메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 110, Issue 7, 2013, Pages 391-411

Rethinking turing's test

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84890032410     PISSN: 0022362X     EISSN: 19398549     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.5840/jphil2013110722     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (22)

References (98)
  • 3
    • 79952428470 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Manchester computer: A revised history
    • January-March
    • For a comprehensive history, see Copeland, "The Manchester Computer: A Revised History," IEEE Annals of the History of Computing, xxxiii, 1 ( January-March 2011): 4-37.
    • (2011) IEEE Annals of the History of Computing , vol.33 , Issue.1 , pp. 4-37
    • Copeland1
  • 4
    • 0002988210 scopus 로고
    • Computing machinery and intelligence
    • October
    • Alan M. Turing, "Computing Machinery and Intelligence," Mind, lix, 236 (October 1950): 433-60. See p. 436. turing 391 0022-362X/13/1007/391- 411
    • (1950) Mind , vol.59 , Issue.236 , pp. 433-460
    • Turing, A.M.1
  • 6
    • 0013151006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford
    • Reproduced in Copeland, ed., The Essential Turing (New York: Oxford, 2004), pp. 410-32.
    • (2004) The Essential Turing , pp. 410-432
    • Copeland1
  • 10
    • 85039633755 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Artificial intelligence: History, foundations, and philosophical issues
    • Copeland and Proudfoot, "Artificial Intelligence: History, Foundations, and Philosophical Issues" and "Turing and the Computer."
    • Turing and the Computer
    • Copeland1    Proudfoot2
  • 11
    • 77951998929 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Turing et al., "Can Automatic Calculating Machines Be Said to Think ," p. 495. In 1950 Turing famously predicted that "in about fifty years' time it will be possible to programme computers, with a storage capacity of about 109, to make them play the imitation game so well that an average interrogator will not have more than 70 per cent. chance of making the right identification after five minutes of questioning"
    • Can Automatic Calculating Machines Be Said to Think , pp. 495
    • Turing1
  • 12
    • 0011983060 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ("Computing Machinery and Intelligence," p. 442). His 1952 prediction does not specify the computer's storage capacity or the test's duration. In response to Max Newman's question as to when a machine will "stand any chance [of passing the test] with no questions barred," Turing simply said "at least 100 years"
    • Computing Machinery and Intelligence , pp. 442
  • 15
    • 84881239217 scopus 로고
    • Can machines think
    • April
    • Wolfe Mays, "Can Machines Think ," Philosophy, xxvii, 101 (April 1952): 148-62.
    • (1952) Philosophy , vol.27 , Issue.101 , pp. 148-162
    • Mays, W.1
  • 16
    • 30144434199 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If not turing's test, then what
    • Winter
    • See pp. 151, 160. A recent example of the canonical view is Paul R. Cohen, "If Not Turing's Test, Then What ," AI Magazine, xxvi, 4 (Winter 2005): 61-67.
    • (2005) AI Magazine , vol.26 , Issue.4 , pp. 61-67
    • Cohen, P.R.1
  • 17
    • 0000660051 scopus 로고
    • An analysis of the turing test
    • October
    • James H. Moor, "An Analysis of the Turing Test," Philosophical Studies, xxx, 4 (October 1976): 249-57;
    • (1976) Philosophical Studies , vol.30 , Issue.4 , pp. 249-257
    • Moor, J.H.1
  • 18
    • 0005016360 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Turing test
    • Stuart Shapiro, ed. New York: Wiley
    • and Moor, "Turing Test," in Stuart Shapiro, ed., Encyclopedia of Artificial Intelligence, vol. 2 (New York: Wiley, 1987), pp. 1126-30.
