-
1
-
-
0034659898
-
Genomics, gene expression, and DNA arrays
-
David J. Lockhart and Elizabeth A. Winzeler, "Genomics, Gene Expression, and DNA Arrays, " Nature 405, no. 6788 (2000): 827-36.
-
(2000)
Nature
, vol.405
, Issue.6788
, pp. 827-836
-
-
Lockhart, D.J.1
Winzeler, E.A.2
-
2
-
-
0031020054
-
The genomics gamble
-
The amount of genetic data available has been increasing tenfold every five years. See Jon Cohen, "The Genomics Gamble, " Science 767, no. 5303 (1997): 767-68.
-
(1997)
Science
, vol.767
, Issue.5303
, pp. 767-768
-
-
Cohen, J.1
-
3
-
-
85013961122
-
-
note
-
An individual's phenotype is the physical profile he or she presents to the external world. Thus, for example, one might say that an individual's phenotype includes asthmatic breathing.
-
-
-
-
4
-
-
85013918351
-
-
note
-
An individual's genotype comprises the genetic information contained in his or her chromosomes.
-
-
-
-
5
-
-
0034660560
-
Pharmacogenetics and the practice of medicine
-
Lucid discussions of the use of SNPs in medicine include Allen Roses, "Pharmacogenetics and the Practice of Medicine, " Nature 405, no. 6788 (2000): 857-65; and Jeanette J. McCarthy and Rolf Hilfiker, "The Use of Single-Nucleotide Polymorphism Maps in Pharmacogenomics, " Nature Biotechnology 18, no. 5 (2000): 505-9.
-
(2000)
Nature
, vol.405
, Issue.6788
, pp. 857-865
-
-
Roses, A.1
-
6
-
-
0034022213
-
The use of single-nucleotide polymorphism maps in pharmacogenomics
-
Lucid discussions of the use of SNPs in medicine include Allen Roses, "Pharmacogenetics and the Practice of Medicine, " Nature 405, no. 6788 (2000): 857-65; and Jeanette J. McCarthy and Rolf Hilfiker, "The Use of Single-Nucleotide Polymorphism Maps in Pharmacogenomics, " Nature Biotechnology 18, no. 5 (2000): 505-9.
-
(2000)
Nature Biotechnology
, vol.18
, Issue.5
, pp. 505-509
-
-
McCarthy, J.J.1
Hilfiker, R.2
-
7
-
-
0347079845
-
The information revolution reaches pharmaceuticals: Balancing innovation incentives, cost, and access in the post-genomics era
-
Indeed, in "The Information Revolution Reaches Pharmaceuticals: Balancing Innovation Incentives, Cost, and Access in the Post-Genomics Era, " Illinois Law Review 2001, no. 1 (2001): 173-210, I argue that one of the chief benefits of making drug development an information science involves the possibility of reduced preclinical and clinical development costs.
-
(2001)
Illinois Law Review
, vol.2001
, Issue.1
, pp. 173-210
-
-
-
8
-
-
85013867406
-
-
note
-
To be sure, an orphan group created through SNP testing is not necessarily worse off than it would have been in the days before SNP testing. In the days before SNP testing, the group would have been prescribed either a drug that had adverse effects, an ineffective drug (that is, a drug that worked only for other genotypic groups), or no drug at all (if the population with the relevant phenotype was so fragmented into separate genotypic groups that no single drug for the phenotype could have passed the Food and Drug Administration's efficacy standards). Nonetheless, in the past, the orphan group would have been difficult, if not impossible, to identify. In the same way that ordinary diagnostic techniques have given us the ability to identify groups with rare phenotypic diseases, SNP testing will give us the ability to identify, and perform further study on, groups orphaned by their SNP inheritance.
-
-
-
-
9
-
-
21244503448
-
A tale of two proteins: The FDA's uncertain interpretation of the orphan drug act
-
In some cases, drugs developed to treat a particular orphan phenotype have emerged as treatments for more common diseases. Thus, for example, the human growth hormone developed to treat hypopituitary dwarfism ended up being useful in treating other growth deficiencies; see Robert A. Bohrer and John T. Prince, "A Tale of Two Proteins: The FDA's Uncertain Interpretation of the Orphan Drug Act, " Harvard Journal of Law and Technology 12, no. 1 (1999): 381. For this reason, the designation of human growth hormone (and other drugs that have ended up being useful for relatively large populations, such as the anti-AIDS drug AZT) as orphan drugs that deserve protection under the Orphan Drug Act (discussed below) has proved controversial. Ibid., 332. This possible problem with orphandrug protection is but one example of the general difficulty biomedical-research regulators face when the implications of the research they are considering are not fully known. A discussion of this general problem is beyond the scope of this essay.
-
(1999)
Harvard Journal of Law and Technology
, vol.12
, Issue.1
, pp. 381
-
-
Bohrer, R.A.1
Prince, J.T.2
-
10
-
-
85013909822
-
-
note
-
In addition, if a particular phenotype has no genotypic subgroup that is sufficiently large to provide an appropriate market, then the entire phenotype could be considered orphaned. The analysis in this essay would apply to each of the orphan genotypes within the orphan phenotype.
-
-
-
-
11
-
-
85013895089
-
-
note
-
In addition, even if pharmacogenomics does not ultimately yield many new orphan genotypes, the number of orphan phenotypes that are emerging may be sufficiently large such that reconsideration of the current system is warranted.
-
-
-
-
12
-
-
85013985380
-
-
See SNP Consortium, "SNP Data Release: September 2001, " available on-line at http: //snp.cshl.org/data; and Celera Corporation, "Academic and Non-Profit Offerings: From Data to Discovery, " available on-line at http://www.celera.com/genomics/academic/ home.cfm?ppage=cpage=snps.
-
SNP Data Release: September 2001
-
-
-
13
-
-
85013900913
-
-
See SNP Consortium, "SNP Data Release: September 2001, " available on-line at http: //snp.cshl.org/data; and Celera Corporation, "Academic and Non-Profit Offerings: From Data to Discovery, " available on-line at http://www.celera.com/genomics/academic/home.cfm?ppage=cpage=snps.
-
Academic and Non-Profit Offerings: From Data to Discovery
-
-
-
14
-
-
85013900913
-
-
See SNP Consortium, "SNP Data Release: September 2001, " available on-line at http: //snp.cshl.org/data; and Celera Corporation, "Academic and Non-Profit Offerings: From Data to Discovery, " available on-line at http://www.celera.com/genomics/academic/ home.cfm?ppage=cpage=snps.
