메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 16, Issue 2, 2010, Pages 111-133

Legal formalism and legal realism: What is the issue?

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 78650756127     PISSN: 13523252     EISSN: 14698048     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S1352325210000121     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (71)

References (61)
  • 2
    • 85022396911 scopus 로고
    • in Taking Rights Seriously (1977); and Dworkin, Law's Empire ch. 6
    • See, e.g., Ronald Dworkin, Hard Cases, in Taking Rights Seriously (1977); and Dworkin, Law's Empire ch. 6 (1986).
    • (1986) Hard Cases
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 4
    • 85022410625 scopus 로고
    • A Return to Stare Decisis, 14 A.B.A. J. 75. In this situation type, courts found a way to enforce the promise. By contrast, in cases involving the situation type “employee promises not to compete with an employer after leaving his or her employ,” courts have found a way to invalidate the promise.
    • The example is from Herman Oliphant, A Return to Stare Decisis, 14 A.B.A. J. 75 (1928). In this situation type, courts found a way to enforce the promise. By contrast, in cases involving the situation type “employee promises not to compete with an employer after leaving his or her employ,” courts have found a way to invalidate the promise.
    • (1928) The example is from Herman Oliphant
  • 5
    • 85022383099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Brian Leiter, Naturalizing Jurisprudence: Essays on American Legal Realism and Naturalism in Legal Philosophy, esp. chs. 1-3. For a more concise account, see Leiter, American Legal Realism, in The Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory (M. Golding & W. Edmundson eds., 2005). The description in the text pertains to what I call the “Sociological Wing” of realism, which was the dominant strand. The views of Jerome Frank were a bit different on the second and third points.
    • For detailed discussion and evidence, see Brian Leiter, Naturalizing Jurisprudence: Essays on American Legal Realism and Naturalism in Legal Philosophy (2007), esp. chs. 1-3. For a more concise account, see Leiter, American Legal Realism, in The Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory (M. Golding & W. Edmundson eds., 2005). The description in the text pertains to what I call the “Sociological Wing” of realism, which was the dominant strand. The views of Jerome Frank were a bit different on the second and third points.
    • (2007) For detailed discussion and evidence
  • 8
    • 85022444964 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In chs. 7 and 8, he also takes on contemporary political scientists who have often taken a straw-man view of adjudication as their target. (I do agree with Fred Schauer, though, who points out to me that the political-science work on courts is a useful corrective to much doctrinal scholarship in constitutional law, which talks as though the doctrine is really explanatory of Supreme Court decisions.)
    • In chs. 7 and 8, he also takes on contemporary political scientists who have often taken a straw-man view of adjudication as their target. I have no brief here on behalf of their accounts, and if Tamanaha's book has the salutary effect of improving the quality of their work, that will be to his lasting credit. (I do agree with Fred Schauer, though, who points out to me that the political-science work on courts is a useful corrective to much doctrinal scholarship in constitutional law, which talks as though the doctrine is really explanatory of Supreme Court decisions.)
    • I have no brief here on behalf of their accounts, and if Tamanaha's book has the salutary effect of improving the quality of their work, that will be to his lasting credit
  • 9
    • 85022437655 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at 3. This non sequitur is not simply an artifact of the introduction to the book; Tamanaha repeats it again much later: “Any approach that defines ‘formalism’ in these terms has doubtful validity, as earlier chapters demonstrated. These ideas were not widely held in the U.S. legal tradition, if they were held by any jurists at all” (id. at 160).
    • Tamanaha, I have no brief here on behalf of their accounts, and if Tamanaha's book has the salutary effect of improving the quality of their work, that will be to his lasting credit note 10, at 3. This non sequitur is not simply an artifact of the introduction to the book; Tamanaha repeats it again much later: “Any approach that defines ‘formalism’ in these terms has doubtful validity, as earlier chapters demonstrated. These ideas were not widely held in the U.S. legal tradition, if they were held by any jurists at all” (id. at 160).