    • Encyclopedia of Artificial Intelligence , vol.2 , Issue.1987 , pp. 1126-1130
    • Moor1
  • 22
    • 84924003277 scopus 로고
    • Psychologism and behaviorism
    • January
    • Early proponents of the canonical view did not distinguish between an operationalist and a dispositional (or capacity) interpretation of the Turing test, unlike later proponents (such as Ned Block, "Psychologism and Behaviorism," Philosophical Review, xc, 1 ( January 1981): 5-43;
    • (1981) Philosophical Review , vol.90 , Issue.1 , pp. 5-43
    • Block, N.1
  • 23
    • 0003269980 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The mind as the software of the brain
    • Edward E. Smith and Daniel N. Osherson, eds., 2nd ed. (Cambridge: MIT)
    • and Block, "The Mind as the Software of the Brain," in Edward E. Smith and Daniel N. Osherson, eds., An Invitation to Cognitive Science, Volume 3: Thinking, 2nd ed. (Cambridge: MIT, 1995), pp. 377-425)
    • (1995) An Invitation to Cognitive Science, Volume 3: Thinking , pp. 377-425
    • Block1
  • 24
    • 4344610012 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Turing's ideas and models of computation
    • Christof Teuscher, ed.(New York: Springer)
    • A recent example of the popular variant of the canonical view is Eugene Eberbach, Dina Goldin, and Peter Wegner, "Turing's Ideas and Models of Computation," in Christof Teuscher, ed., Alan Turing: Life and Legacy of a Great Thinker (New York: Springer, 2004), pp. 159-94.
    • (2004) Alan Turing: Life and Legacy of A Great Thinker , pp. 159-194
    • Eberbach, E.1    Goldin, D.2    Wegner, P.3
  • 27
    • 84952728954 scopus 로고
    • Turing's sexual guessing game
    • Commentators who take this line include Judith Genova, "Turing's Sexual Guessing Game," Social Epistemology, viii, 4 (1994): 313-26;
    • (1994) Social Epistemology , vol.8 , Issue.4 , pp. 313-326
    • Genova, J.1
  • 30
    • 48549099118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The voice of the turtle: Whatever happened to AI
    • Summer
    • Douglas B. Lenat, "The Voice of the Turtle: Whatever Happened to AI ," AI Magazine, xxix, 2 (Summer 2008): 11-22;
    • (2008) AI Magazine , vol.29 , Issue.2 , pp. 11-22
    • Lenat, D.B.1
  • 31
    • 84890069911 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Building a machine smart enough to pass the turing test: Could we, should we, will we
    • Robert Epstein, Gary Roberts, and Grace Beber, eds. (Berlin: Springer)
    • Lenat, "Building a Machine Smart Enough to Pass the Turing Test: Could We, Should We, Will We ," in Robert Epstein, Gary Roberts, and Grace Beber, eds., Parsing the Turing Test: Philosophical and Methodological Issues in the Quest for the Thinking Computer (Berlin: Springer, 2008), pp. 261-82.
    • (2008) Parsing the Turing Test: Philosophical and Methodological Issues in the Quest for the Thinking Computer , pp. 261-282
    • Lenat1
  • 32
    • 84871797354 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Copeland points this out ("The Turing Test," p. 9).
    • The Turing Test , pp. 9
  • 36
    • 52649098688 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Realism and response-dependence
    • October
    • and Philip Pettit, "Realism and Response-Dependence," Mind, c, 4 (October 1991): 587-626.
    • (1991) Mind , vol.100 , Issue.4 , pp. 587-626
    • Pettit, P.1
  • 38
    • 61149405931 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • How (not) to specify normal conditions for response-dependent concepts
    • June
    • Recent accounts include Jussi Haukioja, "How (Not) to Specify Normal Conditions for Response-Dependent Concepts," Australasian Journal of Philosophy, lxxxv, 2 ( June 2007): 325-31;
    • (2007) Australasian Journal of Philosophy , vol.85 , Issue.2 , pp. 325-331
    • Haukioja, J.1
  • 39
    • 84890067994 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Response-dependence
    • October
    • and David Yates, "Response-Dependence," Philosophical Books, xlix, 4 (October 2008): 344-54.
    • (2008) Philosophical Books , vol.49 , Issue.4 , pp. 344-354
    • Yates, D.1
  • 40
    • 0003269980 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • According to Block, "there is a gap in Turing's proposal: we are not told how the judge is to be chosen. A judge who was a leading authority on genuinely intelligent machines might know how to tell them apart from people....Turing acknowledged this point by jettisoning the claim that being able to pass the Turing test is a necessary condition of intelligence" ("The Mind as the Software of the Brain," pp. 378-79). However, Turing did exclude experts-and at no point did he suggest that the game provided a necessary condition of intelligence (see section i).
    • The Mind As the Software of the Brain , pp. 378-379
  • 43
    • 0001883047 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On conceptual wings: Rethinking the goals of artificial intelligence
    • Kenneth Ford and Patrick Hayes, "On Conceptual Wings: Rethinking the Goals of Artificial Intelligence," Scientific American Presents, ix (1998): 78-83. See p. 81.
