , pp. 274
    • Simmons, A.J.1
  • 106
    • 10144225424 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • CG also works reciprocally to establish obligations in regard to indispensable public goods, though I of course view this as a strength rather than a weakness of MP theory.
  • 107
    • 10144245093 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It is worth noting that an additional advantage of increasing the number of principles involved in MP theory is that, if one principle is refuted, the theory could still ground comprehensive general political obligations through operation of the remaining principles.
  • 108
    • 10144221132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Previous versions of this essay were presented at the College of William and Mary and to the University of Virginia Political Theory Colloquium. I am grateful to both audiences and to many colleagues and friends for helpful comments. These include Lawrie Balfour, Colin Bird, Richard Dagger, Joshua Dienstag, David Klein, Don Moon, Peter Rinderle, Stephen White, Jonathan Wolff, and my anonymous readers.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.