    • I have no brief here on behalf of their accounts, and if Tamanaha's book has the salutary effect of improving the quality of their work, that will be to his lasting credit note 10
    • Tamanaha1
  • 15
    • 85022398554 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin does believe that the duty of the judge is always to discover the law that already exists in every case, although he does not subscribe to Tamanaha's second “formalist” thesis, about which more infra. The absence of Dworkin, the “ideal type” of the interesting legal formalist, from Tamanaha's analysis betrays the superficiality of the book's jurisprudential argument.
    • While historically Natural Law Formalism was associated with Blackstone, it does still have one well-known defender, who is almost entirely absent from Tamanaha's book: Ronald Dworkin. Dworkin does believe that the duty of the judge is always to discover the law that already exists in every case, although he does not subscribe to Tamanaha's second “formalist” thesis, about which more infra. The absence of Dworkin, the “ideal type” of the interesting legal formalist, from Tamanaha's analysis betrays the superficiality of the book's jurisprudential argument.
    • While historically Natural Law Formalism was associated with Blackstone, it does still have one well-known defender, who is almost entirely absent from Tamanaha's book: Ronald Dworkin
  • 16
    • 85022385807 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 34: They were made by leading lawyers and judges in high-profile settings. What they say is manifestly at odds with the conventional story about purportedly dominant legal formalist beliefs at the time.”
    • See id. at 34: “All of the preceding statements were made in the heart of the so-called formalist age. They were made by leading lawyers and judges in high-profile settings. What they say is manifestly at odds with the conventional story about purportedly dominant legal formalist beliefs at the time.”
    • “All of the preceding statements were made in the heart of the so-called formalist age
  • 17
    • 85022431054 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I discuss infra some cases where he does not. I leave it to intellectual historians to carry out a more systematic examination of the sources on which Tamanaha's argument depends.
    • There is also the question of whether Tamanaha represents his quoted sources fairly. I discuss infra some cases where he does not. I leave it to intellectual historians to carry out a more systematic examination of the sources on which Tamanaha's argument depends.
    • There is also the question of whether Tamanaha represents his quoted sources fairly
  • 19
    • 85022352336 scopus 로고
    • And Jerome Frank famously cites Chancellor Kent, writing a century earlier, in support of the thesis that judges first get a “hunch” about the fair outcome and then search for legal reasons to support that conclusion. See Jerome Frank, Law and the Modern Mind ch. 12 n.3. Even Tamanaha notices that Frank cites jurists from the nineteenth century (see Tamanaha, There is also the question of whether Tamanaha represents his quoted sources fairly note 10 note 10, at 93). I concentrate on Tamanaha's evidence that further predates the 1920s.
    • Some of the “evidence” from scholars and jurists in the early 1900s is hardly apposite: no one thinks realism arose ex nihilo; it had, of course, a prehistory in the work of earlier thinkers such as Oliver Wendell Holmes and Benjamin Cardozo. And Jerome Frank famously cites Chancellor Kent, writing a century earlier, in support of the thesis that judges first get a “hunch” about the fair outcome and then search for legal reasons to support that conclusion. See Jerome Frank, Law and the Modern Mind ch. 12 n.3 (1930). Even Tamanaha notices that Frank cites jurists from the nineteenth century (see Tamanaha, There is also the question of whether Tamanaha represents his quoted sources fairly note 10 note 10, at 93). I concentrate on Tamanaha's evidence that further predates the 1920s.
    • (1930) Some of the “evidence” from scholars and jurists in the early 1900s is hardly apposite: no one thinks realism arose ex nihilo; it had, of course, a prehistory in the work of earlier thinkers such as Oliver Wendell Holmes and Benjamin Cardozo
  • 21
    • 85022394441 scopus 로고
    • The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457 about the three possible explanations for why a judge might make a particular legal argument (e.g., implying a condition in a contract in a particular case): “It is because of some belief as to the practice of the community or a class, or because of some opinion as to policy, or, in short, because of some attitude of yours [the judge's] upon a matter not capable of exact quantitative measurement, and therefore not capable of founding exact logical conclusions.” Id. at 466. The Realists of the 1920s and 1930s focused almost wholly on the first and third possibilities, not the second.
