메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 6, Issue 2, 2000, Pages 127-170

Law, morality, and the guidance of conduct

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 85016690251     PISSN: 13523252     EISSN: 14698048     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/s1352325200062017     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (48)

References (62)
  • 1
    • 78650447024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • J. LEGAL STUD. 139 (1982), reprinted in Jules L. Coleman, MARKETS, MORALS AND THE LAW
    • See, e.g., Jules Coleman, Negative and Positive Positivism, J. LEGAL STUD. 139 (1982), reprinted in Jules L. Coleman, MARKETS, MORALS AND THE LAW 3 (1988).
    • (1988) Negative and Positive Positivism , pp. 3
    • Coleman, J.1
  • 3
    • 85022397347 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in TAKING RIGHTS SERIOUSLY 14 (1977). For an extensive discussion of the Hart/Dworkin debate, see Scott J. Shapiro, On Hart's Way Out, 4 LEGAL THEORY
    • See Ronald Dworkin, The Model of Rules I, in TAKING RIGHTS SERIOUSLY 14 (1977). For an extensive discussion of the Hart/Dworkin debate, see Scott J. Shapiro, On Hart's Way Out, 4 LEGAL THEORY 469, 477-89 (1998).
    • (1998) The Model of Rules I , vol.469 , pp. 477-489
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 5
    • 85016697222 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Conventionality, and the Practical Difference Thesis, 4 LEGAL THEORY
    • See Jules Coleman, Incorporationism, Conventionality, and the Practical Difference Thesis, 4 LEGAL THEORY 381 (1998).
    • (1998) Incorporationism , pp. 381
    • Coleman, J.1
  • 6
    • 85022442460 scopus 로고
    • (Penelope A. Bullock & Joseph Raz eds., 2d ed. ).
    • See H.L.A. Hart, THE CONCEPT OF LAW 249 (Penelope A. Bullock & Joseph Raz eds., 2d ed. 1994).
    • (1994) THE CONCEPT OF LAW 249
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 7
    • 85055357306 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • THE CONCEPT OF LAW 249 note
    • See Shapiro, THE CONCEPT OF LAW 249 note 3.
    • Shapiro , pp. 3
  • 8
    • 0009327079 scopus 로고
    • 200 (2d ed. ). Needless to say, Raz also rejects inclusive legal positivism.
    • See Joseph Raz, THE CONCEPT OF A LEGAL SYSTEM, 200 (2d ed. 1980). Needless to say, Raz also rejects inclusive legal positivism.
    • (1980) THE CONCEPT OF A LEGAL SYSTEM
    • Raz, J.1
  • 9
    • 31144469768 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6 LEGAL THEORY 1-43 (2000); WillWaluchow, Authority and the Practical Difference Thesis, 6 LEGAL THEORY 45-81(2000); Matthew Kramer, How Moral Principles Can Enter Into the Law, 6 LEGAL THEORY 83-108.
    • See Kenneth Himma, H.L.A. Hart and the Practical Difference Thesis, 6 LEGAL THEORY 1-43 (2000); WillWaluchow, Authority and the Practical Difference Thesis, 6 LEGAL THEORY 45-81(2000); Matthew Kramer, How Moral Principles Can Enter Into the Law, 6 LEGAL THEORY 83-108(2000).
    • (2000) H.L.A. Hart and the Practical Difference Thesis
    • Himma, K.1
  • 14
    • 85022434913 scopus 로고
    • I am presupposing the Limit Assumption. See David Lewis, COUNTERFACTUALS
    • For the sake of simplicity, I am presupposing the Limit Assumption. See David Lewis, COUNTERFACTUALS 19-21 (1973).
    • (1973) For the sake of simplicity , pp. 19-21
  • 15
    • 85022391634 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Himma, For the sake of simplicity note 9, at
    • Himma refers to it as (MG2). Himma, For the sake of simplicity note 9, at 21.
    • Himma refers to it as (MG2). , pp. 21
  • 16
    • 85022415661 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • According to that characterization, a legal rule R guides a person P to do A only if P might not have done A if he had not appealed to R. The three differences mentioned in the text between (4) and (1), however, apply, mutatis mutandis, to this older characterization as well.
    • As I mentioned in Section I, this is not the characterization of practical difference that I offered in the original article. According to that characterization, a legal rule R guides a person P to do A only if P might not have done A if he had not appealed to R. The three differences mentioned in the text between (4) and (1), however, apply, mutatis mutandis, to this older characterization as well.
    • As I mentioned in Section I, this is not the characterization of practical difference that I offered in the original article.
  • 17
    • 85022451095 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • i.e., that of duality. Just as “It is possible that B” is equivalent to “It is not the case that it is necessary that not-B,” “If B were the case, then C might be the case” is equivalent to “It is not the case that if B were the case, then not-C would be the case.” A might-conditional is true just in case some of the closest worlds to the actual world where the antecedent is true is also a world where the consequent is true. If there are no words where R is not a rule, then it trivially follows that “P might not have done A if R had not been a rule” is false. Hence, (3) is true.