-
Academic and Non-profit Offerings: From Data to Discovery
-
-
-
15
-
-
0001853252
-
Genaissance publishes a study outlining variations in 313 genes
-
July 13
-
These so-called coding SNPs (or "cSNPs") may be more common than was previously thought: a recent study of 313 human genes found an average of fourteen SNP variations per gene. See Geeta Anand, "Genaissance Publishes a Study Outlining Variations in 313 Genes, " Wall Street Journal, July 13, 2001, C1.
-
(2001)
Wall Street Journal
, pp. C1
-
-
Anand, G.1
-
16
-
-
0034638766
-
Pharmacogenetics and adverse drug reactions
-
See Urs A. Meyer, "Pharmacogenetics and Adverse Drug Reactions, " Lancet 356, no. 9242 (2000): 1667-82; and John Weinstein, "Pharmacogenomics - Teaching Old Drugs New Tricks, " New England Journal of Medicine 343, no. 19 (2000): 1408-9.
-
(2000)
Lancet
, vol.356
, Issue.9242
, pp. 1667-1682
-
-
Meyer, U.A.1
-
17
-
-
0034626986
-
Pharmacogenomics - Teaching old drugs new tricks
-
See Urs A. Meyer, "Pharmacogenetics and Adverse Drug Reactions, " Lancet 356, no. 9242 (2000): 1667-82; and John Weinstein, "Pharmacogenomics - Teaching Old Drugs New Tricks, " New England Journal of Medicine 343, no. 19 (2000): 1408-9.
-
(2000)
New England Journal of Medicine
, vol.343
, Issue.19
, pp. 1408-1409
-
-
Weinstein, J.1
-
18
-
-
0007691164
-
Apolipoprotein E4 Allele as a predictor of cholinergic deficits and treatment outcome in Alzheimer disease
-
Judes Poirier et al., "Apolipoprotein E4 Allele as a Predictor of Cholinergic Deficits and Treatment Outcome in Alzheimer Disease, " Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 92, no. 26 (1995): 12260-61.
-
(1995)
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences
, vol.92
, Issue.26
, pp. 12260-12261
-
-
Poirier, J.1
-
19
-
-
85013893229
-
-
note
-
A promoter is a DNA sequence that is responsible for regulating the expression of a particular gene.
-
-
-
-
20
-
-
0033059209
-
Pharmacogenetic association between ALOX5 promoter genotype and the response to anti-asthma treatment
-
J. M. Drazen et al., "Pharmacogenetic Association between ALOX5 Promoter Genotype and the Response to Anti-Asthma Treatment, " Nature Genetics 22, no. 2 (1999): 168-70.
-
(1999)
Nature Genetics
, vol.22
, Issue.2
, pp. 168-170
-
-
Drazen, J.M.1
-
21
-
-
0039623505
-
Medicine gets personal
-
On such patients, see Marc Wortman, "Medicine Gets Personal, " MIT Tech Review 104, no. 1 (2001): 72-78.
-
(2001)
MIT Tech Review
, vol.104
, Issue.1
, pp. 72-78
-
-
Wortman, M.1
-
22
-
-
85013936332
-
-
Orphan Drug Act of 1983, Pub. L. No. 97-414, 96 Stat. 2049 (1983) (codified as amended in scattered sections of 21 U.S.C. and 42 U.S.C.)
-
Orphan Drug Act of 1983, Pub. L. No. 97-414, 96 Stat. 2049 (1983) (codified as amended in scattered sections of 21 U.S.C. and 42 U.S.C.).
-
-
-
-
23
-
-
85013881162
-
-
Food, Drug, and Cosmetics Act, 21 U.S.C. § 301 (1994)
-
Food, Drug, and Cosmetics Act, 21 U.S.C. § 301 (1994).
-
-
-
-
24
-
-
85013920736
-
-
21 U.S.C. § 360bb (1994)
-
21 U.S.C. § 360bb (1994).
-
-
-
-
25
-
-
85013879061
-
-
Orphan Drug Act § 1, 96 Stat. 2049 (1983)
-
Orphan Drug Act § 1, 96 Stat. 2049 (1983).
-
-
-
-
26
-
-
85013941218
-
-
21 U.S.C. § 360ee(b)(2) (1994). Because the United States represents the only major market in which drug prices are not tightly regulated (and hence is the major market in which profits from drug sales are realized), the Orphan Drug Act focuses on U.S. sales. Similarly, in this essay, I will focus on the U.S. market for drugs
-
21 U.S.C. § 360ee(b)(2) (1994). Because the United States represents the only major market in which drug prices are not tightly regulated (and hence is the major market in which profits from drug sales are realized), the Orphan Drug Act focuses on U.S. sales. Similarly, in this essay, I will focus on the U.S. market for drugs.
-
-
-
-
27
-
-
85013890118
-
-
note
-
See 21 C.F.R. § 316.23 (1999): (a) A sponsor may request orphan-drug designation at any time in the drug development process prior to the submission of a marketing application for the drug product for the orphan indication. (b) A sponsor may request orphan-drug designation of an already approved drug product for an unapproved use without regard to whether the prior marketing approval was for an orphan-drug indication. One difficulty with the current system is that it appears to require the manufacturer to identify a particular drug candidate before Orphan Drug Act protections are triggered. Because even initial identification of a candidate drug can be costly, this requirement may place too great a burden on the would-be researcher into an orphan disease. This difficulty could be alleviated by altering the language of the relevant regulations so that Orphan Drug Act protections are available to manufacturers with a research plan for work on a particular orphan disease.
-
-
-
-
28
-
-
85013925929
-
-
See 21 U.S.C. § 360aa(a) (1994) (specifying that an orphan-drug manufacturer may request from the FDA written recommendations for clinical and nonclinical tests that must be conducted for a drug's approval)
-
See 21 U.S.C. § 360aa(a) (1994) (specifying that an orphan-drug manufacturer may request from the FDA written recommendations for clinical and nonclinical tests that must be conducted for a drug's approval).
-
-
-
-
29
-
-
85013960295
-
-
See 21 U.S.C. § 360ee(a) (1994) (providing that "The Secretary may make grants to and enter into contracts with public and private entities and individuals to assist in (1) defraying the costs of qualified testing expenses incurred in connection with the development of drugs for rare diseases and conditions. ")
-
See 21 U.S.C. § 360ee(a) (1994) (providing that "The Secretary may make grants to and enter into contracts with public and private entities and individuals to assist in (1) defraying the costs of qualified testing expenses incurred in connection with the development of drugs for rare diseases and conditions. ").
-
-
-
-
30
-
-
85013967597
-
-
26 U.S.C. § 45C (1994). By contrast, most firms that engage in costly R&D receive a tax credit equal to only 20 percent of R&D spending that exceeds a certain base amount (typically defined by a firm's spending patterns in the previous three years)
-
26 U.S.C. § 45C (1994). By contrast, most firms that engage in costly R&D receive a tax credit equal to only 20 percent of R&D spending that exceeds a certain base amount (typically defined by a firm's spending patterns in the previous three years).
