메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn , Issue , 2009, Pages

The good in the right: A theory of intuition and intrinsic value

(1)  Audi, Robert a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84884003280     PISSN: None     EISSN: None     Source Type: Book    
DOI: None     Document Type: Book
Times cited : (235)

References (101)
  • 6
    • 79953522531 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intuitionism
    • ed. Hugh LaFollette (Oxford: Blackwell)
    • David McNaughton, "Intuitionism," in The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory, ed. Hugh LaFollette (Oxford: Blackwell, 2000), 268-87;
    • (2000) The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory , pp. 268-287
    • McNaughton, D.1
  • 7
    • 0040534510 scopus 로고
    • Moral Pluralism
    • Berys Gaut, "Moral Pluralism," Philosophical Papers 22 (1993): 17-40;
    • (1993) Philosophical Papers , vol.22 , pp. 17-40
    • Gaut, B.1
  • 8
    • 33646132842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Morally Serious Critics of Intuitionism
    • Mark Nelson, "Morally Serious Critics of Intuitionism," Ratio 12 (1999): 54-79;
    • (1999) Ratio , vol.12 , pp. 54-79
    • Nelson, M.1
  • 9
    • 0003457994 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • see Charles Larmore, The Morals of Modernity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996).
    • (1996) The Morals of Modernity
    • Larmore, C.1
  • 10
    • 0004255852 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (London: Macmillan, 1907; reissued by the University of Chicago Press in 1962)
    • Henry Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics (London: Macmillan, 1907; reissued by the University of Chicago Press in 1962), 96. Most references to this book will hereinafter be parenthetically included in the text.
    • The Methods of Ethics , pp. 96
    • Sidgwick, H.1
  • 11
    • 33747894421 scopus 로고
    • Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake?
    • reprinted in his Moral Obligation (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1949), 8, emphasis added
    • H. A. Prichard, "Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake?" Mind 21 (1912); reprinted in his Moral Obligation (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1949), 8, emphasis added.
    • (1912) Mind , vol.21
    • Prichard, H.A.1
  • 12
    • 84883975795 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1928), reprinted in Readings in Ethical Theory, ed. Wilfrid Sellars and John Hospers, 2d ed. (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1970)
    • H. A. Prichard, Duty and Interest (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1928), reprinted in Readings in Ethical Theory, ed. Wilfrid Sellars and John Hospers, 2d ed. (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1970), 694-95.
    • Duty and Interest , pp. 694-695
    • Prichard, H.A.1
  • 13
    • 84884030542 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral Obligation
    • See "Moral Obligation," in his Moral Obligation, 158.
    • his Moral Obligation , pp. 158
  • 14
    • 0004065564 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1930), reprinted by Littlefield, Adams (Paterson, 1959). Page references to this book will hereinafter be parenthetically included in the text
    • C. D. Broad, Five Types of Ethical Theory (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1930), reprinted by Littlefield, Adams (Paterson, 1959). Page references to this book will hereinafter be parenthetically included in the text.
    • Five Types of Ethical Theory
    • Broad, C.D.1
  • 15
    • 84884007048 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Philosophical Naturalism at the Turn of the Century
    • Detailed discussion and references to a wide range of relevant literature are provided in my
    • Detailed discussion and references to a wide range of relevant literature are provided in my "Philosophical Naturalism at the Turn of the Century," Journal of Philosophical Research 25 (2000).
    • (2000) Journal of Philosophical Research , vol.25
  • 16
    • 0004240210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1930), reprinted by Hackett Pub. Co. (Indianapolis, 1988), esp. chap. 2
    • See W. D. Ross, The Right and the Good (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1930), reprinted by Hackett Pub. Co. (Indianapolis, 1988), esp. chap. 2, 16-39.
    • The Right and the Good , pp. 16-39
    • Ross, W.D.1
  • 17
    • 84871647310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971)
    • See A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971), 34-35.
