메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 18, Issue 1, 2001, Pages 93-114

The natural basis of political obligation

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 8344275996     PISSN: 02650525     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0265052501181045     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (6)

References (103)
  • 1
    • 85037272962 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • To avoid unnecessary complexity, I discuss liberal theory on a general level and am not concerned with questions of precise definition. As I use the term, the liberal tradition has at its center the individual and his rights, more or less regardless of how these rights are established and regardless of whether they extend beyond the essentially negative rights of classical liberalism to encompass economic and other welfare rights. Thus, in addition to Locke, Montesquieu, and Mill, this view includes Hobhouse and both Rawls and Nozick.
  • 2
    • 8344270957 scopus 로고
    • The Second Treatise of Government, in Locke, ed. Peter Laslett Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • John Locke, The Second Treatise of Government, in Locke, Two Treatises of Government, ed. Peter Laslett (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988); "Declaration of Independence," reprinted in Alexander Hamilton, John Jay, and James Madison, The Federalist (New York: Modern Library, n.d.), 619-22.
    • (1988) Two Treatises of Government
    • Locke, J.1
  • 3
    • 85037289465 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Declaration of Independence
    • reprinted in New York: Modern Library, n.d.
    • John Locke, The Second Treatise of Government, in Locke, Two Treatises of Government, ed. Peter Laslett (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988); "Declaration of Independence," reprinted in Alexander Hamilton, John Jay, and James Madison, The Federalist (New York: Modern Library, n.d.), 619-22.
    • The Federalist , pp. 619-622
    • Hamilton, A.1    Jay, J.2    Madison, J.3
  • 4
    • 0003364505 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of the Original Contract
    • Hume, ed. Eugene Miller, rev. ed. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Classics
    • David Hume, "Of the Original Contract," in Hume, Essays, Moral, Political, and Literary, ed. Eugene Miller, rev. ed. (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Classics, 1985). See also the important discussion of A. John Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979), chaps. 3 and 4.
    • (1985) Essays, Moral, Political, and Literary
    • Hume, D.1
  • 5
    • 0003890812 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, chaps. 3 and 4
    • David Hume, "Of the Original Contract," in Hume, Essays, Moral, Political, and Literary, ed. Eugene Miller, rev. ed. (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Classics, 1985). See also the important discussion of A. John Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979), chaps. 3 and 4.
    • (1979) Moral Principles and Political Obligations
    • Simmons, A.J.1
  • 6
    • 84959651776 scopus 로고
    • Obligation and Consent
    • December
    • See Hannah Pitkin, "Obligation and Consent," American Political Science Review 59, no. 4 (December 1955): 990-99; Jeremy Waldron, "Theoretical Foundations of Liberalism," Philosophical Quarterly 37, no. 147 (April 1987): 127-50; and Immanuel Kant, "On the Common Saying: 'This May Be True in Theory, but It Does Not Apply in Practice,'" in Kant, Kant's Political Writings, ed. Hans Reiss (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970).
    • (1955) American Political Science Review , vol.59 , Issue.4 , pp. 990-999
    • Pitkin, H.1
  • 7
    • 77951897375 scopus 로고
    • Theoretical Foundations of Liberalism
    • April
    • See Hannah Pitkin, "Obligation and Consent," American Political Science Review 59, no. 4 (December 1955): 990-99; Jeremy Waldron, "Theoretical Foundations of Liberalism," Philosophical Quarterly 37, no. 147 (April 1987): 127-50; and Immanuel Kant, "On the Common Saying: 'This May Be True in Theory, but It Does Not Apply in Practice,'" in Kant, Kant's Political Writings, ed. Hans Reiss (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970).
    • (1987) Philosophical Quarterly , vol.37 , Issue.147 , pp. 127-150
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 8
    • 84959651776 scopus 로고
    • On the Common Saying: 'This May Be True in Theory, but It Does Not Apply in Practice,'
    • Kant, Kant's ed. Hans Reiss Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See Hannah Pitkin, "Obligation and Consent," American Political Science Review 59, no. 4 (December 1955): 990-99; Jeremy Waldron, "Theoretical Foundations of Liberalism," Philosophical Quarterly 37, no. 147 (April 1987): 127-50; and Immanuel Kant, "On the Common Saying: 'This May Be True in Theory, but It Does Not Apply in Practice,'" in Kant, Kant's Political Writings, ed. Hans Reiss (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970).
    • (1970) Political Writings
    • Kant, I.1
  • 9
    • 0032219767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Savage, MD: Rowman and Littlefield
    • A full exposition of fairness theory, on which I will draw here, can be found in George Klosko, The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation (Savage, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1992). Other grounds of political obligation that do not involve voluntary commitment include gratitude, a natural duty of justice, and consequentialism. For an additional possibility, reciprocity, see Mark Hall and George Klosko, "Political Obligation and the United States Supreme Court," Journal of Politics 60, no. 2 (May 1998): 466-68.