-
-
-
-
31
-
-
85013958476
-
-
Under the patent statute, an invention must not only be new (see 35 U.S.C. § 102 [1994]), but it must also be something that would not have been obvious, at the time it was made, to a person of ordinary skill in the relevant field. See 35 U.S.C. § 103 (1994)
-
Under the patent statute, an invention must not only be new (see 35 U.S.C. § 102 [1994]), but it must also be something that would not have been obvious, at the time it was made, to a person of ordinary skill in the relevant field. See 35 U.S.C. § 103 (1994).
-
-
-
-
33
-
-
85013892748
-
Rationing access to medical care: Some sober second thoughts
-
See, e.g., Richard Epstein, "Rationing Access to Medical Care: Some Sober Second Thoughts, " Stanford Law and Policy Review 3 (1991): 81-89; and Loren E. Lomasky, "Medical Progress and National Health Care, " in Marshall Cohen, Thomas Nagel, and Thomas Scanlon, eds., Medicine and Moral Philosophy (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1981), 115.
-
(1991)
Stanford Law and Policy Review
, vol.3
, pp. 81-89
-
-
Epstein, R.1
-
34
-
-
0039031342
-
Medical progress and national health care
-
Marshall Cohen, Thomas Nagel, and Thomas Scanlon, eds., Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
-
See, e.g., Richard Epstein, "Rationing Access to Medical Care: Some Sober Second Thoughts, " Stanford Law and Policy Review 3 (1991): 81-89; and Loren E. Lomasky, "Medical Progress and National Health Care, " in Marshall Cohen, Thomas Nagel, and Thomas Scanlon, eds., Medicine and Moral Philosophy (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1981), 115.
-
(1981)
Medicine and Moral Philosophy
, pp. 115
-
-
Lomasky, L.E.1
-
35
-
-
0039623504
-
-
Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office
-
See President's Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research, Securing Access to Health Care: A Report on the Ethical Implications of Differences in the Availability of Health Services (Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1983), 1:3-6, 1:18-47; and also Tom L. Beauchamp and James F. Childress, Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 4th ed. (New York: Oxford University Press, 1994), 356 (developing the argument for an individual right to basic health care and noting that such a right holds out the potential for "compromise among libertarians, utilitarians, communitarians, and egalitarians").
-
(1983)
Securing Access to Health Care: A Report on the Ethical Implications of Differences in the Availability of Health Services
, vol.1
, pp. 3-6
-
-
-
36
-
-
0040809908
-
-
See President's Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research, Securing Access to Health Care: A Report on the Ethical Implications of Differences in the Availability of Health Services (Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1983), 1:3-6, 1:18-47; and also Tom L. Beauchamp and James F. Childress, Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 4th ed. (New York: Oxford University Press, 1994), 356 (developing the argument for an individual right to basic health care and noting that such a right holds out the potential for "compromise among libertarians, utilitarians, communitarians, and egalitarians").
-
Securing Access to Health Care: A Report on the Ethical Implications of Differences in the Availability of Health Services
, vol.1
, pp. 18-47
-
-
-
37
-
-
0003663231
-
-
New York: Oxford University Press
-
See President's Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research, Securing Access to Health Care: A Report on the Ethical Implications of Differences in the Availability of Health Services (Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1983), 1:3-6, 1:18-47; and also Tom L. Beauchamp and James F. Childress, Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 4th ed. (New York: Oxford University Press, 1994), 356 (developing the argument for an individual right to basic health care and noting that such a right holds out the potential for "compromise among libertarians, utilitarians, communitarians, and egalitarians").
-
(1994)
Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 4th Ed.
, pp. 356
-
-
Beauchamp, T.L.1
Childress, J.F.2
-
38
-
-
0021559716
-
The right to a decent minimum of health care
-
See generally Allen E. Buchanan, "The Right to a Decent Minimum of Health Care, " Philosophy and Public Affairs 13, no. 1 (1984): 55-78.
-
(1984)
Philosophy and Public Affairs
, vol.13
, Issue.1
, pp. 55-78
-
-
Buchanan, A.E.1
-
39
-
-
0004294588
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
See, e.g., Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996), 213-23. Gutmann and Thompson discuss not only health care but also the full range of social goods that are, in their estimation, necessary to protect basic opportunity. These include food, shelter, education, and health care.
-
(1996)
Democracy and Disagreement
, pp. 213-223
-
-
Gutmann, A.1
Thompson, D.2
-
40
-
-
0003412671
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
See Norman Daniels, Just Health Care (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), 36-58.
-
(1985)
Just Health Care
, pp. 36-58
-
-
Daniels, N.1
-
41
-
-
0028678333
-
Allocating health care morally
-
See, e.g., Einer Elhauge, "Allocating Health Care Morally, " California Law Review 82, no. 6 (1994): 1493-96.
-
(1994)
California Law Review
, vol.82
, Issue.6
, pp. 1493-1496
-
-
Elhauge, E.1
-
42
-
-
84974487449
-
The moral justification of cost-benefit analysis
-
In order to comport fully with utilitarianism, cost-benefit analysis should not assume (as it often does) that the benefit an individual derives from a particular item is equivalent to his or her willingness to pay for that item. While an individual's willingness to pay is clearly income-dependent, utilitarians reject the idea that utility is necessarily income-dependent. See Donald Hubin, "The Moral Justification of Cost-Benefit Analysis, " Economics and Philosophy 10, no. 2 (1994): 187-88 (noting that because cost-benefit analysis often measures benefit in terms that reflect ability to pay, it tends to discount the utility of poor individuals). As discussed further below, the calculation of benefit that is used in medical cost-benefit analysis is not dependent on willingness to pay. Thus, medical cost-benefit analysis is not subject to the critique that it favors wealthy individuals over poor ones.
-
(1994)
Economics and Philosophy
, vol.10
, Issue.2
, pp. 187-188
-
-
Hubin, D.1
-
43
-
-
1542638561
-
Rationing through choice: A new approach to cost-effectiveness analysis in health care
-
Oregon subsequently revised its initial application of cost-benefit methodology, primarily in response to criticism that that application of the methodology undervalued the saving of identifiable lives. See Arti K. Rai, "Rationing through Choice: A New Approach to Cost-Effectiveness Analysis in Health Care, " Indiana Law Journal 72, no. 4 (1997): 1054. Although Oregon's revised methodology placed greater emphasis on saving identifiable lives, it placed much less emphasis on overall medical benefits. Ibid., 1073-74. The focus on health benefits was further diluted by the federal government's determination that efforts to assess quality of life in measuring medical benefits violate the Americans with Disabilities Act. As a consequence of this determination, Oregon was forced to ignore quality-of-life improvements when it assessed medical interventions. When the Oregon plan was finally implemented in February 1994, it did not incorporate cost-benefit methodology to any significant degree.