    • (1998) Scientific American Presents , vol.9 , pp. 78-83
    • Ford, K.1    Hayes, P.2
  • 44
    • 33744807562 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Learning and conceptual change: The view from the neurons
    • Andy Clark and Peter Millican, eds. (Oxford: University Press)
    • Paul Churchland, "Learning and Conceptual Change: The View from the Neurons," in Andy Clark and Peter Millican, eds., The Legacy of Alan Turing, Volume II: Connectionism, Concepts, and Folk Psychology (Oxford: University Press, 1996), pp. 7-43. See p. 8.
    • (1996) The Legacy of Alan Turing, Volume II: Connectionism, Concepts, and Folk Psychology , pp. 7-43
    • Churchland, P.1
  • 46
    • 85039649380 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Block claims that Turing "was willing to settle for a 'sufficient condition' formulation of his behaviorist definition of intelligence" ("Psychologism and Behaviorism," p. 15). See note 32.
    • Psychologism and Behaviorism , pp. 15
  • 49
    • 0007214911 scopus 로고
    • Two notions of necessity
    • July
    • See Martin Davies and Humberstone, "Two Notions of Necessity," Philosophical Studies, xxxviii, 1 ( July 1980): 1-30.
    • (1980) Philosophical Studies , vol.37 , Issue.1 , pp. 1-30
    • Davies, M.1    Humberstone2
  • 50
    • 85039632636 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See pp. 21-24. In Crossley and Humberstone's original paper, they suggest that "actually" has the logic of a "rigid operator," using the phrase analogously to Kripke's "rigid designator" ("The Logic of 'Actually'," p. 14).
    • The Logic of 'Actually' , pp. 14
    • Crossley1    Humberstone2
  • 52
    • 84886039028 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Skin deep or in the eye of the beholder. The metaphysics of aesthetic and sensory properties
    • November
    • On rigid and non-rigid response-dependence theories see, for example, Nick Zangwill, "Skin Deep or in the Eye of the Beholder. The Metaphysics of Aesthetic and Sensory Properties," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, lxi, 3 (November 2000): 595-618
    • (2000) Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , vol.61 , Issue.3 , pp. 595-618
    • Zangwill, N.1
  • 53
    • 80053150106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Three dogmas of response-dependence
    • April
    • Mark LeBar, "Three Dogmas of Response-Dependence," Philosophical Studies, cxxiii, 3 (April 2005): 175-211.
    • (2005) Philosophical Studies , vol.123 , Issue.3 , pp. 175-211
    • Lebar, M.1
  • 57
    • 84871797354 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also "Turing Test," p. 1127.
    • Turing Test , pp. 1127
  • 58
    • 60949152072 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The turing test as interactive proof
    • December
    • Stuart Shieber, "The Turing Test as Interactive Proof," Noûs, xli, 4 (December 2007): 686-713. To avoid confusion, it is worth pointing out that, in Shieber's sense, "interaction" is quite unlike Turing's requirement that the interrogator be "taken in" by the machine; rather, the interrogator and the contestant "engage in rounds of messagepassing" (ibid., p. 696). Likewise, although Eberbach, Goldin, and Wegner use the phrase 'interactive Turing Test', as they use the expression an interactive test is just one where the computer interacts with the environment-that is, the human interrogator ("Turing's Ideas and Models of Computation," p. 185). This is again very different from Turing's emphasis on the interrogator's response (Eberbach, Goldin, and Wegner take the canonical view that the Turing test is behaviorist).
    • (2007) Noûs , vol.41 , Issue.4 , pp. 686-713
    • Shieber, S.1
  • 59
    • 85039650304 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Shieber, "The Turing Test as Interactive Proof," p. 706. Shieber does not argue that the modified compact conception is true, but only that Block's putative counterexample does not defeat this conception.
    • The Turing Test As Interactive Proof , pp. 706
    • Shieber1
  • 60
    • 0013143715 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A theory of normal and ideal conditions
    • October
    • see also Pettit, "A Theory of Normal and Ideal Conditions," Philosophical Studies, xcvi, 1 (October 1999): 21-44.