    • (1992) The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation
    • Klosko, G.1
  • 10
    • 0032219767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political Obligation and the United States Supreme Court
    • May
    • A full exposition of fairness theory, on which I will draw here, can be found in George Klosko, The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation (Savage, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1992). Other grounds of political obligation that do not involve voluntary commitment include gratitude, a natural duty of justice, and consequentialism. For an additional possibility, reciprocity, see Mark Hall and George Klosko, "Political Obligation and the United States Supreme Court," Journal of Politics 60, no. 2 (May 1998): 466-68.
    • (1998) Journal of Politics , vol.60 , Issue.2 , pp. 466-468
    • Hall, M.1    Klosko, G.2
  • 11
    • 0010195165 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • A. John Simmons, On the Edge of Anarchy (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993), 256-60.
    • (1993) On the Edge of Anarchy , pp. 256-260
    • Simmons, A.J.1
  • 12
    • 85037262529 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It is possible to deny the need for the services in question altogether, which would make it easier to defeat arguments for political obligations. Such an approach, however, would take one beyond the parameters of liberal theory. In this essay, I confine my attention to liberal theory, and so do not discuss this approach. In addition, although the specific benefits discussed in this essay are those of a modern industrial society, my arguments could easily be recast to be made applicable to other kinds of societies.
  • 13
    • 0004253960 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See especially Michael Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice, 2d ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998); and Charles Taylor, "Atomism," in Taylor, Philosophy and the Human Sciences (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985).
    • (1998) Liberalism and the Limits of Justice, 2d Ed.
    • Sandel, M.1
  • 14
    • 0001753541 scopus 로고
    • Atomism
    • Taylor, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See especially Michael Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice, 2d ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998); and Charles Taylor, "Atomism," in Taylor, Philosophy and the Human Sciences (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985).
    • (1985) Philosophy and the Human Sciences
    • Taylor, C.1
  • 15
    • 0000982081 scopus 로고
    • Are There Any Natural Rights?
    • April
    • H. L. A. Hart, "Are There Any Natural Rights?" Philosophical Review 64, no. 2 (April 1955): 185. Some of the language used below in describing the workings of the principle is from Klosko, Principle of Fairness.
    • (1955) Philosophical Review , vol.64 , Issue.2 , pp. 185
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 16
    • 0040610230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • H. L. A. Hart, "Are There Any Natural Rights?" Philosophical Review 64, no. 2 (April 1955): 185. Some of the language used below in describing the workings of the principle is from Klosko, Principle of Fairness.
    • Principle of Fairness
    • Klosko1
  • 17
    • 0004214471 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • David Lyons, Forms and Limits of Utilitarianism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1965), 164; John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 112. The underlying moral principle is analyzed by Richard Arneson, "The Principle of Fairness and Free-Rider Problems," Ethics 92, no. 4 (July 1982): 616-33.
    • (1965) Forms and Limits of Utilitarianism , pp. 164
    • Lyons, D.1
  • 18
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • David Lyons, Forms and Limits of Utilitarianism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1965), 164; John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 112. The underlying moral principle is analyzed by Richard Arneson, "The Principle of Fairness and Free-Rider Problems," Ethics 92, no. 4 (July 1982): 616-33.
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice , pp. 112
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 19
    • 0001207085 scopus 로고
    • The Principle of Fairness and Free-Rider Problems
    • July
    • David Lyons, Forms and Limits of Utilitarianism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1965), 164; John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 112. The underlying moral principle is analyzed by Richard Arneson, "The Principle of Fairness and Free-Rider Problems," Ethics 92, no. 4 (July 1982): 616-33.
    • (1982) Ethics , vol.92 , Issue.4 , pp. 616-633
    • Arneson, R.1
  • 21
    • 85037287513 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Though I will not discuss other possible members of this class, I do not rule out that others may exist.
  • 22
    • 63849086576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The dependence of political obligation on accepting benefits is noted in Rawls, Theory of Justice, 113-16; as well as Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), 95; and Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986), 192-93.
    • Theory of Justice , pp. 113-116
    • Rawls1
  • 23
    • 0004273805 scopus 로고
    • New York: Basic Books
    • The dependence of political obligation on accepting benefits is noted in Rawls, Theory of Justice, 113-16; as well as Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), 95; and Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986), 192-93.
    • (1974) Anarchy, State, and Utopia , pp. 95
    • Nozick, R.1
  • 24
    • 84936068266 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • The dependence of political obligation on accepting benefits is noted in Rawls, Theory of Justice, 113-16; as well as Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), 95; and Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986), 192-93.
