메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 26, Issue 4, 1997, Pages 303-350

Limits to health care: Fair procedures, democratic deliberation, and the legitimacy problem for insurers

(2)  Daniels, Norman a   Sabin, James a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords

HORMONE;

EID: 0031217084     PISSN: 00483915     EISSN: 10884963     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1088-4963.1997.tb00082.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (496)

References (49)
  • 1
    • 53249151807 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Medical insurance traditionally excludes beneficial nonmedical services (e.g., dental, home supports); it also arbitrarily limits beneficial mental health services (e.g., 10 not 20 therapy sessions, or 30 not 35 hospital days). The use of guidelines, utilization review, and systematic technology assessment arguably limits some beneficial services at the margin, including cases when a patient or clinician has good reason to object to the limits.
  • 2
    • 53249137997 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Decisions about new technologies are only the tip of the limit-setting iceberg. Much of what is said about these decisions can be generalized to other, explicit limit-setting decisions, including practice guidelines approved by MCOs. Despite their importance, we will not discuss the discretionary, limit-setting decisions of practitioners who limit care because they are responding to economic incentives to reduce treatment.
  • 3
    • 53249086037 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Since even "unmanaged" indemnity insurers manage coverage for new technologies, lumping them together is less problematic than it might otherwise be
    • Since even "unmanaged" indemnity insurers manage coverage for new technologies, lumping them together is less problematic than it might otherwise be.
  • 4
    • 0026199061 scopus 로고
    • When Is Home Care Medically Necessary?
    • July-August
    • The term "medical necessity" is partly intended to confer legitimacy on some decisions about limiting our obligations to provide medical assistance. See Norman Daniels and James E. Sabin, "When Is Home Care Medically Necessary?" Hastings Center Report 21, no. 4 (July-August 1991): 37-38,
    • (1991) Hastings Center Report , vol.21 , Issue.4 , pp. 37-38
    • Daniels, N.1    Sabin, J.E.2
  • 5
    • 0028537106 scopus 로고
    • Determining 'Medical Necessity' in Mental Health Practice: A Study of Clinical Reasoning and a Proposal for Insurance Policy
    • November-December
    • and James E. Sabin and Norman Daniels, "Determining 'Medical Necessity' in Mental Health Practice: A Study of Clinical Reasoning and a Proposal for Insurance Policy," Hastings Center Report 24, no. 6 (November-December 1994): 5-13.
    • (1994) Hastings Center Report , vol.24 , Issue.6 , pp. 5-13
    • Sabin, J.E.1    Daniels, N.2
  • 7
    • 0000260962 scopus 로고
    • Uncertainty and the Welfare Economics of Medical Care
    • Kenneth Arrow, "Uncertainty and the Welfare Economics of Medical Care," American Economic Review 53 (1963): 941-73.
    • (1963) American Economic Review , vol.53 , pp. 941-973
    • Arrow, K.1
  • 8
    • 84937273267 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chapter 2
    • Despite the failure of the Clinton effort at universal coverage and the recent elimination of entitlement status to Medicaid, survey evidence still points to widespread support for universal coverage in the U.S., and we should be wary of drawing inferences about the decline of support from the complex political events involved in welfare reform and the failure of health care reform. See Daniels, Light, and Caplan, Benchmarks of Fairness for Health Care Reform, Chapter 2.
    • Benchmarks of Fairness for Health Care Reform
    • Daniels1    Light2    Caplan3
  • 9
    • 53249117383 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A possible exception might be people with physical disabilities, though we generally see our obligation to them as requiring that existing transportation for others be accessible to them
    • A possible exception might be people with physical disabilities, though we generally see our obligation to them as requiring that existing transportation for others be accessible to them.
  • 10
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • Formal equality of opportunity (careers open to talents) prohibits legal or quasi-legal barriers to access to jobs and offices. Equality of fair opportunity corrects for socially induced disadvantages in the development of talents and skills that result from social practices such as racism, sexism, or significant inequalities in family background. See John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 65ff.
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 11
    • 0003412671 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Cambridge University Press, Chapter 3
    • By subsuming health care under the fair equality of opportunity principle, Daniels extends Rawls' principle and theory. See Norman Daniels, Just Health Care (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1985), Chapter 3.
    • (1985) Just Health Care
    • Daniels, N.1
  • 12
    • 0003412671 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Daniels argues that the fact that we have social obligations to provide universal coverage for medical needs does not imply that individual physicians have some specific set of obligations to treat all needy patients (Daniels, Just Health Care, pp. 115-19).
    • Just Health Care , pp. 115-119
    • Daniels1