-
(1997)
Indiana Law Journal
, vol.72
, Issue.4
, pp. 1054
-
-
Rai, A.K.1
-
44
-
-
1542638561
-
-
Oregon subsequently revised its initial application of cost-benefit methodology, primarily in response to criticism that that application of the methodology undervalued the saving of identifiable lives. See Arti K. Rai, "Rationing through Choice: A New Approach to Cost-Effectiveness Analysis in Health Care, " Indiana Law Journal 72, no. 4 (1997): 1054. Although Oregon's revised methodology placed greater emphasis on saving identifiable lives, it placed much less emphasis on overall medical benefits. Ibid., 1073-74. The focus on health benefits was further diluted by the federal government's determination that efforts to assess quality of life in measuring medical benefits violate the Americans with Disabilities Act. As a consequence of this determination, Oregon was forced to ignore quality-of-life improvements when it assessed medical interventions. When the Oregon plan was finally implemented in February 1994, it did not incorporate cost-benefit methodology to any significant degree.
-
Indiana Law Journal
, pp. 1073-1074
-
-
-
47
-
-
85013963946
-
-
Ibid., 103-5. While Daniels argues for preferring the young from a liberal egalitarian standpoint Daniel Callahan reaches a similar conclusion from a communitarian standpoint Callahan asserts that once an individual has achieved her "natural life span, " society's goal should be to relieve suffering rather than to pursue life-extending care. Daniel Callahan, What Kind of Life: The Limits on Medical Progress (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1990), 141.
-
Just Health Care
, pp. 103-105
-
-
-
48
-
-
0003917264
-
-
New York: Simon and Schuster
-
Ibid., 103-5. While Daniels argues for preferring the young from a liberal egalitarian standpoint Daniel Callahan reaches a similar conclusion from a communitarian standpoint Callahan asserts that once an individual has achieved her "natural life span, " society's goal should be to relieve suffering rather than to pursue life-extending care. Daniel Callahan, What Kind of Life: The Limits on Medical Progress (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1990), 141.
-
(1990)
What Kind of Life: The Limits on Medical Progress
, pp. 141
-
-
Callahan, D.1
-
49
-
-
0004294588
-
-
Gutmann and Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement, 192-94. Utilitarianism is also controversial to the extent that it focuses on the informed preferences of individuals and not on the deliberative process by which groups of individuals might come to a collective understanding of their preferences. Ibid., 173-77. However, as I will argue below, even though utilitarian philosophy may not stress deliberation, utilitarian methodologies like cost-benefit analysis can significantly enhance the deliberative process.
-
Democracy and Disagreement
, pp. 192-194
-
-
Gutmann1
Thompson2
-
50
-
-
85013928982
-
-
Gutmann and Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement, 192-94. Utilitarianism is also controversial to the extent that it focuses on the informed preferences of individuals and not on the deliberative process by which groups of individuals might come to a collective understanding of their preferences. Ibid., 173-77. However, as I will argue below, even though utilitarian philosophy may not stress deliberation, utilitarian methodologies like cost-benefit analysis can significantly enhance the deliberative process.
-
Democracy and Disagreement
, pp. 173-177
-
-
-
51
-
-
85013992495
-
-
See, e.g., Rai, "Rationing through Choice, " 1024 (discussing this sort of "bottomless pit" problem).
-
Rationing Through Choice
, pp. 1024
-
-
Rai1
-
52
-
-
0040809927
-
-
See ibid., 1021-30; Einer Elhauge, "Allocating Health Care Morally, " 1465-72; and Ezekiel Emanuel, The Ends of Human Life (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1991), 114-45.
-
Rationing Through Choice
, pp. 1021-1030
-
-
-
53
-
-
0039623508
-
-
See ibid., 1021-30; Einer Elhauge, "Allocating Health Care Morally, " 1465-72; and Ezekiel Emanuel, The Ends of Human Life (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1991), 114-45.
-
Allocating Health Care Morally
, pp. 1465-1472
-
-
Elhauge, E.1
-
54
-
-
0003687668
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
See ibid., 1021-30; Einer Elhauge, "Allocating Health Care Morally, " 1465-72; and Ezekiel Emanuel, The Ends of Human Life (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1991), 114-45.
-
(1991)
The Ends of Human Life
, pp. 114-145
-
-
Emanuel, E.1
-
55
-
-
0003624191
-
-
New York: Columbia University Press
-
See John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), 9: "The aim of justice as fairness, then, is practical: it presents itself as a conception of justice that may be shared by citizens as a basis of a reasoned, informed, and willing political judgment" (emphasis added).
-
(1993)
Political Liberalism
, pp. 9
-
-
Rawls, J.1
-
56
-
-
0031217084
-
Limits to health care: Fair procedures, democratic deliberation, and the legitimacy problem for insurers
-
See generally Norman Daniels and James Sabin, "Limits to Health Care: Fair Procedures, Democratic Deliberation, and the Legitimacy Problem for Insurers, " Philosophy and Public Affairs 26, no. 4 (1997): 303-50.
-
(1997)
Philosophy and Public Affairs
, vol.26
, Issue.4
, pp. 303-350
-
-
Daniels, N.1
Sabin, J.2
-
57
-
-
0004294588
-
-
Gutmann and Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement. As Gutmann and Thompson emphasize, they diverge from some advocates of deliberation in believing that political deliberation cannot itself be the "sovereign guide" to resolving moral disagreements. Rather, Gutmann and Thompson contend that liberty and basic opportunity must operate as substantive concepts that guide the content of deliberation. Ibid., 17-18.
-
Democracy and Disagreement
-
-
Gutmann1
Thompson2
-
58
-
-
85013928982
-
-
Gutmann and Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement. As Gutmann and Thompson emphasize, they diverge from some advocates of deliberation in believing that political deliberation cannot itself be the "sovereign guide" to resolving moral disagreements. Rather, Gutmann and Thompson contend that liberty and basic opportunity must operate as substantive concepts that guide the content of deliberation. Ibid., 17-18.
-
Democracy and Disagreement
, pp. 17-18
-
-
-
61
-
-
85013895734
-
-
Ibid., 323. In their essay, Daniels and Sabin are focusing on allocation decisions made by private health-insurance organizations. However, their arguments are equally applicable to public institutions.
-
Limits to Health Care
, pp. 323
-
-
-
62
-
-
85013895734
-
-
n. 24
-
Ibid., 326 n. 24, citing Frederick Schauer, "Giving Reasons, " Stanford Law Review 47, no. 4 (1995): 657.
