메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 92, Issue 2, 2001, Pages 153-179

Feeling, desire and interest in Kant's theory of action

(1)  Grenberg, Jeanine M a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 60950442758     PISSN: 00228877     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1515/kant.92.2.153     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (26)

References (25)
  • 1
    • 70450008121 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In referring to Kant's works, I will first note the Akademie pagination, and then the pagination of the following translations (abbreviations used to refer to these translations in the text are noted in parentheses at the end of the entry, Critique of Judgment. Translation by Werner S. Pluhar. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Col, 1987, CJ);
    • In referring to Kant's works, I will first note the Akademie pagination, and then the pagination of the following translations (abbreviations used to refer to these translations in the text are noted in parentheses at the end of the entry): Critique of Judgment. Translation by Werner S. Pluhar. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Col, 1987. (CJ)
  • 2
    • 0004183724 scopus 로고
    • Critique of Practical Reason (third edition)
    • New York: Macmillan Publishing Company, (CprR)
    • Critique of Practical Reason (third edition). Translated by Lewis White Beck. New York: Macmillan Publishing Company, 1956. (CprR)
    • (1956) Translated by Lewis White Beck
  • 3
    • 79957213973 scopus 로고
    • New York: St. Martin's Press (CPR)
    • Critique of Pure Reason. Translated by Norman Kemp Smith. New York: St. Martin's Press, 1965. (CPR)
    • (1965) Critique of Pure Reason
    • Smith, N.K.1
  • 4
    • 0004305896 scopus 로고
    • Translated by H.J. Paton. New York: Harper and Row, (Gr)
    • Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Translated by H.J. Paton. New York: Harper and Row, 1948. (Gr)
    • (1948) Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals
  • 5
    • 0004207225 scopus 로고
    • Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co., (LE)
    • Lectures on Ethics. Translated by Louis Infield. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co., 1980. (LE)
    • (1980) Lectures on Ethics
    • Infield, L.1
  • 6
    • 0004291536 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Translated by Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • The Metaphysics of Morals. Translated by Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996. (MM)
    • (1996) The Metaphysics of Morals , vol.2000
  • 7
    • 0003411955 scopus 로고
    • Translated by Theodore M. Greene and Hoyt H. Hudson. New York: Haprer and Row (Rel)
    • Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone. Translated by Theodore M. Greene and Hoyt H. Hudson. New York: Haprer and Row, 1960. (Rel)
    • (1960) Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone
  • 9
    • 0004051088 scopus 로고
    • especially, Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press
    • See especially Herman, Barbara. The Practice of Moral Judgment. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press, 1993
    • (1993) The Practice of Moral Judgment
    • Herman, B.1
  • 11
    • 33748780931 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Making Room for Character
    • Stephen Engstrom and Jennifer Whiting, eds. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Herman, Barbara. "Making Room for Character," in: Aristotle, Kant and the Stoics: Rethinking Happiness and Duty, Stephen Engstrom and Jennifer Whiting, eds. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996
    • (1996) Aristotle, Kant and the Stoics: Rethinking Happiness and Duty
    • Herman, B.1
  • 12
    • 0004160442 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Korsgaard, Christine. Sources of Normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996
    • (1996) Sources of Normativity
    • Korsgaard, C.1
  • 13
    • 0002341908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Herman (1996) does engage in the most extended discussion of the interrelationship of desire and reason in action, but does so without attributing the ideas specifically to Kant
    • and Sherman, Nancy. Making a Necessity of Virtue: Aristotle and Kant on Virtue. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997; Herman (1996) does engage in the most extended discussion of the interrelationship of desire and reason in action, but does so without attributing the ideas specifically to Kant
    • (1997) Making a Necessity of Virtue: Aristotle and Kant on Virtue
    • Sherman, N.1
  • 14
    • 79958958286 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Even Allison himself, when he turns to explaining moral action, insists that to respect [the law] is to have a sufficient reason (although not a desire) to obey it. (Allison, 127) As such, what is incorporated in moral action is not a sensible drive, but a pure intellectual awareness
    • Even Allison himself, when he turns to explaining moral action, insists that "to respect [the law] is to have a sufficient reason (although not a desire) to obey it." (Allison, 127) As such, what is incorporated in moral action is not a sensible drive, but a pure intellectual awareness