    • (1986) Law's Empire , pp. 192-193
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 28
    • 0004248087 scopus 로고
    • Durham, NC: Duke University Press
    • Throughout this essay, I generally use the terms "nonexcludable goods" and "public goods" interchangeably. As the term is commonly used, public goods are not only nonexcludable, but are also characterized by "nonrival consumption," that is, A's consumption of the good does not affect the amount available for consumption by other individuals. This aspect of public goods is not of immediate concern here. On public goods, see John G. Head, Public Goods and Public Welfare (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1974). Returning to the three conditions, it should be noted that for condition (2) to be satisfied, the public goods in question must be worth their costs for all recipients, including those who would prefer not to cooperate rather than to have the costs imposed on them. For reasons of space, I discuss only condition (2) in this essay. Throughout, I assume that conditions (1) and (3) are met, and so do not examine them in detail. For discussion of these and other important aspects of the principle of fairness, see Klosko, Principle of Fairness.
    • (1974) Public Goods and Public Welfare
    • Head, J.G.1
  • 29
    • 0040610230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Throughout this essay, I generally use the terms "nonexcludable goods" and "public goods" interchangeably. As the term is commonly used, public goods are not only nonexcludable, but are also characterized by "nonrival consumption," that is, A's consumption of the good does not affect the amount available for consumption by other individuals. This aspect of public goods is not of immediate concern here. On public goods, see John G. Head, Public Goods and Public Welfare (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1974). Returning to the three conditions, it should be noted that for condition (2) to be satisfied, the public goods in question must be worth their costs for all recipients, including those who would prefer not to cooperate rather than to have the costs imposed on them. For reasons of space, I discuss only condition (2) in this essay. Throughout, I assume that conditions (1) and (3) are met, and so do not examine them in detail. For discussion of these and other important aspects of the principle of fairness, see Klosko, Principle of Fairness.
    • Principle of Fairness
    • Klosko1
  • 30
    • 0040610230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The main exceptions would be circumstances under which the benefits were not worth their costs. For example, in hopeless circumstances, military defense will not be worth the costs needed to secure it. See Klosko, Principle of Fairness, 55-56.
    • Principle of Fairness , pp. 55-56
    • Klosko1
  • 31
    • 0040610230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 2
    • The discussion here draws on Klosko, Principle of Fairness, chap. 2, where I also consider and counter other possible arguments against obligations in such cases.
    • Principle of Fairness
    • Klosko1
  • 32
    • 85023995431 scopus 로고
    • Political Obligation and the Natural Duties of Justice
    • Summer
    • Because the benefits supplied by the state are indispensable, the principle of fairness is able to generate obligations even when compliance with them is costly. Theories with other bases - in particular, those based on a natural duty of justice - are able to generate only weak obligations; see George Klosko, "Political Obligation and the Natural Duties of Justice," Philosophy and Public Affairs 23, no. 3 (Summer 1994): 251-70. On the role of indispensability in fixing the content of political obligations, see George Klosko, "Fixed Content of Political Obligation," Political Studies 46, no. 1 (March 1998): 53-67.
    • (1994) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.23 , Issue.3 , pp. 251-270
    • Klosko, G.1
  • 33
    • 0039494608 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fixed Content of Political Obligation
    • March
    • Because the benefits supplied by the state are indispensable, the principle of fairness is able to generate obligations even when compliance with them is costly. Theories with other bases - in particular, those based on a natural duty of justice - are able to generate only weak obligations; see George Klosko, "Political Obligation and the Natural Duties of Justice," Philosophy and Public Affairs 23, no. 3 (Summer 1994): 251-70. On the role of indispensability in fixing the content of political obligations, see George Klosko, "Fixed Content of Political Obligation," Political Studies 46, no. 1 (March 1998): 53-67.
    • (1998) Political Studies , vol.46 , Issue.1 , pp. 53-67
    • Klosko, G.1
  • 34
    • 0003529325 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, chap. 9
    • For our purposes, it is not necessary to distinguish law and order from the legal order. The benefits from both can be considered together under the designation "law and order." The highly integrated character of modern society and the role of authority in overseeing this integration are well discussed by John Finnis in his Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980), chap. 9. An eloquent account of the value of stable background conditions is given by Edmund Burke in his November 1789 letter to Charles Depont, reprinted in Burke, The Selected Letters of Edmund Burke, ed. Harvey Mansfield (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 256-58.
    • (1980) Natural Law and Natural Rights
    • Finnis, J.1
  • 35
    • 85037285909 scopus 로고
    • ed. Harvey Mansfield Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • For our purposes, it is not necessary to distinguish law and order from the legal order. The benefits from both can be considered together under the designation "law and order." The highly integrated character of modern society and the role of authority in overseeing this integration are well discussed by John Finnis in his Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980), chap. 9. An eloquent account of the value of stable background conditions is given by Edmund Burke in his November 1789 letter to Charles Depont, reprinted in Burke, The Selected Letters of Edmund Burke, ed. Harvey Mansfield (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 256-58.