    • The closest one comes in a central realist text is the comment in Oliver Wendell Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457 (1897) about the three possible explanations for why a judge might make a particular legal argument (e.g., implying a condition in a contract in a particular case): “It is because of some belief as to the practice of the community or a class, or because of some opinion as to policy, or, in short, because of some attitude of yours [the judge's] upon a matter not capable of exact quantitative measurement, and therefore not capable of founding exact logical conclusions.” Id. at 466. The Realists of the 1920s and 1930s focused almost wholly on the first and third possibilities, not the second.
    • (1897) The closest one comes in a central realist text is the comment in Oliver Wendell Holmes
  • 23
    • 85022364724 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Naturalizing, The closest one comes in a central realist text is the comment in Oliver Wendell Holmes note 10 note 8, chs. 1 & 3.
    • I discuss this and the evidence in Leiter, Naturalizing, The closest one comes in a central realist text is the comment in Oliver Wendell Holmes note 10 note 8, chs. 1 & 3.
    • I discuss this and the evidence in Leiter
  • 27
    • 27144549758 scopus 로고
    • 43 Harv. L. Rev. 863 (1930) Karl Llewellyn, Remarks on the Theory of Appellate Decision and the Rules and Canons about How Statutes Are to Be Construed, 3 Vand. L. Rev. 395
    • See Max Radin, Statutory Interpretation, 43 Harv. L. Rev. 863 (1930) Karl Llewellyn, Remarks on the Theory of Appellate Decision and the Rules and Canons about How Statutes Are to Be Construed, 3 Vand. L. Rev. 395 (1950).
    • (1950) Statutory Interpretation
    • Radin, M.1
  • 29
    • 84871790445 scopus 로고
    • 24 Am. L. Rev. 1, 15, quoted in Tamanaha, Statutory Interpretation note 10 note 10, at
    • James C. Carter, The Provinces of the Written and the Unwritten Law, 24 Am. L. Rev. 1, 15 (1890), quoted in Tamanaha, Statutory Interpretation note 10 note 10, at 83.
    • (1890) The Provinces of the Written and the Unwritten Law , pp. 83
    • Carter, J.C.1
  • 32
    • 85022371769 scopus 로고
    • Past and Future, 7 S. L. Rev.
    • William G. Hammond, American Law Schools, Past and Future, 7 S. L. Rev. 400, 413 (1881).
    • (1881) American Law Schools , vol.400 , pp. 413
    • Hammond, W.G.1
  • 33
    • 85022379236 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at 68. He also denies that “the legal realists formed a group or movement.” Id. at 68. His evidence is that “the main characterizations of legal realism put forth by theorists and historians”-he cites only Laura Kalman, Robert Summers, John Henry Schlegel, and Morton Horwitz-are “the promotion of an instrumental view of law as a means to serve social ends, the pursuit of social scientific approaches to law, the efforts of reformers to transform legal education in order to improve legal practice and judging, and attempts by reformers to advance a progressive political agenda in and through the law-or some amalgamation of all four.” Id. at 70. He then fairly notes that those often listed as Realists “did not agree among themselves on these positions.” Id. Since he inexplicably omits attempts by jurisprudential writers explicitly to state distinctive jurisprudential theses characteristic of realism-namely, mine and Fred Schauer's (though he otherwise cites our work)-this is hardly surprising. But we return to this issue infra.
    • Tamanaha, American Law Schools note 10, at 68. He also denies that “the legal realists formed a group or movement.” Id. at 68. His evidence is that “the main characterizations of legal realism put forth by theorists and historians”-he cites only Laura Kalman, Robert Summers, John Henry Schlegel, and Morton Horwitz-are “the promotion of an instrumental view of law as a means to serve social ends, the pursuit of social scientific approaches to law, the efforts of reformers to transform legal education in order to improve legal practice and judging, and attempts by reformers to advance a progressive political agenda in and through the law-or some amalgamation of all four.” Id. at 70. He then fairly notes that those often listed as Realists “did not agree among themselves on these positions.” Id. Since he inexplicably omits attempts by jurisprudential writers explicitly to state distinctive jurisprudential theses characteristic of realism-namely, mine and Fred Schauer's (though he otherwise cites our work)-this is hardly surprising. But we return to this issue infra.