    • According to the Lewis-Stalnaker semantics, might-counterfactuals bear the same relation to would-counterfactuals as possibility bears to necessity, i.e., that of duality. Just as “It is possible that B” is equivalent to “It is not the case that it is necessary that not-B,” “If B were the case, then C might be the case” is equivalent to “It is not the case that if B were the case, then not-C would be the case.” A might-conditional is true just in case some of the closest worlds to the actual world where the antecedent is true is also a world where the consequent is true. If there are no words where R is not a rule, then it trivially follows that “P might not have done A if R had not been a rule” is false. Hence, (3) is true.
    • According to the Lewis-Stalnaker semantics, might-counterfactuals bear the same relation to would-counterfactuals as possibility bears to necessity
  • 20
    • 85022368082 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I do not mean to imply that morality is absolute. Someone can be amoral relativist and still believe that morality is static. For themoral relativist can believe that even though there are many “moralities,” each one is static. For the sake of convenience, however, I have been talking, and will continue to talk, as if there were only one correct moral system.
    • By claiming that morality is a static system, I do not mean to imply that morality is absolute. Someone can be amoral relativist and still believe that morality is static. For themoral relativist can believe that even though there are many “moralities,” each one is static. For the sake of convenience, however, I have been talking, and will continue to talk, as if there were only one correct moral system.
    • By claiming that morality is a static system
  • 27
    • 85022400045 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LAW, LIBERTY AND MORALITY note 6, at 54-56
    • See Hart, LAW, LIBERTY AND MORALITY note 6, at 54-56, 86-88.
    • Hart , pp. 86-88
  • 28
    • 85022394202 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in TAKING RIGHTS SERIOUSLY, Hart note 3, at
    • See Ronald Dworkin, The Model of Rule II, in TAKING RIGHTS SERIOUSLY, Hart note 3, at 46, 52-53.
    • The Model of Rule II , vol.46 , pp. 52-53
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 31
    • 85022440674 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Recall Weber's description of the charismatic leader: “It has been written that…, but I say unto you….” note 9 note 6, at
    • Hart, Recall Weber's description of the charismatic leader: “It has been written that…, but I say unto you….” note 9 note 6, at 141.
    • Hart , pp. 141
  • 32
    • 77956842168 scopus 로고
    • 115 N.Y. 506, 22 N.E. 188
    • Riggs v. Palmer, 115 N.Y. 506, 22 N.E. 188 (1889).
    • (1889) Riggs v. Palmer
  • 33
    • 85022380333 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • When I say that an agent has learned information “from the rule,” this should be understood as short-hand for the agent having learned the information from some statement of the rule's content. note 6, at
    • Hart, When I say that an agent has learned information “from the rule,” this should be understood as short-hand for the agent having learned the information from some statement of the rule's content. note 6, at 40.
    • Hart , pp. 40
  • 36
    • 0003691257 scopus 로고
    • Chapter 3 (C.B. Machpherson, ed., ) (1690).
    • John Locke, TWO TREATISES OF GOVERNMENT, Chapter 3 (C.B. Machpherson, ed., 1980) (1690).
    • (1980) TWO TREATISES OF GOVERNMENT
    • Locke, J.1
  • 37
    • 85022426892 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • TWO TREATISES OF GOVERNMENT note 6, at
    • Hart, TWO TREATISES OF GOVERNMENT note 6, at 40.
    • Hart , pp. 40
  • 44
    • 85022445608 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • e.g., a norm could not be valid simply because a judge had a “hunch” that the rule was correct. Id. at 93. (Kramer, unfortunately, does not specify the content of this hunch-I assume he means a hunch that the rule is morally acceptable.)
    • Kramer believes that even a robust incorporationist would place some restrictions on the rule of recognition, e.g., a norm could not be valid simply because a judge had a “hunch” that the rule was correct. Id. at 93. (Kramer, unfortunately, does not specify the content of this hunch-I assume he means a hunch that the rule is morally acceptable.)
    • Kramer believes that even a robust incorporationist would place some restrictions on the rule of recognition
  • 46
    • 85022429638 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kramer's discussion of citizens’ expectations. note 6, at
    • Hart, Kramer's discussion of citizens’ expectations. note 6, at 112-17.