    • (1984) The Selected Letters of Edmund Burke , pp. 256-258
    • Burke1
  • 36
    • 0004344619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 5
    • For Simmons's other criticisms of the principle of fairness, see Simmons, Moral Principles, chap. 5; and A. John Simmons, "The Anarchist Position: A Reply to Klosko and Senor," Philosophy and Public Affairs 16, no. 3 (Summer 1987): 260-68. I respond to these arguments in Klosko, Principle of Fairness.
    • Moral Principles
    • Simmons1
  • 37
    • 84928458490 scopus 로고
    • The Anarchist Position: A Reply to Klosko and Senor
    • Summer
    • For Simmons's other criticisms of the principle of fairness, see Simmons, Moral Principles, chap. 5; and A. John Simmons, "The Anarchist Position: A Reply to Klosko and Senor," Philosophy and Public Affairs 16, no. 3 (Summer 1987): 260-68. I respond to these arguments in Klosko, Principle of Fairness.
    • (1987) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.16 , Issue.3 , pp. 260-268
    • Simmons, A.J.1
  • 38
    • 0040610230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For Simmons's other criticisms of the principle of fairness, see Simmons, Moral Principles, chap. 5; and A. John Simmons, "The Anarchist Position: A Reply to Klosko and Senor," Philosophy and Public Affairs 16, no. 3 (Summer 1987): 260-68. I respond to these arguments in Klosko, Principle of Fairness.
    • Principle of Fairness
    • Klosko1
  • 40
    • 0033162124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • sec. 95
    • Locke, Second Treatise, sec. 95. In his most recent work, Simmons describes "the natural freedom of persons" as "a basic and plausible Lockean premise." A. John Simmons, "Justification and Legitimacy," Ethics 109, no. 4 (July 1999): 752.
    • Second Treatise
    • Locke1
  • 41
    • 0033162124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Justification and Legitimacy
    • July
    • Locke, Second Treatise, sec. 95. In his most recent work, Simmons describes "the natural freedom of persons" as "a basic and plausible Lockean premise." A. John Simmons, "Justification and Legitimacy," Ethics 109, no. 4 (July 1999): 752.
    • (1999) Ethics , vol.109 , Issue.4 , pp. 752
    • Simmons, A.J.1
  • 45
    • 0040610230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 2
    • The means through which the imposition of obligations on Jones can be justified are discussed in Klosko, Principle of Fairness, chap. 2; for reasons of space, I do not repeat that material here. We should note, however, that in all cases, ceteris paribus principles hold in regard to conditions. The obligations in question are prima facie and so hold in the absence of strong countervailing considerations; for a brief discussion of prima facie obligations, see Klosko, Principle of Fairness, 12-14.
    • Principle of Fairness
    • Klosko1
  • 46
    • 0040610230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The means through which the imposition of obligations on Jones can be justified are discussed in Klosko, Principle of Fairness, chap. 2; for reasons of space, I do not repeat that material here. We should note, however, that in all cases, ceteris paribus principles hold in regard to conditions. The obligations in question are prima facie and so hold in the absence of strong countervailing considerations; for a brief discussion of prima facie obligations, see Klosko, Principle of Fairness, 12-14.
    • Principle of Fairness , pp. 12-14
    • Klosko1
  • 47
    • 0040610230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As argued in Klosko, Principle of Fairness, 48-49, the burden of proof here is on proponents of a given cooperative scheme. Given the great value of indispensable goods, however, it should be possible for them to meet this in many cases.
    • Principle of Fairness , pp. 48-49
    • Klosko1
  • 49
    • 85037257316 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Both quotations arc from ibid
    • Both quotations arc from ibid.
  • 50
    • 0004344619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Simmons's argument here represents a departure from his position in Moral Principles. In that work, he is within the liberal tradition, as he does not question state supply of indispensable benefits. The essence of his argument for "philosophical anarchism" is that, without questioning state supply, none of the basic arguments for political obligations survives scrutiny. In On the Edge of Anarchy, in contrast, Simmons departs from mainstream liberalism and is in effect an anarchist in a more conventional sense, in that he is committed to the nonliberal factual claim that voluntary association can provide important benefits we require.
    • Moral Principles
    • Simmons1
  • 51
    • 0010195165 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Simmons's argument here represents a departure from his position in Moral Principles. In that work, he is within the liberal tradition, as he does not question state supply of indispensable benefits. The essence of his argument for "philosophical anarchism" is that, without questioning state supply, none of the basic arguments for political obligations survives scrutiny. In On the Edge of Anarchy, in contrast, Simmons departs from mainstream liberalism and is in effect an anarchist in a more conventional sense, in that he is committed to the nonliberal factual claim that voluntary association can provide important benefits we require.
    • On the Edge of Anarchy
  • 52
    • 85037283044 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I am grateful to Colin Bird for discussion on this point.