    • American Law Schools note 10
    • Tamanaha1
  • 35
    • 0040223973 scopus 로고
    • in A Companion to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory (D. Patterson ed., 1995); and my 1997 paper Leiter, Rethinking Legal Realism, Note that balanced realism is not simply an empirical observation about judicial behavior; it is predicated on a jurisprudential view about the indeterminacy of legal reasoning such that judges do have choices to make and can quite properly construe rules and precedents in different ways, etc note 16, which Tamanaha does cite but not for its precise characterization of realism. And for Schauer's work on realism, see, e.g., Frederick Schauer, Judging in a Corner of the Law, 61 S. Cal. L. Rev. 1717 (1988) and Frederick Schauer, Playing by the Rules, at 191-196. Schauer gives a concise summary of his views on realism in Frederick Schauer, Thinking Like a Lawyer ch. 7 (2009).
    • See, e.g., Brian Leiter, Legal Realism, in A Companion to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory (D. Patterson ed., 1995); and my 1997 paper Leiter, Rethinking Legal Realism, Note that balanced realism is not simply an empirical observation about judicial behavior; it is predicated on a jurisprudential view about the indeterminacy of legal reasoning such that judges do have choices to make and can quite properly construe rules and precedents in different ways, etc note 16, which Tamanaha does cite but not for its precise characterization of realism. And for Schauer's work on realism, see, e.g., Frederick Schauer, Judging in a Corner of the Law, 61 S. Cal. L. Rev. 1717 (1988) and Frederick Schauer, Playing by the Rules (1991), at 191-196. Schauer gives a concise summary of his views on realism in Frederick Schauer, Thinking Like a Lawyer ch. 7 (2009).
    • (1991) Legal Realism
    • Leiter, B.1
  • 37
    • 85022370622 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see, e.g., Michael Steven Green, Legal Realism as Theory of Law, 46 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 1915. While I think Green wrong, partly on textual and partly on philosophical grounds, Green's work is jurisprudentially interesting because it articulates precise and distinctive realist theses about law and adjudication.
    • A contrast can be usefully drawn here with the work by Michael Steven Green on realism; see, e.g., Michael Steven Green, Legal Realism as Theory of Law, 46 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 1915 (2005). While I think Green wrong, partly on textual and partly on philosophical grounds, Green's work is jurisprudentially interesting because it articulates precise and distinctive realist theses about law and adjudication.
    • (2005) A contrast can be usefully drawn here with the work by Michael Steven Green on realism
  • 38
    • 85022418553 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A contrast can be usefully drawn here with the work by Michael Steven Green on realism; note 57, at 192, quoted in Tamanaha, A contrast can be usefully drawn here with the work by Michael Steven Green on realism; note 10, at
    • Schauer, Playing, A contrast can be usefully drawn here with the work by Michael Steven Green on realism; note 57, at 192, quoted in Tamanaha, A contrast can be usefully drawn here with the work by Michael Steven Green on realism; note 10, at 93-94.
    • Playing , pp. 93-94
    • Schauer1
  • 40
    • 85022395102 scopus 로고
    • Id note 57 and even earlier, Schauer, Easy Cases, 58 S. Cal. L. Rev. 399
    • See Frederick Schauer, Judging in a Corner, Id note 57 and even earlier, Schauer, Easy Cases, 58 S. Cal. L. Rev. 399 (1985).