  • 13
    • 0343714840 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press, Chapter 4
    • Similarly, insurers who legally exclude high-risk patients from coverage are not to be blamed for violating an obligation of justice, even if the exclusion of these patients is unjust (see Norman Daniels, Seeking Fair Treatment: From the AIDS Epidemic to National Health Care Reform (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995), Chapter 4). The obligation here is society's, not the corporations'. But the social obligation means that collective action must be taken to specify the obligations of individual practitioners and corporations, modifying "business as usual" if that is needed to produce just outcomes.
    • (1995) Seeking Fair Treatment: From the AIDS Epidemic to National Health Care Reform
    • Daniels, N.1
  • 16
    • 0029116891 scopus 로고
    • High-dose Chemotherapy with Hematopoietic Rescue as Primary Treatment for Metastatic Breast Cancer: A Randomized Trial
    • The MAP criteria are as follows: a. The technology must have final approval from the appropriate government regulatory body. b. The scientific evidence must permit conclusions concerning the effect of the technology on health outcomes. c. The technology must improve the net health outcome. d. The technology must be as beneficial as any established alternative. e. The improvement must be attainable outside the investigational settings. MAP does not make coverage decisions, however; MCOs do. A South African study (WR. Bezwoda, L. Seymour, RD. Dansey, "High-dose Chemotherapy with Hematopoietic Rescue as Primary Treatment for Metastatic Breast Cancer: A Randomized Trial," Journal of Clinical Oncology 13 [1995]: 2483-89), the only published randomized clinical trial available as of mid-1966, used as its control a regimen of standard chemotherapy that was inferior in outcomes to the conventional therapy that would standardly be available in the U.S. and elsewhere. Consequently, it should not persuade us of the superior efficacy of the high-dose regimen. Using the same criteria, Blue Shield of Northern California judged the therapy "investigational" even after the national MAP voted the opposite.
    • (1995) Journal of Clinical Oncology , vol.13 , pp. 2483-2489
    • Bezwoda, W.R.1    Seymour, L.2    Dansey, R.D.3
  • 19
    • 0027588005 scopus 로고
    • Rationing Fairly: Programmatic Considerations
    • Also see Norman Daniels, "Rationing Fairly: Programmatic Considerations," Bioethics 7 (1993): 223-33,
    • (1993) Bioethics , vol.7 , pp. 223-233
    • Daniels, N.1
  • 22
    • 0027471732 scopus 로고
    • The Relevance of Health State after Treatment in Prioritising between Different Patients
    • The claim is based on observations over several years of how audiences of students and medical personal vote on hypothetical cases of this sort. Eric Nord has reported variations in attitudes toward priorities of this sort between different groups of students and professionals. See Eric Nord, "The Relevance of Health State After Treatment in Prioritising between Different Patients," Journal of Medical Ethics 19 (1993): 37-42.
    • (1993) Journal of Medical Ethics , vol.19 , pp. 37-42
    • Nord, E.1
  • 23
    • 0028789137 scopus 로고
    • Maximizing Health Benefits vs Egalitarianism: An Australian Survey of Health Issues
    • There is some cross-national evidence that people are not straight maximizers in Eric Nord, Jeff Richardson, Andrew Street, Helga Kuhse, and Peter Singer, "Maximizing Health Benefits vs Egalitarianism: An Australian Survey of Health Issues," Social Science and Medicine 41, no. 10 (1995): 1429-37.
    • (1995) Social Science and Medicine , vol.41 , Issue.10 , pp. 1429-1437
    • Nord, E.1    Richardson, J.2    Street, A.3    Kuhse, H.4    Singer, P.5
  • 24
    • 53249086036 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • A distinct minority of students and health professionals would argue as follows: if helping the less-sick patient actually returns her to a level of functioning that permits her to work and carry out other social activities, whereas helping the sicker patient does not accomplish this outcome, then it is more important to help the healthier patient. Some holding this view reason that the healthier patient will then return more to society, but others justify their view by saying the healthier patient is likely to be happier than the sicker one, focusing only on the relative well-being of the patients, not on their social contribution.
  • 25
    • 0003780123 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Frances Kamm suggests this may be true. Her brilliant discussion of cases often points to less disagreement than we find in thinking about them with students or public audiences. See Frances Kamm, Morality and Mortality, Volume 1: Death and Whom to Save From It (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993).
    • (1993) Morality and Mortality, Volume 1: Death and Whom to Save from It , vol.1
    • Kamm, F.1
  • 29
    • 0002000290 scopus 로고
    • Contractualism and Utilitarianism
    • Amartya Sen and Bernard Williams, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • and T. M. Scanlon, "Contractualism and Utilitarianism," in Amartya Sen and Bernard Williams, Utilitarianism and Beyond (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), pp. 103-28 .
    • (1982) Utilitarianism and Beyond , pp. 103-128
    • Scanlon, T.M.1
  • 31
    • 0004294588 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • These conditions were developed independently but fit reasonably well with the principles of publicity, reciprocity, and accountability governing democratic deliberation cited by Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1996).