  • 53
    • 85037259340 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It could be argued that from a Lockean perspective, the individual himself should be the judge of feasibility. Although I agree that there is a presumption in favor of the individual's judgment, this does not hold without limits; some external standard of plausible feasibility should be appealed to here as well. Although this claim is necessarily somewhat vague - and no doubt controversial - on an abstract level, it becomes less so as it is employed in particular cases. As Richard Arneson argues, the fact that someone believes that "national defense is manna from heaven" does not free that individual from obligations he would otherwise have. In a case such as this, the individual has an obligation to acquaint himself with the morally relevant facts of the situation. Arneson, "Principle of Fairness," 632. When the individual's alternative measures do not satisfy a plausible standard of feasibility, the presumption that he should judge for himself is overruled.
    • Principle of Fairness , pp. 632
    • Arneson1
  • 54
    • 85037264782 scopus 로고
    • The State and Revolution, in Lenin, ed. Robert C. Tucker New York: Norton
    • Vladimir I. Lenin, The State and Revolution, in Lenin, The Lenin Anthology, ed. Robert C. Tucker (New York: Norton, 1975), 380.
    • (1975) The Lenin Anthology , pp. 380
    • Lenin, V.I.1
  • 55
    • 0040610230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although not discussed in this essay, a set of acceptable rights is presupposed by fairness theory. A principle of political obligation is only a single moral requirement, which must exist in the context of - and be consistent with - a network of other acceptable principles. For discussion of how considerations along these lines limit political obligations under fairness theory, see Klosko, Principle of Fairness, 122-25. Defining the boundary between acceptable and unacceptable violations of rights raises complex issues that cannot be discussed here. At the very least, for an alternative mechanism to meet this transition requirement, the transition from existing society cannot cause greater violations of rights than would be alleviated by the development of the alternative mechanism. For discussion of this point, I am grateful to David Brink.
    • Principle of Fairness , pp. 122-125
    • Klosko1
  • 56
    • 0040610230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It could be argued that trash collection is of little importance and is not a public good. However, brief reflection indicates that an acceptable means of dealing with trash is a necessary public health measure, and that some combination of this and other such measures constitutes an indispensable public good. For discussion of how to determine the form in which an essential public good should be provided, see Klosko, Principle of Fairness, 80-81.
    • Principle of Fairness , pp. 80-81
    • Klosko1
  • 57
    • 0001845081 scopus 로고
    • Politics as a Vocation
    • Weber, ed. and trans. H. H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Max Weber, "Politics as a Vocation," in Weber, From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, ed. and trans. H. H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1946), 78.
    • (1946) From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology , pp. 78
    • Weber, M.1
  • 58
    • 0037535404 scopus 로고
    • New York: Harper and Row
    • Libertarian anarchists have described several reasonably plausible arrangements for immediate physical protection; these arrangements have been based on voluntary protective associations. See David Friedman, The Machinery of Freedom (New York: Harper and Row, 1973); David Friedman, "Anarchy and Efficient Law," in John Sanders and Jan Narveson, eds., For and Against the State (Savage, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1996), 235-54; Bruce Benson, The Enterprise of Law (San Francisco, CA: Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy, 1990); and Murray Rothbard, For a New Liberty (New York: Macmillan, 1978). Central to these proposals is the idea that many aspects of protection are excludable goods and thus are subject to market forces. As Friedman points out, in existing societies, significant percentages of security expenditures and security personnel are private. Friedman, Machinery of Freedom, 219; see also Benson, Enterprise of Law. Detailed examination of these anarchist proposals is not possible in this essay. However, even if protection could be provided through voluntary associations, theorists have not shown how such associations can provide other essential public goods.
    • (1973) The Machinery of Freedom
    • Friedman, D.1
  • 59
    • 8344277477 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Anarchy and Efficient Law
    • John Sanders and Jan Narveson, eds., Savage, MD: Rowman and Littlefield
    • Libertarian anarchists have described several reasonably plausible arrangements for immediate physical protection; these arrangements have been based on voluntary protective associations. See David Friedman, The Machinery of Freedom (New York: Harper and Row, 1973); David Friedman, "Anarchy and Efficient Law," in John Sanders and Jan Narveson, eds., For and Against the State (Savage, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1996), 235-54; Bruce Benson, The Enterprise of Law (San Francisco, CA: Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy, 1990); and Murray Rothbard, For a New Liberty (New York: Macmillan, 1978). Central to these proposals is the idea that many aspects of protection are excludable goods and thus are subject to market forces. As Friedman points out, in existing societies, significant percentages of security expenditures and security personnel are private. Friedman, Machinery of Freedom, 219; see also Benson, Enterprise of Law. Detailed examination of these anarchist proposals is not possible in this essay. However, even if protection could be provided through voluntary associations, theorists have not shown how such associations can provide other essential public goods.