    • (1985) Judging in a Corner
    • Schauer, F.1
  • 41
    • 85022436133 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I have already commented Judging in a Corner on Tamanaha's misrepresentation of James Carter's views in the context of his criticism of my claim that the distinctive realist thesis is about responsiveness to situation types as the best explanation of appellate decisions. Tamanaha also purports at one point to be disputing my claim that “American Legal Realism was, quite justifiably, the major intellectual event in 20th century American legal practice and scholarship” (Leiter, Naturalizing, Judging in a Corner note 8, at 1), but since he does not, as we see above, actually discuss the distinctive views of the Realists, on which my claim was predicated, there is no dispute. Everyone can agree with Tamanaha that before realism, there were at least some jurists and scholars who recognized the influence of politics on judicial decision-making and were skeptical that mechanical deduction did any justice to the nature of legal reasoning, but this would do nothing to show that “Realism about judging was commonplace decades before the legal realists came on the scene.” Tamanaha, Judging in a Corner note 10, at 68. A more egregious case-because I point out the error to Tamanaha in an earlier version of this material-is the purported criticism (id. at 2) of my account of formalism in Brian Leiter, Positivism, Formalism, Realism, 99 Colum. L. Rev. 1138, without noting that I was articulating competing substantive views of adjudication, not making an historical claim of the kind he is criticizing. Even if most late-nineteenth-century writers were “realists” instead of “formalists,” this would have no bearing on the jurisprudential question about how we ought to understand adjudication.
    • I confine my comments on Tamanaha's mistaken criticisms of me to a footnote. I have already commented Judging in a Corner on Tamanaha's misrepresentation of James Carter's views in the context of his criticism of my claim that the distinctive realist thesis is about responsiveness to situation types as the best explanation of appellate decisions. Tamanaha also purports at one point to be disputing my claim that “American Legal Realism was, quite justifiably, the major intellectual event in 20th century American legal practice and scholarship” (Leiter, Naturalizing, Judging in a Corner note 8, at 1), but since he does not, as we see above, actually discuss the distinctive views of the Realists, on which my claim was predicated, there is no dispute. Everyone can agree with Tamanaha that before realism, there were at least some jurists and scholars who recognized the influence of politics on judicial decision-making and were skeptical that mechanical deduction did any justice to the nature of legal reasoning, but this would do nothing to show that “Realism about judging was commonplace decades before the legal realists came on the scene.” Tamanaha, Judging in a Corner note 10, at 68. A more egregious case-because I point out the error to Tamanaha in an earlier version of this material-is the purported criticism (id. at 2) of my account of formalism in Brian Leiter, Positivism, Formalism, Realism, 99 Colum. L. Rev. 1138 (1999), without noting that I was articulating competing substantive views of adjudication, not making an historical claim of the kind he is criticizing. Even if most late-nineteenth-century writers were “realists” instead of “formalists,” this would have no bearing on the jurisprudential question about how we ought to understand adjudication.
    • (1999) I confine my comments on Tamanaha's mistaken criticisms of me to a footnote
  • 43
    • 85022397906 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Michael S. Moore, Educating Oneself in Public: Critical Essays in Jurisprudence 32-35. H.L.A. Hart, who seems to embrace what Tamanaha is calling “balanced realism” (again, it is hard to say for sure because the characterization is vague and shifting), thought he had a dispute with the Realists, and rightly so.
    • See, e.g., Green, I confine my comments on Tamanaha's mistaken criticisms of me to a footnote note 10 note 59 see also Michael S. Moore, Educating Oneself in Public: Critical Essays in Jurisprudence 32-35 (2000). H.L.A. Hart, who seems to embrace what Tamanaha is calling “balanced realism” (again, it is hard to say for sure because the characterization is vague and shifting), thought he had a dispute with the Realists, and rightly so.