    • A Theory of Justice , pp. 34-35
  • 18
    • 84884025002 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • the 1950s and 1960s "it was taken for granted that intuitionism in ethics was an epistemological doctrine . . . the kind of view held, for instance, by W. D. Ross and H. A. Prichard." See "What Does Intuitionism Imply?" in Human Agency, ed. R. Dancy, J. Moravcsik, and C. Taylor (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1988)
    • According to Bernard Williams, in the 1950s and 1960s "it was taken for granted that intuitionism in ethics was an epistemological doctrine . . . the kind of view held, for instance, by W. D. Ross and H. A. Prichard." See "What Does Intuitionism Imply?" in Human Agency, ed. R. Dancy, J. Moravcsik, and C. Taylor (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1988), 198.
    • According to Bernard Williams , pp. 198
    • Dancy, R.1    Moravcsik, J.2    Taylor, C.3
  • 19
    • 84883951229 scopus 로고
    • An intuitionist must believe in simple indefinable properties, properties that are of a peculiar non-natural or normative sort, a priori or nonempirical concepts, and self-evident or synthetic necessary propositions
    • 2d ed. (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall)
    • William K. Frankena, "An intuitionist must believe in simple indefinable properties, properties that are of a peculiar non-natural or normative sort, a priori or nonempirical concepts, and self-evident or synthetic necessary propositions." See Ethics, 2d ed. (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1973), 103.
    • (1973) See Ethics , pp. 103
    • Frankena, W.K.1
  • 20
    • 84884087983 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at least, intuitionism need not be pluralist, presented at the Pacific Division of the American Philosophical Association
    • Bruce Russell, at least, intuitionism need not be pluralist. See his "In Defense of Intuitionism," presented at the Pacific Division of the American Philosophical Association in 1999.
    • (1999) In Defense of Intuitionism
    • Russell, B.1
  • 27
    • 84884079834 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sidgwick and the Boundaries of Intuitionism
    • see "Sidgwick and the Boundaries of Intuitionism," in Stratton-Lake, Ethical Intuitionism, 57-60.
    • Stratton-Lake, Ethical Intuitionism , pp. 57-60
  • 28
    • 33748794707 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intuition and the Autonomy of Philosophy
    • ed. Michael R. DePaul and William Ramsey (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield)
    • "Intuition and the Autonomy of Philosophy," in Rethinking Intuition, ed. Michael R. DePaul and William Ramsey (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1998). This volume also contains instructive papers by psychologists and philosophical accounts of intuition largely complementary to mine ("Minimal Intuition," by Ernest Sosa, 257-69, and "Southern Fundamentalism and the Ends of Philosophy," by George Graham and Terry Horgan, 271-92), as well as one which provides cognitive-psychological hypotheses that bear on the status of my account ("Philosophical Theory and Intuitional Evidence," by Alvin I. Goldman and Joel Pust, 179-97). Cf. William Tolhurst, "Seemings," American Philosophical Quarterly 35 (1998).
    • (1998) Rethinking Intuition
  • 30
    • 84884042617 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A. C. Ewing is explicit on the point, at least for basic intuitions. See, e.g., Ethics (London: English Universities Press, 1953), 136, where he says that "propositions, particularly in ethics but also in other fields of thought, sometimes present themselves to a person in such a way that he . . . knows or rationally believes them to be true without having reasons or at least seems to himself to do so . . . some ethical propositions must be known immediately if any are to be known at all." Cf. his The Fundamental Questions of Philosophy (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1951), 48-49.
    • explicit on the point, at least for basic intuitions
    • Ewing, A.C.1
  • 31
    • 84883990886 scopus 로고
    • propositions, particularly in ethics but also in other fields of thought, sometimes present themselves to a person in such a way that he . . . knows or rationally believes them to be true without having reasons or at least seems to himself to do so . . . some ethical propositions must be known immediately if any are to be known at all
    • where he says that "propositions, particularly in ethics but also in other fields of thought, sometimes present themselves to a person in such a way that he . . . knows or rationally believes them to be true without having reasons or at least seems to himself to do so . . . some ethical propositions must be known immediately if any are to be known at all." Cf. his The Fundamental Questions of Philosophy (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1951), 48-49.