    • (1996) For and Against the State , pp. 235-254
    • Friedman, D.1
  • 60
    • 0004191921 scopus 로고
    • San Francisco, CA: Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy
    • Libertarian anarchists have described several reasonably plausible arrangements for immediate physical protection; these arrangements have been based on voluntary protective associations. See David Friedman, The Machinery of Freedom (New York: Harper and Row, 1973); David Friedman, "Anarchy and Efficient Law," in John Sanders and Jan Narveson, eds., For and Against the State (Savage, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1996), 235-54; Bruce Benson, The Enterprise of Law (San Francisco, CA: Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy, 1990); and Murray Rothbard, For a New Liberty (New York: Macmillan, 1978). Central to these proposals is the idea that many aspects of protection are excludable goods and thus are subject to market forces. As Friedman points out, in existing societies, significant percentages of security expenditures and security personnel are private. Friedman, Machinery of Freedom, 219; see also Benson, Enterprise of Law. Detailed examination of these anarchist proposals is not possible in this essay. However, even if protection could be provided through voluntary associations, theorists have not shown how such associations can provide other essential public goods.
    • (1990) The Enterprise of Law
    • Benson, B.1
  • 61
    • 0004251098 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Macmillan
    • Libertarian anarchists have described several reasonably plausible arrangements for immediate physical protection; these arrangements have been based on voluntary protective associations. See David Friedman, The Machinery of Freedom (New York: Harper and Row, 1973); David Friedman, "Anarchy and Efficient Law," in John Sanders and Jan Narveson, eds., For and Against the State (Savage, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1996), 235-54; Bruce Benson, The Enterprise of Law (San Francisco, CA: Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy, 1990); and Murray Rothbard, For a New Liberty (New York: Macmillan, 1978). Central to these proposals is the idea that many aspects of protection are excludable goods and thus are subject to market forces. As Friedman points out, in existing societies, significant percentages of security expenditures and security personnel are private. Friedman, Machinery of Freedom, 219; see also Benson, Enterprise of Law. Detailed examination of these anarchist proposals is not possible in this essay. However, even if protection could be provided through voluntary associations, theorists have not shown how such associations can provide other essential public goods.
    • (1978) For a New Liberty
    • Rothbard, M.1
  • 62
    • 0041622540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Libertarian anarchists have described several reasonably plausible arrangements for immediate physical protection; these arrangements have been based on voluntary protective associations. See David Friedman, The Machinery of Freedom (New York: Harper and Row, 1973); David Friedman, "Anarchy and Efficient Law," in John Sanders and Jan Narveson, eds., For and Against the State (Savage, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1996), 235-54; Bruce Benson, The Enterprise of Law (San Francisco, CA: Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy, 1990); and Murray Rothbard, For a New Liberty (New York: Macmillan, 1978). Central to these proposals is the idea that many aspects of protection are excludable goods and thus are subject to market forces. As Friedman points out, in existing societies, significant percentages of security expenditures and security personnel are private. Friedman, Machinery of Freedom, 219; see also Benson, Enterprise of Law. Detailed examination of these anarchist proposals is not possible in this essay. However, even if protection could be provided through voluntary associations, theorists have not shown how such associations can provide other essential public goods.
    • Machinery of Freedom , pp. 219
    • Friedman1
  • 63
    • 0004253496 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Libertarian anarchists have described several reasonably plausible arrangements for immediate physical protection; these arrangements have been based on voluntary protective associations. See David Friedman, The Machinery of Freedom (New York: Harper and Row, 1973); David Friedman, "Anarchy and Efficient Law," in John Sanders and Jan Narveson, eds., For and Against the State (Savage, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1996), 235-54; Bruce Benson, The Enterprise of Law (San Francisco, CA: Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy, 1990); and Murray Rothbard, For a New Liberty (New York: Macmillan, 1978). Central to these proposals is the idea that many aspects of protection are excludable goods and thus are subject to market forces. As Friedman points out, in existing societies, significant percentages of security expenditures and security personnel are private. Friedman, Machinery of Freedom, 219; see also Benson, Enterprise of Law. Detailed examination of these anarchist proposals is not possible in this essay. However, even if protection could be provided through voluntary associations, theorists have not shown how such associations can provide other essential public goods.
    • Enterprise of Law
    • Benson1
  • 64
    • 0041622540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 34
    • Friedman characterizes provision of defense as "the hard problem"; his suggestions here are highly speculative (Friedman, Machinery of Freedom, chap. 34). Rothbard's suggestions are similarly improbable (Rothbard, For a New Liberty, 237-41 and chap. 14). Benson concedes the need for state provision of defense (Benson, Enterprise of Law, 373). Game-theoretic explanations of alternative provision also have problems with respect to defense; see note 63 below.