-
Limits to Health Care
, pp. 326
-
-
-
63
-
-
71849088940
-
Giving reasons
-
Ibid., 326 n. 24, citing Frederick Schauer, "Giving Reasons, " Stanford Law Review 47, no. 4 (1995): 657.
-
(1995)
Stanford Law Review
, vol.47
, Issue.4
, pp. 657
-
-
Schauer, F.1
-
64
-
-
0040215395
-
Implementing cost-benefit analysis when preferences are distorted
-
Matthew D. Adler and Eric A. Posner, "Implementing Cost-Benefit Analysis When Preferences Are Distorted, " Journal of Legal Studies 29 (2000): 1106.
-
(2000)
Journal of Legal Studies
, vol.29
, pp. 1106
-
-
Adler, M.D.1
Posner, E.A.2
-
65
-
-
0347107211
-
Cognition and cost-benefit analysis
-
For example, individuals often do a very poor job of assessing the probability of uncertain events. See generally Cass S. Sunstein, "Cognition and Cost-Benefit Analysis, " Journal of Legal Studies 29, no. 2 (2000): 1059-97; see also Rai, "Rationing through Choice, " 1069.
-
(2000)
Journal of Legal Studies
, vol.29
, Issue.2
, pp. 1059-1097
-
-
Sunstein, C.S.1
-
66
-
-
0347107211
-
-
For example, individuals often do a very poor job of assessing the probability of uncertain events. See generally Cass S. Sunstein, "Cognition and Cost-Benefit Analysis, " Journal of Legal Studies 29, no. 2 (2000): 1059-97; see also Rai, "Rationing through Choice, " 1069.
-
Rationing Through Choice
, pp. 1069
-
-
Rai1
-
68
-
-
0040809919
-
-
Ibid. (observing that many moral and political theories hold that "a policy's effect on people's welfare is a relevant, though not necessarily conclusive, consideration").
-
Implementing Cost-benefit Analysis
, pp. 1106
-
-
-
69
-
-
0040809919
-
-
See generally Adler and Posner, "Implementing Cost-Benefit Analysis"; and Sunstein, "Cognition and Cost-Benefit Analysis." Even Gutmann and Thompson, who offer a vigorous critique of cost-benefit analysis and of utilitarianism more generally, note that utilitarian analysis "deserves a place in deliberative democracy." Gutmann and Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement, 196. Similarly, Daniels and Sabin suggest that private insurance companies should use cost-effectiveness criteria and should be forthcoming about such use. See Daniels and Sabin, "Limits to Health Care, " 335: "If people share the goal of meeting the varied medical needs of a population covered by limited resources, and they share a commitment to justifying limitations by reference to reasons all can consider appropriate and relevant, then they will be interested in a reason that says a particular technology falls below some defensible threshold of cost-effectiveness or relative cost-worthiness."
-
Implementing Cost-benefit Analysis
-
-
Adler1
Posner2
-
70
-
-
62749083104
-
-
See generally Adler and Posner, "Implementing Cost-Benefit Analysis"; and Sunstein, "Cognition and Cost-Benefit Analysis." Even Gutmann and Thompson, who offer a vigorous critique of cost-benefit analysis and of utilitarianism more generally, note that utilitarian analysis "deserves a place in deliberative democracy." Gutmann and Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement, 196. Similarly, Daniels and Sabin suggest that private insurance companies should use cost-effectiveness criteria and should be forthcoming about such use. See Daniels and Sabin, "Limits to Health Care, " 335: "If people share the goal of meeting the varied medical needs of a population covered by limited resources, and they share a commitment to justifying limitations by reference to reasons all can consider appropriate and relevant, then they will be interested in a reason that says a particular technology falls below some defensible threshold of cost-effectiveness or relative cost-worthiness."
-
Cognition and Cost-benefit Analysis
-
-
Sunstein1
-
71
-
-
0004294588
-
-
See generally Adler and Posner, "Implementing Cost-Benefit Analysis"; and Sunstein, "Cognition and Cost-Benefit Analysis." Even Gutmann and Thompson, who offer a vigorous critique of cost-benefit analysis and of utilitarianism more generally, note that utilitarian analysis "deserves a place in deliberative democracy." Gutmann and Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement, 196. Similarly, Daniels and Sabin suggest that private insurance companies should use cost-effectiveness criteria and should be forthcoming about such use. See Daniels and Sabin, "Limits to Health Care, " 335: "If people share the goal of meeting the varied medical needs of a population covered by limited resources, and they share a commitment to justifying limitations by reference to reasons all can consider appropriate and relevant, then they will be interested in a reason that says a particular technology falls below some defensible threshold of cost-effectiveness or relative cost-worthiness."
-
Democracy and Disagreement
, pp. 196
-
-
Gutmann1
Thompson2
-
72
-
-
0040215411
-
-
See generally Adler and Posner, "Implementing Cost-Benefit Analysis"; and Sunstein, "Cognition and Cost-Benefit Analysis." Even Gutmann and Thompson, who offer a vigorous critique of cost-benefit analysis and of utilitarianism more generally, note that utilitarian analysis "deserves a place in deliberative democracy." Gutmann and Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement, 196. Similarly, Daniels and Sabin suggest that private insurance companies should use cost-effectiveness criteria and should be forthcoming about such use. See Daniels and Sabin, "Limits to Health Care, " 335: "If people share the goal of meeting the varied medical needs of a population covered by limited resources, and they share a commitment to justifying limitations by reference to reasons all can consider appropriate and relevant, then they will be interested in a reason that says a particular technology falls below some defensible threshold of cost-effectiveness or relative cost-worthiness."
-
Limits to Health Care
, pp. 335
-
-
Daniels1
Sabin2
-
73
-
-
85013897583
-
-
note
-
By executive order, Presidents Reagan, George H. W. Bush, Clinton, and George W. Bush have all required cost-benefit analysis of major regulations.
-
-
-
-
74
-
-
0003564175
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
See generally Stephen Breyer, Breaking the Vicious Circle: Toward Effective Risk Regulation (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993); and W. Kip Viscusi, Fatal Tradeoffs: Public and Private Responsibilities for Risk (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992).
-
(1993)
Breaking the Vicious Circle: Toward Effective Risk Regulation
-
-
Breyer, S.1
-
75
-
-
0003621511
-
-
New York: Oxford University Press
-
See generally Stephen Breyer, Breaking the Vicious Circle: Toward Effective Risk Regulation (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993); and W. Kip Viscusi, Fatal Tradeoffs: Public and Private Responsibilities for Risk (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992).