    • (1951) his The Fundamental Questions of Philosophy (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul) , pp. 48-49
  • 35
    • 84884003060 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • He also brings Broad to mind in calling intuitions in the sense that concerns him
    • He also brings Broad to mind in calling intuitions in the sense that concerns him "both non-empirical and immediate" (41).
    • Both non-empirical and immediate , pp. 41
  • 36
    • 84883918259 scopus 로고
    • traditional rationalist account of a priori knowledge as the intuitive grasp or apprehension of necessity
    • Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • Laurence BonJour's construal of the "traditional rationalist account of a priori knowledge as the intuitive grasp or apprehension of necessity" in his The Structure of Empirical Knowledge (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1985), 207.
    • (1985) his The Structure of Empirical Knowledge , pp. 207
    • BonJour's, L.1
  • 37
    • 84883954323 scopus 로고
    • the tradition . . . held that self-evident propositions- simple truths of arithmetic and logic, for example-are such that we can't even grasp or understand them without seeing that they are true . . . A better position, I think, is that a self-evident proposition is such that a properly functioning (mature) human being can't grasp it without believing it
    • As Alvin Plantinga puts it, Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • As Alvin Plantinga puts it, "the tradition . . . held that self-evident propositions- simple truths of arithmetic and logic, for example-are such that we can't even grasp or understand them without seeing that they are true . . . A better position, I think, is that a self-evident proposition is such that a properly functioning (mature) human being can't grasp it without believing it." See Warrant and Proper Function (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993), 108-9. The view developed in this chapter contrasts with both positions.
    • (1993) Warrant and Proper Function , pp. 108-19
  • 38
    • 84883967380 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Self-Evidence
    • This is an issue discussed in some detail in my
    • This is an issue discussed in some detail in my "Self-Evidence," Philosophical Perspectives 13 (1999).
    • (1999) Philosophical Perspectives , vol.13
  • 39
    • 84883930004 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Feminist Skepticism, Authority, and Transparency
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • On the importance of this in ethics, see Margaret Walker's "Feminist Skepticism, Authority, and Transparency," inWalter Sinnott-Armstrong and Mark Timmons, Moral Knowledge? (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996).
    • (1996) Walter Sinnott-Armstrong and Mark Timmons, Moral Knowledge?
    • Walker's, M.1
  • 43
    • 84884115165 scopus 로고
    • Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill
    • Lewis White Beck (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1958), secs. 29-31.
    • (1958) secs. , pp. 29-31
    • Beck, L.W.1
  • 44
    • 84883908698 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Outline of a Contextualist Moral Epistemology
    • Morality without Foundations (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999). Cf. the contextual particularism of Jonathan Dancy's view in Moral Reasons (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993), esp. chaps. 4-6. Some of Dancy's views are considered in sec.
    • For a portrait and defense of contextualism in moral epistemology, see Mark Timmons, "Outline of a Contextualist Moral Epistemology," in Sinnott-Armstrong and Timmons, Moral Knowledge?, and Morality without Foundations (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999). Cf. the contextual particularism of Jonathan Dancy's view in Moral Reasons (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993), esp. chaps. 4-6. Some of Dancy's views are considered in sec. 5.
    • Sinnott-Armstrong and Timmons, Moral Knowledge? , pp. 5
    • Timmons, M.1
  • 45
    • 84972372138 scopus 로고
    • Ethical Intuitionism II
    • A similar objection is voiced and partially answered by J. R. Lucas, in a paper defending Rossian intuitionism against objections by P. F. Strawson and others. See "Ethical Intuitionism II," Philosophy 46, no. 175 (1971): 1-11, 5.
    • (1971) Philosophy , vol.46 , Issue.175
  • 47
    • 61449562217 scopus 로고
    • London: Swan Sonnenschein & Co.