    • (1999) Philosophical Studies , vol.96 , Issue.1 , pp. 21-44
    • Pettit1
  • 63
    • 85039651438 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Piccinini remarks: Turing called intelligence an "emotional concept," meaning that there is no objective way to apply it. Direct experience with a machine, which plays chess in a way that cannot be distinguished from human playing, could convince one to attribute intelligence to the machine. This is very likely to be an important part of the historical root for Turing's proposal of the imitation game....[Turing] hoped that, by experiencing the versatility of digital computers at tasks normally thought to require intelligence, people would modify their usage of terms like "intelligence" and "thinking," so that such terms apply to the machines themselves. ("Turing's Rules for the Imitation Game," p. 117)
    • Turing's Rules for the Imitation Game , pp. 117
  • 64
    • 0011983060 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On this reading, Turing's goal for the imitation game is pragmatic-altering common linguistic usage. However, Turing claimed that the imitation game provides a criterion of thinking. Although he predicted that linguistic usage would change ("Computing Machinery and Intellligence," p. 442)
    • Computing Machinery and Intellligence , pp. 442
  • 67
    • 0010435094 scopus 로고
    • Intelligence without reason
    • Luc Steels and Brooks, eds., (Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum), See p. 57
    • Rodney A. Brooks, "Intelligence without Reason," in Luc Steels and Brooks, eds., The Artificial Life Route to Artificial Intelligence (Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum, 1995), pp. 25-81. See p. 57.
    • (1995) The Artificial Life Route to Artificial Intelligence , pp. 25-81
    • Brooks, R.A.1
  • 68
    • 33746614836 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mindless intelligence
    • (May/June), See 51
    • Jordan B. Pollack, "Mindless Intelligence," IEEE Intelligent Systems, xxi, 3 (May/June 2006): 50-56. See p. 51.
    • (2006) IEEE Intelligent Systems , vol.21 , Issue.3 , pp. 50-56
    • Pollack, J.B.1
  • 69
    • 79953183327 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Anthropomorphism and AI: Turing's much misunderstood imitation game
    • April
    • See Proudfoot, "Anthropomorphism and AI: Turing's Much Misunderstood Imitation Game," Artificial Intelligence, clxxv, 5-6 (April 2011): 950-57;
    • (2011) Artificial Intelligence , vol.175 , Issue.5-6 , pp. 950-957
    • Proudfoot1
  • 70
    • 3242746729 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The implications of an externalist theory of rule-following behaviour for robot cognition
    • August
    • and Proudfoot, "The Implications of an Externalist Theory of Rule-Following Behaviour for Robot Cognition," Minds and Machines, xiv, 3 (August 2004): 283-308.
    • (2004) Minds and Machines , vol.14 , Issue.3 , pp. 283-308
    • Proudfoot1
  • 72
    • 0037219850 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Emotive qualities in lip-synchronized robot speech
    • Breazeal, "Emotive Qualities in Lip-Synchronized Robot Speech," Advanced Robotics, xvii, 2 (2003): 97-113;
    • (2003) Advanced Robotics , vol.17 , Issue.2 , pp. 97-113
    • Breazeal1
  • 73
    • 73549089533 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Role of expressive behaviour for robots that learn from people
    • Dec. 12
    • Breazeal, "Role of Expressive Behaviour for Robots that Learn from People," Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, ccclxiv, 1535 (Dec. 12, 2009): 3527-38
    • (2009) Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B , vol.365 , Issue.1535 , pp. 3527-3538
    • Breazeal1
  • 74
    • 42249104344 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • How social is social responses to computers the function of the degree of anthropomorphism in computer representations
    • July
    • AI researchers deliberately exploit the tendency to anthropomorphize, for example to aid human-computer interaction (on the efficacy of anthropomorphism, see Li Gong, "How Social is Social Responses to Computers The Function of the Degree of Anthropomorphism in Computer Representations," Computers in Human Behavior, xxiv, 4 ( July 2008): 1494-509)
    • (2008) Computers in Human Behavior , vol.24 , Issue.4 , pp. 1494-1509
    • Gong, L.1
  • 75
    • 0037475130 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Toward sociable robots
    • Mar. 31
    • Kismet is constructed so that untrained human observers believe that they understand its "facial" and "bodily" displays, and respond to its behavior as to ordinary human social signals (see Breazeal, "Toward Sociable Robots," Robotics and Autonomous Systems, xlii, 3-4 (Mar. 31, 2003): 167-75;
    • (2003) Robotics and Autonomous Systems , vol.42 , Issue.3-4 , pp. 167-175
    • Breazeal1
  • 76
    • 0037699913 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Emotion and sociable humanoid robots
    • July
    • and Breazeal, "Emotion and Sociable Humanoid Robots," International Journal of Human-Computer Studies, lix, 1-2 ( July 2003): 119-55)
    • (2003) International Journal of Human-Computer Studies , vol.59 , Issue.1-2 , pp. 119-155
    • Breazeal1
  • 77
    • 34447343105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Socially intelligent robots: Dimensions of human-robot interaction
    • The grand goal is to build a "socially intelligent" robot (see Kerstin Dautenhahn, "Socially Intelligent Robots: Dimensions of Human-Robot Interaction," Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, ccclxii, 1480 (2007): 679-704)
    • (2007) Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B , vol.362 , Issue.1480 , pp. 679-704
    • Dautenhahn, K.1
  • 79
    • 84949775131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Affective interaction between humans and robots
    • Jozef Kelemen And Petr Sosík eds., Berlin: Springer-Verlag
    • Breazeal, "Affective Interaction between Humans and Robots," in Jozef Kelemen and Petr Sosík, eds., Advances in Artificial Life: 6th European Conference, ECAL 2001 (Berlin: Springer-Verlag, 2001), pp. 582-91.