-
(1992)
Fatal Tradeoffs: Public and Private Responsibilities for Risk
-
-
Viscusi, W.K.1
-
76
-
-
0003441274
-
-
NIH publication number 97-4265, September
-
NIH Working Group on Priority Setting, "Setting Research Priorities and the National Institutes of Health" (NIH publication number 97-4265, September 1997). As Rebecca Dresser has pointed out, current levels of NIH funding for particular diseases are strongly correlated with the welfare losses that the diseases cause. Rebecca Dresser, When Science Offers Salvation (New York: Oxford University Press, 2001), 83. As discussed further below, these welfare losses are typically calculated in units called quality-adjusted life-years, or QALYs.
-
(1997)
Setting Research Priorities and the National Institutes of Health
-
-
-
77
-
-
0009668229
-
-
New York: Oxford University Press
-
NIH Working Group on Priority Setting, "Setting Research Priorities and the National Institutes of Health" (NIH publication number 97-4265, September 1997). As Rebecca Dresser has pointed out, current levels of NIH funding for particular diseases are strongly correlated with the welfare losses that the diseases cause. Rebecca Dresser, When Science Offers Salvation (New York: Oxford University Press, 2001), 83. As discussed further below, these welfare losses are typically calculated in units called quality-adjusted life-years, or QALYs.
-
(2001)
When Science Offers Salvation
, pp. 83
-
-
Dresser, R.1
-
79
-
-
85013979621
-
-
note
-
The marginal cost is effectively zero because the cost of the chemical(s) that make up the drug is generally negligible.
-
-
-
-
80
-
-
0141604347
-
Special provisions for pharmaceuticals: Have they outlived their usefulness?
-
See Alfred Engelberg, "Special Provisions for Pharmaceuticals: Have They Outlived Their Usefulness?" IDEA 39, no. 3 (1999): 420 (noting that it is common practice to file patent applications before human testing has begun, because waiting might result in the information relevant to the invention becoming generally known and therefore unpatentable).
-
(1999)
IDEA
, vol.39
, Issue.3
, pp. 420
-
-
Engelberg, A.1
-
81
-
-
85013876339
-
-
The Drug Price Competition and Restoration Act of 1984, Pub. L. No. 98-417, 98 Stat. 1585 (1984) (codified as amended throughout 21 U.S.C. [1994])
-
The Drug Price Competition and Restoration Act of 1984, Pub. L. No. 98-417, 98 Stat. 1585 (1984) (codified as amended throughout 21 U.S.C. [1994]).
-
-
-
-
82
-
-
85013969090
-
-
35 U.S.C. § 156 (1994). Hatch-Waxman imposes a five-year cap on the extension term that can be granted
-
35 U.S.C. § 156 (1994). Hatch-Waxman imposes a five-year cap on the extension term that can be granted.
-
-
-
-
83
-
-
0141604347
-
-
See Engelberg, "Special Provisions for Pharmaceuticals, " 420 (citing analysis issued by the Patent and Trademark Office). Indeed, with respect to particularly lucrative drugs, drug manufacturers sometimes manage to gain patent protection for more than fourteen years after FDA approval. They obtain this additional protection by strategically seeking additional patents on a drug several years before the basic patent that received the Hatch-Waxman extension is set to expire. Ibid., 415, 420. Although these additional patents are often somewhat marginal in that they claim uses for the drug that have not previously been approved, specific drug formulations, or even tablet shape (see ibid.), they can succeed in delaying competition by generic drugs. Such delay results because the Hatch-Waxman Act contains a provision requiring the FDA to stay the approval process for a generic drug for thirty months if a brand-name manufacturer claims that one of its patents, no matter how marginal, is being infringed by the generic. I discuss these problems with the Hatch-Waxman Act in Rai, "The Information Revolution Reaches Pharmaceuticals, " 183-85.
-
Special Provisions for Pharmaceuticals
, pp. 420
-
-
Engelberg1
-
84
-
-
0040215394
-
-
See Engelberg, "Special Provisions for Pharmaceuticals, " 420 (citing analysis issued by the Patent and Trademark Office). Indeed, with respect to particularly lucrative drugs, drug manufacturers sometimes manage to gain patent protection for more than fourteen years after FDA approval. They obtain this additional protection by strategically seeking additional patents on a drug several years before the basic patent that received the Hatch-Waxman extension is set to expire. Ibid., 415, 420. Although these additional patents are often somewhat marginal in that they claim uses for the drug that have not previously been approved, specific drug formulations, or even tablet shape (see ibid.), they can succeed in delaying competition by generic drugs. Such delay results because the Hatch-Waxman Act contains a provision requiring the FDA to stay the approval process for a generic drug for thirty months if a brand-name manufacturer claims that one of its patents, no matter how marginal, is being infringed by the generic. I discuss these problems with the Hatch-Waxman Act in Rai, "The Information Revolution Reaches Pharmaceuticals, " 183-85.
-
Special Provisions for Pharmaceuticals
, pp. 415
-
-
-
85
-
-
85013981059
-
-
See Engelberg, "Special Provisions for Pharmaceuticals, " 420 (citing analysis issued by the Patent and Trademark Office). Indeed, with respect to particularly lucrative drugs, drug manufacturers sometimes manage to gain patent protection for more than fourteen years after FDA approval. They obtain this additional protection by strategically seeking additional patents on a drug several years before the basic patent that received the Hatch-Waxman extension is set to expire. Ibid., 415, 420. Although these additional patents are often somewhat marginal in that they claim uses for the drug that have not previously been approved, specific drug formulations, or even tablet shape (see ibid.), they can succeed in delaying competition by generic drugs. Such delay results because the Hatch-Waxman Act contains a provision requiring the FDA to stay the approval process for a generic drug for thirty months if a brand-name manufacturer claims that one of its patents, no matter how marginal, is being infringed by the generic. I discuss these problems with the Hatch-Waxman Act in Rai, "The Information Revolution Reaches Pharmaceuticals, " 183-85.
-
The Information Revolution Reaches Pharmaceuticals
, pp. 183-185
-
-
-
86
-
-
85013984578
-
-
note
-
To be sure, the widespread presence of insurance in health-care markets may lead purchasers to consume health care whose costs exceed its benefits. For the purposes of this essay, however, I assume that health-care markets function efficiently because insurers have implemented mechanisms for curbing this insurance-induced tendency to overspend.