    • Machinery of Freedom
    • Friedman1
  • 65
    • 0004251098 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 14
    • Friedman characterizes provision of defense as "the hard problem"; his suggestions here are highly speculative (Friedman, Machinery of Freedom, chap. 34). Rothbard's suggestions are similarly improbable (Rothbard, For a New Liberty, 237-41 and chap. 14). Benson concedes the need for state provision of defense (Benson, Enterprise of Law, 373). Game-theoretic explanations of alternative provision also have problems with respect to defense; see note 63 below.
    • For a New Liberty , pp. 237-241
    • Rothbard1
  • 66
    • 0004253496 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Friedman characterizes provision of defense as "the hard problem"; his suggestions here are highly speculative (Friedman, Machinery of Freedom, chap. 34). Rothbard's suggestions are similarly improbable (Rothbard, For a New Liberty, 237-41 and chap. 14). Benson concedes the need for state provision of defense (Benson, Enterprise of Law, 373). Game-theoretic explanations of alternative provision also have problems with respect to defense; see note 63 below.
    • Enterprise of Law , pp. 373
    • Benson1
  • 67
    • 0003471635 scopus 로고
    • London: Croom Helm
    • That the territorial basis of state services is a problem for consent theory is seen in Harry Beran, The Consent Theory of Political Obligation (London: Croom Helm, 1987); for discussion, see Allen Buchanan, Secession: The Morality of Political Divorce (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1991), 70-73.
    • (1987) The Consent Theory of Political Obligation
    • Beran, H.1
  • 68
    • 0003587889 scopus 로고
    • Boulder, CO: Westview Press
    • That the territorial basis of state services is a problem for consent theory is seen in Harry Beran, The Consent Theory of Political Obligation (London: Croom Helm, 1987); for discussion, see Allen Buchanan, Secession: The Morality of Political Divorce (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1991), 70-73.
    • (1991) Secession: The Morality of Political Divorce , pp. 70-73
    • Buchanan, A.1
  • 69
    • 85037276285 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • n. 18
    • Small territories like Monaco or Lichtenstein are sheltered by the protective umbrella provided by the great powers, and therefore arguably have political obligations to those countries. For brief discussion, see Klosko, "Political Obligation and the Natural Duties of Justice," 260 n. 18.
    • Political Obligation and the Natural Duties of Justice , pp. 260
    • Klosko1
  • 70
    • 85037283292 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See note 36 above
    • See note 36 above.
  • 71
    • 85037259013 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Though I will not go into depth on the matter, I should note here that the plausibility condition's background requirement plays an important role, both here and in the next section, in ruling out changes in conditions that would make organized coercive mechanisms unnecessary. For example, a proponent of some alternative mechanism who is faced with the objections to alternative supply presented in this section could not respond to these objections by saying that his mechanism would work if large-scale changes in human wants and desires could be brought about.
  • 72
    • 0003364505 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I quote Hume: "Almost all the governments, which exist at present, or of which there remains any record in story, have been founded originally, either on usurpation or conquest, or both, without any pretence of a fair consent of voluntary subjection of the people." Hume, "Of the Original Contract," 471.
    • Of the Original Contract , pp. 471
    • Hume1
  • 73
    • 0040610230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The moral context and additional requirements of fairness theory are discussed throughout Klosko, Principle of Fairness; see also note 36 above.
    • Principle of Fairness
    • Klosko1
  • 74
    • 85037286540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In cases where there are such morally relevant differences, one might wonder whether the differences (1) cause the dissolution of existent political obligations, or (2) prevent any such obligations from being constituted in the first place. Though I will not discuss the matter here, I believe the latter option is more likely.
  • 75
    • 0040610230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 3
    • See Klosko, Principle of Fairness, chap. 3. For discussion of the attitudes in modern liberal states toward democratic institutions and democracy as a value, see George Klosko, Democratic Procedures and Liberal Consensus (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), chap. 5.
    • Principle of Fairness
    • Klosko1
  • 76
    • 84921981845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, chap. 5
    • See Klosko, Principle of Fairness, chap. 3. For discussion of the attitudes in modern liberal states toward democratic institutions and democracy as a value, see George Klosko, Democratic Procedures and Liberal Consensus (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), chap. 5.
    • (2000) Democratic Procedures and Liberal Consensus
    • Klosko, G.1
  • 77
    • 0040556953 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • This fact would perhaps constitute a morally relevant difference if Jones's alternative preferences were so strong as to raise questions of conscience, in which case imposing majority decisions on him would represent an injustice. Though I cannot discuss here the complex issues concerning pacifists and conscientious objectors, I do believe that their situations involve this sort of strong alternative preference. In such cases, however, the recognition that the individual still has some obligations is seen in provisions for alternative service. For discussion of conscientious-objection practices in some two dozen countries, see Charles C. Moskos and John Whiteclay Chambers, eds., The New Conscientious Objection (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993).