    • (2001) Advances in Artificial Life: 6th European Conference, ECAL 2001 , pp. 582-591
    • Breazeal1
  • 85
    • 84890111996 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Can a robot smile wittgenstein on facial expression
    • forthcoming in Timothy P. Racine and Kathleen L. Slaney, eds., (New York: Palgrave Macmillan)
    • On "expressive" face robots, see Proudfoot, "Can a Robot Smile Wittgenstein on Facial Expression," forthcoming in Timothy P. Racine and Kathleen L. Slaney, eds., A Wittgensteinian Perspective on the Use of Conceptual Analysis in Psychology (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2013), pp. 172-84.
    • (2013) A Wittgensteinian Perspective on the Use of Conceptual Analysis in Psychology , pp. 172-184
    • Proudfoot1
  • 87
    • 85039638591 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • http://www.loebner.net/Prizef/loebner-prize.html.
  • 90
    • 0037475127 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Anthropomorphism and the social robot
    • Mar. 31, 179
    • (Duffy, "Anthropomorphism and the Social Robot," Robotics and Autonomous Systems, xlii, 3-4 (Mar. 31, 2003): 177-90; see p. 179). However, the behavior of Loebner Contest judges shows the contrary: the design of Turing's game discourages anthropomorphism.
    • (2003) Robotics and Autonomous Systems , vol.42 , Issue.3-4 , pp. 177-190
    • Duffy1
  • 94
    • 0034161510 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The turing test: The first 50 years
    • Mar. 1
    • Robert M. French, "The Turing Test: The First 50 Years," Trends in Cognitive Science, iv, 3 (Mar. 1, 2000): 115-22. See p. 116.
    • (2000) Trends in Cognitive Science , vol.4 , Issue.3 , pp. 115-122
    • French, R.M.1
  • 95
    • 0023015368 scopus 로고
    • Anthropomorphism and mechanomorphism: Two faces of the human machine
    • Linnda Caporael argues that Turing's imitation game cannot be used as a criterion for thinking; she says, "[I]f there is an inherent anthropomorphic bias [in human reasoning], the imitation principle clearly incorporates a confirmatory bias, and is therefore unreliable" (Caporael, "Anthropomorphism and Mechanomorphism:Two Faces of the Human Machine," Computers in Human Behavior, ii, 3 (1986): 215-34; see pp. 228-29). On the contrary, any "inherent anthropomorphic bias" is a controlled variable in Turing's experiment.
    • (1986) Computers in Human Behavior , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 215-234
    • Caporael1
  • 96
    • 84890048786 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Subcognition and the limits of the turing test
    • Millican and Clark, eds, (Oxford:University Press)
    • French, "Subcognition and the Limits of the Turing Test," in Millican and Clark, eds., The Legacy of Alan Turing, Volume I: Machines and Thought (Oxford: University Press, 1996), pp. 11-26. See p. 12.
    • (1996) The Legacy of Alan Turing Volume I: Machines and Thought , pp. 11-26
    • French1
  • 97
    • 84904380176 scopus 로고
    • Intelligent machinery, a heretical theory BBC radio broadcast
    • Reproduced in Copeland, ed
    • Turing, "Intelligent Machinery, A Heretical Theory," BBC radio broadcast (c. 1951). Reproduced in Copeland, ed., The Essential Turing, pp. 472-75;
    • (1951) The Essential Turing , pp. 472-475
    • Turing1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.