    • Hart , pp. 112-117
  • 48
    • 85022353486 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But such principles would be of heuristic value only and not an independent basis for deciding cases. On this point Kramer agrees: “Although those moral precepts might fulfill a heuristic function, they do not constitute any decision-determining reasons (beyond those constituted by the instruction in the Rule of Recognition requiring judges to dispose of hard cases on the basis of moral precepts).” Id. at
    • To be sure, a judge might appeal to moral principles themselves to aid him in applying the rule of recognition. But such principles would be of heuristic value only and not an independent basis for deciding cases. On this point Kramer agrees: “Although those moral precepts might fulfill a heuristic function, they do not constitute any decision-determining reasons (beyond those constituted by the instruction in the Rule of Recognition requiring judges to dispose of hard cases on the basis of moral precepts).” Id. at 101.
    • To be sure, a judge might appeal to moral principles themselves to aid him in applying the rule of recognition. , pp. 101
  • 53
    • 85022364307 scopus 로고
    • Commands and Authoritative Reasons, in ESSAYS ON BENTHAM
    • See Hart, Commands and Authoritative Reasons, in ESSAYS ON BENTHAM 253-55 (1982).
    • (1982) Hart , pp. 253-255
  • 54
    • 85022412756 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am arguing by cases. Having shown that judges cannot be epistemically guided by rules whose morality is a necessary, but not individually sufficient, condition on their legality, I argue that judges cannot be motivationally guided by such rules either. Nevertheless, I do think it is plausible to interpret Hart as having considered the motivational guidance of judges to be one of the functions of legal rules. He writes: “What is crucial for legislation is that certain things said or done by certain persons which can be construed as guiding actions should be recognized by the Courts as constituting just such peremptory reasons for action, and so as law-making events.” Id. at 260. I, therefore, disagree with Himma when he argues that there is no reason to believe such a claim. See Himma, Hart note 9, at 38-39. Nothing much rides on the truth of this assertion, however, for no argument that I have presented depends on it. If judges need not be motivationally guided by the rules that they must apply, then they must be epistemically guided by them, and I have argued that this is not possible. Himma is also wrong to have claimed that the argument in section I above presupposes that judges must be capable of being motivationally guided by primary legal rules. See id. at 34. It only requires that these rules be capable of making a practical difference.
    • I am not here taking a position on whether judges must be capable of being motivationally guided by legal rules. I am arguing by cases. Having shown that judges cannot be epistemically guided by rules whose morality is a necessary, but not individually sufficient, condition on their legality, I argue that judges cannot be motivationally guided by such rules either. Nevertheless, I do think it is plausible to interpret Hart as having considered the motivational guidance of judges to be one of the functions of legal rules. He writes: “What is crucial for legislation is that certain things said or done by certain persons which can be construed as guiding actions should be recognized by the Courts as constituting just such peremptory reasons for action, and so as law-making events.” Id. at 260. I, therefore, disagree with Himma when he argues that there is no reason to believe such a claim. See Himma, Hart note 9, at 38-39. Nothing much rides on the truth of this assertion, however, for no argument that I have presented depends on it. If judges need not be motivationally guided by the rules that they must apply, then they must be epistemically guided by them, and I have argued that this is not possible. Himma is also wrong to have claimed that the argument in section I above presupposes that judges must be capable of being motivationally guided by primary legal rules. See id. at 34. It only requires that these rules be capable of making a practical difference.
    • I am not here taking a position on whether judges must be capable of being motivationally guided by legal rules.
  • 57
    • 85022394815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • However, he does not say that his theory is the same as Raz's. Rather, he says: “But I don't think I should have seen the full importance of Hobbes’ remarks on these topics had I not had the benefit of the work of Joseph Raz on what he terms ‘exclusionary reasons’ which resembles in many respects the notion I have taken from Hobbes.” Hart, One wonders how Raz himself would deal with Kramer's objection, given that Raz has famously argued that inclusive legal positivism is incompatible with the preemptive nature of legal rules. note 73, at 244 (emphasis added).
    • Hart does mention in Commands and Authoritative Reasons that his analysis of authoritative directives was inspired by Raz's work on exclusionary reasons. However, he does not say that his theory is the same as Raz's. Rather, he says: “But I don't think I should have seen the full importance of Hobbes’ remarks on these topics had I not had the benefit of the work of Joseph Raz on what he terms ‘exclusionary reasons’ which resembles in many respects the notion I have taken from Hobbes.” Hart, One wonders how Raz himself would deal with Kramer's objection, given that Raz has famously argued that inclusive legal positivism is incompatible with the preemptive nature of legal rules. note 73, at 244 (emphasis added).
    • Hart does mention in Commands and Authoritative Reasons that his analysis of authoritative directives was inspired by Raz's work on exclusionary reasons.
  • 58
    • 85022407571 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart does mention in Commands and Authoritative Reasons that his analysis of authoritative directives was inspired by Raz's work on exclusionary reasons. note 6, at 139 (emphasis added).
    • Hart, Hart does mention in Commands and Authoritative Reasons that his analysis of authoritative directives was inspired by Raz's work on exclusionary reasons. note 6, at 139 (emphasis added).
    • Hart


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.