    • (2000) I confine my comments on Tamanaha's mistaken criticisms of me to a footnote note 10 note 59
    • Green1
  • 44
    • 85022353645 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at 91. In ch. 10, esp. 186-196, Tamanaha expands on his earlier description of “balanced realism,” attributing to realism nine claims about adjudication (his rambling discussion is somewhat repetitive, so I have trimmed the list a bit here): (1) “When judges perceive facts, interpret the law, and render judgments, they are influenced by cognitive framing in the same ways that all cognition is influenced” (id. at 187), but the inevitability of cognitive framing is not the same as “willful judging,” which, unlike the former, “is not ubiquitous and is not inevitable” (id. at 188); (2) “when judges render legal decisions, except in the most routine cases, the purposes behind the applicable rules and the consequences of the decision will have a bearing” (id. at 189); (3) “uncertainties will inevitably arise in interpretation and application of legal rules and principles” (id. at 190); (4) “the region of legal uncertainty is where judges render decisions with the least legal guidance, and where judges’ mix of legal and social views has the most leeway and impact-though still in a context thick with legal norms” (id. at 190); (5) “judges are sometimes confronted with what they consider ‘bad rules’ or ‘bad results,’” although they “do not take a uniform position or follow the same course in such situations” (id. at 191), though sometimes, in cases of this kind, there “is an enhanced potential for the influence of the personal values of” the judge to affect the decision (id. at 192); (6) “the common law and statutes contain a variety of standards like fairness and reasonableness, or provisions that require balancing, or that require judges … to make judgments. The judgments called for cannot be made in a rule-like fashion and are not determined by legal factors alone,” although judges may often agree due to their sharing “similar training in the legal tradition and its values” as well as “social views” (id. at 192); (7) “judges are not machines or computers” (id. at 194); (8) “judicial decisions frequently are consistent with and determined by the law” (id. at 194); (9) “law is continuously being worked out by judges” (id. at 195). Some of these claims are, at this level of generality, quite banal or merely the flip side of the denial of Vulgar Formalism (e.g., 3, 7 & 9); some are of dubious realist pedigree (e.g., 1, 2 & 6); and some are contested by other accounts of adjudication, as discussed in the text.
    • Tamanaha, I confine my comments on Tamanaha's mistaken criticisms of me to a footnote note 10 note 59 note 10, at 91. In ch. 10, esp. 186-196, Tamanaha expands on his earlier description of “balanced realism,” attributing to realism nine claims about adjudication (his rambling discussion is somewhat repetitive, so I have trimmed the list a bit here): (1) “When judges perceive facts, interpret the law, and render judgments, they are influenced by cognitive framing in the same ways that all cognition is influenced” (id. at 187), but the inevitability of cognitive framing is not the same as “willful judging,” which, unlike the former, “is not ubiquitous and is not inevitable” (id. at 188); (2) “when judges render legal decisions, except in the most routine cases, the purposes behind the applicable rules and the consequences of the decision will have a bearing” (id. at 189); (3) “uncertainties will inevitably arise in interpretation and application of legal rules and principles” (id. at 190); (4) “the region of legal uncertainty is where judges render decisions with the least legal guidance, and where judges’ mix of legal and social views has the most leeway and impact-though still in a context thick with legal norms” (id. at 190); (5) “judges are sometimes confronted with what they consider ‘bad rules’ or ‘bad results,’” although they “do not take a uniform position or follow the same course in such situations” (id. at 191), though sometimes, in cases of this kind, there “is an enhanced potential for the influence of the personal values of” the judge to affect the decision (id. at 192); (6) “the common law and statutes contain a variety of standards like fairness and reasonableness, or provisions that require balancing, or that require judges … to make judgments. The judgments called for cannot be made in a rule-like fashion and are not determined by legal factors alone,” although judges may often agree due to their sharing “similar training in the legal tradition and its values” as well as “social views” (id. at 192); (7) “judges are not machines or computers” (id. at 194); (8) “judicial decisions frequently are consistent with and determined by the law” (id. at 194); (9) “law is continuously being worked out by judges” (id. at 195). Some of these claims are, at this level of generality, quite banal or merely the flip side of the denial of Vulgar Formalism (e.g., 3, 7 & 9); some are of dubious realist pedigree (e.g., 1, 2 & 6); and some are contested by other accounts of adjudication, as discussed in the text.