-
-
-
-
87
-
-
0017347943
-
Foundations of cost-effectiveness analysis for health and medical practices
-
See, e.g., Milton C. Weinstein and William B. Stason, "Foundations of Cost-Effectiveness Analysis for Health and Medical Practices, " New England Journal of Medicine 296, no. 13 (1977): 718. There is some debate about whether future medical costs unrelated to the relevant disease and/or future nonmedical costs should be included in the cost calculation. See ibid. (arguing that future unrelated medical costs should be included); and David Meltzer, "Accounting for Future Costs in Medical Cost-Effectiveness Analysis, " Journal of Health Economics 16, no. 1 (1997): 33-64 (arguing that future nonmedical costs should also be included). See also U.S. Department of Health and Human Services, Office of Public Health and Science, Office of Disease Prevention and Health Promotion, Panel on Cost-Effectiveness in Health and Medicine, Cost-Effectiveness in Health and Medicine (Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1996) (arguing that future nonmedical costs should not be included). Resolving these debates is not essential for the purposes of this essay.
-
(1977)
New England Journal of Medicine
, vol.296
, Issue.13
, pp. 718
-
-
Weinstein, M.C.1
Stason, W.B.2
-
88
-
-
0030915977
-
Accounting for future costs in medical cost-effectiveness analysis
-
See, e.g., Milton C. Weinstein and William B. Stason, "Foundations of Cost-Effectiveness Analysis for Health and Medical Practices, " New England Journal of Medicine 296, no. 13 (1977): 718. There is some debate about whether future medical costs unrelated to the relevant disease and/or future nonmedical costs should be included in the cost calculation. See ibid. (arguing that future unrelated medical costs should be included); and David Meltzer, "Accounting for Future Costs in Medical Cost-Effectiveness Analysis, " Journal of Health Economics 16, no. 1 (1997): 33-64 (arguing that future nonmedical costs should also be included). See also U.S. Department of Health and Human Services, Office of Public Health and Science, Office of Disease Prevention and Health Promotion, Panel on Cost-Effectiveness in Health and Medicine, Cost-Effectiveness in Health and Medicine (Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1996) (arguing that future nonmedical costs should not be included). Resolving these debates is not essential for the purposes of this essay.
-
(1997)
Journal of Health Economics
, vol.16
, Issue.1
, pp. 33-64
-
-
Meltzer, D.1
-
89
-
-
0017347943
-
-
Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office
-
See, e.g., Milton C. Weinstein and William B. Stason, "Foundations of Cost-Effectiveness Analysis for Health and Medical Practices, " New England Journal of Medicine 296, no. 13 (1977): 718. There is some debate about whether future medical costs unrelated to the relevant disease and/or future nonmedical costs should be included in the cost calculation. See ibid. (arguing that future unrelated medical costs should be included); and David Meltzer, "Accounting for Future Costs in Medical Cost-Effectiveness Analysis, " Journal of Health Economics 16, no. 1 (1997): 33-64 (arguing that future nonmedical costs should also be included). See also U.S. Department of Health and Human Services, Office of Public Health and Science, Office of Disease Prevention and Health Promotion, Panel on Cost-Effectiveness in Health and Medicine, Cost-Effectiveness in Health and Medicine (Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1996) (arguing that future nonmedical costs should not be included). Resolving these debates is not essential for the purposes of this essay.
-
(1996)
Cost-effectiveness in Health and Medicine
-
-
-
91
-
-
0000045869
-
How should what economists call 'social values' be measured?
-
See, e.g., Paul Menzel, "How Should What Economists Call 'Social Values' Be Measured?" Journal of Ethics 3, no. 3 (1999): 249-73; and Rai, "Rationing through Choice, " 1070-77.
-
(1999)
Journal of Ethics
, vol.3
, Issue.3
, pp. 249-273
-
-
Menzel, P.1
-
92
-
-
0000045869
-
-
See, e.g., Paul Menzel, "How Should What Economists Call 'Social Values' Be Measured?" Journal of Ethics 3, no. 3 (1999): 249-73; and Rai, "Rationing through Choice, " 1070-77.
-
Rationing Through Choice
, pp. 1070-1077
-
-
Rai1
-
93
-
-
0025937985
-
Oregon's methods: Did cost-effectiveness fail?
-
See David Eddy, "Oregon's Methods: Did Cost-Effectiveness Fail?" Journal of the American Medical Association 266, no. 15 (1991): 2140. For a similar suggestion, see Menzel, "How Should 'Social Values' Be Measured?" 261-65.
-
(1991)
Journal of the American Medical Association
, vol.266
, Issue.15
, pp. 2140
-
-
Eddy, D.1
-
94
-
-
0025937985
-
-
See David Eddy, "Oregon's Methods: Did Cost-Effectiveness Fail?" Journal of the American Medical Association 266, no. 15 (1991): 2140. For a similar suggestion, see Menzel, "How Should 'Social Values' Be Measured?" 261-65.
-
How Should 'Social Values' Be Measured?
, pp. 261-265
-
-
Menzel1
-
95
-
-
0344646776
-
Is technological change in medicine worth it?
-
See David M. Cutler and Mark McClellan, "Is Technological Change in Medicine Worth It?" Health Affairs 20, no. 5 (2001): 1129-45.
-
(2001)
Health Affairs
, vol.20
, Issue.5
, pp. 1129-1145
-
-
Cutler, D.M.1
McClellan, M.2
-
96
-
-
85013992495
-
-
I analyze the arguments put forward by some of these commentators in Rai, "Rationing through Choice, " 1076-97. A recent interesting treatment of the discrimination issue is found in Menzel, "How Should 'Social Values' Be Measured?" 259-73.
-
Rationing Through Choice
, pp. 1076-1097
-
-
Rai1
-
97
-
-
0039623486
-
-
I analyze the arguments put forward by some of these commentators in Rai, "Rationing through Choice, " 1076-97. A recent interesting treatment of the discrimination issue is found in Menzel, "How Should 'Social Values' Be Measured?" 259-73.
-
How Should 'Social Values' Be Measured?
, pp. 259-273
-
-
Menzel1
-
98
-
-
85013971248
-
-
The Americans with Disabilities Act, 42 U.S.C. §§ 12101 et seq. (1994)
-
The Americans with Disabilities Act, 42 U.S.C. §§ 12101 et seq. (1994).
-
-
-
-
99
-
-
0028798707
-
Economic decision making in healthcare: A standard approach to discounting health outcomes
-
See Alan L. Hillman, "Economic Decision Making in Healthcare: A Standard Approach to Discounting Health Outcomes, " Pharmacoeconomics 7, no. 3 (1995): 199.
-
(1995)
Pharmacoeconomics
, vol.7
, Issue.3
, pp. 199
-
-
Hillman, A.L.1
-
100
-
-
85013932276
-
-
note
-
r. By contrast, in a more formal mathematical treatment, interest might be calculated instantaneously.
-
-
-
-
101
-
-
0026840489
-
Discounting and health benefits
-
See Michael Parsonage and Henry Neuberger, "Discounting and Health Benefits, " Health Economics 1, no. 1 (1992): 71-79.