    • See Henry Sidgwick, Practical Ethics (London: Swan Sonnenschein & Co., 1909), 8.
    • (1909) Practical Ethics , pp. 8
    • Sidgwick, H.1
  • 49
  • 50
    • 84861487849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral Dilemmas and Rights
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Since I am only sketching a normative theory, I largely ignore the point that one may have conflicting sets of duties, say two pulling one way and two pulling another. Moreover, I take a set of duties to A that conflicts with a set of duties to B (where A and B are incompatible) to be final only if the deontic weight of the first set is greater than that of the second. If they are equally weighty, presumably one is morally free to A and to B (though the choice may be difficult or even in some way tragic). Cf. David O. Brink, "Moral Conflict and Its Structure," Philosophical Review 103, no. 2 (1994): 215-47, critically discussed by Walter Sinnott-Armstrong in "Moral Dilemmas and Rights," in Moral Dilemmas and Moral Theory, ed. H. E. Mason (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996).
    • (1996) Moral Dilemmas and Moral Theory
    • Mason, H.E.1
  • 51
    • 48749122445 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Decision Procedures, Moral Criteria, and the Problem of Relevant Descriptions
    • Mark C. Timmons, "Decision Procedures, Moral Criteria, and the Problem of Relevant Descriptions," Jahrbuch für Recht und Ethic 5 (1997).
    • (1997) Jahrbuch für Recht und Ethic , vol.5
    • Timmons, M.C.1
  • 54
    • 0011273024 scopus 로고
    • The Practice of Moral Judgment
    • A brief account of how maxims should be formulated, with special emphasis on intention, is given in chap. 3 of my Practical Reasoning. A much more detailed treatment of the question in given by Derek Parfit in his forthcoming Tanner Lectures on Kant's ethics. For a valuable short treatment, see Jens Timmerman, "Kant's Puzzling Ethics of Maxims," Harvard Review of Philosophy 8 (2000). Also instructive is Barbara Herman, "The Practice of Moral Judgment," Journal of Philosophy 82 (1985).
    • (1985) Journal of Philosophy , vol.82
  • 56
    • 84884084381 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Utilitarian doctrine . . . is that each man ought to consider the happiness of any other as theoretically of equal importance with his own, and only of less importance practically, in so far as he is better able to realise the latter)
    • Ross's affirmation of a duty to produce as much good as we can (27) and Sidgwick:
    • Cf. Ross's affirmation of a duty to produce as much good as we can (27) and Sidgwick: "The Utilitarian doctrine . . . is that each man ought to consider the happiness of any other as theoretically of equal importance with his own, and only of less importance practically, in so far as he is better able to realise the latter)," Methods, 252.
    • Methods , pp. 252
  • 58
    • 84884041535 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The autonomy of the will is the sole principle of all moral laws . . . the moral law expresses nothing else than the autonomy of the pure practical reason, i.e., freedom
    • Kant says, e.g., "The autonomy of the will is the sole principle of all moral laws . . . the moral law expresses nothing else than the autonomy of the pure practical reason, i.e., freedom." See the Critique of Practical Reason, sec. 33 (34-35).
    • the Critique of Practical Reason, sec. , vol.33 , pp. 34-35
    • Kant1
  • 63
    • 84884084304 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am more skeptical than Audi about the possibility of any other theory providing independent support for a list of duties of Ross's kind. Kantianism, for example, appears to hold that some principles are exceptionless, and not prima facie
    • David McNaughton might have been thinking of such passages in saying, "I am more skeptical than Audi about the possibility of any other theory providing independent support for a list of duties of Ross's kind. Kantianism, for example, appears to hold that some principles are exceptionless, and not prima facie." See "Intuitionism," 283.
    • Intuitionism , pp. 283
    • McNaughton, D.1
  • 65
    • 84883898935 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (secs. 421-23)
    • See, e.g., The Doctrine of Virtue, 84-87 (secs. 421-23).