    • I confine my comments on Tamanaha's mistaken criticisms of me to a footnote note 10 note 59 note 10
    • Tamanaha1
  • 45
    • 85022436338 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 32 Clev. St. L. Rev. 385, 388 (1983). Notwithstanding the admission of “balanced realism” by Judge Edwards, it is perhaps worth noting that he himself may be understating the role of nonlegal influences on the decisions of his own court, as suggested in Richard L. Revesz, Ideology, Collegiality, and the D.C. Circuit: A Reply to Chief Judge Harry T. Edwards, 85 Va. L. Rev. 805
    • Harry T. Edwards, The Role of a Judge in Modern Society: Some Reflections on Current Practice in Federal Appellate Adjudication, 32 Clev. St. L. Rev. 385, 388 (1983). Notwithstanding the admission of “balanced realism” by Judge Edwards, it is perhaps worth noting that he himself may be understating the role of nonlegal influences on the decisions of his own court, as suggested in Richard L. Revesz, Ideology, Collegiality, and the D.C. Circuit: A Reply to Chief Judge Harry T. Edwards, 85 Va. L. Rev. 805 (1999).
    • (1999) The Role of a Judge in Modern Society: Some Reflections on Current Practice in Federal Appellate Adjudication
    • Edwards, H.T.1
  • 49
    • 85022449445 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Sotomayor Nomination, Part II The Federalist Society (July 13, ), http://www.fed-soc.org/debates/dbtid.30/default.asp. Seidman says
    • The Federalist Society Online Debate Series, The Sotomayor Nomination, Part II The Federalist Society (July 13, 2009), http://www.fed-soc.org/debates/dbtid.30/default.asp. Seidman says
    • (2009) The Federalist Society Online Debate Series
  • 50
    • 85022382235 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Times Literary Supplement, Feb. 26, 2010, at 24 (reviewing Frederick Schauer, Thinking Like a Lawyer ).
    • Brian Leiter, Rule and Reason, Times Literary Supplement, Feb. 26, 2010, at 24 (reviewing Frederick Schauer, Thinking Like a Lawyer (2009)).
    • (2009) Rule and Reason
    • Leiter, B.1
  • 52
    • 85022350374 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Most constitutional theorists are simply attracted to the idea that moral considerations are relevant to adjudicating weighty constitutional issues-a view, of course, that does nothing to distinguish Dworkin's jurisprudence from that of the legal positivists. See Brian Leiter, The Radicalism of Legal Positivism, Guild Practitioner
    • The “Dworkin lite” that is popular among constitutional theorists does not appear to commit them to Dworkin's views about the rational determinacy of law and the autonomy of legal reasoning. Most constitutional theorists are simply attracted to the idea that moral considerations are relevant to adjudicating weighty constitutional issues-a view, of course, that does nothing to distinguish Dworkin's jurisprudence from that of the legal positivists. See Brian Leiter, The Radicalism of Legal Positivism, Guild Practitioner (2010).
    • (2010) The “Dworkin lite” that is popular among constitutional theorists does not appear to commit them to Dworkin's views about the rational determinacy of law and the autonomy of legal reasoning
  • 54
    • 85022393715 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U. Tex. L. Public Law Research Paper No. 138 (Jan. 23, ), available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1113461.
    • See Brian Leiter, In Praise of Realism (and Against “Nonsense” Jurisprudence), U. Tex. L. Public Law Research Paper No. 138 (Jan. 23, 2010), available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1113461.
    • (2010) Praise of Realism (and Against “Nonsense” Jurisprudence)
    • Leiter, B.1
  • 56
    • 0041032227 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 111 Ethics 278, reprinted in Leiter, Naturalizing, Praise of Realism (and Against “Nonsense” Jurisprudence) note 10 note
    • See Brian Leiter, Legal Realism and Legal Positivism Reconsidered, 111 Ethics 278 (2001), reprinted in Leiter, Naturalizing, Praise of Realism (and Against “Nonsense” Jurisprudence) note 10 note 8.
    • (2001) Legal Realism and Legal Positivism Reconsidered , pp. 8
    • Leiter, B.1
  • 58
    • 85022429719 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dictionary.com, http://dictionary.reference.com/browse/vehicle (last viewed July 2, ).
    • Vehicle, Dictionary.com, http://dictionary.reference.com/browse/vehicle (last viewed July 2, 2010).
    • (2010) Vehicle


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.