    • (1996) Democracy and Disagreement
    • Gutmann, A.1    Thompson, D.2
  • 32
    • 33747511875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pacific Division of the American Philosophical Association, March 28
    • For reservations about their account, see Norman Daniels, "Enabling Democratic Deliberation," Pacific Division of the American Philosophical Association, March 28, 1997.
    • (1997) Enabling Democratic Deliberation
    • Daniels, N.1
  • 33
    • 0002889566 scopus 로고
    • Goals of Medicine: Setting New Priorities
    • November-December
    • See Hastings Center, "Goals of Medicine: Setting New Priorities," in Hastings Center Report 26:6 (November-December, 1966): S1-S28, Special Supplement;
    • (1966) Hastings Center Report , vol.26 , Issue.6 SPECIAL SUPPL.
  • 34
    • 0030278118 scopus 로고
    • Justice, Fair Procedures, and the Goals of Medicine
    • November-December
    • see also Norman Daniels, "Justice, Fair Procedures, and the Goals of Medicine," Hastings Center Report 26:6 (November-December 1966): 10-12.
    • (1966) Hastings Center Report , vol.26 , Issue.6 , pp. 10-12
    • Daniels, N.1
  • 35
    • 85017285588 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Directly Deliberative Polyarchy
    • forthcoming
    • See Joshua Cohen and Charles Sobel, "Directly Deliberative Polyarchy," European Law Journal (forthcoming), for a discussion of the value of democratic deliberation in decentralized institutions that converges with points we make here.
    • European Law Journal
    • Cohen, J.1    Sobel, C.2
  • 36
    • 71849088940 scopus 로고
    • Giving Reasons
    • Frederick Schauer notes that "decisionmakers themselves are unlikely to fully apprehend and appreciate this function [that reason-giving increases discipline], for most decisionmakers underestimate the need for external quality control of their own decisions. But when institutional designers have grounds for believing that decisions will systematically be the product of bias, self-interest, insufficient reflection, or simply excess haste, requiring decisionmakers to give reasons may counteract some of these tendencies." Frederick Shauer, "Giving Reasons," Stanford Law Review 47, no. 4 (1995): 633-59, at 657.
    • (1995) Stanford Law Review , vol.47 , Issue.4 , pp. 633-659
    • Shauer, F.1
  • 39
    • 0004236541 scopus 로고
    • Growth Hormone Therapy for Short Stature: Can We Support the Treatment/Enhancement Distinction?
    • also Norman Daniels, "Growth Hormone Therapy for Short Stature: Can We Support the Treatment/Enhancement Distinction?" Growth: Genetics and Hormones 8, suppl. 1 (1992): 46-48.
    • (1992) Growth: Genetics and Hormones , vol.8 , Issue.1 SUPPL. , pp. 46-48
    • Daniels, N.1
  • 40
    • 53249156153 scopus 로고
    • Justice and the Dissemination of Big Ticket Technologies
    • Deborah Mathieu, Boulder: Westview
    • See Norman Daniels, "Justice and the Dissemination of Big Ticket Technologies," in Deborah Mathieu, Organ Substitution Technology: Ethical, Legal, and Public Policy Issues (Boulder: Westview, 1988), pp.211-20.
    • (1988) Organ Substitution Technology: Ethical, Legal, and Public Policy Issues , pp. 211-220
    • Daniels, N.1
  • 42
    • 0002805654 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy
    • Seyla Benhabib, ed., Princeton University Press
    • Joshua Cohen, "Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy," in Seyla Benhabib, ed., Democracy and Difference: Changing Boundaries of the Political (Princeton University Press, 1996), pp. 95-119;
    • (1996) Democracy and Difference: Changing Boundaries of the Political , pp. 95-119
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 43
    • 0003998520 scopus 로고
    • Pluralism and Proceduralism
    • Joshua Cohen, "Pluralism and Proceduralism," Chicago-Kent Law Review 69, no. 3 (1994): 589-618;
    • (1994) Chicago-Kent Law Review , vol.69 , Issue.3 , pp. 589-618
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 44
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993);
    • (1993) Political Liberalism
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 45
    • 0003974417 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • Cass Sunstein, The Partial Constitution (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1993).
    • (1993) The Partial Constitution
    • Sunstein, C.1
  • 47
    • 0003903243 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cohen notes that an aggregative view might arguably be extended to give some protection from outcomes that involved discrimination against those who are targets of stereotyping or hostility, e.g., against people with disabilities or racial minorities. A process that allowed simple aggregation of those preferences arguably does not give people equal consideration and so violates its own rationale. Cohen, "Deliberative Democracy," p. 15.
    • Deliberative Democracy , pp. 15
    • Cohen1
  • 48
    • 53249095710 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • If organizations that put reasons forward (call them ice breakers) actually benefited, then the coordination problem we describe comes from a misestimate of what self-interested action calls for. It is the misestimate that sets up the public-goods problem (the many-person prisoners dilemma) informally described in the text. If organizations that act as ice breakers when others fail to do so actually do worse, then we have a true many-persons prisoners dilemma.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.