    • The Doctrine of Virtue , pp. 84-87
  • 66
    • 60950442758 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Feeling, Desire and Interest in Kant's Theory of Action
    • see Jeanine M. Grenberg, "Feeling, Desire and Interest in Kant's Theory of Action," Kant-Studien 92 (2001).
    • (2001) Kant-Studien , vol.92
    • Grenberg, J.M.1
  • 68
    • 0004240210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These terms are found in Ross
    • These terms are found in Ross, The Right and the Good, 21
    • The Right and the Good , pp. 21
  • 73
    • 0005041662 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See Noah Lemos, Intrinsic Value (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994)
    • (1994) Intrinsic Value
    • Lemos, N.1
  • 74
    • 80054464941 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Virtual Intrinsic Value and the Principle of Organic Unities
    • see Michael J. Zimmerman, "Virtual Intrinsic Value and the Principle of Organic Unities," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59 (1999): 653-66.
    • (1999) Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , vol.59 , pp. 653-666
    • Zimmerman, M.J.1
  • 76
    • 84884120584 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • all of them may be kept on the list, and perhaps others may be added, if it is understood that it is the experience of them that is good in itself. Sidgwick seems to me to be right on this point . . . truth is not itself intrinsically good . . . what is good in itself is knowledge or belief in the truth
    • As William K. Frankena has done: he says, of the items on a very diverse list, "all of them may be kept on the list, and perhaps others may be added, if it is understood that it is the experience of them that is good in itself. Sidgwick seems to me to be right on this point . . . truth is not itself intrinsically good . . . what is good in itself is knowledge or belief in the truth." Ethics, 89.
    • Ethics , pp. 89
    • Frankena, W.K.1
  • 77
    • 84874999120 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Principia, esp. 83-85.
    • Principia , pp. 83-85
  • 78
  • 80
    • 84884018233 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An action of this kind [helping others from a "sympathetic temper" and an "inner pleasure in spreading happiness"], however right and however amiable it may be, has still no genuinely moral worth
    • Kant says, e.g., that "an action of this kind [helping others from a "sympathetic temper" and an "inner pleasure in spreading happiness"], however right and however amiable it may be, has still no genuinely moral worth." See the Groundwork, sec. 10.
    • Groundwork , pp. 10
    • Kant1
  • 81
    • 84884059508 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • see, e.g. his Well-Being (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986).
    • (1986) his Well-Being
  • 82
    • 84884094208 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • morality was made for man, not man for morality
    • As William Frankena put it, "morality was made for man, not man for morality." See Ethics, 44.
    • Ethics , pp. 44
    • Frankena, W.1
  • 83
    • 84884076229 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • When we think of an act as right we think that either something good or some pleasure for another will be brought into being
    • Ross says, e.g., that "when we think of an act as right we think that either something good or some pleasure for another will be brought into being" (The Right and the Good, 162),
    • The Right and the Good , pp. 162
    • Ross1
  • 84
    • 0006969395 scopus 로고
    • How to Be a Moral Realist
    • A similar compatibility with my view might hold for the moral realism of Richard Boyd's related , Ithaca: Cornell University Press
    • A similar compatibility with my view might hold for the moral realism of Richard Boyd's related "How to Be a Moral Realist," in Essays on Moral Realism, ed. Geoffrey Sayre-McCord (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1988).
    • (1988) Essays on Moral Realism
    • Sayre-McCord, G.1
  • 85
    • 84882668432 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Paton trans.)
    • See the Groundwork, sec. 428 (Paton trans.).
    • the Groundwork , pp. 428
  • 86
    • 84874999120 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Principia, 149.
    • Principia , pp. 149
  • 88
    • 84883945985 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Robert Nozick, ed. David Schmidtz (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002).
    • (2002)
    • Nozick, R.1    Schmidtz, D.2
  • 89
    • 84883972970 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I take this objection from Rawls
    • I take this objection from Rawls, "Kantian Constructivism"; see esp. 91-92.