  • 15
    • 79958875673 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I will not in this paper, deal specifically with the question of moral action, though the influence of feeling which I discuss here can be shown to hold in the moral case as well. Providing such an argument would require a more thorough investigation of the moral feeling of respect and a discussion of the more stringent limitations placed upon an act in order that it qualify for the attribution of moral worth. For the beginnings of such a discussion, Anthropology from a Metaphysical Point of View, forthcoming in the Journal of the History of Philosophy
    • I will not in this paper, deal specifically with the question of moral action, though the influence of feeling which I discuss here can be shown to hold in the moral case as well. Providing such an argument would require a more thorough investigation of the moral feeling of respect and a discussion of the more stringent limitations placed upon an act in order that it qualify for the attribution of moral worth. For the beginnings of such a discussion, see my "Anthropology from a Metaphysical Point of View," forthcoming in the Journal of the History of Philosophy
  • 16
    • 79958923442 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Triebfeder is often translated as incentive, but I translate it as drive, to emphasize that it always involves a sensible influence on the faculty of desire
    • Triebfeder is often translated as "incentive", but I translate it as "drive", to emphasize that it always involves a sensible influence on the faculty of desire
  • 17
    • 84868472689 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • also CprR 4:9n/9n: "The faculty of desire is the faculty ... a being has of causing, through its ideas, the reality of the objects of these ideas
    • See also CprR 4:9n/9n: "The faculty of desire is the faculty ... a being has of causing, through its ideas, the reality of the objects of these ideas."
  • 18
    • 79958883864 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gr 4:412-413/80-81.
    • See, for example, Gr 4:412-413/80-81
  • 19
    • 79958967063 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [I]f reason solely by itself is not sufficient to determine the will ... then actions which are recognized to be objectively necessary are subjectively contingent. (Gr 4:412-13/80) MM 6:218/20, where Kant notes that a law ... represents an action that is to be done as objectively necessary, but that such representation is a merely theoretical cognition of a possible determination of choice, and not choice itself
    • "[I]f reason solely by itself is not sufficient to determine the will ... then actions which are recognized to be objectively necessary are subjectively contingent." (Gr 4:412-13/80) See also MM 6:218/20, where Kant notes that "a law ... represents an action that is to be done as objectively necessary," but that such representation "is a merely theoretical cognition of a possible determination of choice," and not choice itself
  • 20
    • 79958998941 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gr 4:412-13/80, where Kant notes that, in objective determination of the will, if the will is exposed also to subjecitve conditions (certain impulsions) which do not always harmonize with the objective ones ... then actions which are recognized to be objectively necessary are subjectively contingent
    • See Gr 4:412-13/80, where Kant notes that, in objective determination of the will, "if the will is exposed also to subjecitve conditions (certain impulsions) which do not always harmonize with the objective ones ... then actions which are recognized to be objectively necessary are subjectively contingent."
  • 21
    • 79959019891 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • also CJ 5:206/46-48.
    • See also CJ 5:206/46-48
  • 22
    • 84868472688 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Susceptibility to the representation is called feeling, which is the effect of a representation that may be either sensible or intellectual." (MM 6:211/12)
    • "Susceptibility to the representation is called feeling, which is the effect of a representation that may be either sensible or intellectual." (MM 6:211/12)
  • 23
    • 79958879469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • also MM 6:381/146: An end is an object of the choice (of a rational being), through the representation of which choice is determined to an action to bring this object about.
    • See also MM 6:381/146): "An end is an object of the choice (of a rational being), through the representation of which choice is determined to an action to bring this object about."
  • 24
    • 79958869706 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gr 4:407/74-75.
    • See Gr 4:407/74-75
  • 25
    • 79958936232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • also CPR A 802, B 830/633 and CPR A 534, B 562/465.
    • See also CPR A 802, B 830/633 and CPR A 534, B 562/465


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.