-
(1992)
Health Economics
, vol.1
, Issue.1
, pp. 71-79
-
-
Parsonage, M.1
Neuberger, H.2
-
102
-
-
0039623483
-
-
Ibid., 73. See also Lisa Heinzerling, "Regulatory Costs of Mythic Proportions, " Yale Law Journal 107, no. 7 (1998): 2046-49; and Hillman and Kim, "Economic Decision Making in Healthcare, " 200. The available data here has generally been gathered from experimental studies of subjects who are asked questions about how they value future harms and from evidence on workers' willingness to accept wage premiums in exchange for future health risks.
-
Health Economics
, pp. 73
-
-
-
103
-
-
0039623483
-
Regulatory costs of mythic proportions
-
Ibid., 73. See also Lisa Heinzerling, "Regulatory Costs of Mythic Proportions, " Yale Law Journal 107, no. 7 (1998): 2046-49; and Hillman and Kim, "Economic Decision Making in Healthcare, " 200. The available data here has generally been gathered from experimental studies of subjects who are asked questions about how they value future harms and from evidence on workers' willingness to accept wage premiums in exchange for future health risks.
-
(1998)
Yale Law Journal
, vol.107
, Issue.7
, pp. 2046-2049
-
-
Heinzerling, L.1
-
104
-
-
0039623483
-
-
Ibid., 73. See also Lisa Heinzerling, "Regulatory Costs of Mythic Proportions, " Yale Law Journal 107, no. 7 (1998): 2046-49; and Hillman and Kim, "Economic Decision Making in Healthcare, " 200. The available data here has generally been gathered from experimental studies of subjects who are asked questions about how they value future harms and from evidence on workers' willingness to accept wage premiums in exchange for future health risks.
-
Economic Decision Making in Healthcare
, pp. 200
-
-
Hillman1
Kim2
-
107
-
-
0033127822
-
Environmental regulation, cost-benefit analysis, and the discounting of human lives
-
See Richard Revesz, "Environmental Regulation, Cost-Benefit Analysis, and the Discounting of Human Lives, " Columbia Law Review 99, no. 4 (1999): 975-79; and Daniel Farber and Paul A. Hemmersbaugh, "The Shadow of the Future: Discount Rates, Later Generations, and the Environment, " Vanderbilt Law Review 46, no. 2 (1993): 283-85.
-
(1999)
Columbia Law Review
, vol.99
, Issue.4
, pp. 975-979
-
-
Revesz, R.1
-
108
-
-
21144481908
-
The shadow of the future: Discount rates, later generations, and the environment
-
See Richard Revesz, "Environmental Regulation, Cost-Benefit Analysis, and the Discounting of Human Lives, " Columbia Law Review 99, no. 4 (1999): 975-79; and Daniel Farber and Paul A. Hemmersbaugh, "The Shadow of the Future: Discount Rates, Later Generations, and the Environment, " Vanderbilt Law Review 46, no. 2 (1993): 283-85.
-
(1993)
Vanderbilt Law Review
, vol.46
, Issue.2
, pp. 283-285
-
-
Farber, D.1
Hemmersbaugh, P.A.2
-
109
-
-
85013971060
-
-
note
-
To the extent that the time horizon is extended because particular drugs yield appreciable benefits even after one generation, considerations of intergenerational justice might require using a somewhat lower discount rate for future generations than is used for the current generation. The lower the discount rate for future generations, the greater the weight attached to their interests.
-
-
-
-
110
-
-
85013924771
-
-
note
-
0.
-
-
-
-
111
-
-
85013893164
-
-
note
-
For purposes of this essay, I make the simplifying assumption that benefits accrue, and are discounted at, the end of each year.
-
-
-
-
112
-
-
85013918090
-
-
note
-
In fact, there is reason to believe that the pharmaceutical industry uses a discount rate significantly higher than the real interest rate for money. To the extent that the pharmaceutical industry demands rates of return higher than those found in other industries (in order to compensate for the high level of risk involved in pharmaceutical development), it may discount future income flow more steeply than other industries do. For purposes of this essay, however, I will make the conservative assumption of a 3 percent real discount rate for money, even in the pharmaceutical industry.
-
-
-
-
113
-
-
85013951896
-
-
The precise nature of a drug manufacturer's monopoly power will depend on the scope of its patent, the possible availability of substitutes for the relevant drug, the price-sensitivity of consumers, and the amount of price discrimination that health insurers can secure in virtue of their bargaining power. In the case of pharmaceutical products, patents are often broad and consumers (particularly insured consumers) are quite price-insensitive. Thus, even though competitors to a patented drug generally emerge after a few years, their potential impact on price competition is softened by the fact that they are imperfect substitutes that price-insensitive consumers will not readily embrace. Rai, "The Information Revolution Reaches Pharmaceuticals, " 206.
-
The Information Revolution Reaches Pharmaceuticals
, pp. 206
-
-
Rai1
-
114
-
-
0003646313
-
-
New York: W. W. Norton
-
Hal Varian, Intermediate Microeconomics: A Modern Approach, 5th ed. (New York: W. W. Norton, 1999), 420-24. Unlike the competitive producer, who produces to the point where price equals marginal cost, the monopolistic producer typically operates only at prices well above marginal cost. Ibid., 420. This is particularly true in industries like the prescription-drug industry, where the marginal costs of production are virtually zero.
-
(1999)
Intermediate Microeconomics: A Modern Approach, 5th Ed.
, pp. 420-424
-
-
Varian, H.1
-
115
-
-
85013972366
-
-
Hal Varian, Intermediate Microeconomics: A Modern Approach, 5th ed. (New York: W. W. Norton, 1999), 420-24. Unlike the competitive producer, who produces to the point where price equals marginal cost, the monopolistic producer typically operates only at prices well above marginal cost. Ibid., 420. This is particularly true in industries like the prescription-drug industry, where the marginal costs of production are virtually zero.
-
Intermediate Microeconomics: A Modern Approach, 5th Ed.
, pp. 420
-
-
-
117
-
-
0039623408
-
Funding fairness: Public investment, proprietary rights, and access to health care technology
-
See William Sage, "Funding Fairness: Public Investment, Proprietary Rights, and Access to Health Care Technology, " Virginia Law Review 82, no. 8 (1996): 1741-42: "[A]n obvious side-effect of patent monopolies - like other monopolies - is to increase price and decrease output. As a result, patented inventions may not be affordable to those who need them. If equity is a concern in the provision of health care services, awarding patents, especially for breakthrough therapies, tends in the opposite direction."
-
(1996)
Virginia Law Review
, vol.82
, Issue.8
, pp. 1741-1742
-
-
Sage, W.1
|