    • (1993) The New Conscientious Objection
    • Moskos, C.C.1    Chambers, J.W.2
  • 78
    • 0004052665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See Michael Taylor, The Possibility of Cooperation (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), discussed below. Similar views are advanced by many additional scholars; the contributors to Sanders and Narveson's For and Against the State constitute a representative sample.
    • (1987) The Possibility of Cooperation
    • Taylor, M.1
  • 79
    • 0010133855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Michael Taylor, The Possibility of Cooperation (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), discussed below. Similar views are advanced by many additional scholars; the contributors to Sanders and Narveson's For and Against the State constitute a representative sample.
    • For and Against the State
    • Sanders1    Narveson2
  • 80
    • 0014413249 scopus 로고
    • The Tragedy of the Commons
    • December
    • Garrett Hardin, "The Tragedy of the Commons," Science 162, no. 13 (December 1968): 1247.
    • (1968) Science , vol.162 , Issue.13 , pp. 1247
    • Hardin, G.1
  • 83
    • 85037280324 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Under other conditions, a correct construal of the situation would posit it as a game of chicken rather than as a prisoners' dilemma; see note 62 below.
  • 85
    • 0004052665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 3
    • See ibid., chap. 3, for discussion of this process, including the complexities concerning discounts on future payoffs, a factor I have omitted here.
    • Possibility of Cooperation , pp. 12
    • Taylor1
  • 86
    • 12144259402 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge
    • Anthony de Jasay, for one, argues that treating large-number games as supergames solves the difficulties that they present. See Anthony de Jasay, Against Politics (London: Routledge, 1997), 206-8, 215-16. However, he deals only with performance and nonperformance of contracts, as opposed to wider forms of noncompliance, including noncontribution to necessary public goods. In the context of contributing toward these goods, noncompliance can be far more difficult to detect (as discussed below), and raises problems that de Jasay's argument does not address. For example, in many public-goods cases, a given individual's incentives to enforce another individual's compliance are significantly different from the incentives he would have in a contract situation. In a typical public-goods case, Jones's defection causes no detectable damage and so does not harm Smith or affect the costs associated with Smith's compliance.
    • (1997) Against Politics , pp. 206-208
    • De Jasay, A.1
  • 88
    • 0004305444 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Mancur Olson, The Logic of Collective Action (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1965), 36, 48.
    • (1965) The Logic of Collective Action , pp. 36
    • Olson, M.1
  • 91
    • 0004052665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 2
    • These problems cannot be overcome by analyzing public-goods provision with the model of the game of chicken; see Taylor, Possibility of Cooperation, chap. 2. In a chicken scenario, different individuals or subgroups must be able to supply the relevant goods without outside assistance. However, in a large society, this condition will not ordinarily hold for the public goods that interest us. In addition, one must explain the incentives of individuals in these subgroups; these incentives appear to conform to those found in an N-person PD.
    • Possibility of Cooperation
    • Taylor1
  • 92
    • 12144259402 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The problems with game theory are epitomized by its inability to deal with providing defense. For instance, in Against Politics, de Jasay gives the problem extremely scant attention and offers no solution. See de Jasay, Against Politics, 208. In Sanders and Narveson's For and Against the State, a collection in which the practical and moral necessity of the state is assessed from a variety of game-theoretic perspectives, the problem of defense receives no serious attention.
    • Against Politics , pp. 208
    • De Jasay1
  • 93
    • 0010133855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The problems with game theory are epitomized by its inability to deal with providing defense. For instance, in Against Politics, de Jasay gives the problem extremely scant attention and offers no solution. See de Jasay, Against Politics, 208. In Sanders and Narveson's For and Against the State, a collection in which the practical and moral necessity of the state is assessed from a variety of game-theoretic perspectives, the problem of defense receives no serious attention.
    • For and Against the State
    • Sanders1    Narveson2
  • 95
    • 85040890266 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Elinor Ostrom, Governing the Commons: The Evolution of Institutions for Collective Action (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990). Conclusions similar to Ostrom's are also presented in Robert Ellickson, Order Without Law (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1991).
    • (1991) Order Without Law
    • Ellickson, R.1
  • 100
    • 85037272846 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Games, Anarchy, and the Nonnecessity of the State
    • Sanders and Narveson, eds.
    • The experimental evidence supporting nonstate solutions to PD problems suffers from severe flaws. Specifically, the experiments that provided this evidence involved small groups of subjects and assigned artificially low values to the costs and benefits of cooperation. See Howard Harriott, "Games, Anarchy, and the Nonnecessity of the State," in Sanders and Narveson, eds., For and Against the State, 131-34.
    • For and Against the State , pp. 131-134
    • Harriott, H.1
  • 103
    • 0012271444 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, chap. 4
    • For discussion of other specific moral requirements generated by membership in communities, see Richard Dagger, Civic Virtues (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997), chap. 4.
    • (1997) Civic Virtues
    • Dagger, R.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.