    • Kantian Constructivism , pp. 91-92
  • 90
    • 0039758758 scopus 로고
    • Projection and Truth in Ethics
    • Lawrence: University of Kansas, reprinted in Moral Discourse and Practice, ed. Stephen Darwall, Allan Gibbard, and Peter Railton (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997), 215-25. It is interesting to note the lengths to which Rawls went in criticizing intuitionism; perhaps this is in part because, as a kind of intuitivist, he shared some important intuitionist ideas. He says, e.g., in Justice as Fairness: A Restatement (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2001), "A second reason the ideal cannot be fully attained is that the balance of reasons itself rests on judgment, though judgment informed and guided by reasoning . . . we must rely on judgment as to what considerations are more or less significant, and when in practice to close the list of reasons" (134). Even in A Theory of Justice, there is at least one place where he seems to allow, as an intuitionist would, for possible exceptions to the priority of the liberty principle over the difference principle (45).
    • The first objection is echoed by John McDowell in "Projection and Truth in Ethics," The Lindley Lecture (Lawrence: University of Kansas, 1987), reprinted in Moral Discourse and Practice, ed. Stephen Darwall, Allan Gibbard, and Peter Railton (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997), 215-25. It is interesting to note the lengths to which Rawls went in criticizing intuitionism; perhaps this is in part because, as a kind of intuitivist, he shared some important intuitionist ideas. He says, e.g., in Justice as Fairness: A Restatement (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2001), "A second reason the ideal cannot be fully attained is that the balance of reasons itself rests on judgment, though judgment informed and guided by reasoning . . . we must rely on judgment as to what considerations are more or less significant, and when in practice to close the list of reasons" (134). Even in A Theory of Justice, there is at least one place where he seems to allow, as an intuitionist would, for possible exceptions to the priority of the liberty principle over the difference principle (45).
    • (1987) The Lindley Lecture
    • McDowell, J.1
  • 91
    • 0004240210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ross notes defeasibility when he compares moral convictions with sense-perceptions
    • Ross notes defeasibility when he compares moral convictions with sense-perceptions, The Right and the Good, 41.
    • The Right and the Good , pp. 41
  • 92
    • 0342370365 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An Unconnected Heap of Duties?
    • This is treated by David McNaughton, "An Unconnected Heap of Duties?" Philosophical Quarterly 46 (1996): 443-47;
    • (1996) Philosophical Quarterly , vol.46 , pp. 443-447
    • McNaughton, D.1
  • 93
    • 0007414761 scopus 로고
    • Philadelphia: Temple University Press
    • see Terrance McConnell, Gratitude (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1993).
    • (1993) Gratitude
    • McConnell, T.1
  • 95
    • 60949230403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Defending Deontology
    • both for interpretation of Rossian intuitionism and for criticism of an attempt (quite different from the approach outlined here) to derive a related deontological standard from considerations of value
    • See also David McNaughton and Piers Rawling, "On Defending Deontology," Ratio 11, no. 1 (1998): 37-54, both for interpretation of Rossian intuitionism and for criticism of an attempt (quite different from the approach outlined here) to derive a related deontological standard from considerations of value.
    • (1998) Ratio , vol.11 , Issue.1 , pp. 37-54
    • McNaughton, D.1    Rawling, P.2
  • 97
    • 0003593197 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Rosalind Hursthouse, On Virtue Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999).
    • (1999) On Virtue Ethics
    • Hursthouse, R.1
  • 99
    • 84883973593 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reasons and Rationality in the Moral Philosophy of Bernard Gert
    • ed.Walter Sinnott-Armstrong and Robert Audi, Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield
    • see my "Reasons and Rationality in the Moral Philosophy of Bernard Gert," in Rationality, Rules, and Ideals: Critical Essays on Bernard Gert's Moral Theory, ed.Walter Sinnott-Armstrong and Robert Audi (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 2002).
    • (2002) Rationality, Rules, and Ideals: Critical Essays on Bernard Gert's Moral Theory


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.